Beyond Art Dominic McIver Lopes DRAFT . April , Chapter added February , NOT FOR CITATION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION OF THE AUTHOR Contents Acknowledgements Introduction Part I Beyond Art After the Beginning of Art Passing the Buck on Art Art in Culture The Myth of Artistic Value Part II Beyond Bricolage Appreciative Kinds and Media Appreciative Practices Aesthetic Appreciation Much Ado about Art Works Cited Whatever I think about I at the same time learn something about it and about thought, so that the structures of its objects as revealed by thought are revelations about the structure of thought itself. – Arthur Danto, Transfiguration of the Commonplace It is far easier to throw out the baby with the bathwater than to perceive that you were mistaken about which was which. – Peter Kivy, Philosophies of Arts Introduction What is art? This is one of the great, sticky questions of the last hundred years. It has inspired heaps of books, some of which focus so fiercely on the question that they take it for their titles, either straight up or in some playful variation. Tolstoy’s What Is Art? begat Clive Bell’s more emphatically named Art of , and some recent aesthetics best sellers are Matthew Kieran’s Revealing Art and Cynthia Freeland’s But Is It Art? The pattern seems to be this: put the question, give an answer, reject the answer, put the question again…. Equating this circling with a lack of progress, the weary and impatient have wished to dismiss the whole business as doomed… but that would be a mistake. Works of art are usually meant to put our minds in gear, some are very much worth thinking about, and one profitable way to think about them is via the question, what is art? While the question seems inevitable in confronting certain avant-garde works, even quite traditional art works freshen up when we step far enough back from our assumptions that we begin to wonder what art is. Tucked away in a corner of the Louvre, remote from the throngs there to visit the Mona Lisa, are some still lifes by Chardin; and these small paintings of kitchen utensils and bowls of fruit have dedicated admirers. From the alien perspective of someone totally unfamiliar with what happens in galleries like the Louvre, this is extremely puzzling. The Chardins carry no interesting messages or strong charges of emotion: their subject matter is simply prosaic. To concede they cause pleasure makes a mockery of the dedication they inspire, if the pleasure is like that of consuming the fruit and water they depict. If the pleasure is some je ne sais quoi, then the puzzle repeats itself. The point is not that the puzzle is impossible to solve. On the contrary, there is a great deal to think about before we reach that pessimistic conclusion, and this thinking may shed light on what is so compelling in the Chardins. Rather, the point is that the philosophical stance the puzzle asks us to take, in company with Tolstoy and Bell, Kieran and Freeland, is one from which we might profitably come to appreciate the Chardins. 5 So the question ‘what is art?’ makes a serviceable heuristic for any of us to use as we engage with and appreciate our favourite works of art (see Kennick ). The heuristic is common in professional and academic criticism, notably in the tradition of Clive Bell and Clement Greenberg. Cynics of the sociological debunking variety might speculate that criticism in this tradition dresses itself up in philosophical questions in a bid to establish its intellectual seriousness. However, even were this cynical indictment true, it would not diminish the contributions, actual and potential, that reflections about the nature of art can make to the task of art appreciation. Asking ‘what is art?’ is a stratagem of art criticism that sometimes pays off. For that reason alone, the question is a good question. Nothing in this book should put us beyond asking ‘what is art?’ in this spirit. But although it is sometimes an option to ask what art is, that question is great and sticky partly because it is thought to be mandatory, not merely heuristic. This book argues that it is a mistake to think it mandatory to pose the ‘what is art?’ question as motivating a philosophical inquiry into art. Put bluntly, the ‘what is art question?’ is the wrong question for philosophy. Philosophical discussions of the nature of art often start out by declaring the topic’s central and foundational role in aesthetics. The first word in contemporary aesthetics is Monroe Beardsley’s book, Aesthetics, which opens by declaring that ‘there would be no problems of aesthetics… if no one ever talked about works of art’ ([], ). A similar sentiment kicks off Richard Wollheim’s classic Art and Its Objects, where he ventures that ‘the nature of art… is one of the most elusive of the traditional problems of human culture’ ([], ). Twenty years later he called it ‘the core of aesthetics’ (, ). Peter Kivy reckons the topic ‘the most widely and persistently pursued problem in aesthetics or the philosophy of art’ (, ) and Gary Iseminger notes that it ‘did so much to shape what has come to be called “analytic aesthetics”’ (, vii). A comprehensive bibliography published in runs longer than twenty pages (Choi ), and the topic is standard fare in the anthologies and textbooks through which the field is introduced to students. 6 In his final word on the ‘what is art?’ question, Beardsley () provides four reasons why it deserves a central and foundational role in the field. First, any philosopher of art should be ‘curious to know what he is philosophizing about’. Presumably, anyone who philosophizes about X (for any X) should be curious about the nature of X. Second, philosophy has the job of engineering and testing the conceptual foundations of other disciplines, including the social sciences. That means delivering a theory of art as a phenomenon that figures in scientific hypotheses, as distinct from other phenomena, such as religious observance, political negotiation, economic exchange, and medical treatment. Third, any critic needs ‘criteria for deciding what sorts of things he is to criticize’, and philosophy presumably supplies the criteria. Fourth, an answer to the ‘what is art?’ question is a practical necessity to the legislator and administrator, who must decide what items to exempt from import duties and obscenity laws, and what items are candidates for funding by such bodies as the National Endowment for the Arts. Lurking in the background of Beardsley’s list is a concern driven by avant-garde works, for it it surely does seem that we have no choice but to ask ‘what is art?’ when we find ourselves face to face with certain art works. After all, they are works that cut their avant-garde chops by interrogating assumptions about art. Contrast Chardin’s still lifes in the Louvre with a landmark in the history of mid-century art, Robert Barry’s Inert Gas Series of . In March of that year, Barry released a litre of krypton into the atmosphere in Beverly Hills, before going on to release xenon in the mountains, argon on the beach, and helium in the Mohave desert. Barry is reported to have explained that ‘nothing seems to me the most potent thing in the world’ (Lippard , ). Of course, this gnomic utterance does nothing to help make sense of the work, which must after all be something, not nothing. Is it the gas? The act of emptying it into the air? The documentary evidence that is now collected by museums? The idea of releasing some gas and documenting it? No answer is obvious and none is remotely satisfactory because it is hard to see how any of these candidates could shoulder the mantle of art work. Imagine someone who simply does not see what all the fuss is about, for 7 whom it is plain as can be that the gas (or any other candidate) is the art work. Such a person misses the work’s Chimera-like complexity: they fail to grasp that it puts into question the nature of art. This description of Barry’s production blithely assumed that it is a work of art. With that assumption in place, the work seems to raise the question what is art, if it is art. However, as we all know perfectly well, the artistic status of productions like Barry’s is tremendously controversial. A very fine line separates ‘what is art, if that is art?’ from another question: ‘is that art?’ Having crossed the line, it is fair game to answer ‘no! that is not art’. Some go so far as to allege that productions like the Inert Gas Series perpetrate some kind of hoax. They are the highbrow counterpart of kitsch, passing themselves off as art despite overindulging the intellect as kitsch passes itself off as art despite overindulging the emotions. Call Barry’s Inert Gas Series and other cases that entice us across the line the ‘hard cases’. Hard cases provoke the question, what is art? Since the hard cases attract intense attention, it is prudent to clarify the label. Count as a hard case any work whose status as art is controversial. Thus labelling a work as ‘hard case’ should be neutral on the work’s art status. A work’s being a hard case is consistent with its being a work of art and also with its not being a work of art. If it is in fact a work of art then it is puzzling what would make it a work of art; and if it is not in fact a work of art then there must be plenty of reason to take it for one. No case is less hard for being deprecated as not art or for being promoted as art: deprecation and promotion generally make a hard case harder, not easier. Beardsley’s third and fourth reasons clearly echo a concern with hard cases. Art is a ‘fighting word’ in criticism. That is, calling an item art elevates it, while withholding the attribution puts down anything with artistic aspirations, so that critics commonly wield the name of art in commendation and withhold it in reprimand. Arthur Danto recalls that, ‘New York critics were known to say of something they disapproved of that it was not really art, when there was very little else but art that it could be’ (, ). Meanwhile, Beardsley’s mention of the legislator 8 and administrator was prescient. Within a few years of , when Beardsley’s essay was published, came the so-called culture wars, in which legislators and political activists, mostly in the United States, loudly quarrelled over the display and funding and hence the implied artistic status of certain items – notably the siting of Richard Serra’s Tilted Arc across the plaza of the Jacob Javitz Federal Building in New York, the public exhibition of Robert Mapplethorpe’s X Portfolio, and the performances of the ‘NEA Four’. A more prosaic and recent example is a European Commission ruling that a light installation by Dan Flavin does not qualify for the lower sales tax applicable to works of art. The Commission found that Flavin’s installation has ‘the characteristics of lighting fittings… and is therefore to be classified… as wall lighting fittings’ (Artinfo ). The second chapter of this book argues that the hard cases drive recent philosophy, which has taken up the ‘what is art?’ question in response to disputes over art status. Nobody has the ambition of refereeing every hard case by every hard case. The expectation is rather that philosophy should provide a general answer to the ‘what is art?’ question which will do two things. It will explain why the hard cases are hard cases. It will also distinguish in a principled way between art and non-art, no matter whether any particular hard case lands on the art or the non-art side of that boundary. So here is a fifth reason why the ‘what is art?’ question might be thought to deserve a central place in aesthetics. There are hard cases, they are worth taking seriously as hard cases, and the way to take them seriously as hard cases is by investigating the nature of art. If this is correct, the ‘what is art?’ question gains traction in philosophy partly because it seems to be mandatory in face of certain avant-garde art works. It follows that if the question is not mandatory in face of these works, then perhaps it is not mandatory in philosophy. Chapters and argue that we do not need an answer to the ‘what is art?’ question in order to take the hard cases seriously. What about Beardsley’s second reason why philosophy should include an examination of the nature of art? Beardsley argues that social scientists routinely distinguish artistic activity from other 9 activities, thereby deploying a concept of art, and it falls to philosophy to engineer the conceptual foundations of social science. Chapter proposes that the kind of answer to the ‘what is art?’ question that is implicated in social science is not the kind of answer that mandates confronting the hard cases. The ‘what is art?’ question can be a good heuristic when the task at hand is appreciating works of art: Beardsley goes a step further in suggesting that an understanding of the nature of art is needed to ground art critical practice. Here Beardsley is mildly radical, for traditional theories of taste and aesthetic judgement, such as those of Hume and Kant, were not associated with the ‘what is art?’ question. More radical still is the now common view that criticism deals in artistic value as distinct from aesthetic value. Chapter five argues that there is no such thing as artistic value. That leaves the argument that since philosophers of X should be curious about the nature of X, philosophers of art, in particular, should examine the nature of art, in particular. This line of thought touches on how to think about the configuration of the research enterprise known as aesthetics or the philosophy of art. Since nomenclature does not legislate activity, it is fair to shrug off the designation ‘philosophy of art’ and to look into what phenomenon –or indeed phenomena – might go in for X. Aesthetics is a contender, after all. No matter how it ultimately gets characterized, the field combines the study of art with non-art – undesigned nature, for example, as well as tea kettles, automobiles, sports, scientific theories, and, yes, philosophical writing. These kinds of items and activities continue to draw out philosophical insights (e.g. Parsons and Carlson , Saito , and Thompson ). Does philosophy of art exclude aesthetics? Or is it in included in aesthetics? The X is up for grabs. Another option opens up if Beardsley’s argument wrongly assumes that X must unify the field in a way that is illuminating. Whether or not X is something artistic or aesthetic, it encompasses a dizzying array of phenomena. Even the central cases induce a little queasiness – consider Chardin’s still lifes, John Coltrane’s improvisations, Ovid’s Metamorphoses, Henry Moore’s bronzes, and Mies van der Rohe’s office towers. Technically, little effort is 10 needed to unify this diversity. Any items may constitute the members of a set – call it ‘art’, for example. Or we may identify art works as those phenomena. Or maybe art is primitive. Each of these manoeuvres provides a unified phenomenon for the philosophy of art to be about. The trouble is that they are not informative. They answer the ‘what is art?’ question without adding much if anything to what we already know when we ask it. The lesson is that it is not always true that philosophers of X should be curious about the nature of X, for knowing the nature of X may not repay any curiosity. An answer to the ‘what is art?’ question may turn out to illuminate nothing, or not much of anything. Philosophy, as it is done in this book, is not taxonomy. It does not take phenomena fixed in advanced and then answer, for each such phenomenon X, ‘what is X?’ within a philosophy of X. A ‘what is X?’ question should invite answers that illuminate what we care about. In order to get the illumination we seek, the trick is to alight on the right phenomena. That is part of the job of philosophy. It cannot take for granted that philosophy of art or aesthetics should investigate the nature of art or the aesthetic. These investigations may not be informative. Not everyone working in the field presses the ‘what is art?’ question. In near defiance of its title, Malcolm Budd’s influential Values of Art () carefully ignores the whole business. Kendall Walton expressly doubts that an answer to the question is ‘likely to provide any significant philosophical insight or illumination’ (, ) and his subsequent work proves that a great deal can be achieved while turning the question a stony shoulder. Imposing unity on a hodgepodge for the sake of faux informativeness can have a distorting effect, and Kivy warns that the field’s, overriding concern was, and continues to be, the search for sameness; and that search has blinded the philosophical community to a bevy of questions of more than trivial importance, involving the arts not in their sameness but in their particularity... [it has] determined the way we perceive, 11 misperceive, or fail to perceive the individual arts in various pernicious ways (1997, 53). So three options for filling in X in Beardsley’s argument are: X is art, X is the aesthetic, and X is a grab bag of phenomena that are not illuminated by lumping them together as a unity. Here is where things stand. This book argues that taking the hard cases seriously does not mandate an answer to the ‘what is art?’ question. In addition, an answer to this question that revolves upon the hard cases is not the kind of answer that is suitable to the hypotheses of the social sciences or to practices of art appreciation. Finally, it is up for grabs whether an answer to the question of what counts as art can be illuminating. The book also takes Kivy’s warning to heart. Chapter proposes to answer the ‘what is art?’ by redirecting it to where illumination is likely to be found – in trying to understand specific kinds of art and their appreciation. Chapters to set out a general framework in which to pursue this understanding. Chapter sets the stage by surveying the rich variety of phenomena to be understood. Chapter develops an account of the specific kinds that should replace the generic kind, art. Chapters considers what it is to appreciate items as belonging to these kinds, and Chapter sketches an account of what it is for this appreciation to be aesthetic. In the closing chapter, these advances are applied to the hard cases in a way that takes them seriously, vindicating the proposal that an answer to the ‘what is art?’ question is not needed to take the hard cases seriously. If lumpers vie with splitters and globalizers with localizers, then this approach may seem to champion the splitters over the globalizers. In truth, however, these are false dichotomies. Just as lumpers lump together smaller pieces, localizers localize in a more global context. The principal ambition of this book is to provide a framework at a higher level for philosophical theorizing at a more specific level. That does not collapse the levels into one. In a metaphor that will recur in the pages to follow, it passes the buck from one level of theorizing to the other. So then, what is art? Sticky questions do deserve answers, and the next chapter supplies an answer in the form of a theory of art 12 that changes the topic away from ‘what is art?’ Hegel lamented that in aesthetics ‘the rights of genius, its works and their effects, have been made to prevail against the presumptions of legalisms and the watery wastes of theories’ ([], ????). Of course philosophy makes bad art criticism, at least generally. The heuristic power of the ‘what is art?’ question should not be confused with the claim it stakes in philosophy. PART I Beyond Art In a slightly snippy mood, the great art historian E. H. Gombrich warned that ‘Art with a capital A has come to be something of a bogey and a fetish’ (, ???). Groucho Marx, in a somewhat different mood, agreed that ‘Art is Art isn’t it? Still, on the other hand, east is east and west is west and if you take cranberries and stew them like applesauce they taste much more like prunes than rhubarb does’ (Heerman ). The reflections of these two scholars nicely complement each other, for they combine to advise that it should not be terribly difficult to say what is art, so long as we begin with a relatively modest conception of art and then take care not to expect results that are big news to anyone. Acting on this advice is the buck passing theory of art. Passing the Buck A good recipe for trouble is trying to grasp what a theory says without keeping in view the question it proposes to answer. Philosophical theories typically answer ‘what is…?‘ questions. What is flirting, for example? A theory of flirting supplies an answer (e.g. Jenkins ). What is knowledge? This harder question holds out for a correct theory of knowledge. Following suit, ‘what is art?’ might expect to find its answer in a theory of art. However, the buck passing theory of art gets its impetus from the fact that matters are not quite so simple when it comes to art. The question ‘what is art?’ is a catch-all that finds non-competing answers in different kinds of theories. Rephrased a little more constructively, the domain of art is structured, and stating the buck passing theory means articulating this structure – the buck must pass from somewhere to somewhere. The idea is not to warm over the threadbare observation, once routinely offered in an anti-theoretical spirit, that the term ‘art’ has a number of different uses. Obviously ‘art’ is used very differently in listing an early music performance on the village 14 arts calendar, in musing about the art of medicine (or war), in describing the style of a bungalow as ‘arts and crafts’, and in exclaiming, when you finally reach the Chardins after a long romp through the Louvre, ‘now finally, that’s art!’ This observation poses a challenge only given the ambition to answer the ‘what is art?’ question with a theory that explains all this diversity in a unified manner. That was always too ambitious (Weitz ). The task at hand is not to analyze lexical usage, but rather to build theories that illuminate phenomena we care about, whether or not those theories end up tracking lexical usage. In contemporary treatments, the ‘what is art?’ question is almost always answered by theories that state what makes certain items works of art. Paradigm examples of these items include Chardin’s Still Life of Cooking Utensils, Cauldron, Frying Pan, and Eggs, John Coltrane’s ‘A Love Supreme’, Ted Hughes Tales from Ovid, Henry Moore’s Archer, and the Seagrams Building in New York. Other good candidates include Diane Arbus’s Child with Toy Hand Grenade in Central Park, Otis Redding’s ‘Respect’ as sung by Aretha Franklin, The Queen of Soul, Sergio Leone’s The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly, George Balanchine’s choreography of Serenade for the American Ballet in , and Isamu Noguchi’s coffee table for Herman Miller. All of these are works of art. Call a theory that states what makes any item a work of art a theory of art. Such a theory completes the schema, x is a work of art = x is… by filling in the blank with a set of conditions. Completing this schema standardly yields the completion of the further schema, x is a work of art if and only if x is…. The left hand side of each of these schemas brings out that a theory of art is work oriented: it states what it is to be a work of art and it answers the question, what is a work of art? To set up a contrast with the buck passing theory of art, here is a small sampler of theories that complete the schema in quite different ways. In George Dickie’s first formulation of an institutional theory of art, an art work is an artifact upon which 15 some person or persons acting on behalf of the art world have conferred the status of candidate for appreciation (, ). According to Beardsley’s aesthetic theory of art, an art work is ‘something produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to satisfy the aesthetic interest’ (, ???). Each of these theories states a single, albeit complex condition that makes an item a work of art. Berys Gaut () proposes a theory of art with highly disjunctive and variegated conditions (see also Tatarkiewicz and Dutton ). A work of art is an artifact that satisfies any one of several clusters of conditions. None of these conditions is necessary but the conditions in each cluster are jointly sufficient for being a work of art. Candidate conditions include having positive aesthetic properties, being expressive of emotion, being intellectually challenging, being original, being the product of a high degree of skill, and being the result of an intention to make a work of art. As these three theories illustrate, a theory of art is likely to invite further work. What is a candidate for appreciation? What is the aesthetic interest? What specific clusters of conditions make an item a work of art? Good theories of art set new tasks through which a better understanding of art emerges. The buck passing theory of art is somewhat more than an invitation to further work; it is an instruction to move the work to different theoretical terrain. Here is the theory: x is a work of art = x is a work of K, where K is an art. Some arts include painting, music, literature, sculpture, architecture, photography, cinema, dance, and design. These are not works; they are activities whose products are works. So the buck passing theory of art states that a work of art is a product of a certain activity, namely one of the various arts. To some eyes (not all), this simply states the obvious; indeed, Groucho-like, it seems to state what is so obvious that it is scarcely illuminating. Compare it to Dickie’s institutional theory, Beardsley’s aesthetic theory, and Gaut’s cluster theory. Whereas each of these promises to tell us what a work of art without making immediate use of a concept of art, the buck passing theory 16 seems almost trivial. The complaint that the theory is uninformative is a serious one, and facing up to it will ultimately help reveal the power of the buck passing theory. For now, note that what the theory does is raise two further questions, each of these a distinct specification of the generic ‘what is art?’ question, each answered in turn by a different kind of theory. The value of the back passing theory hangs on these being good questions. The first question is: what is an art? This question finds its answer in completing the schema, K is an art = K is…. Call any completion of this schema a theory of the arts. A theory of the arts will say what makes painting and dance arts and it will display why philosophy and skateboarding are not arts. As the schema shows, a theory of the arts is not the same as a theory of art. Given a list of the arts, another question is, what is each art? What is architecture, if architecture is an art? And what is cinema, if it is another art? Presumably each of these activities has a characteristic product, works of architecture and movies respectively, so we can replace ‘what is architecture?’ with ‘what is a work of architecture?’ – ditto for each of the other arts. The resulting questions, one for each art, find their answers in completions of the schema, x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is…. Call a completion of this schema for any art K a theory of an art. A theory of architecture will say what makes the Seagrams Building a work of architecture and a theory of cinema will say what makes The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly a work of cinema. Again, the schema for theories of the arts represents how they differ from a theory of art and a theory of the arts. The schema for theories of the arts has a special feature: it has no full completion that covers all the arts in one fell swoop. The reason, expressed intuitively, is that works of cinema are not works of architecture, so a theory of architecture will not say what makes Leone’s movie a work of cinema. Expressed 17 schematically, any theory of an art must complete the right hand side of the schema schema by stating conditions that hold for the art in question and not for other arts. Suppose, for example, that what makes an item a work in an art form is its taking advantage of a medium associated with the art form. Then maybe a work of K is a work that is F in virtue of its taking advantage of K’s medium. It will not do to say that a work of architecture is one that is F in virtue of its taking advantage of some medium or other. That is not a theory of architecture. A work of architecture is F only in virtue of its taking advantage of the medium of architecture. In sum, the buck passing theory of art formulates a strategy. It advises that the heavy lifting be done not by a theory of art but by a theory of the arts or theories of the arts. The theory is strategically informative. Strategic Priorities A strategy guides us to a goal along a route that is efficient, but efficiency can put the goal at risk and sure fire goal-achieving strategies can be wretchedly inefficient. Since the buck-passing theory offers a strategy, it is fair to how efficient it promises to be. In replacing the generic ‘what is art?’ with some more specific questions the buck is passed to a theory of the arts and also to the several theories of the individual arts. Stalwart followers of and contributors to recent discussions of theories of art should not despair that one task has been replaced with several or that there is now more rather than less to do. Additional work is fine so long as it is profitable. Moreover, the work was always there to be done, and a start has been made on some of it. Wollheim foregrounded the need for a theory of the arts by making it a key concern of Art and Its Objects ([]), and progress has clearly been made in fashioning clear, testable, and even plausible theories of some of the arts (e.g. Wollheim , Lamarque and Olsen , Sparshott , Lopes b, Gaut ). The buck passing theory of art is not a make-work project. Nevertheless, those engaged in the theory of art business have usually given it priority over a theory of the arts and theories of the arts, expecting that a theory of art, once firmly in place, might 18 lead into a theory of the arts and theories of the arts. Suppose that Beardsley’s aesthetic theory of art is correct and (condensing it a little) a work of art is an item designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest. Perhaps, then, an art is an activity whose products are designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest. Music, dance, landscape architecture and the other arts output works so designed. Perhaps, again, for any art K, a work of K is a work designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest by taking advantage of K’s medium. For example, a work of dance is a work designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest by taking advantage of the rhythmical movements of the body. In principle nothing prevents giving priority to theories of art. The question, as with all matters of strategy, is whether it pays off to do so. However, it is not a priori the more efficient strategy, for a theory of art directly implies neither a theory of the arts nor a theory of any particular art. Consider first the derivation of a theory of the arts from a theory of art, such as Beardsley’s. Logic alone leads from Beardsley’s theory of art to the claim that an art is an activity whose products are designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest only on the assumption that an art is an activity whose products are works of art. This assumption might be false. Not much reflection is needed to see how a case could be made that not all products of an art are works of art. You might reason that ordinary coffee mugs are products of the art of ceramics but they are not works of art – because, indeed, they are not designed to sate any aesthetic interest. Without the assumption that bridges Beardsley’s theory of art to a Beardsleyan theory of arts, the latter stands in need of independent support. The inference from Beardsley’s theory of art to a Beardsleyan theory of any given art also requires a bridging assumption. A theory of art fills in the schema, x is a work of art = x is… with a set of conditions. Whatever they are, call them φ. A theory of an art form, K, fills in the schema, 19 x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is… with a set of conditions – call them ψ. A completion of the former schema clearly need not entail a completion of the latter. A bridging assumption is required. In addition, each art is different from the other arts and this difference must be represented in the bridging assumption. After all, what makes an item a work of art and what makes an item a painting, song, or dance number are not unrelated. A dance number is a work of art partly in virtue of facts that make it a dance number, and what makes a song a piece of music must factor into what makes it a work of art. One option is to make a bridging assumption having this general form: if x is a work of K, where K is an art then x is φ partly in virtue of being ψ. That is no short cut from a theory of art for a theory of a particular art form! Fortunately, there is an alternative, namely to assume that the kinds of features that make an item a work in an art form are the same across all forms. For example, one might say that a work of K is a work of art in virtue of its taking advantage of K’s medium. The bridging assumption would be: if x is a work of K, where K is an art then x is φ partly in virtue of its taking advantage of K’s medium. Add to this an account of K’s medium and a theory of K follows. Whether or not this procedure pans out, it is not labour-free. It requires that the same kinds of features make items members of all of the arts. Exploiting a medium is one option, but there are other options, and some effort is needed to choose one. As an added complexity, it is an open question whether the same option works for every art. Effort is needed either to demonstrate that one option does work for every art or to identify which options work for which arts. Finally, giving up on the bridging assumption means supplying independent support for a theory of any individual art that is modelled on a general theory of art such as Beardsley’s. 20 The lesson is not that it is futile to give a theory of art priority in the hope that it will lead to a theory of the arts or theories of the arts. The lesson is rather that the path from a theory of art to its companion theories is not straightforward, and clearing it may require considerable effort. Giving strategic priority to a theory of art is not a priori more efficient than adopting a buck passing theory of art. Therefore, the buck passing theory of art is a contender. But What Is a Work of Art? Attempting to inform strategy need not entail a sacrifice of substantive informativeness. The buck passing theory might be a ladder that is cast away when no longer needed, but it might also turn out to be the only correct completion of the schema for a theory of art. That is, it might turn out to be final the answer to the question, what is a work of art? This is a consequence of turning the tables in the reasoning above. Supposing the buck passing theory recommends sound strategy and the recommendation is taken up, work will shift to fashioning a theory of the arts or theories of the individual arts. Lamentably, the fact that a strategy is sound is no guarantee of success: some phenomena might resist full theoretical treatment and there may be a limit to what we can know. Nevertheless, our only option is to be optimistic and suppose that the strategy pays out a correct theory of the arts and a complete set of correct theories of those arts. Can we infer a theory of art from the resources thus amassed? Logic alone does not lead from a theory of the arts to a theory of art without the assumption that an art is an activity whose products are works of art. For example, a Beardsleyan aesthetic theory of the arts – namely that the arts are activities whose products are works designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest – does not by itself imply Beardsley’s theory of art – that a work of art is a something designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest. The assumption that an art is an activity whose products are works of art might be false (recall that a case can be made that not all of the products of ceramics are works of art). If this assumption is in fact 21 false, Beardsley’s theory of art cannot rest on a Beardsleyan theory of the arts; it will require independent support. Similar reasoning shows that there is no direct inference from the theories of the individual arts to a theory of art. For example, the step from the claim that a work of K is a work designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest by taking advantage of the medium of K to the claim that a work of art is something designed to satisfy the aesthetic interest entails that works of K are works of art for all K. But this assumption might be false for at least some K. It might turn out that, in some art forms, what makes a work a member of the art form is not that it satisfies the aesthetic interest. In some other art forms it might turn out that what makes a work a member of the art form is not that it does so by taking advantage of the art form’s medium – but rather by some other means. Again, if the required assumption is false, the Beardsleyan theory of art must seek independent support. So far nothing rules out that the ducks will line up to allow the deduction of a theory of art from a theory of the arts or the theories of the arts; and, by the same token, nothing rules out that the ducks will fail to cooperate just as the needed independent support fails to materialize. In this scenario, the buck passing theory of art might be the most illuminating answer to the question of what is a work of art. The theory would be equivalent to what Wollheim called a ‘minimal theory’: works of art just are poems, sculptures, and the like ([], –). Wollheim feared that best we could expect in response to the question ‘what is a work of art?’ is this plurality of answers. It will be useful to consider why anyone might disparage the minimal theory as a booby prize. Could it not explain everything that needs explaining? That remains to be seen. For now, the buck passing theory is a potential contender alongside such theories as Beardsley’s, Dickie’s, and Gaut’s. Two Challenges The chapters to follow tackle two basic challenges to the buck passing theory of art, in order to defend it, reveal its power, and zero in on what it implies. One challenge targets the theory’s 22 informativeness and the other its viability, though the two challenges are closely tied. The proposition that a work of art is a work in some art form implies that x is a work of art if and only if x is a work of K, where K is an art. In light of this implication, the theory makes two commitments. First, any item is a work of art if it is a work of an art form – a work of music, architecture, dance, or the like. There are no further restrictions limiting what can be a work of art. Second, it is not possible for there to be an item that is a work of art and yet does not belong to an art form. Every work of art belongs to some art form. If either of these implications is false, then the theory is not viable. A familiar line of reasoning seems to supply a counterexample to the proposition that any work of an art form is a work of art. Assuming that ceramics is an art, the theory implies that an ordinary coffee mug (the one holding pencils on your desk) is a work of art, if it is a work of ceramics. Of course, the theory leaves open which activities are arts – it passes that buck to a theory of the arts. Even so, not much solace is to be found in denying that ceramics is an art. Similar counterexamples can be generated for most if not all of the arts. However, all is not lost. The theory leaves open what counts as a work of ceramics. So if it ceramics is indeed an art and if the coffee mug is not a work of art, it follows that coffee mug is not a work of ceramics. The burden rests on a theory of ceramics – where that buck gets passed. What about counterexamples to the proposition that every art work belongs to some art form? Works that belong to more than one art form are not genuine counterexamples, since the theory does not imply that every art work belongs to one and only one art. On the contrary, it welcomes works like William Blake’s illustrated poems, which belong doubly to the arts of literature and painting. Whether a theory of literature admits Blake’s Europe as a work of literature or whether a theory of painting admits it as 23 a work of painting, either way the buck passing theory implies that it is a work of art. A genuine counterexample is an art work that belongs to no art form. What about Barry’s Inert Gas Series, for instance? It is arguably not a painting since it is not a marked surface. It could hardly be architecture or sculpture, and if a work of literature must be made out of words, it is not literature either. Could it be landscape architecture or maybe a kind of dance, even if it is not classified that way? No need to settle the matter here: it is enough to see that there are counterexamples to be dealt with. Moreover, it is no coincidence that these counterexamples are exactly the kinds of ‘hard cases’ that have fuelled philosophical work on theories of art. Therefore, if the buck passing theory of art can deal with the hard cases, then the steam is taken out of recent debates about theories of art. As this discussion illustrates, challenges to the viability and informativeness of the buck passing theory are closely tied. To say that theories of art have been fuelled by hard cases is to admit that an informative theory of art should make some sense of the hard cases, in one way or another. At then end of the day, few will be convinced that the buck passing theory of art offers a live option unless it contends in a serious manner with the hard cases. It is not enough to suggest a strategy, nor is it enough that the theory may be the last option standing. The challenge to deal with the hard cases must be taken seriously. With that in mind, the task is to show that the theory deals with the hard cases precisely by passing the right bucks in the right directions. Needless to say, it was partly in reaction to the fetishistic idea of Art about which Gombrich complained that some artists in the last century began to produce the kinds of works that philosophers pressed into action as hard cases. Ironically, these artistic gestures compounded the mystery. Should it come as any surprise that they push us back towards the more deflationary stance represented by Groucho’s philosophy and the proposal to pass the buck? After the Beginning of Art Art began a long time ago and, although they may not be quite so old as art itself, theories of art are also ancient… or that is how the story usually goes. Jerrold Levinson is not alone in counting the question of what makes an item a work of art among ‘probably the most venerable in aesthetics’. Nor is he alone in going on to express some exasperation that the end appears nowhere in sight: ‘after rejecting the many proposals made by philosophers from Plato to the present on grounds of narrowness, tendentiousness, inflexibility, vagueness, or circularity, one would appear to be left with no answer to the question at all, and perhaps a suspicion that it is unanswerable’ (, ). Yet if the search for a theory of art is truly venerable, then it must have been expected to do more than cope with the arrival of the hard cases in the last century. This is the ‘historical objection’ to the buck passing theory of art. The buck passing theory bets that a theory of art is not needed to contend with the hard cases directly, that they are more effectively addressed by a theory of art or theories of the individual arts. Does history deprive these sails of wind? Do theories of art go back far enough that they presumably address a function having nothing to do with the hard cases? The Early Modern ‘Problem of the Arts’ A hundred years ago, Bell identified the ‘central problem of aesthetics’ with the search for ‘the quality that distinguishes works of art from all other classes of objects’ (, ). A recent writer observes that ‘underlying every traditional aesthetic theory is the essentialist presumption that that the expression “work of art” applies to the entities that it does in virtue of some shared essential property or properties’ (Matthews , ). Yet as much as these philosophers may speak for themselves and their twentieth century brethren, their conception of what it takes to answer the question ‘what is art?’ cannot be projected very far backwards. This is a message, albeit often missed, of Paul Kristeller’s classic and erudite study, ‘The Modern System of the Arts’ (–). 25 Kristeller explores three topics, which are easily conflated but must be distinguished. Principal among these is the gradual development of the concept of art until it finally comes together in mid-eighteenth century France. The scheme of classification that Kristeller calls the ‘modern system of the arts’ expresses the content of this concept. Second, some concepts have histories and Kristeller tentatively traces some of the historical causes of the development of the modern system of the arts. Finally, the modern system of the arts comes together partly as it is supplied with a rationale, and Kristeller examines some of the subsequent history of philosophical thought about how to justify of the modern system of the arts. Start with the thesis that a concept of art comes together in the mid-eighteenth century. According to Kristeller, the early modern innovation is to group some activities together with each other and apart from others. The ‘nucleus’ of this new grouping comprises painting, sculpture, architecture, music, and poetry, with several other activities – notably landscape architecture, dance, theatre, and prose literature – slipping in and out of its orbit. This modern system of the arts is distinguished in the thinking of its inventors from the liberal arts, the practical arts, and the sciences. Fishing, physiology, poetry, philosophy, football, travel, chemical engineering, eating, architecture, fashion, trading, astronomy, dance, painting, plumbing... which of these belong together? A grouping is salient for you and me that was not salient for contemporaries of Aristotle and Abelard. To illustrate, ancient Greek and Latin discussions of techne or ars encompass a range of activities whose mastery involves knowledge and which we would now consider skills, crafts, and sciences – almost all the activities listed above (Kristeller –, –). According to the influential scheme proposed by Hugo of St Victor in the twelfth century, architecture, sculpture, and painting are grouped together under armatura, music is classified under mathematics, and poetry is placed with grammar, rhetoric, and logic (Kristeller –, –). Chambers’s Cyclopedia, a ‘universal dictionary of arts and sciences’ published in , classifies painting with optics, music under applied mathematics, gardening under agriculture, and poetry alongside rhetoric, 26 grammar, and heraldry (Kristeller –, ). Only a few decades later, Diderot’s Encyclopédie groups the fine arts together as is now familiar – the change is dramatically graphed in tree diagrams that accompanied the two encyclopaedias (figs. and ). Kristeller identifies some of the factors that, over the centuries, may have driven the innovation, and here are just a few. Attention from the humanists gave poetry ‘honor and glamor’ and a place in their new curriculum (Kristeller –, –). Having gradually gained prestige in Italy from the fourteenth century onwards, painting, sculpture, and architecture came to be classified together as the arti del disegno (Kristeller –, – ). Sixteenth century writing about painting routinely compared it to poetry (Kristeller –, ). The seventeenth century saw the founding of the French academies, which sponsored the first treatises on painting, sculpture, and architecture to stand alongside texts on poetics (Kristeller –, –). Around the same time the pleasures of painting, music, and poetry were recommended (alongside fencing and coin collecting) in what we would now call lifestyle manuals (Kristeller –, ). Contributors to the quarrel between the ancients and the moderns came to distinguish those activities where success depends on accumulated knowledge and mathematical calculation (science, where the moderns win) from those activities where success depends on individual talent (where the ancients win). Thus the new concept of science and a recognition of scientific progress helped spur the formation of the new concept of art (Kristeller –, –). Finally, the early eighteenth century saw the widespread publication of criticism written by and for amateurs (Kristeller –, , ). The ‘problem of the arts’ was now a topic of learned discussion in the salons of Paris. By mid-century a consensus settled on the modern system of the arts. The problem was principally to codify a new system of classification but also to give it a rational foundation. Kristeller argues that this was first accomplished by Charles Batteux (), who proposed that the arts share a feature in common, each aims to imitate beautiful nature (Kristeller –, ). This proposition was immediately challenged by the contributors to Diderot’s Encyclopédie as well as by later writers, but the classification it was 27 meant to justify was widely accepted and soon spread from the salons and philosophy books into common usage. Kristeller’s history is by no means complete and it is unlikely to be correct in every detail, though the main conclusions are considered to be well established. It is enriched by a broader social history which brings into the picture such factors as the development of the Dutch picture market and the opening of the first public galleries, museums, and concert halls, where silent contemplation was expected and where political statement was neutralized (Shiner ). It connects more closely to discussions by philosophers in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries of imagination, creative genius, taste, and aesthetic judgement (Shiner ). It suggests a critique of the anxious policing of the boundary between art and craft, artist and craftsman, especially in so far as it fed various insalubrious doctrines representing art as an autonomous realm (Shiner ). Its account of the Greeks may need correcting if the modern system of the arts is anticipated, for example, in Plato’s mention of the practitioners of mimesis – painters and sculptors, musicians, and poets and their assistants, the rhapsodes, actors, and dancers (Halliwell ). What is well established is that the early moderns clinched the classification that is the modern system of the arts (even if it has an ancient counterpart). Lessons from Kristeller Several lessons are typically drawn from this element of Kristeller’s account, not all are warranted, but three are both warranted and handy for present purposes. Kristeller brings home the historical nature of the concept of art expressed by the modern system of the arts. This concept was acquired at a certain time in a certain place and it spread from there. This is neither surprising nor interesting, for many (and maybe all) concepts are historically conditioned in this sense. Some conclude that there is no art before the eighteenth century. This inference implies that there is no art in a context unless people have a concept of art in that context, and this assumption is false, as Chapter argues. Kristeller’s own view is clear: ‘the 28 various arts are certainly as old as human civilization, but the manner in which we are accustomed to group them… is comparatively recent’ (–, ). One handy lesson is that the concept of art expressed by the modern system of the arts comes together as a theoretical concept. That is to say, it is introduced by means of a theory – Batteux’s version of an imitation theory – and it is understood that what gets classified under the concept is what is identified by the theory. Not all concepts are like this: the folk concepts of gravity, personhood, or the colour red do not spring from theories of gravity, personhood, or colours. The modern system of the arts is more like the concepts of polymers and logical completeness in the sense that it is introduced by means of a theory, though (unlike polymers and logical completeness) it has now entered the conceptual repertoire of the folk. A second handy lesson qualifies the first one: the concept of art expressed by the modern system of the arts is outfitted to achieve certain goals. It should establish the unity of the arts, making salient how to group together painting, sculpture, architecture, music, poetry, and assorted others. It should also make salient what sets these apart from other activities, especially the sciences, applied sciences, and the practical arts and crafts. Finally, it should provide a framework within which to understand the distinctive features of each of the arts. In this regard Kristeller notes Herder’s complaint that Lessing’s contrast between poetry and visual art in the Laocoon delivers an inadequate understanding of the nature of poetry. For Herder, such an understanding requires that poetry be put in contrast with all its sister arts (–, ). The third handy lesson should be obvious by now. The modern system of the arts is a classification of activities which singles out one cluster of activities as arts and distinguishes them from other activities such as the sciences, applied sciences, and crafts. Arts like painting and architecture are clustered together and set apart from activities like anatomical investigation and fashion design. Accordingly, Batteux’s theory states what makes an activity an art form, namely that it aims to imitate beautiful nature. This theory does not say what makes an item a work of art: the modern system 29 of the arts does not classify items into works of art. The eighteenth century ‘problem of the arts’ was not addressed by seeking a theory of art. The early moderns sought a theory of the arts. A theory of the arts is not the same as a theory of art and the work done by the former in classifying, explaining, and problemsolving is not the same as the work that might be done by the latter, so evidence of the venerability of the one is not automatic evidence of the venerability of the other. True, the theories might be linked, as we saw in Chapter . In developing an imitation theory of the arts, the early moderns might have implicitly backed an imitation theory of art. Consider these three propositions: . a work of art is an imitation of beautiful nature, . an art is an activity whose aim is to produce works of art, . an art is an activity whose aim is to produce imitations of beautiful nature. Here, () is an imitation theory of art in the work-oriented sense, () is a theory of the arts in the activity-oriented sense, and () represents a bridging assumption. The early moderns might have backed () implicitly, deducing () from it via (). Or they might have argued for () on independent grounds and taken () to be an obvious by-product, given (). So the question is whether the early moderns reasoned either way, from () to () or () to (). As we also saw in Chapter , the bridging assumption represented by () might be false. However, we need not look for independent evidence that Batteux and his readers accepted (). The role of () as a bridge from () to () or vice versa is close to purely formal. Logic alone warrants attributing () to anyone who explicitly reasons from () to () or () to (). Logic plus charity warrant attributing () to anyone who seems to accept () and () and who only provides an independent argument for one of them. Of course, by the same reasoning, someone’s assent to () is not by itself enough to attribute their assent of (). More is needed to indicate implicit acceptance of (). Is this a trap, a no-win scenario? Batteux and his followers explicitly back () and the question is whether we can also 30 attribute () to them in the absence of explicit assent to (). A statement explicitly backing () is not needed: evidence that they back () implicitly would suffice. Yet would that evidence be, if not ()? The key lies in remembering that theories do work and their resistance to counterexamples would have been an important measure of this work, at least in this context. If the early moderns were not concerned by obvious counterexamples to () then it is not reasonable to attribute their assent to (). Perhaps resistance to counterexamples is not a required of every good theory, but it is in this context. The development of the modern system of the arts was understood in the salons and lecture halls to be a high stakes enterprise, with winners and losers dividing a pot comprising social prestige as well as financial benefits. Although the nucleus of five arts – painting, sculpture, architecture, music, and poetry – was stable for some time, there were intense debate about arts at the boundary. Landscape design was ejected in the nineteenth century, for example, and dance was included. A theory of the arts armed partisans in these debates with sufficient conditions as entry tickets and necessary conditions to exclude outsiders. Moreover, the technique of testing theories by counterexamples was familiar to the relevant parties. A colourful illustration is objections to the principle that an object’s beauty can be realized by its appearing fit for its function (Parsons and Carlson , ch. ). Francis Hutcheson objected that ‘a Coffinshape for a Door would bear a more manifest Aptitude to the human Shape’ than the usual rectangle but is for that reason more ugly (, ???). Edmund Burke added that ‘on that principle, the wedge-like snout of a swine, with its tough cartilage at the end, the little sunk eyes, and the whole make of the head, so well adapted to its offices of digging and rooting, would be extremely beautiful’ (Burke , ???). Burke and Hutcheson were known to critics of Batteux’s imitation theory of the arts. Yet their criticisms took it on its own terms, as a theory of the arts. Their most serious objection was that music does not aim to represent beauty in nature. Peter Kivy has argued that music did not seem to pose a serious counterexample while the paint was 31 still wet on the theory (, ch. ). Purely instrumental music had been a ‘side show’ in western Europe since the Council of Trent, which had ordered that music should no longer provide an independent setting for a text but should echo its linguistic content – and this eventually led to the emergence of the stile rappresentativo and the opera. According to Kivy, it was not until the late eighteenth century that purely instrumental music could form a serious part of a composer’s output. The challenge to the imitation theory was soon appreciated, and responses were soon in the air. Thomas Reid, for example, offered that melody imitates human vocal expression of emotion and harmony imitates expressive conversation (Kivy , –). Several nineteenth century writers also weighed in – Schopenhauer and Hegel, for instance, and alternative theories were put on the table (see Kivy , ch. ). It is striking that nobody seemed to worry that Grünewald’s Crucifixion or the horrible scenes of battle and despoliation in the Iliad are works of art and yet they do not imitate beauty in nature. In view of the fact that there were counterexamples to a theory about what makes an object beautiful and that there were counterexamples to the imitation theory of the arts represented by (), why are there no serious discussions of counterexamples to the imitation theory of art represented by ()? The best explanation is that the early moderns did not take () to imply or be implied by () via (). Nineteenth Century Transitions The ‘problem of the arts’ was not the only item on the agenda in early modern aesthetics, and it was certainly not as prominent subsequently, during the long nineteenth century, though it did continue. As is well known, the nineteenth century considerably expands the options beyond the imitation theory, especially in order to accommodate music (Kivy , ch. ). The textbook examples are the expression theory and formalism. According to one version of the expression theory, an art aims to express and thereby arouse delicate feelings (e.g. Hanslick [], ch. ). 32 A standard version of formalism states that each art aims to create beautiful arrangements using its distinctive materials. Thus Hanslick, who seeks to ‘treat music as an art’ ([], ), proposes that it aims at a ‘specifically musical kind of beauty’ realized in ‘tonally moving forms’ ([], ???). Several variants on each of these theories date from this period. But are there theories of art? Kant does not state a theory of art, even though he had the building blocks for one ready at hand ([]). The third critique concerns judgements, including judgements of taste, many of which are made in response to confrontations with individual works of art (others being responses to nature). Moreover, in section of the third critique, Kant distinguishes art ‘as human skill’ first from nature, then from science, and finally from craft. In the next section, he distinguishes the agreeable arts whose purpose is ‘mere enjoyment’ from fine (schön) art, that furthers the mental powers that facilitate social communication; and later sections discuss the distinctive features of each of the arts. Although there are connections between genius and the fine arts and also between the fine arts and judgements of beauty, Kant does not define the fine arts with reference to a theory of art. Hegel also inherited the early modern emphasis on theories of the arts, which put it to work in a special way within his own systematic philosophy. According to the Lectures on Fine Art, ‘the real world of art is the system of the individual arts’ ([], ), which function to ‘find for the spirit of a people the artistic expression corresponding to it’ ([], ), where an artistic expression is in a sensuous medium ([], ). Thus sculpture expressed the spirit of the Greeks and music that of the Germans. Given this theory of the arts, Hegel explains the role of each art in the historical process of the unfolding of consciousness which culminated in his own philosophy. Indeed, art came to an end when it handed over its historical role to philosophy: ‘art, considered in its highest vocation, is and remains for us a thing of the past’ ([], ). Obviously there has been a great deal of art created since , but this art does not serve art’s ‘highest 33 vocation’. Its less grand new role is to represent human experience and to help us to feel at home in that experience ([], ). In consonance with his theory of the arts, Hegel does tender a theory of art: a work of art is an artifact made for sensuous apprehension, to serve an ‘end and aim in itself’ ([], ). However, this is a simple corollary of the theory of the arts. It does not do any work in Hegel’s system – the theory of the arts does the heavy lifting – and Hegel does not consider how well it holds up on its own. Hegel exemplifies a nineteenth century interest in a ‘higher calling’ for art that also preoccupies Schlegel, the other Schlegel, Schiller, and Schopenhauer. For these writers and others, genuine art or great art reveals transcendent truths: its ‘highest vocation’ is a philosophical one – art is ‘sacralized’, as Jean-Marie Schaffer acutely puts it (). No remotely plausible theory of art can be extracted from this proposition. The realm of art includes art includes works by Bunyan as well as Milton, Boilly as well as Poussin, and Mahavishnu Orchestra as well as Miles Davis. It also includes many superb works that do not reveal transcendent truths or indeed any truths at all. The philosophy of art is not exhausted by any of the various approaches to the ‘what is art?’ question. However interesting or plausible they may or may not be, speculations about some features of (some) art should not be confused for theories of art. Theories of Art and the Hard Cases Batteux and Diderot seek a theory of the arts whereas Beardsley and Dickie seek a theory of art. Whatever the full story about the timing and causes of this shift in emphasis from theories of the arts to theories of art, contemporary interest in theories of art is certainly provoked by and tends to focus on the hard cases. The shift in emphasis from theories of the arts to theories of art does not represent a total break, for theories of the arts have remained a going concern even after the flap over music settled down. For example, the art status of photography and movies has been examined and cross examined by critics and also by philosophers – with Roger Scruton infamously arguing that 34 neither photography nor the movies is not an independent art form () and many others replying (e.g. Lopes , Abell ). By the way, Scruton’s argument against photography’s being an art does not rely on a theory of art; it relies on a partial theory of the arts – on a theory of a subset of the arts, the representational arts. Other arguments for new arts, such as computer art and video games, do rely on a theory of art (e.g. Lopes b, ch. and Tavinor , ch. ). What activities are arts? The question remains a live one (and it is taken up again in Chapter ). However, the hard cases are not seen as challenges to any theory of the arts; they are treated as provocations to theories of art. An encyclopaedia entry surveying theories of art attributes interest in them to ‘dissatisfaction with the fact that certain works are counted as art’ (Barnes , I.). Beardsley confesses that his search for a theory of art sprung from ‘the enormous and even ridiculous variety of objects, events, situations, texts, thoughts, performances, refrainings from any performance, and so on that have, in recent times, drawn the label “artwork” from their authors, admirers, or patient endurers’ (, ). Dickie credits ‘the strange and startling innovations of Duchamp and his latterday followers such as Rauschenberg, Warhol, and Oldenberg’ as the inspiration for his theory of art (, ). Wollheim observed that other works, which he dubbed ‘minimal art’, ‘give rise to certain doubts and anxieties’ ([], ). Robert Stecker, quietly remarks that ‘avant-garde art… has made the nature of art increasingly puzzling’ (, ) and Marcia Eaton defends the necessity of a good theory of art in view of the ‘confusion [people] often feel when they encounter puzzling objects and events in museums, concert halls, or other venues where it is, supposedly, art that is being presented’ (, –). The Kristeller of our times is Noël Carroll. He conjectures that certain upheavals of the last century fuel contemporary searches for theories of art: the driving… force behind the philosophy of art for at least a century – a century which not coincidentally could be called the age of the avant-garde – has been the startling innovations 35 of modern art…. For it is in the twentieth century that the theoretical task of coming to terms with virtually continuous revolutions in artistic practice has become urgent. That is, it is in the twentieth century that the problem of identifying art has become persistently unavoidable’ (, -). The revolutions in artistic practice that Carroll has in mind are not the invention of new art forms. The invention of photography and the movies might have spurred developments in avant-garde painting and theatre, but they were not themselves avant-garde and they did not provoke puzzlement in their audiences. Carroll goes on: ‘the characteristic situation in which this problem [of identifying art] arises is one where a public is presented with an object that defies its expectations about what counts as art and, thereby, leaves the public bewildered’ (, ). How do bewildering avant-garde production entrain theories of art? Often the diagnosis of some bewilderment is that the production in question is art but it does not have the features that are thought to make an item a work of art (e.g. Dickie , ). It is a counterexample to accepted theories of art, which rule it out as a work of art. Faced with this situation, there are two options. One is to side with the traditional theories and deny that the item is a work of art. The other is to whip up a new theory of art that foregrounds a feature that is salient in the avant-garde work (Carroll , ). On many theories, this feature must also be present in more traditional art. The result of this dialectic is a procession over several decades of theories of art, each toppled by a counterexample drawn from the latest avant-garde. The path is littered with corpses. In an interesting twist, the dialectic may include a feedback loop. If philosophers are paying attention to events in the art world, artists sometimes attend to philosophy to; and having encountered the latest theory of art, they might set out to refute it by counterexample. Pushing the envelope is to be expected if the art historian Thomas Crow is right to call the avant-garde the ‘research and development arm of the culture industry’ (, ). Indeed, some argue that nothing as mundane as an artist reacting to some philosophy is required, for the dialectic has an historical 36 inevitability (Danto ). At any rate, the dialectic appears to be in place. In Beardsley contemplated what he imagined to the ultimate affront: ‘an alleged work of conceptual art… that is no more than a closed art gallery with a sign on it saying that the artwork being exhibited that week is just the closed art gallery itself’ (, ???). Robert Barry had done that in . In , Santiago Sierra sent invitation to his latest show at the Lisson Gallery in London. His guests arrived to find the gallery closed. He did not bother with the sign, however. Before looking at how the dialectic plays out where it matters philosophically, in arguments, a word about terminology. Labels like ‘avant-garde’, ‘conceptual art’, ‘Dada’, ‘late modern art’ have more or less stable and focused usage in art studies. None pinpoint exactly the class of works that drive philosophical theories of art. Therefore, let the label ‘hard case’ represent any and only works of art that do drive theories of art in the way described by Carroll. By stipulation, the hard cases are hard cases for theories of art, and nothing more. The Open Concept Argument The two most influential arguments in the literature of the past fifty years both orient on the hard cases in a way that places theories of art at centre stage. The first of these is the open concept argument laid out by Morris Weitz (). Recall that a theory of art fills in the schema, x is a work of art = x is… and implies an analogous completion of the schema, x is a work of art if and only if x is…. Weitz’s main argument is that there is no correct, full, non-trivial completion of the latter so there is no correct, full, non-trivial completion of the former – there is no correct, complete, nontrivial theory of art (, ). In Weitz’s terminology, open concepts have no necessary and sufficient application conditions, whereas concepts with necessary and sufficient application conditions are closed concepts. Rephrasing the main argument, 37 there is no correct, complete, and non-trivial theory of art because art is an open concept. What reason is there to think that art is an open concept? Although only one is widely acknowledged, Weitz gives two arguments which share a premise. He writes that, a concept is open if its conditions of application are emendable and corrigible; i.e., if a situation or case can be imagined or secured which would call for some sort of decision on our part to extend the use of the concept to cover this, or to close the concept and invent a new one to deal with the new case and its new property (, ). The appearance of ‘corrigible’ in the opening phrase of this quotation gives the whole an epistemic ring. Yet the claim cannot be merely that we sometimes make mistakes in stating the application conditions for an open concept. It would not follow from that claim that the concept in question is open and has no necessary and sufficient application conditions. The claim is rather that whether or not any given real or imagined case falls under an open concept calls for a ‘decision on our part’. We have three choices. We may decide X falls under concept F. Or we may decide that X falls under a new concept disjoint from F and we close F by stipulating necessary and sufficient conditions for its application. Or we may decide that X falls under a new concept disjoint from F and we leave F open. In other words, we may decide to close a hitherto open concept by imposing necessary and sufficient conditions on its application. If we do not take that step, then we must decide whether every new case falls under the open concept. Either way, the decision is legislative: our deciding what falls under F is what determines the extension of F. The widely acknowledged argument for the thesis that art is an open concept is art-specific: it conjoins the premise that an open concept calls for a decision on our part with an appeal to the creative condition of art-making. Weitz observes that when it comes to art, ‘new cases can always be envisaged or created by artists, or even nature, which would call for a decision on someone’s part, to extend or to close the old or to invent a new 38 concept’ (, ). He goes on that ‘we can, of course, choose to close the concept. But to do this… is ludicrous since it forecloses on the very conditions of creativity in the arts’ (, ). That is, it denies the ‘very expansive, adventurous character of art, its ever-present changes and novel creations’ (, ). Stitching the pieces together, . if art is an open concept then there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of art, and . if the application of concept of art calls for a decision on our part, then it is open, and . art is creative only if the application of the concept of art calls for a decision on our part, but . art is creative, . so there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of art. The crux of the argument is clearly () and (), expressed in Weitz’s refrain that when it comes to making art, ‘unforeseeable or novel conditions are always forthcoming or envisageable’ (, ). This widely acknowledged argument is also widely denounced, for premise () is either false or the argument begs the question. On one hand, creativity in a domain is not generally incompatible with the concept of that domain being closed. For example, the concept of a mathematic or logical proof is closed, but mathematical and logical proofs are often products of creativity – a series of theorems can meet the definition of a proof in an unforeseeable or novel way. With that in mind, suppose that Beardsley’s aesthetic theory of art is true – perhaps because we have decided to use it to close the concept of art – and nothing is a work of art unless it is produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to satisfy the aesthetic interest. That does not foreclose the ‘very expansive, adventurous character of art, its ever-present changes and novel creations’. Premise () is false. Perhaps, on the other hand, the creative condition of art is more radical than is allowed by an analogy with creativity in other domains, for the very conditions upon being art are subject to change in a ways that are sometimes unforeseeable or novel. Now 39 premise () is equivalent to the claim that art is an open concept and the argument as a whole begs the question. Even so, note how the weight of the argument rests on the hard cases. They get the credit for art’s ‘very expansive, adventurous character’ and, indeed, they push premises () and () towards the question-begging reading. Surveying the parade of theories lured out and then bumped off by one hard case after another, and taking this resistance to theory to signal the heights of creativity, it is tempting to infer that the concept of art must be open. Without the hard cases and the parade ground littered with theoretical corpses, () and () would look pretty flimsy. Aaron Meskin () has stressed a second argument given by Weitz for the thesis that there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of art. This argument also assumes that there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of art if art is an open concept and that the concept of art is open if its application calls for a decision in a metaphysically weighty sense. Meskin points out that Weitz also asserts that there are necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of concepts ‘only in logic or mathematics where concepts are constructed and completely defined’ and not ‘with empirically-descriptive and normative concepts unless we arbitrarily close them by stipulating the ranges of their uses’ (, ). However, art is an empirically-descriptive or normative concept. As the argument goes: . if art is an open concept then there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of art, and . if the application of concept of art calls for a decision on our part, then it is open, and . the concept of art is empirically-descriptive or normative only if the application of the concept of art calls for a decision on our part, but . the concept of art is empirically-descriptive or normative, . so there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of art. Premises () and () express a contrast between concepts like the concept of art and closed concepts like those found in logic and mathematics. 40 Understanding the contrast is the key to this argument. The contrast is not simply identical to a distinction (however it is drawn) between logical and mathematical concepts on one hand and all other concepts on the other, since Weitz accepts that closed concepts range beyond the realms of logic and mathematics. Presumably logical and mathematical concepts are paradigm closed concepts. Other closed concepts resemble them in so far as their application conditions are closed by ‘stipulating the range of their uses’ (, ), ‘for a special purpose’ (, ). The problem, as Weitz sees it, with closing these concepts is that the result fails to model the true diversity of uses of the concept. When it comes to art, the task is described thus: ‘our first problem is the elucidation of the actual employment of the concept of art, to give a logical description of the actual functioning of the concept, including a description of the conditions under which we correctly use it or its correlates’ (, ). We must respect all uses of the concept ‘in the wild’ and not operationalize it for the lab. If this is what Weitz has in mind, the second argument also begs the question. After all, what makes the concept of art empirically-descriptive or normative? Many ordinary concepts are probably closed – for example, mother-in-law, New York Subway token, and toupée; also fraud, gas guzzler, and good umbrella. Presumably these are closed without remainder – stipulating their uses does not limit their uses in the wild. By contrast, what makes art empirically-descriptive or normative is that it is only closed with remainder. Stipulating its uses for some ‘special’ purposes inevitably leaves out other purposes. The trouble is that now the claim expressed in () that art is empirically-descriptive or normative is equivalent to the claim that art is an open concept. Again, however, the important point is how the second argument draws its plausibility from the hard cases. The fact that an ‘elucidation of the actual employment of the concept of art’ means accepting its unruliness stems from the unruliness of the hard cases. The hard cases trigger contrary intuitive responses, any theory of art will stump for some hard cases and against others, and it merely follows that each theory is incomplete. 41 Whether or not these arguments succeed or fail, they illustrate how the hard cases animate the ‘what is art?’ question. The same goes for their continuing appeal, for without the hard cases, skepticism about theories of art would not have much more grip than epistemic skepticism would have without brains in vats. However, here are two notes for future reference. Weitz extends his anti-theoretical stance to theories of the arts as well as theories of art. That is a challenge for the buck passing theory of art. Mitigating this challenge is that the buck passing theory steers clear of a methodological commitment to conceptual analysis. Philosophical theories are tools through which phenomena are discerned and their serving this ‘special purpose’ warrants bracketing intuitions about hard cases (see the Introduction). The Twins Argument If the hard cases lurk in the background of the open concept argument, they proudly assume centre stage in another argument, the argument from indiscernibles or ‘twins’, that originates with Arthur Danto (, , , ) and recurs throughout the repertoire of classic work on theories of art (e.g. Binkley , Carroll ). The twins argument comes in two flavours, classic and canonical. The classical flavour is this (Danto ): C. if the features that make an item a work of art are among or supervene on its perceptible features, then no work of art is perceptually indiscernible from a twin item that is not a work of art, but C. some works of art are perceptually indiscernible from twin items that are not works of art, C. so the features that make an item a work of art are not perceptible and do not supervene on its perceptible feature. Here the target is perceptual theories of art, which maintain that what makes an item a work of art are features that are among or supervene on features that are manifest to the senses. Soon after this argument appeared, however, it was subtly but significantly upgraded so as to target aesthetic theories of art, which maintain 42 that what makes an item a work of art is its aesthetic features. That is, A. if the features that make an item a work of art are aesthetic, then the features that make an item a work of art are among or supervene on its perceptible features, and A. if the features that make an item a work of art are among or supervene on its perceptible features, then no work of art is perceptually indiscernible from a twin item that is not a work of art, but A. some works of art are perceptually indiscernible from twin items that are not works of art, A. so the features that make an item a work of art are not aesthetic. This is now the canonical form of the argument. Both arguments share the premise that some works of art have perceptually indiscernible non-art twins: these are hard cases. Danto’s inspiration was Andy Warhol’s Brillo Boxes, plywood replicas of boxes for Brillo soap pads, first shown at the Stable Gallery in New York in . Brillo Boxes is a work of art, but not Brillo boxes. Other twins are John Cage’s ’” and four and a half minutes of not playing a piano, Robert Rauschenberg’s Erased de Kooning Drawing and a blank sheet of paper, and William Carlos Williams’s ‘This Is Just to Say’ and a (sort-of) apology note. These are actual twins, and their population is augmented in the literature by many counterfactual twins. Danto signals their importance, writing that ‘nothing in which indiscernibles consist can be the basis of a good theory of art’ (, ). The argument in its canonical flavour carries more punch than the classically flavoured argument, since aesthetic theories of art have been a going concern, the deep motivation for the twins argument comes from anti-aesthetic art, and the twins cases embody the most powerful conception of anti-aesthetic art. Art that is not beautiful, that is outright shocking or disturbing, mounts no real challenge to aesthetic theories of art. For example, Beardsley’s theory that a work of art is something produced to satisfy the aesthetic interest does not imply that works of art must 43 be beautiful. Shocking and disturbing art can be very interesting; the charming and delightful count too. A more serious challenge to aesthetic theories of art would come from ‘beige’ works – works that appeal to no aesthetic interest whatsoever. The trouble is that aesthetic qualities are so easy to come by that the challenge is easy to deflect. It is child’s play to attribute interesting aesthetic qualities to Brillo Boxes, ’”, Erased de Kooning Drawing, and ‘This Is Just to Say’. The power of the canonical twins argument lies in its showing that, whatever aesthetic qualities these works may have, their non-art twins have the same aesthetic qualities, so their aesthetic qualities do not make them works of art. The twins argument works by showing the aesthetic to be irrelevant to art. The argument is not decisive. There is of course the option to deny (A) and insist no hard case is a work of art. There is also the option to accept (A), to allow that at least hard cases are works of art, but to deny (A), the assumption that a work’s art-making aesthetic features are among or supervene on its perceptible features. Danto attributes (A) to a tradition which held that ‘one could walk through any space whatever and pick the artworks out with a high probability of attaining a perfect score’ (, ) – equipped, he means, with nothing more than a naked eye. Thus Danto imagines a Mr Testadura, an old-fashioned sort, steeped in this tradition, who visits his local MoMA and cannot tell the art from the non-art – who mistakes Robert Rauschenberg’s Bed for the kind of item sold at Sears. Yet theories of the aesthetic that imply (A) are contentious. Some early modern theories of the aesthetic are inconsistent with (A): they are devised not in order to serve aesthetic theories of art but also to cover aesthetic responses to nature and to ideas, particularly scientific theories (Shelley ). A widely accepted argument by Walton (, see also Hopkins ) allows for nothing stronger than: (A′) if the features that make an item a work of art are aesthetic, then the features that make an item a work of art partly supervene on its perceptible features. Since this claim is inconsistent with (A), the canonical version of the twins argument breaks down. At any rate, rejecting (A) 44 allows room to claim that Brillo Boxes and Brillo boxes differ aesthetically despite their retinal indiscernibility, and that claim may provide enough footing for an aesthetic theory of art. Looking in the other direction, many of those who are moved by the twins argument have gone on to propose non-aesthetic theories of art, following Danto’s suggestion that the twins reveal ‘a variety of elements that as a matter of intuition belong to the concept of an art work’ (, ). For example, Brillo Boxes, ’”, Erased de Kooning Drawing, and ‘This Is Just to Say’ differ from their non-art twins in their historical origins, their pedigrees. So maybe what makes something a work of art is its provenance. An extreme view is that any actual object might have been a work of art – in some possible world its provenance is one that makes it a work of art (e.g. Danto , xviii). Only the twins breathe life into this thought. Although I could not have been John Cage, I might have been a composer like him, and were I composer like him, these four and a half minutes of silence in my office today might have been a work of art. The hard cases that motivate the argument against aesthetic theories of art also inspire alternative theories. The buck passing theory of art assumes that theories of art get their impetus from the hard cases. After all, the content of the theory is advisory; it advises us to pass the buck on the assurance that the hard cases can be quite effectively dealt with by theories of the arts or theories of the individual arts. The ‘historical objection’ to the buck passing theory was that theories of art go back much further than the hard cases. So presumably they are not mainly designed to address the hard cases. So the advice to pass the buck is premature at best. The objection fails. Arguments like the open concept argument and the twins argument implicate the hard cases in a way that raises the question of what it is for an item to be a work of art. This is a question that theories of art try to answer. No arguments like these antedate the hard cases. The questions raised in the tradition are ones that seek answers through theories of the arts or theories of the individual arts. The ‘historical objection’ conflates these different kinds of theories. 45 In effect, the buck passing theory advises a return to the traditional concerns and it advises a return to tradition precisely so as to contend with what seem like distinctively modern problem cases. Any irony is merely apparent. The real irony lies with the historical objection. It projects contemporary theoretical concerns onto the past in a way that deprives us of crucial distinctions between different kinds of theories and the tasks to which they are suited. But these are the distinctions we need to effectively contend with the hard cases. Passing the Buck on Art Grant that a theory of art should answer the ‘what is art?’ question by contending with the hard cases in an effective way. The buck passing theory of art does its job if it is a good idea to deal with the hard cases by referring them elsewhere, to a theory of the arts or to theories of the individual arts. Its advising us that this is how to deal with the hard cases makes the theory informative. In the first place, buck stopping theories of art have reached an impasse in their dealings with the hard cases and this impasse is a good reason to take the buck passing theory seriously and look elsewhere for tools to cope with the hard cases. The impasse starts with a dilemma and a dilemma requires contending claims. Second, the buck passing theory clears the impasse and makes it possible to cope with the hard cases. Two Stances Philosophy often obeys Newton’s third law of motion. Notwithstanding the efforts of Weitz () and others (esp. Kennick and Ziff ) to scotch the whole theory of art enterprise by demonstrating that there is no correct, complete, nontrivial theory of art, recent decades have seen an explosion of new theories. Each of them is interesting and has contributed something to our understanding of art, whether or not it ultimately stands up to scrutiny. Obviously, a survey of all existing theories would require many pages, with many more pages needed to assess each one individually. Others have already taken a close look at many theories and weighed up their strengths and weaknesses (e.g. Davies and Stecker ). Moreover, the task at hand does not require muscling it out with each contender. Since the dilemma arises because each theory takes one of two broad stances, we can ignore the detailed differences between theories. There are many ways to classify theories of art. Groucho’s theory is trivial, by contrast with non-trivial theories, such as the buck passing theory (which is not trivial even if it is shown to be uninformative). Some theories are reductive, stating what makes 47 something a work of art in more basic, independent terms. For example, Beardsley’s theory of art refers to aesthetic interest and his theory of aesthetic interest makes no mention of art (). Both versions of Dickie’s institutional theory are non-reductive, though they may be explanatory and informative ( and ). In the later version, a work of art is defined with reference to an art maker and an art world public, and these are defined in turn with reference to what they do with works of art. Dickie argues that only this sort of circularity can model what he calls the ‘inflected nature of art’ (, , see also –). Unlike all these theories, Gaut’s cluster theory is disjunctive (), as are many of the theories that vie for top billing nowadays (e.g. Levinson and Stecker , ch. ). Such classifications of theories are formal in the sense that they concern only the logical structures of the theories. Differences between each category are fully represented when it is left open what features complete the theory schema, so long as the logical relationships between features in the schema are specified (e.g. Longworth and Scarantino ). Stance-based classifications of buck-stopping theories of art are substantive and not merely formal: theories sharing a stance agree on what they take to be the broad kinds of features that make items works of art. Theories taking either stance may be trivial or non-trivial, reductive or non-reductive, disjunctive or nondisjunctive. So each stance takes in many possible theories that differ from each other with respect to what specific kinds of features each takes to be an art-making feature and also with respect to the logical relationships each takes to hold between those features (and the property of being a work of art). The stances are very general indeed. A very rough sketch of the contrast between them was originally suggested by Maurice Mandelbaum, who distinguished theories of art couched in terms of ‘exhibited’ properties from those couched in terms of the work’s relation to its context of making (). What is aptly called the ‘traditional stance’ is characterized by theories which hold that some of the features that make any given item a work of art are its exhibited features. Familiar candidates for these features include being an imitation of beauty in nature, expressing feeling, having significant form, and satisfying an 48 aesthetic interest. Each of these is an exhibited feature of works in the sense that it supervenes upon the works’ perceptible or semantic features. For example, a dance’s expressing a feeling supervenes upon a visible pattern of movements through a space and a poem’s imitation of beauty in nature supervenes on the meanings of the words that make it up. The significant form of a building might be realized through a visible relationship between materials on one hand and volumes and masses on the other. A bronze might satisfy an aesthetic interest in view of the apparent beauty of its patina. Traditional theories imply that nothing is a work of art except that such exhibited features help make it so. The alternative to the traditional stance is the genetic stance. Any theory taking this stance is consistent with the proposition that in some cases what makes an item a work of art is nothing more than some of its genetic features, where these do not supervene on its perceptible or semantic features. Rather, the genetic features of a work have to do with the circumstances or context of its making. Dickie’s institutional theory of art is a genetic theory. According to its later formulation, a work of art is an artifact of a kind made to be presented to an art world public (, ). Being made to be presented to an art world public is a feature that a work has because it was made in an institutional context. It does not supervene on the work’s perceptible or semantic features. Jerrold Levinson defends a non-institutional genetic theory of art that grounds a work’s being art in a history. In a compact statement of the theory, a work of art is an item intended for regard in some way or ways past artworks are or were correctly regarded (Levinson , ). In sum, genetic theories trace the art status of a work to its origins rather than its appearance or meaning. Other stances are possible because some art-making features might be neither exhibited nor genetic, but every known theory takes one of these two stances. Moreover, none can take both: the stances are contraries. A theory that conjoins being made in an institutional context with satisfying an aesthetic interest takes the traditional stance since it implies that some of the features that make any given item a work of art are exhibited features. A theory that disjoins the same two features takes the genetic stance 49 since it is consistent with the proposition that in some cases what makes an item a work of art is its genesis alone. Although no theories cross both stances, it does not follow that theories taking one stance deny that works have the features that characterize the competing stance. Dickie’s institutional theory of art is consistent with the undeniable fact that works of art do have exhibited features that supervene on their perceptible or semantic features. Likewise, an aesthetic theory of art is consistent with the undeniable fact that works have historical and institutional origins. A contextualist version of the aesthetic theory of art goes further, allowing the aesthetic features of a work to supervene partly on some of the work’s genetic features in cases where perceptual or semantic features also partly supervene on genetic features (see Walton ). The disagreement across stances is not about what features art works happen to have but about which ones make them works of art. Aficionados of the literature will have noticed that the division of theories into these two stances is not the standard typology, which divides theories into functional and procedural varieties (Davies ). According to functional theories, what makes something a work of art is a function it has, such as satisfying aesthetic interest. According to procedural theories, what makes an item an artwork is a matter of the ‘procedures, rules, formulas, recipes, or whatever by which artworks are generated’ (Davies , ). Procedural theories take the genetic stance and functional theories take the traditional stance. However, nonfunctional theories may take the traditional stance. Consider the theory that a work of art is an artifact of great beauty. This is a theory of art – it completes the schema for a theory of art – and, moreover, it takes the traditional stance, yet it is not a functional theory. Being beautiful is not a function of an artifact, though an artifact may serve a function because it is beautiful. By analogy, weighing a hundred grams is not a function of an artifact, though the artifact may serve the function of measuring out coffee because it weighs a hundred grams. At any rate, the classification of theories into traditional and genetic stances may replace the classification of theories as functional and procedural without loss, 50 particularly for the purpose of characterizing the dilemma (cf. Davies , –). A Dilemma As is only to be expected, the boundary between traditional and genetic theories is crowded with hard cases. On one hand, hard cases are frequently born of a contrary spirit, a preoccupation with toppling prevailing conceptions of art as represented by traditional theories of art. If, despite the fact that works like Brillo Boxes and ’” have plenty of exhibited features, none of these features play a role in making them works of art, then traditional theories of art are in trouble. On the other hand, those who favour the genetic stance freely admit to being inspired by cases such as these, under the assumption that at least some of them are works of art. What makes them works of art? Their provenance, say the genetic theories. Thus Dickie remarks that hard cases ‘reveal the institutional essence of art’ for ‘our attention is forced away from the objects’ obvious properties to a consideration of the objects in their social context’ (, ). With genetic theories waiting eagerly in the wings, we should make sure that the hard cases really do manage to brush off traditional theories of art. Any given case is a work of art or it is not. If it is not, then it is not a counterexample to a traditional theory of art. So one strategy for traditional theories of art is, as Nick Zangwill (b) puts it, to ‘brazen it out’ and deny that the hard cases are works of art. However, if the case at hand is a work of art, then either it is a counterexample to traditional theories of art or it is not. These theories get the brush off only if it is a counterexample. But it is not a counterexample if part of what makes it art are its exhibited features. So another strategy for traditional theories of art is, as Zangwill (b) puts it, to ‘sneak past’ the hard cases and avoid the brush off by insisting that they have what traditional theories say it takes to be works of art. There are two ways to try to sneak past the hard cases: one pins its hopes on each hard case having aesthetic features (e.g. Lind , –). The classic photograph by Alfred Stieglitz brings out the pristine, graceful curves of Duchamp’s Fountain, for 51 example. However, this move is too sneaky by half, for almost anything has some aesthetic features. Might any non-art item with some aesthetic features have a twin that is art? This move saves aesthetic theories at the price of making them nearly empty. Another way to sneak past the hard cases is to bring in help, to accept that what makes an item a work of art is a combination of its aesthetic and genetic features. This move concedes the force of the hard cases without giving up on traditional theories of art. Presumably, then, the provenance of a work of art is a factor that determines its aesthetic qualities, so that a work of art does differ aesthetically from its non-art twin (see Davies , –). Duchamp’s Fountain is sometimes said to be witty or provocative, quite in contrast to its non-art counterparts; and that can only be a result of its provenance. Alas, this move only makes it past some hard cases. Non-art twins are not items like copies of the Mona Lisa or epic poems in tetrameter banged out by monkeys; they are snow shovels, urinals, blank sheets of paper, notes left on the fridge door, stretches of not playing a piano, and other perfectly ordinary elements of everyday life. Nothing singles out items like these for the kind of special treatment that would endow them with the provenance making them works of art; yet, by hypothesis, some of them are works of art. Perhaps some of them acquire new aesthetic properties with their art-making provenance, but there is no reason that all should. Provenance is not aesthetic magic. There remain hard cases of works that are no different aesthetically from their non-art twins. These works are anti-aesthetic not in the sense that they lack aesthetic features but in the sense that they lack artmaking aesthetic features. Faced with these hard cases, traditional aesthetic theories of art must either concede defeat or brazen it out and deny that the hard cases are works of art. Some deny exactly this (e.g. Beardsley , Tolhurst ). Doing so is brazen. Zangwill sums up the line that must taken by those who brazen it out: they assert ‘it is absurd to make the whole philosophy of art turn on the antics of a minute minority’ and so ‘turn snooty and insist on the insignificance of the excluded object’ (b, –). A real life example is Denis Dutton, whose view is not ‘snooty’: he complains 52 that ‘the obsession with accounting for art’s most problematic outliers… has left aesthetics ignoring the center of art and its values ‘ (, ). The non-traditionalist reply is that although the hard cases are recent and constitute a numerical minority of all art works, they are nonetheless important, indeed central, and not so easy to shrug off. As Carroll reports, ‘anti-aesthetic art has existed for over eighty-five years, and it has been classified as art by art historians, critics, collectors, and a great many informed viewers. Nor is it a marginal movement in twentieth-century art. It has often commanded the limelight’ (, –). The alleged marginality of the hard cases is not common ground. It is part of the dilemma. In the end, traditional and genetic theories render contrary verdicts on the hard cases. Traditionalists reason that unless these works have the exhibited features that make them art works, they are not art. Geneticists, impressed by the central and important role of the hard cases in twentieth century art, counter that they are art: they have the right provenance. Dickie claims as a virtue of his genetic theory that it counts the hard cases as art; Beardsley counters that it is a virtue of his traditional theory that it denies them art status. As long as a theory of art should cope one way or another with the hard cases, we can ride with traditionalists and deny that the hard cases are art works, or we can ride with the geneticists and carry the flag for the hard cases. We must choose which class of theories gets the extension of art right. Impasse This would not be the first time in philosophy that a choice between theories or theoretical stances represents a clash in intuitions. However, a dilemma is not by itself an impasse; it might be the starting point for making progress. In deciding for or against the hard cases, a correct theory of art might rectify false intuitions. What is needed are independent grounds for theory choice –grounds that go beyond matching intuitions. The trouble is that there is no consensus on what is to be expected of a theory of art beyond conformity to intuitions. What is worse, 53 disagreement about what is to be expected of a theory of art probably stems from clashing intuitions about the hard cases. That is deep disagreement. That is an impasse. The rather extensive debates about theories of art is inevitably shaped by expectations about what to look for in an adequate theory of art. Gaut explicitly supplies a list of three conditions to be met by any adequate theory of art (, –). First is intuitive adequacy: an adequate theory ‘must agree with our intuitions about what we would say about actual and counterfactual cases’ (Gaut , ). In particular, any theory must face up to cases that test its provisions. Second is normative adequacy, which is consists in a reflective equilibrium between a theory and the relevant intuitions. When intuitions clash with a theory, this reflective equilibrium is achieved when the theory provides an ‘error theory’ – that is, an explanation of why some people have the faulty intuitions and hence why competing theories seem attractive. Third is heuristic utility: an adequate theory should fit into a larger package of theories that together illuminate the domain in question. A fourth measure of theory quality goes without saying. No theory is worth choosing unless it has the virtues to be expected of any theory – coherence and internal consistency, for example – and the same goes for a theory of art. Not everyone accepts Gaut’s first two adequacy conditions just as formulated. Some play down intuitions in favour of facts about practices. As Carroll puts it, ‘a comprehensive theory of art must accommodate the facts as [the theorist] finds them revealed in our practices’ (, ). This is consistent with Gaut’s first condition if intuitions are constitutive of the practices Carroll has in mind, but not if intuitions might fail to track the relevant facts about the relevant practices. In that case, well designed empirical studies of artistic practices are needed to provide the data against which to test theories of art. And in that case, the normative adequacy of a theory will consist in its setting straight practices that have gone off the rails by explaining why they go off the rails. The distinction between testing the extensional and normative adequacy of theories against intuitions and facts about practices is important, but it does not help navigate the impasse between 54 traditional and genetic theories of art. Those whose intuitions count the hard cases as art endorse those practices of the art world in which the hard cases are treated as art. Those whose intuitions balk at the hard cases either frown on those practices and advocate their reform or maintain that they have been misunderstood. More to the point is disagreement about what relative weight to give to each of Gaut’s three conditions. The first two conditions go hand in hand but a theory that does well by those conditions may have poor heuristic utility and a theory high in heuristic utility might not measure up to our intuitions or practices. Gaut puts greatest weight on the first condition; others put greater weight on the heuristic utility condition. Zangwill loudly complains that philosophers, being wracked with feelings of extensional inadequacy, make extensional adequacy their God and he recommends that a theory of X should explain ‘much else that we independently believe about X things‘ (c, ). Forced to choose between extensional and normative adequacy on one hand and heuristic utility on the other, we should choose the latter. Traditional and genetic theories face off over extensional adequacy. Some intuitions and practices favour traditional theories; some favour genetic theories. Moreover, each stance can make a case for normative adequacy because each can whip up an error theory of the other. The quick recipe is simply to accuse the erroneous theory of taking a contingent feature of art to be essential to being a work of art. It is common ground that most works of art serve aesthetic functions, as it is common ground that they are made in special circumstances. Geneticists diagnose traditionalist intuitions as wrongly essentializing the aesthetic (or something like it) and they distinguish aesthetic practices from art practices. For their part, traditionalists take geneticist intuitions to wrongly essentialize provenance, as would practices that make nothing but provenance necessary for art status. In the circumstances, criteria for making a good choice between the stances must be neutral on the hard cases. Neutrality is not to be found in considerations of extensional and normative adequacy. Putting the point another way, there is no reason to discount the real possibility that intuitions about the hard cases 55 are theory laden, and so too are the relevant practices. There is reason to suspect that the theories represent – and do not adjudicate –differences over the hard cases. That is an impasse. Next up, heuristic utility. Zangwill’s idea is that a theory of art should set the stage to explain ‘the fact that we value and desire the making and the consuming of art’ (c, ). Traditional theories of art are often crafted to explain ‘the value and importance of art’ (Davies , ). That is, individual works of art have more or less value and a theory of art might ground principles that say what it is for value to accrue to any given artwork. Thus one might prefer a theory of art if it determines these principles. Others insist on a similar tie between art and the aesthetic, which they take to favour aesthetic theories of art (Beardsley , –). The trouble is that this criterion of theory choice is not common ground between the traditional and genetic stances. It favours traditional theories and traditionalists favour it; it disfavours genetic theories and genetic theories reject it in turn. Insisting that a theory of art should solve the mystery of art’s value, Beardsley touts his own theory for implying that ‘it is good for us to experience, at least occasionally and to a degree seldom made possible except by artworks, the immediate sense (say) of inclusive self-integration and complex harmony with phenomenal objects’ (, ). Dickie, like others defending genetic theories, agree that we need to explain what it is for works of art to have value, but he denies that this explanation must be grounded in a theory of art (Dickie ). As Davies puts it, we should not assume that ‘a successful definition of art should account for the place of art in our lives – that will be a separate matter’ (, ). All that follows from the fact that we value and desire the making and consuming of art is that there is more to a complete understanding of art than can be extracted from a theory of art (Davies , ). A dramatic illustration of the problem is ready to be extracted from Beardley’s memorable tirade against genetic theories of art: To classify [the hard cases] as artworks just because they make comments on art would be to classify a lot of dull and 56 sometimes unintelligible magazine articles and newspaper reviews as artworks, and where is the advantage of that? To classify them as artworks just because they are exhibited is, to my mind, intellectually spineless, and it results in classifying the exhibits at commercial expositions, science museums, stamp clubs, and World’s Fairs as artworks. Where is the advantage of that? To classify them as artworks just because they are called art by those who are called artists because they make things they call art is not to classify at all, but to think in circles. Perhaps these objects deserve a special name, but not the name of art. The distinction between objects that do and objects that do not enter into artistic activities by reason of their connection with the aesthetic interest is still vital to preserve, and no other word than ‘art’ is as suitable to mark it (, ???). In this passage Beardsley makes extensional adequacy answerable to ‘advantage’ and thus faults the extensional implications of (some caricatures of) genetic theories of art. The reply from the opposition? It is enough to know what makes makes an item a work of art. Other matters are important, but they are independent agenda items. There is no reason to rule out the suspicion that traditional and genetic theories of art () pump different intuitions about the hard cases and () endorse different criteria of theory choice, where () results from (). Again, that is an impasse. What is left? Only the general virtues to be expected of any philosophical theory of any phenomenon – virtues like coherence and internal consistency. Plenty of effort has already gone into inspecting the details of existing theories for such traits, or their absence. None of this effort rules out either stance, even if it rules out some specific theories within each stance. In the first place, the stances are extremely abstract. No theory knocked off the path to general theoretical virtue just because it analyzes a phenomenon in terms of exhibited features or genetic features. There are perfectly decent traditional and genetic (e.g. causal) theories of all kinds of phenomena. Moreover, it is important to remember that perfectly decent theories may be trivial or non-trivial, reductive 57 or non-reductive, disjunctive or non-disjunctive. Many traditional theories are reductive and traditionalists tend to complain that genetic theories are often non-reductive – that is, circular. Not surprisingly, geneticists with non-reductive theories assert back that a non-reductive theory is just what the doctor ordered. They are right this far: there are perfectly decent non-reductive theories. For example, an argument is a set of premises and conclusions, where a premise is the part of the set from which the conclusion is inferred and the conclusion is the part inferred from the premises (Yanal , ???). Again, it is an impasse if traditional and genetic theories of art () pump different intuitions about the hard cases and () insist that theories of art have different general theoretical traits, where () is is a consequence of (). Unlike a dilemma, an impasse is often invisible to those it ensnares. Those who cherish the intuitions driving their thinking about art are as likely as not to shrug off the diagnosis that they are ensnared in an impasse. They naturally believe that they have dealt with the hard cases as befits the hard cases, whether they rule them in or out of the domain of art works. What is needed now is a way to contend effectively with the hard cases without slighting the intuitions that divide opinion on them. The Informativeness Challenge The impasse between genetic and traditional theories of art is most prominently represented as a collision over the hard cases. The collision is not epistemic – it does not spring from ignorance about whether the hard cases are or are not works of art. Rather, it involves a dispute about what makes anything a work of art, when it is a work of art, and the hard cases serve as test cases. They raise the question, what makes anything art if that is (not) art? The buck passing theory proposes an answer, namely that, x is a work of art = x is a work of K, where K is an art. This theory is methodologically informative, advising that any problem whose solution we seek in a theory of art we should actually seek elsewhere – either in a theory of the arts or in 58 theories of the individual arts. Since the hard cases represent a problem to be solved by a theory of art, the buck passing theory proposes to solve it by bouncing it to these other theories. Thus the theory is a success if it copes with the hard cases in a way that cashiers buck stopping theories of art. It cashiers buck stopping theories of art if theories of the individual arts are good tools for coming to grips with the hard cases. Here is why they are good tools for coming to grips with the hard cases. To begin with, every hard case for theories of art is just as much a hard case for a theory of one or more art forms. Consider Duchamp’s Fountain. Its status as a hard case is represented in the proposition that, . Fountain is a work of art. Fountain is a hard case because what makes () true or false is a flashpoint for theories of art. However, if Fountain is a work of art, then we may ask what kind of work it is. Patently not a poem, a movie, or a tea ceremony. When we ask if Fountain is art, we are not open to entertaining the claim that it is a dance or a symphony. Presumably, . if Fountain is art then it is a sculpture. At least, that is what the critical and historical record seems to indicate. It follows from () and () that, . Fountain is a sculpture. Whether () is true or false is a flashpoint for theories of sculpture. What, after all, makes an item a work of sculpture, if Fountain is a sculpture? Indeed, () is if anything more puzzling than (). Likewise consider this analogous triad: . ’” is a work of art, . if ’” is a work of art then it is a work of music, . ’” is a work of music. Again, () puts in play the question of what makes the item a work of art whereas () puts in play the question of what makes it a 59 work of music. Well might one ask what makes an item a work of music if a few minutes of not playing a piano can be a work of music. Is it genuinely an option to fret about what does or does not make ’” a work of art and remain sanguine about what does or does not make it a work of music? No wonder that collisions between theories of art that centre on () neatly correspond with collisions between theories of sculpture and music that centre on (). Anyone who favours a genetic theory of art that explains what makes () true will likely favour a genetic theory of sculpture or music that explains what makes () true, and anyone who favours a traditional theory of art that explains what makes () false will likely favour a traditional theory of sculpture or music that explains what makes () false. Why would the provenance of Fountain make it art if its aesthetic features make it a sculpture? Why endorse an aesthetic theory of art in conjunction with a genetic theory of music? This neat correspondence explains why, when it comes to the hard cases, the action tends to gravitate towards theories of art. Disputes centred on () naturally escalate into disputes centred on (), given () as leverage to threaten modus tollens. If ’” is not a work of music because it lacks the aesthetic or other exhibited features that would make it one, then it is not a work of art, given that it is a work of art only if it is a work of music. The traditionalist gauntlet being thus flung, the battle over theories of art is begun. Yet the same correspondence allows the tables to be turned. Baffled by Fountain or ’”, some reach for genetic theories that rule them in as works of art and others reach for traditional theories that rule them out. However, we might wonder instead: if Fountain is sculpture then what makes anything sculpture? and if ’” is music then what makes anything music? Centring attention on () rather than () represents the hard cases as hard cases. In this regard Fountain and ’” are nothing special. Christo’s wraps, Ben Vautier’s ‘Regardez moi cela suffit je suis art’, examples of Augusto Boal’s ‘theatre of the invisible’, and bp nichols’s ‘Cold Mountain’ are hard cases for theories of art. Christo’s wraps are hard cases for a theory of landscape architecture, Vautier’s intervention is a hard case for a theory of 60 painting, invisible plays are hard cases for a theory of theatre, and ‘Cold Mountain’ is a hard case for a theory of poetry. So the first point is that the hard cases are hard cases just as much for theories of the art forms as they are for theories of art. The second point is that once theories of the art forms have settled what they are equipped to settle with respect to the hard cases, they leave nothing to be settled a theory of art. If it is settled by a theory of sculpture what makes Fountain a sculpture and it is settled by a theory of music what makes ’” a piece of music, then a theory of art has nothing to add on the score. The same goes (assuming () is true) if it is settled by a theory of sculpture that Fountain lacks what it takes to be a sculpture and it is settled by a theory of music that ’” lacks what it takes to be a work of music. The reason is that the fact that an item is a work in an art form implies that it is a work of art. As we saw in Chapter , theories of the individual arts are under orders to answer the coffee mug objection. Supposing that ceramics is an art, surely the coffee mug on my desk is no work of art, though it is ceramic. Similarly, if architecture is the art of building then my garden shed is a work of art… but, alas, my garden shed is no work of art. What follows is that a theory of each art must distinguish works in the art from items in associated media. A theory of ceramic art must distinguish between a piece of bizen ware and my coffee mug. A theory of architecture (the art of building) must distinguish between Santiago Calatrava’s Puente del Alamillo in Seville on one hand and my garden shed on the other. No theory is a theory of an art form if it allows that () can be true when () is false. What if () is true and () is false? This scenario would seem to call in a buck stopping theory of art. If a theory of sculpture implies that Fountain does not have what it takes to be a sculpture and yet Fountain is a work of art, then surely we need a theory of art to tell us what makes it a work of art? Not quite. Asserting () and denying () is logically inconsistent with (). In light of how it is presented in the art galleries and the history books, the following conditional might seem to be true: Fountain is a sculpture, if it is a work of art. However, this conditional might well be false. The buck-passing theory of art 61 conjoined with () and the denial of () simply implies that Fountain belongs to some art form other than sculpture. To deal with Fountain in this scenario is to refer it to a theory of the art form it actually belongs to (not sculpture). The first point was that the hard cases for theories of art are just as much hard cases for theories of the art forms. The second point is that, once it has settled what makes a hard case a work in the relevant art form, a theory of that art form leaves nothing for a theory of art to settle. A third point is that the workload is asymmetrically distributed across theories of the several art forms, on one hand, and buck stopping theories of art, on the other. The former have rosier prospects than the latter. That is also good news for a buck passing theory of art. One might think that the coffee mug objection imposes a heavier burden on theories of the arts than on buck stopping theories of art. Not so. A theory of each art form must imply a distinction between works in that art form and items in associated media, but a buck stopping theory of art must imply the same distinction. Moreover, it is subject to a rather weighty constraint that individual theories of the arts are free to ignore. Buck stopping theories of art must draw the distinction uniformly, so that what distinguishes Calatrava’s bridge from my garden shed also distinguishes bizen ware from Walmart ware. By contrast, theories of the arts need not take a uniform approach, as long as they pair up with a buck passing theory of art. First, correct theories of some art forms might be traditional while correct theories of other arts are genetic. Maybe what makes an item a work of music is just its formal beauty even though the right provenance is all that it takes for some texts to be literary works. Second, traditional theories of music and painting need not refer to exhibited features of the same kind. Maybe part of what makes an item a painting is its representational character whereas what makes an item a work of music is nothing but its formal beauty. Traditional theories of some art forms are also more promising than a traditional theory of art. The latter posits exhibited features shared by ‘Duppy Conqueror’ and ‘Ash Wednesday’, but not by a Rangers game or a window display at Macy’s. A dance has it, but not an ice dance; a ballet has it, but not a gymnastics routine; The 62 Picture of Dorian Grey has it, but not Richard Ellman’s biography of Oscar Wilde. Finding the exhibited features is a punishing prospect, and these are not even hard cases. By contrast, the buck passing theory of art sets a traditional theory of music free to characterize the what makes an item music in specifically musical terms. Recall Hanslick’s account of musical works as realizing ‘specifically musical kind of beauty’ through ‘tonally moving forms’ ([], ???). Finally, buck stopping theories of art are entangled in an impasse, and theories entangled in an impasse do not have good prospects, all else being equal. Might the buck passing theory of art do nothing more than relocate the impasse in theories of the arts? Possibly, but there is reason to be optimistic. Patchwork theories typically face less intractable challenges than grand unifying theories since they can tap a richer store of undisputed facts specific to their patch to overcome disagreement. It is also inherently unlikely that every theory of every single art form will end up in impasse (that would indicate a wilful bloodymindedness that no amount of philosophy could hope to cure). Admittedly, these are barely principled reasons for optimism. Such a reason does emerge, though, by addressing a challenge to the viability of the buck passing theory of art. The Viability Challenge The best case to be made for the buck passing theory of art is that it is informative and viable. If theories of art are set the task of coming to grips with the hard cases and if the buck passing theory of art performs this task as expected, it is informative. Nevertheless, its being informative counts for little unless it is viable, and there is an objection to its viability. As it happens, an answer to this challenge touches on the theory’s informativeness. The challenge is simple but potent. The buck passing theory of art implies the biconditional: x is a work of art if and only if x is a work of K, where K is an art. 63 Is it true that belonging to an art form is a necessary condition on being a work of art? Is it true that every work of art belongs to some art form? Are none of them free agents? As we have seen, it is possible that in the following triad () is true and () is false, so long as () is also false: . Fountain is a work of art, . if Fountain is art then it is a sculpture, . Fountain is a sculpture. The buck passing theory of art says that if () is true and () is false, then Fountain is a work in some art form other than sculpture. But is it true that every work of art belongs to some art form and none is a free agent? If some are free agents, the buck passing theory of art is not viable. The free agents are counterexamples of the most lethal kind. Not only is the above biconditional false, but the counterexample would call specifically for a buck stopping theory of art. Suppose that Fountain is a free agent – a work of art that belongs to no art form. It follows that no theory of any of the arts will state what makes it a work in that art and no theory of any art will imply that it has what it takes to be a work of art. So comes to mind the question what makes it a work of art. No theory of any of the arts can supply the answer. We need a buck-stopping theory of art. To make matters worse, there is historical evidence of free agency. One of the standard stories told about the s has it that some art of this era broke free of the conventions, media, traditions, institutional frameworks, or whatever other fetters tied works of art to forms of art. It ‘dematerialized’ (Lippard ). For the sake of the buck passing theory of art there can be no free agents. One strategy is to insist on this. It is what the theory implies and the fact that the theory is worth having on other grounds is reason enough to accept the implication. Free agency is merely apparent. However, this strategy may be held in reserve as a fallback since there is good reason to doubt that free agency is anything but a mirage. 64 Four responses can be made to the challenge posed by an alleged free agent. The first admits that no theory of any art form accepts the item, but find that it is not, upon closer examination, a work of art. The second admits that the item is indeed a work of art, but finds that, upon closer examination, a theory of a familiar art form admits it. Many works can be dealt with in one of these two ways: doing so will help to make sense of these works for what they are. However, not all works get a fair shake if dealt with in one of these ways. A third response to a candidate for free agency admits that the item in question is a work of art and proposes that it also pioneers a new art form. The number of the arts continually grows, notable recent additions being photography, film, video, computer art, and conceptual art. The fourth response is to throw in the towel: a that no theory of any art form admits the work and yet it is a work of art. Only the fourth response defeats the buck passing theory of art, and it is not mandatory for any case. Any reason we have to say that an item is an art work that does not belong to any art form is reason to say that it pioneers a new art form. Or, more weakly, the fact that a work belongs to no familiar art form and yet is a work of art is reason enough to project a new art form. The move is not ad hoc. The hypothesis that an alleged free rider belongs to one or more pioneering art forms allows us to to understand it in its own terms, as a works of art that pushes the boundaries, the standard story notwithstanding. Suppose that a theory of theatre implies that a work of ‘invisible theatre’ is not theatre and the work finds no safe harbour with any other known art form. This is a fruitful discovery. It does not follow that the work is not art, and if the work is art then it follows from that fact together with the buck passing theory that the work pioneers a new art form. The innovations of the avant-garde are represented on this hypothesis as innovations. Needless to say, the proof of an abductive argument like this lies in the details. These must await Chapter . That theories of art are caught in an impasse does not impeach any particular theory of art, whether it be traditional or genetic. The impasse is methodological, not probative. But it does raise the 65 question, what if we do not look to theories of art to cope with the hard cases? What if we look to a theory of the arts and theories of the art forms instead? There is reason to think that looking in that direction will pay off. That is reason in favour of the buck passing theory of art. Art in Culture That art is a cultural phenomenon is a platitude, or rather a bundle of them. A culture is often defined in part as an entity having a tradition of art; its art is part of what makes it distinctive and indeed valuable; a healthy art scene relies on a cultural infrastructure; and practices of making and using works of art are transmitted from one generation to another through learning. Such banalities ring true even on the buck passing theory of art. Yet truth be told, the theory does not assign art a robust role in the cultural explanations proffered by anthropologists, sociologists, psychologists, historians, or other students of culture. No matter. This is as it should be. Art Radar The starting point in defence of this extraordinary thesis is a distinction that has so far been skirted – a distinction between art on one hand and the concept of art on the other. The hard cases are typically seen as challenges both to the concept of art and to theories of art, for they are typically seen as challenges to the former because they are challenges to the latter. The Iliad, Peiro della Francesca’s Annunciation, the Kailasanatha Temple at Ellora, ‘Swing Low Sweet Chariot,’ an Eagle and Raven Dance at Skidegate: texts, objects, and performances like these are works of art. A theory of art is a proposition that states what features of these and other art works make them works of art. Some hold that there is no such proposition, no theory of art. Others, as we have seen, offer theories of art – traditional theories, genetic theories, and the buck passing theory. At the same time, many folk have a concept of art, for this concept has been widespread for at least a century across the globe and across socioeconomic groups. The consensus in psychology and philosophy is that concepts are mental representations (see Margolis and Laurence ). The consensus is not total. Some argue that concepts are abstract objects, such as Fregean senses (e.g. Peacock ). Others argue that concepts are nothing more than abilities manifest in the performance of 67 discrimination or inference tasks – for example, a concept of a sycamore might be an ability to reliably discriminate sycamores from non-sycamores (e.g. Dummett ). Luckily, a foray into theories of concepts is not needed. Nobody writing on the ‘what is art?’ question denies that in normal circumstances a concept of art is attributable to a thinker in order to explain her thinking and reasoning about art works and her detecting them in her environment. This much is neutral between theories of concepts. Works like Fountain and ’” are test cases for theories of art because they focus the mind on the question of what makes something a work of art. What makes something a work of art if Fountain is, contrary to certain appearances, a work of art? Or if it is not a work of art, contrary to certain other appearances? Good questions! They are not, however, the same question as this: is Fountain a work of art? Or this: by what marks can one tell whether Fountain is a work of art? Or indeed: what facts about Fountain would justify the belief that it is a work of art? It is no news that the hard cases raise these and similar questions in spades. For sake of simplicity, set aside questions with epistemic elements and consider only those questions raised by the hard cases that probe the concept of art as it is implicated in reasoning about art works and detecting them in her environment. The point or purpose of a concept of art is to enable us to reason about and detect works of art. Beardsley’s remark that an answer to the ‘what is art?’ question is a practical necessity to legislators and administrators has been echoed repeatedly. Carroll stresses in his philosophy of art textbook that, without some sense of how to classify certain objects and performances as artworks, the Museum of Modern Art wouldn’t know what to collect, the National Endowment for the Arts wouldn’t know to whom to give money…. Nor even… would economists know how to evaluate empirical claims like ‘Art is a significant component of the financial well-being of New York City’ (, –). An answer to the ‘what is art?’ question that serves the purposes mentioned by Beardsley and Carroll is an explication of the 68 structure of a concept of art. Carroll goes on to say that ‘it is the task of the analytic philosophy of art to make sure that [our handle on the concept of art] is a sturdy one by reflecting on the concept of art and articulating its elements in as precise a manner as possible’ (, ). If a concept of art is implicated in reasoning and detection then its being put under stress by hard cases is likely to show up in errors of critical reasoning or egregious false positives and false negatives in detecting works of art in the environment. The received story is that contemporary art viewers evidence both signs of stress. Folk are presented with an item – a urinal or about four and a half minutes of no piano being played – and they cannot tell that they are presented with works of art. When they learn that these are works of art, they suspect that they no longer know what to look for in a work of art. If we are to believe the endless stream of New Yorker cartoons, they are left wondering whether the fire extinguisher in the corner of the gallery is a work of art. Back in , William Kennick set a test for having the concept of art: a thinker has a concept of art just in case he or she mostly succeeds when sent into a warehouse under orders to bring out all and only works of art (, –). A few years later, having absorbed the lesson of Warhol’s Brillo Boxes, Danto described a fictional Testadura, who fails the warehouse test. Sent into the warehouse, Testadura mistakes art for non-art: he leaves behind works like Fountain, Brillo Boxes, and ’”. Danto’s point is that we are all, now, Testaduras. We cannot tell art from non-art. As a result, we make blunders in reasoning about art – the cliché is the gallery goer’s outburst that ‘my little Tommy could do this!’ When made aware that our concept of art has broken down, we wonder if we know what we mean by ‘art’. At any rate, it has gone without question that the hard cases challenge the concept of art. So, then, what it is about this concept that makes it vulnerable to challenge from such quarters? A widely accepted diagnosis has it that the concept of art has been implemented in a way that makes an implicit commitment to one or more inadequate theories of art. The concept naturally fails if these theories are wrong about what look for in detecting works of 69 art. For example, a concept of art that makes an implicit commitment to the imitation theory sets you up to detect works of art by detecting imitations of beauty in nature, but a great many works of art do not imitate beauty in nature, and so the concept breaks down. The pattern repeats as each new theory of art spreads through the folk, updating their concept of art, only to find itself outflanked by a new generation of hard cases. The upshot is a nice explanation of the considerable bafflement experienced by art audiences for the last century. This hypothesis, that the hard cases challenge the folk concept of art because it makes implicit commitments to inadequate theories of art, can be taken to support the proposition that an adequate theory of art is one implicit in a folk concept of art that is immune to challenges from hard cases. If the hard cases challenge the folk concept of art because it makes implicit commitment to an inadequate theory of art, then it seems reasonable to think that a good theory of art will be one that is implicit in a stable folk concept of art. This reasoning assumes that a theory of art results from an analysis of the folk concept of art – an assumption that is accepted explicitly or implicitly by many contributors to the ‘what is art?’ literature (Meskin , –). Dickie writes that a theory of art attempts to ‘make clear to us in a self-conscious and explicit way what we already in some sense know’ (Dickie , ). As Stecker puts it, a correct theory of art states the features ‘that invariably inform the classifications of those who understand the meaning of “art”’ (, ). Traditional and genetic theories of art can be adapted to answer the call in somewhat different ways. Traditional theories draw a line around a cluster of exhibited features which reliably mark works of art. Genetic theories scrub that line and send us looking for facts about provenance to detect works of art. The prospects for putting the buck passing theory of art to work in this way are much less rosy. It lacks the resources to ease the challenge of the hard cases if what makes the hard cases hard is that they fly below the art work detection radar. Promulgating the theory that a work of art is a work in one of the arts is hardly likely to increase the range or signal strength of the detection mechanism. It adds nothing to what those who have a concept of 70 art already know. That is what makes it a buck passing theory of art. Here is an argument against the buck passing theory of art. If the hard cases challenge the folk concept of art then an adequate theory of art is one that implements a stable folk concept of art – that is, one left undisturbed by hard cases. The hard cases do challenge the folk concept of art, so an adequate theory of art is one that is implicit in a folk stable concept of art. The buck passing theory of art is a theory of art but it is not implemented in a stable folk concept of art, so the buck passing theory of art is inadequate. If the buck passing theory of art is adequate, then one or more of the premises of this argument is false. In fact, two are false. The first is the empirical hypothesis that the hard cases challenge the concept of art. The evidence for this hypothesis is that the hard cases provoke considerable bafflement, but there is another explanation of this fact. The story of Testadura is not only a fiction; it is a false one. We are not one bit like Testadura. In standard circumstances, anyone minimally schooled in art (even just pre-twentieth century art) can reliably tell art from non-art. Nobody is perfect, stuff happens, and the concept of art is vague (along with most of our other concepts). That said, Duchamp’s Fountain is not routinely or systematically taken for an ordinary urinal, and ’” is not routinely or systematically taken for an unscheduled intermission. The reference to ‘standard circumstances’ is the key. Nobody has any trouble recognizing (purported) works of art in museums or concert halls – set in display cases or ‘performed’ by people sitting at pianos. In circumstances such as these, Fountain and ’” are no less obviously marked out for us as works of art than Winged Victory or The Magic Flute. In general, recognizing anything depends on context. I can tell red from orange in standard lighting conditions, not any lighting conditions. I can recognize my keys in part because I know what they look like and also because they are in the dish in the front hall. Placing a red item in a strange light may subvert my ability to detect its colour, and I cannot recognize my keys in a lineup of similar keys. Likewise, placed in context, the urinal or four and a 71 half minutes of not playing the piano come across as works of art. Special conditions, like Kennick’s warehouse, do subvert art detection, but that is not surprising. Many concepts are confounded in some conditions. A special feature of art drives the point home. One can make a work of art whose detection requires picking up on contextual cues, and a great deal of recent art plays on context in this way. According to one observer, much contemporary art ‘is rooted in an anti-museum attitude… it is museums and art galleries that are the primary locus for such art… [which] needs an institutional context to be seen’ (Rush , ). Moreover, it is fair game to rely on expert advice in one’s detection tasks. Placing an item on a plinth or labelling it ‘Ming Dynasty’ communicates expert advice that aids art detection. Nevertheless, the hard cases do induce bafflement. They challenge folk concepts of the arts. Nobody attending a performance of ’” doubts that they are to take the performance as art. That is what they know for sure and will bet money on. After all, what else could be going on? The trouble is that they are told that it is music, though they detect music by listening for (something like) rhythmically and tonically patterned sound. If ’” is a work of music, then it puts pressure on the concept of a musical work as (something like) rhythmically and tonically patterned sound. Concepts of art forms such as music, dance, and painting are not in quite the same boat as the concept of art, for context and the advice of experts play a lesser role in detecting items in at least some art forms. So the hypothesis is that bafflement induced by a hard case is not to be understood as a challenge to a concept of art but rather as a challenge to a concept of some art form. As ever, more needs to be said in defence of this hypothesis – see Chapter . Note for now that the hypothesis is plausible enough to compete with the received story, which finds its archetype in the Tale of Testadura. And that is enough to weaken the argument against the buck passing theory of art. 72 Theories and Concepts of Art The freely admitted fact that the buck passing theory of art is not much use for those interested in the concept of art can be turned against the theory, given the assumption that if the hard cases challenge the concept of art then an adequate theory of art is one that is implicit in a stable concept of art. This assumption is toothless unless the hard cases challenge the concept of art. Since they do not, the assumption is toothless. Even so, the assumption is not only toothless; it is also false. Suppose the argument in the previous section fails and the hard cases are best understood as challenging the concept of art (and not merely some art form concepts). Also suppose that the concept of art is vulnerable to this challenge because it makes implicit commitment to an inadequate theory of art. What follows directly from this is that it would be a nice to upgrade the concept of art by severing its allegiance to the inadequate theories. It does not follow that it must be joined in a new allegiance with a correct theory of art. In general, having a concept of a kind does not imply any theoretical commitments. There is nothing special about the concept of art. A stable concept of art need not make an implicit commitment to any theory of art whatsoever. Under the influence of a reading of Wittgenstein, Weitz () and Kennick () reason that there is no correct, non-trivial theory of art, but the folk have a concept of art, so having a concept of art does not involve a theory of art. Instead family resemblances among works of art are the means by which they are recognized as works of art. A statement of such family resemblances among works of art is not a theory of art. After all, the resemblances that enable us to recognize individuals as belonging to the same (biological) family do not make them members of the same family. More recently, Noël Carroll () has coupled agnosticism about whether there is a correct theory of art with a nontheoretical account of art detection (see also Dean ). Carroll argues that the hard cases are philosophically interesting because they show that theories of art are useful in detecting art (, -). He proposes instead that we detect works of art ‘by 73 means of historical narratives which connect contested candidates to art history in a way that discloses that the mutations in question are part of the evolving species of art’ (, ). These narratives relate ‘how [a hard case] came to be produced as an intelligible response to an antecedently acknowledged arthistorical situation’ (, ). It is ultimately an empirical question whether the concept of art is implicitly theoretical or whether it works by non-theoretical means such as family resemblances, prototypes, or narratives. Perhaps the concept of art is a kludge or a bag of tricks comprising a number of mechanisms which together enable us folk to detect works of art with an acceptable degree of reliability in ecologically realistic circumstances – that is, in the actual world. The kludge might be counterfactually fragile: it could break down were it tried out in non-actual circumstances. The same goes for most perfectly good concepts. The deeper point is that having a stable concept of a kind is consistent with considerable, indeed massive, ignorance about the nature of the kind (Putnam ). Users of a concept of art may take advantage of the fact that works of art in their environment often have certain features – exhibited features, features of provenance, contextual features – in order to detect them reliably. Contextual features are especially helpful in detecting works of art in view of the fact that at least since the early modern period a great of art is presented in venues that have been created for the purpose of presenting works of art – theatres and concert halls, art galleries, and literary magazines, for example. As to the nature of art… they defer to the experts. Stecker correctly points out that the fact that the folk concept of art is not implicitly theoretical does not mean that we may not use a theory of art to alleviate some conceptual bafflement (Stecker , ). A theory of art plugged into an upgraded concept of art might be the cure the we seek. By the same token, the fact that some theory might alleviate some conceptual bafflement does not imply that a theory of art fails unless it does so. As we have seen, that implication requires the assumption that theories of art are wrought by analysis of the folk concept of art. That is, it requires the claim that an adequate theory of art is one that is implicit in a 74 stable folk concept of art. It should be clear now that this is not a claim to be assumed lightly. Denying the claim does not imply that art is a natural kind. In particular, it is consistent with what nobody denies, that if there are any features that make items works of art, some of them are response-dependent. There would be no works of art without agents who treat them in certain ways. The choice is not to find the nature of art either to be implicit in the folk concept of art or in a concept of art that figures in the hypotheses and explanations of the natural sciences. That is a false dichotomy. Art is not a natural kind: it does not figure in the hypotheses and explanations of the natural sciences. But neither must the nature of art be implicit in a folk concept of art. What is left? The third option is that the place to look for the nature of art is in the hypotheses and explanations of the social sciences, which include history as well as psychology, anthropology, sociology, and economics (Moravcsik , Dickie ). These are sometimes ‘debunking’ hypotheses that are inconsistent with theories implicit in folk concepts (Lopes forthcoming). They open up a gap between the self-understanding expressible in folk terms and the self-understanding that can be won through scientific discovery. Such a gap does not require that folks concepts be set against natural kind concepts: folk concepts need only be set against the concepts implicated in expert intellectual labour. It is to these expert labourers that we folk defer when it comes to what makes any item a work of art. In his classic paper on theories of art, Timothy Binkley wrote that ‘what counts as a work of art must be discovered by examining the practice of art’ (, ). Carroll agrees that ‘as a philosopher of a practice, one must go where the practice does’ (, ). Such injunctions are common. Taking them seriously means looking to how social science deploys the concept of art. The buck passing theory of art is intended as a game changer. Game changers are hard to believe: they are correct only if we are making fundamental errors. This was expressed in an argument against the buck passing theory of art. As this argument goes, if the hard cases challenge the folk concept of art then an adequate 75 theory of art is one that is implicit in a stable folk concept of art, so the buck passing theory of art is inadequate because the hard cases do challenge the folk concept of art and the buck passing theory of art is no help in stabilizing the folk concept of art. One error in this argument is that the hard cases do not challenge the folk concept of art. Another was in thinking that an adequate theory of art must be implicit in a stable folk concept of art. Art in Cultural Explanation This chapter opened with the admission that the buck passing theory of art is not much use to social science, though it was quickly added that the admission is immaterial because a theory of art should not assign to art a robust role in cultural explanations. Yet the previous section concludes that social scientific hypotheses and explanations are the source for a theory of art. The tension is only apparent. Art and the concept of art – each of these phenomena may be studied theoretically or empirically. One might seek a theory of art stating what features that make any item a work of art, or one might study the features that art works actually have among the Dene or eighteenth-century Parisians. One might seek an account of what it is for any concept to be a concept of art, or one might study the features by means of which art works are stereotyped by the Baule or Hegelian philosophers. Beardsley urged that a theory of art ‘should be of the greatest possible utility to enquirers in other fields besides aesthetics – fields to which aesthetics itself should (sometimes) be thought of as a support and underpinning’ (, ). Fans of genetic theories of art may and do concur (e.g. Dickie , –). It seems a sentiment hard to deny that theories of X should be useful to those who study X. Why should art prove an exception? Consider that Beardsley goes on to write that ‘it stands to reason that someone starting out to write a history of (visual) art would want to have a reasonably definite idea of what it is he is writing a history of’ (, ). The parentheses around ‘visual’ represent a fudge. Drop them and the claim is that a historian of visual art would want to know the nature of visual art. But would he want 76 to know the nature of art? The nature of music, epic poetry, and ballet lie beyond his field of expertise. Now try dropping the ‘visual’, as the parentheses suggest. Presumably the historian who would want to know the nature of art is the historian of art as a whole (not just visual art). There is no such beast. The reason is that, keeping in mind that art is one thing and the concept of art is another, art as a whole is not the object of inquiry in any social science. That is, there are no serious psychological, anthropological, sociological, or historical hypotheses about all and only works of art. There are many serious hypotheses about images, works of music, novels, and works in other art forms, as there are about works in genres like melodrama and the epic and styles like the Baroque and post-modernism. None of these hypotheses are even implicitly about all art in the sense that they are to be tested against any art work – a sociological finding about the social function of musical works among American teenagers is not weakened by the fact that oil paintings do not have the same function: when the topic is music, it is not visual art. Moreover, any hypotheses about all art works are also hypotheses about non-art. It is true that making works of art is an exercise in creativity, but that is not unique to art. The psychologist Rolf Reber () proposes to explain positive responses to works of art as the result of processing fluency, but he takes processing fluency to explain positive responses to nonart too. Karl Marx held that art is epiphenomenal superstructure – but so are many other elements of culture (Eagleton ). Denis Dutton suggests that works of art are products of sexual selection – they indicate personal charm (Dutton ). As Dutton admits, the same goes for pocket handkerchiefs and wittily presented philosophical arguments. If ‘art’ is a term in cultural explanations, buck stopping theories of art predict that some cultural explanations are true of all and only works of art. The buck passing theory predicts that what might at first glance appear to be hypotheses about all and only works of art are actually hypotheses about broader or narrower kinds. The buck passing theory of art better fits the data. In the cultural explanation game, every square marked ‘art’ is a shoot leading down to a species of art or a ladder leading up to 77 a more generic phenomenon. The concept of art deployed in cultural explanations requires nothing more than the buck passing theory of art. That is just to say that references to works of art do not play a robust role in cultural explanations. Works of art, being cultural products, are fitting objects of social scientific inquiry, and so is the concept of art, especially in so far as it changes over time and varies from one cultural context to another. Historians, sociologists, and anthropologists describe the concept of art that is deployed in a cultural setting, as does Kristeller (see Chapter ). Moreover, cultural explanations which attribute the concept of art to thinkers in a cultural context are robust in the sense that they fail if the concept of art is replaced with a concept of a species of art or with a concept of a more generic phenomenon. The buck passing theory of art predicts that references to works of art do not play a robust role in cultural explanations; it is consistent with the fact that references to the concept of art do play a robust role in cultural explanations provided that the two kinds of explanations are decoupled. Are they decoupled? Much contemporary social science takes the stance that they are not, and the rationale for this stance is worth pausing over. In part it derives from an appreciation that it is often fruitful to attempt to view works of art in a cultural setting from an ‘internal’ perspective, by using the concept of art endemic in the setting. Taking this perspective may reveal features of art works that would be missed otherwise. Added to this is a concern that the only alternative to taking an internal perspective is using a concept of art from an alien setting, which is potentially distorting at best and oppressive at worst. The sensitivity is at its highest in anthropological writing about ‘primitive art’. As the worry is often expressed, ‘by calling them “works of art” I imply that the people who make and use these objects have the same or very similar attitudes and beliefs involved in the English meaning of “work of art”’ (Blocker , ). So it is commonly held that to study art in a cultural setting one ought to study art as it is conceptualized in that setting. These methodological norms embodied in these reflections are frequently supported by a claim about the relationship between 78 works of art and the concept of art in a cultural setting. The claim posits a dependence of the former on the latter, and it is most striking in arguments from the empirical observation that members of C lack a concept of art to the conclusion that they have no art: . members of C have no concept of art, . there are works of art in C only if members of C have a concept of art, so . there are no works of art in C. Following a discussion of Baule attitudes to their carvings, David Novitz concludes that the works ‘occupy a very different social location from the location occupied by works of art in our culture, and ... as a result of this, it would be at best misleading, at worst inaccurate, to describe them as works of art’ (, ). The anthropologist Susan Vogel writes that ‘although Baule art is important in the Western view of African art, the people who made and used these objects do not conceive of them as “art”… “art” in our sense does not exist in Baule villages’ (, ). Interestingly, philosophers who have rejected the reasoning from () to () simply reverse its direction, keeping () as the fulcrum (e.g. Dutton , Davies , Dutton ). They complain that the criteria for concept attribution assumed in evidence typically given in support of () – for example, that members of C have no word in their language synonymous with ‘art’ – are far too stringent. For example, Shakespeare and his European contemporaries had no word synonymous with ‘art’ so it follows by the above reasoning that plays like King Lear are not art works. But they are art works. So they argue instead: !. there are works of art in C, . there are works of art in C only if some members of C have a concept of art, so !. members of C have a concept of art. By this reasoning, the presence of art works in C warrants attributing a concept of art to members of C. 79 The arguments from () to () and (!) to (!) represent deep disagreements with interesting implications (see Lopes a), but they share () as an assumption. The trouble is that it is hard to square the robust role of the concept of art in cultural explanations with the conjunction of () and the buck passing theory of art. According to that theory, there is art in C if there are songs in C (songs being works of art). Given (), it follows that members of C have a concept of art. That is, given (), the fact that people sing in C is sufficient by itself for attributing a concept of art to members of C. The buck passing theory ends up trivializing the concept of art. By contrast, those who reason from (!) to (!) have buck stopping theories of art which set the bar high enough for the truth of (!) that (!) is informative. For these theories, () is not a trap, as it is for the buck passing theory. Nobody has provided an argument for (), but the following thought is in the air. Making works of art is a complex business which could not be conducted by anyone lacking a conception of what they are up to (Wollheim [], –). This thought suggests what is probably the best argument to be given for (). Making a work of art necessarily involves an intention to make a work of art, but one cannot intend to make an art work unless one has a concept of art, so any culture with works of art is a culture whose members have a concept of art. This ‘argument from intentions’ is unsound. Its second premise, that one cannot intend to make a work of art unless one has a concept of art, follows from the plausible principle that one cannot intend to make an F unless one has a concept of Fs. However, its first premise, that making a work of art necessarily involves an intention to make a work of art, is false. Granted that art-making is a necessarily intentional activity, it does not follow that works of art are made with the intention to make art. They might be made with a different intention. An art work might be art accidentally. Define making accidentally as follows: S accidentally makes an F just in case S intends to make a G, an F is not a G, S fails to make a G, and, in failing to make a G, S makes an F. 80 Intending to make a loaf of bread, I blunder and make a doorstop instead. Intending to make a whatsit, I blunder and make an art work instead. I need not have a concept of art that I use in making my art work. There is little chance that all the works of art in a cultural setting, if there are a lot of them, are made accidentally. All else being equal, the hypothesis that members of the culture intend to make works of art is to be preferred to the hypothesis that they output thousands of art works per year purely by accident. To block accidental art-making, () should be strengthened: *. there is widespread art-making in C only if some members of C have a concept of art. Indeed, (*) better serves the spirit of the arguments from () to () and (!) to (!) than does (). Not all non-intentional making is accidental (Wollheim , ). A mixture of saltpetre, charcoal, and sulphur was apparently manufactured first for fireworks and was only later adapted for guns. The early manufacturers of this mixture intended to make black powder but not gunpowder. By making black powder, they made gunpowder, for black powder is gunpowder, but intending to make black powder is not intending to make gunpowder – intending is an opaque context. Moreover, they did not make gunpowder accidentally – they did not make it as a byproduct of bumbling in the process of making black powder. Rather, they made gunpowder ‘incidentally’: S makes an F incidentally just in case S intends to make a G, S does not intend to make an F, S makes a G, and in making a G, S also makes an F. When an F is made incidentally, it is an F and a G but it is not made with an intention that it be an F and it is not made accidentally. Black powder is gunpowder, but incidental making does not require an identity. The Pella are a remote tribe who intentionally make windows. Since glass has properties that suit it for use in windows, many Pella windows are made from glass; and since the 81 properties that make glass good for windows also make it good for mirrors, some Pella windows (especially their skyscraper windows) are mirrors. The reason is not that mirrors are windows but rather that glass mirrors and glass windows share many properties in common. Nonetheless, the Pella do not intend to make mirrors, for they do not have a concept of mirrors; they do not have a concept of mirrors because they are blind. Pella mirrors are made incidentally. Works of art might be made incidentally too. This can happen in countless ways, of course, but the buck passing theory allows for works of art to be made incidentally by art-makers who intend to make pots, songs, epic poems, totem poles, or hypertext fictions but who do not intend to make works of art, perhaps because they lack the concept of art. In fact the theory predicts widespread incidental art-making in some cultures, and there are such cultures (e.g. pre-modern Europe). The theory also implies that art is not an essentially artifactual kind, a kind whose members are necessarily products of an intention to make items of that very kind. That is not an objection to the theory, however. Not all artifactual kinds are essentially artifactual kinds (Hilpinen and Thomasson ). Paths are artifacts although many paths are not made with an intention to make a path – they are made by people simply intending to take the most convenient route across the land. The buck passing theory of art implies that the argument from intentions is unsound. Unless there is another argument for () or (*), cultural explanations of art and the concept of art may be decoupled. Decoupling makes room for a theory of art which assigns no robust role to references to art in cultural explanations and yet makes no commitment to a trivialized concept of art incapable of playing the robust role it needs to play in cultural explanations. Beyond Parochialism Has the buck passing theory of art been flipped from the frying pan into the fire? The conjunction of the theory with () or (*) delivers a concept of art too trivialized to be an object of social 82 scientific study, and the response is to deny () and (*). However, () and (*) are often endorsed in support of a methodological norm, that works of art in C should be understood as much as possible using concepts endemic in C. Following the norm reveals features of art works that would be missed otherwise, and it guards against the imposition of an alien concept of art in studying works of art in a cultural setting. But denying () and (*) implies that there may be no concept of art in a culture with works of art. Studying these works surely requires the imposition of an alien concept of art? Surely it is better to comply with the the norm and affirm (*) in conjunction with () or (!)? One strategy is to try to defang these questions by showing that there is no epistemic or moral wrong in using a concept of art from one setting to understand art in another setting. The buck passing theory provides no particular reason to favour this strategy, but it does contribute to the alternative approach, which is to leave in the fangs and supply an antidote. Remember that the following is a false dilemma: to understand works of art in C we must either use the concept of art endemic in C or resort to a folk concept of art imported from outside C. The missing option is to use no folk concept of art. If every work of art is a work in one or more art forms, then studies of works of art in C may understand them using art form concepts available in C. Thus to attribute works of art to C is nothing more than to acknowledge that members of C make pots and skyscrapers. These may be conceptualized using the concepts of pots and skyscrapers available in C. The attribution need not come with any baggage that packs a folk concept of art. Moreover, the buck passing theory of art allows for taking a local perspective on art forms. The theory states that, x is a work of art = x is a work in K, where K is an art. For Calatrava’s Puente del Alamillo to be a work of art is for it to be a work of architecture, where architecture is an art. It follows that there are two ways for an item to fail to be a work of art: it may fail to be a K or K may fail to be an art. Presumably, the Puente del Alamillo might have failed to be a work of art even 83 where it is a work of architecture. Also, if some K might not have been arts, some other K might have been arts. For example, the Bluenose is a work of naval architecture and it would have been a work of art were naval architecture one of the arts. The truth of these counterfactuals is secured by the proposition that, (w) x is a work of art in w if and only if x is a K in w and K is an art form in w. Interpreted as consistent with this proposition, the buck-passing theory of art does not restrict what art forms are possible to those that are actual. By contrast, according to a modally parochial interpretation of the theory, what makes an item a work of art is that it belongs to a kind that is actually an art form. Given a list, L, of the kinds that are actually arts: (w) x is a work of art in w if and only if x is a K in w and K is in L. Naval architecture is actually not an art form, so this implies that the Bluenose could not have been an art work as long (as it is a ship). Architecture is actually an art form, so the Puente del Alamillo is necessarily a work of art as long as it is a bridge. Indeed, the good ship Bluenose is not an art work even in worlds where naval architecture is counted by its inhabitants as an art and the Calatrava bridge is a work of art even in worlds where architecture is not counted by its inhabitants an art. This distinction is easily adapted to represent culturally local and parochial interpretations of the buck-passing theory. Where L is a list of ‘our’ arts (say, the arts of actual westerners), the parochial interpretation is: (w) x is a work of art in w if and only if x is a K in w and K is an art form in L. Ikebana is not in L, so the example of ikebana on my hall table is not and indeed could not be a work of art in any culture. Ballet is in L, so Swan Lake is a work of art as long as it is a ballet. According to the local interpretation: 84 (w) x is a work of art in w if and only if x is a K in w, x was made in C in w, and K is an art form in C in w. Since ikebana is actually an art in Japan, the arrangement on my hall table is a work of art. It would not be if ikebana were not an art form in any culture. Finally, an intermediate interpretation relativizes what is a work of art to a community: (w) x is a work of art in C in w if and only if x is a K in w x was made in C in w, and K is an art form in C in w. Since ikebana is actually an art in Japan, an ikebana arrangement is a work of art in, for example, a chashitsu – but not on my hall table. Interpreted parochially, the buck passing theory of art flouts the norm that works of art in C should be understood using concepts available in C; it complies with the norm if it is interpreted locally. Which interpretation is correct? As always, the one that is implicit in the explanations of artistic phenomena that emerge from history, anthropology, sociology, and the other social sciences. If the norm is correct, then it would seem that that the correct interpretation of the theory is the local one. Gregory Currie (, ) has characterized two of Jerrold Levinson’s (, , , b) formulations of his historical theory of art as parochial and local in a similar way. The gist of Levinson’s theory is that ‘something is art if and only if it is or was intended or projected for overall regard as some prior art is or was correctly regarded’ (b, ). On the local interpretation, an item made in C is a work of art only if it was intended or projected for a regard that is or was correct in C. According to the parochial interpretation, being art at a time is defined ‘by reference to the actual body of things that are art prior to that time’ (Levinson , ). The actual extension of art determines what regards are and were correct in any modal or cultural context. Thus ‘the concrete history of art is logically implicated in the way the concept of art operates’ (Levinson , ). The two interpretations are not logically consistent. One solution is to distinguish, using one interpretation in a theory of art and the other in an explication of the concept of art. There is 85 evidence that Levinson thinks the parochial interpretation elucidates our concept of art. For example, Gaut objected that there might be works of art that ‘stand in no art-historically significant relation at all to any of our art’ (, ). Levinson replied that ‘insofar as anything outside our art tradition is properly said to fall under our concept of art, it is because we can appropriately relate it to our tradition of art, and in particular to the normative regards that have, as a contingent matter of fact, emerged in that tradition’ (Levinson , ). In other words, the parochial interpretation elucidates our concept of art – what Currie calls ‘art-for-us’ (, ). By contrast, when Stephen Davies suggested an aesthetic theory of ‘what, in surveying the known art traditions of the world, makes them all art traditions rather than internally historical traditions of some other sort of making’ he countered that he would ‘historicize’ in the same way for each one (, ). In the modal case ‘we have every reason to count or acknowledge as art what they count or acknowledge as art, that is, things intended for regard the way earlier presumed art in that world was correctly regarded (Levinson , ). In other words, the local interpretation provides a (genetic) theory of art. Our concept of art might be as Levinson describes it. Locating its contours, wherever they lie, is an important task. It belongs to a full description of our history and social organization, and it also helps to explain the contingent features of the works of art we have – the buck passing theory of art does not imply that endemic concepts of art are causally inert. Perhaps, in addition, the method of probing intuitions is a good way to locate the contours of the concept and the places where they break down into indeterminacy. Nonetheless, an elucidation of the concept of art need not the furnish a correct theory of art. Social concepts are not necessarily transparent to social reality. The nature of social reality is only, even if only dimly, illuminated by social science. The Myth of Artistic Value Art works are objects of appreciation and, since appreciation involves evaluation, they are objects of evaluation too. Rembrandt’s portraits bring home the truth of the human condition, Ryoanji is drop-dead beautiful, music promotes prenatal cognitive development, a good story helps to while away long airplane journeys, bebop sells us on democracy, dance boosts cardiac fitness. According to tradition, not all of these values are characteristic of art: art works characteristically bear aesthetic value. Breaking with tradition, some now say that art works bear artistic value, as distinct from aesthetic value. However, there is no characteristic artistic value distinct from aesthetic value. Moreover, the argument for this thesis suggests that what fills the breach is a concoction aesthetic value mixed with a proposal inspired by the buck passing theory of art. From Aesthetic Value to Value in Art The case for the thesis that there is no characteristic artistic value distinct from aesthetic value depends on what is being denied – that is, on what artistic value is taken to be. That has never been set out explicitly and clearly. All we have to go on is the fact that conceptions of artistic value are developed with aesthetic value as a foil, either in reasoning where artistic value emerges as an alternative to aesthetic value or where aesthetic value figures as a subspecies of artistic value. Unsurprisingly, the recent history of art supplies what might be a wedge to split artistic value from aesthetic value. Many works of art tax our understanding of aesthetic value in a way that seems to point to a need for a conception of artistic value. However, the conception of aesthetic value that serves as a foil to a conception of artistic value must not be tendentiously narrow. Ancient tradition identifies aesthetic goodness with a relatively narrow or ‘thick’ conception of beauty which, as Wollheim powerfully puts it, 87 would exclude much of the material that has inspired the artist of the last one hundred and fifty years: the modern city, and its teeming chaos, the life of the poor and the outcast, sexuality in all its varieties, violence, suffering, and war, and the mute tribute expected by quiet domesticity (, –). Modern theories of aesthetic value embrace the value realized by the kinds of art works Wollheim has in mind (e.g. Budd , Zangwill b, Iseminger ). These theories must go into the foil. Danto hails ‘the discovery that something can be good art without being beautiful as one of the great conceptual clarifications of twentieth-century philosophy of art’ (, ; see also Danto , ). This clarification is not enough by itself to set artistic value apart from aesthetic value, for it has been built recent updates to theories of aesthetic value (see Chapter ). A better wedge for splitting artistic from aesthetic value is the hard cases, especially as they figure in a twins argument. The twins arguments in Chapter concern theories of art, not artistic value. According to the canonical formulation of the argument, if the features that make an item a work of art are aesthetic, then the features that make an item a work of art are among or supervene on its perceptible features, and if the features that make an item a work of art are among or supervene on its perceptible features, then no work of art is perceptually indiscernible from a non-art twin, but some works of art are perceptually indiscernible from non-art twins, so the features that make an item a work of art are not aesthetic. A parallel argument concerns value: . if the value of a work of art is wholly aesthetic, then its value supervenes on its perceptible features, and . if the value of a work supervenes on its perceptible features, then no work differs in value from an indiscernible twin, but . some works differ in value from indiscernible twins, . so the value of a work of art is not wholly aesthetic, C. so works of art bear artistic value distinct from aesthetic value. 88 This is not the only argument that might split artistic from aesthetic value, and it is rarely laid out so explicitly (an exception is Goldman , ), but it undoubtedly lurks in the background of thinking about artistic value. Clearly () follows from () to () and, moreover, () and () are true. Premise () follows from the definition of supervenience. A good example of () is a work and a perfect forgery of it. They differ in value. It is only because forgeries generally have considerably less (market, historical, craft) value than the originals they copy that forgers go to great lengths to deceive others about the origins of their wares. Similarly, in one of Danto’s examples, our use of Rauschenberg’s Bed differs enormously from our use of a bed purchased at a department store. The best explanation of this is that they differ in kinds of values they have. What about ()? This premise takes a stand on the nature of aesthetic value, as supervening wholly on perceptual features. The best way to disable the argument is to deny (). If (C) is false and there is no artistic value, then () might be replaced with a better theory of aesthetic value. Such a theory would have to explain the difference in aesthetic value between a work and a perfect forgery of it (e.g. Hopkins ). The main issue is how to understand the inference from () to (C), for that inference betrays a conception of artistic value. One option is to take the inference at face value. (C) follows directly from () if artistic value is any value to be found in a work of art. After all, nothing in () restricts the types of values with respect to which a work and its twin differ. A painting and a forgery of it may differ in pecuniary value, or maybe the forgery is a better source of information about contemporary forging techniques. On this reading, (C) simply indicates that aesthetic value is not the only kind of value realized by works of art. Works of art can be more or less good or bad in a variety of respects, and an inventory of specific values of specific art works can be used to generate an inventory of kinds of value to be found in some works of art. The list includes aesthetic value, cognitive value, moral value, therapeutic value, political value, propaganda value, economic value, decorative value, hedonic value, entertainment value, distraction value, prurient value, theological 89 value, communicative value, bragging value, collector value… . The inventory is lengthy indeed. Its usefulness is diminished by the fact that many of the values of specific art works are adventitious. It is a merit of the print hanging over my mantelpiece that it conceals a flaw in the wall behind it. The tempo of a song might nicely time a cyclist’s cadence for a given route over the Pyrenées. A Holmes story might have the flaw of spreading false beliefs about the locomotion of snakes. The adventitious values of works of art can shed little light on characteristically artistic value. There are several plausible ways to exclude adventitious values of art works from consideration, and any one will do for now. Suppose that there is value in an art work to the extent that it serves the purposes for which it was made or distributed (see Wolterstorff , ; Iseminger ; cf. Parsons and Carlson ). This proposal delivers a theory of ‘value in art’: V is a value in art = V is realized in a work of art to the extent that the work serves the purposes for which it was made or distributed. Not all values that happen to be realized by a work of art are values in art, since not all values that happen to be realized by art works are values that they were made or distributed in order to realize. This is why the decorative merit of my print, the athletic merit of the song, and the cognitive demerit of the Holmes story are not values in art. Still, the inventory of values in art remains very long because artists make works and art promoters distribute them with many purposes in view. No less an authority than Horace tells us that ‘the aim of the poet is to benefit or amuse, or to make his words at once please and give lessons of life’. Entertainment value and cognitive value are values in art. Matisse adds therapeutic value when he describes art as ‘like a mental soother, something like good armchair in which to rest from physical fatigue’. Works of art have been made or distributed in order to raise (or lower) political consciousness, to engender a closer union with the divine, to titillate, to unify the decor, and to send signals about 90 social status. Traditionally, at least, art works have been made or distributed to serve aesthetic and cognitive purposes too. With this in mind, here is a theory of artistic value on which (C) follows directly from (). Call it the trivial theory: V is an artistic value = V is a value in art. Thus any value is an artistic value just in case some work of art is made or distributed in order to realize that value. Examples of artistic values recognized by the trivial theory include aesthetic value, propaganda value, theological value, moral value, therapeutic value, prurient value, and decorative value. Although the trivial theory validates a direct inference from () to (C), it utterly fails to capture the force of the twins argument. Nobody needs an argument to learn that aesthetic value is not the only value in art – it is as plain as anything that a forgery and its original differ in pecuniary and historical value, for example. Moreover, nobody who thinks that artistic value is just value in art needs an argument to learn that artistic value is not the same as aesthetic value. Something more is at stake in the twins argument. Instead of taking the inference from () to (C) at face value, suppose we take it to imply a theory of artistic value according to which not all values in art are artistic values. Most values in art, including some of those listed above, hardly come across as artistic values. A theory of artistic value that is stronger than the trivial theory will state what makes some – not all – values in art characteristically artistic values. Reading the twins argument as implying something stronger than the trivial theory explains why that argument has been reckoned so informative and important. () does not make the obvious point that a forgery and its original differ with respect to some value or other. When conjoined with a non-aesthetic conception of artistic value that is stronger than the trivial theory, it makes the more interesting point that they differ with respect to some non-aesthetic artistic value. Notice, by the way, that there is no point arguing that artistic value is a phantom if the trivial theory is true. The phantom is a stronger conception of artistic value that is implied by the inference from () to (C). 91 From Value in Art to Artistic Value To have true bite the twins argument requires a distinction between mere value in art and artistic value; the same distinction is implied by the current debate about whether the artistic value of an artwork may comprise some other values that it realizes, notably cognitive and moral values (e.g. Lamarque and Olsen , Stecker , Carroll , Kieran , John ). In his groundbreaking contribution to this debate, Carroll (b) distinguishes first between autonomism and moralism, and then between radical and moderate versions of each. According to radical autonomism, ‘it is inappropriate or even incoherent to assess artworks in terms of their consequences for cognition, morality and politics’ (Carroll b, ). Moderate autonomism allows that ‘some art may by its very nature engage moral understanding and may be coherently discussed and even evaluated morally’ (Carroll b, ). Daniel Jacobson () complains that Carroll’s distinction between radical and moderate autonomism fails to describe the positions as actually occupied. Classical autonomists such as A. C. Bradley and Arnold Isenberg never denied that works of art can be assessed morally. For example, Bradley wrote that ‘the intrinsic value of poetry might be so small, and its ulterior effects so mischievous, that it had better not exist’ (quoted in Jacobson , ). Bradley could not have written this sincerely while holding that it is inappropriate or incoherent to assess poetry for its moral consequences. So who is right, Carroll or Jacobson? Is radical autonomism an occupied position? Assume that if an item has a given kind of value, then it is always coherent and sometimes appropriate to attribute that kind of value to it. Conjoin this assumption with the trivial theory of artistic value and Jacobson is right to dismiss attempts to distinguish radical from moderate autonomism. No autonomist seriously denies that some works of art have mischievous moral consequences and so none deprecates attributions of moral value to art works as inappropriate and incoherent. Yet, turning the tables, there is room to distinguish radical and moderate autonomism if the trivial theory of artistic value is 92 replaced with something stronger. A radical autonomist who grants that works of art have moral value may hold that moral value, though it is a value in art, is not an artistic value. Carroll imputes to Clive Bell, a radical autonomist, the view that ‘it is virtually unintelligible to talk of art qua art in terms of nonaesthetic concerns with cognition, morality, politics, and so on’ (b, ). Notice the phrase in italics added to the official statement of radical autonomism given above. On this version of radical autonomism, Bell may accept that works of art have moral value even as he denies that they have moral value qua art. Moreover, if radical autonomism is a contrary of moderate autonomism, which states that ‘some art may by its very nature engage moral understanding and may be coherently discussed and even evaluated morally’, then radical autonomism denies that any art by its very nature engages moral understanding or has moral value. The thought is that artistic value is not mere value in art; it is value as art, value that an art work has by its nature. What Carroll calls the ‘common denominator argument’ for radical autonomism suggests that this is the right characterization of the view. The argument is this (Carroll b, ). No value is an artistic value unless it is a value in all art works, and moral value is not a value in all art works, so moral value is not an artistic value. Given the trivial theory, the opening premise of this argument is untenable: it would say, against the spirit of the trivial theory, that no value is a value in some art works unless it is a value in all art works. So the common denominator argument should be taken to imply that not all value in art is artistic value. As a matter of fact, Bell and other radical autonomists (e.g. Beardsley []) agreed, holding that the only characteristically artistic value is aesthetic value. Few will lose any sleep worrying about how to provide safe harbour for radical autonomism, but many would be shocked to hear that moralism – also known as ‘ethicism’ – is trivially true. According to Gaut’s () statement of ethicism, some ethical defects in works of art are aesthetic defects (and some ethical merits in works of art are aesthetic merits). The ‘merited response argument’ for the first, negative (unbracketed) conjunct goes like this (Gaut , ): 93 . if prescribed responses to a work of art are not merited because they are unethical, that is a failure of the work, and . what responses a work of art prescribes is aesthetically relevant, . so if prescribed responses to a work are not merited because they are unethical, then that is an aesthetic defect of the work, . so a work’s prescribing unethical responses is an aesthetic defect. Since Gaut reduces aesthetic value to artistic value, (), (), and () are equivalent to: ’. what responses a work of art prescribes is artistically relevant, ’. so if prescribed responses to a work are not merited because they are unethical, then that is an artistic defect of the work, ’. so a work’s prescribing unethical responses is an artistic defect. Having made the same substitution of ‘artistic’ for ‘aesthetic’, George Dickie complains that the merited response argument is ‘pedestrian’: it is trivial that an ethical defect in a work of art is an artistic defect (, –). If artistic value is value in art, then Dickie is right and the conclusion of the merited response argument is trivial; but the argument is interesting and informative given something stronger than the trivial theory. Since some works of art are made and distributed at least in part to prescribe ethical responses, ethical value is a value in these works of art. According to the trivial theory, any value in some work of art is an artistic value. So ethical value in these works is artistic value. This shortcut to ethicism relies on nothing more than the indubitable observation that some works of art have ethical value plus the stipulation of the trivial theory. Given the trivial theory, ethicism is true but hardly interesting. Therefore, if ethicism is interesting, arguments like Gaut’s require a meatier conception of artistic value than is supplied by the trivial theory. 94 To pull these thoughts about radical autonomism and ethicism together, if the trivial theory is correct, it is hard to see how to sustain a distinction between radical autonomism, moderate autonomism, and ethicism. Everybody accepts that works of art can be morally mischievous or beneficial: they can be offensive or they can get us to do the right thing. In addition, everybody accepts that some works of art are made or distributed in order to engender these morally good and bad effects. It follows that moral value is a value in art and, given the trivial theory, that moral value is an artistic value. Only by denying the trivial theory and by distinguishing mere value in art from artistic value is there room for genuine disagreement about whether an art work’s moral value is ever an artistic value. Value as Art Carroll equates artistic value with a work’s value ‘qua art’ and Gaut identifies the ‘aesthetic value’ of a work of art with its value ‘qua work of art’ (, ). The proposition that artistic value is the value of a work of art as art is not yet a theory of artistic value that is stronger than the trivial theory. What is it for something to have value as art, where not all values in art are values as art? Taking a hint from Carroll’s characterization of artistic value as a value that an art work realizes ‘by its very nature’, one might try to extract a theory of artistic value from a theory of art – that is, a buck stopping theory of art. The assumption would be that the value of an art work as art is a value realized by the features that make it a work of art. The operation turns out to be rather too delicate, however. Most theories on offer plainly cannot deliver a theory of artistic value. Institutional theories of art are ruled out, since they take what makes an item a work of art to be a kind of feature that ends up unable to realize artistic value (e.g. Dickie ). Aesthetic theories of art are also ruled out if artistic value is supposed to be distinct from aesthetic value. Keeping in mind that the conception of aesthetic value that serves as a foil to artistic value cannot be overly narrow, an aesthetic theory of art need not wear the name on its sleeve. The 95 theory that a work of art is an imitation of beauty in nature is an aesthetic theory of art. A case could be made that most of the features proposed for Gaut’s disjunctive theory of art are aesthetic – having positive aesthetic properties, being expressive of emotion, being intellectually challenging, having complex meanings, being formally complex and coherent, being original, and being the product of a high degree of skill (, ). It is a fair question whether any given theory of art is aesthetic or not. What options remain? Some who appeal to artistic value explicitly shun theories of art (e.g. Carroll and b). No help there. Nowadays the most influential non-aesthetic, noninstitutional theory of art is Levinson’s view that what makes an item a work of art is its having been ‘intended or projected for overall regard as some prior art is or was correctly regarded’ (b, ). An example of the ‘overall regard’ appropriate to a painting is: ‘with attention to color, with attention to painterly detail, with awareness of stylistic features, with awareness of art-historical background, with sensitivity to formal structure and expressive effect, with an eye to representational seeing, with willingness to view patiently and sustainedly’ (Levinson , ). This is perfectly consistent with standard theories of aesthetic value, like Malcolm Budd’s (). So is the partial theory of art recently accepted by Danto (, ), namely that a work of art must be about something and must embody its meaning (see also Fodor ). The assumption that the value of an art work as art is a value realized by the features that make it a work of art is not trivial. Without a weighty argument for this assumption, those who believe in artistic value cannot hold it against a buck stopping theory of art that it fails to deliver a theory of artistic value clearly distinct from aesthetic value. Nobody should be surprised that a conception of artistic value cannot be read off any viable theory of art on offer. The lesson is that conceptions of artistic value have a source independent of theories of art. In an anti-theoretical spirit, one might observe that attributions of value as art figure in our critical practices, so that the nature of artistic value can be straightforwardly read off those practices. However, many outlets for art criticism – from Sotheby’s 96 catalogues to Martha Stewart Living to informal conversations – attribute a mixture of many kinds of value to art works. As Gaut reminds us, ‘art critical evaluations are as such aimed at the evaluation of art qua art: that is, not art as investment, as a social symbol and so on’ (, ). Since discourse about art mixes evaluations of art as art with other evaluations of art, we need a theory that distinguishes evaluations of art as art with other evaluations in order to distinguish art criticism from other evaluative discourse. The only way forward is to seek a theory of artistic value not derived from a theory of art and not simply read off art criticism. Nobody who appeals to artistic value has spelled out such a theory, but two models lie to hand. Both were devised to account for the value of works in specific art forms. Perhaps they can be refitted to serve as theories of artistic value. Art as a Category of Art The first model is Walton’s () discussion of categories of art (see also Laetz ). If art is a category of art, then the value of a work as art may be its value when appreciated in the category that includes all works of art. Walton considers categories of art that are characterized in terms of certain properties of the works that belong to the category. These properties are perceptible but not aesthetic (though they include the perceptible properties upon which the aesthetic properties of works in the category supervene). In particular, Walton’s categories are characterized by the perceptible, non-aesthetic properties that are ‘standard’, ‘contrastandard’, and ‘variable’ in the category – those whose possession counts towards, counts against, and counts neither for nor against a work’s belonging to the category. For example, in painting, flatness is standard, having moving parts is contra-standard, and having some red bits is variable. Categories of art have two interesting features. First, it is possible in principle to tell by perception alone what category a work of art belongs to. The category of painting having been characterized visually, we can see whether or not a work is a 97 painting. Second, there are innumerable categories of art, though most of them play no role in our actual appreciative practices. The unfamiliar category of guernicas is made up of works that realize the two-dimensional depictive pattern of Picasso’s Guernica in different degrees of relief, so that ‘some guernicas have rolling surfaces, others are sharp and jagged, still others contain several relatively flat planes at various angles to each other, and so forth’ (Walton , ). Picasso’s Guernica belongs to the category of painting and also the category of guernicas. With this conception of categories of art in place, Walton argues for several theses, and here are three. First, the aesthetic properties an art work seems to have depend upon the category in which we appreciate it. Viewed as a painting, Guernica seems ‘violent, dynamic, vital, disturbing’, but it would seem ‘cold, stark, lifeless, or serene and restful’ if viewed as a guernica (Walton , ). Although the category of guernicas has no psychological reality for us, Gombrich () provides a real example. Viewed in the category of abstract painting, Mondrian’s Broadway Boogie-Woogie seems cool and orderly. Viewed in the category of De Stijl, it seems to buzz energetically. A second thesis is that the first thesis is explained by the fact that a category of art has standard, contra-standard, and variable features. The features that make Guernica seem dynamic when it is viewed in the category of painting are standard in the category of guernicas, where its flatness becomes salient and it comes to seem lifeless. When it is viewed in De Stijl, where a monochrome grid is standard, the coloured grid makes Broadway Boogie-Woogie seem to buzz energetically. This effect is lost when the painting is viewed in the category of abstract painting, where the grid is variable. Third, the aesthetic properties a work actually has are those it seems to have when we appreciate it in a ‘correct’ category. Guernica is a guernica but it is not correct to appreciate it in the category of guernicas, so it is not cold, stark, or lifeless. Rather, it is violent, dynamic, vital, and disturbing because it so appears when it is viewed in the category of painting and it is correct to view it in the category of painting. It is correct to view Broadway Boogie-Woogie in the category of abstract painting and also in the 98 category of De Stijl, so it is cool and orderly and also buzzes energetically, depending on its category. To be useful in modelling artistic value, this framework must be retrofitted. Properties must include values, so that the value that a work seems to have depends on the category in which it is appreciated, and the value that a work has is the value it seems to have when it is appreciated in a correct category. Stipulate also that a work’s value as a K is the value it appears to have when it is correctly appreciated in the category of Ks. Broadway BoogieWoogie is correctly appreciated in the categories of abstract painting and De Stijl, so its value as an abstract painting is the value it seems to have when it is appreciated in the category of abstract painting and its value as a work of De Stijl is the value it seems to have when it is appreciated in the category of De Stijl. Finally, in so far as the twins argument motivates appeals to artistic value, it makes sense to allow for categories of art that have some non-perceptual features as standard, contra-standard, or variable. (Technically, this is not a change to Walton’s framework, since he never claims that all categories of art are perceptual.) The proposal is that the value of a work as art is the value it has when and only when it is appreciated in the category made up of all and only works of art. That is, V is a value of an art work as art = V is a value the work appears to have when and only when it is appreciated in the category of art comprising all works of art. Just as a work’s value as music is the value it seems to have as it is correctly appreciated in the category of musical works, a work’s value as art is the value it seems to have as it is correctly appreciated in the widest category of all art. The beauty of this proposal is that it does seem to distinguish artistic value from mere value in art. The idea is that some values of a work are not apparent unless the work is appreciated in the right comparison class and the right comparison class for artistic values is the class of art works. Attributing a mere value in art might also implicate a comparison class. An obvious example is a work’s pecuniary value – consider circumstances in which ‘you 99 paid a lot of money for that’ is true and false. However, the pecuniary value of a work is not apparent when and only when it is placed in the comparison class comprising all and only art works. The same goes for propaganda value, value as a sign of social standing, and the like. One objection to the proposal is that, if some philosophers are right, it turns out that aesthetic value is not an artistic value. According to formalists, the aesthetic value of a work is at least sometimes independent of any comparison class (esp. Zangwill ). There is something to this. Surely some works of art are simply beautiful: they are no less beautiful when set among the angels and no more beautiful on display in Hades. However, to get in the spirit of the exercise we should assume, contra formalism, that Walton’s three theses are true when it comes to such categories as music and painting. Any objection should target artistic value specifically. The trouble with the proposal is that no work of art is appreciated the category comprising all works of art. Consider what is required in order to appreciate a work in any category of art. A category of art is made up of a number of works and the act of appreciating a work in the category must be sensitive, in some way, to the category’s membership. This requirement should be not read as too demanding. Clearly we may appreciate a work in a category without knowing every feature of every work in the category and without even bringing to mind any other work in the category. Nevertheless, one does not appreciate works of art in a category if one systematically excludes a subset of works in the category. Suppose, for example, that we correctly appreciate items in the categories of red things, yellow things, blue things, and the like. Suppose also that when we take ourselves to appreciate items in the category of coloured things, we always exclude some tints, so that when someone claims to appreciate a red item in the category of coloured things, it turns out that their appreciation is no different than their appreciation of the item in the category of red things. What does it mean to say, in this scenario, that we appreciate anything in the category of coloured things? In general, 100 S appreciates x in category of art K only if there is no category of art K*, where K* is a proper subcategory of K, where it is correct to appreciate x in K*, and where S’s appreciation of x in K* would not differ from S’s appreciation of x in K. That is, when we exclude works in one or more categories of art that are proper subcategories of K, with the effect that an appreciation of a work in K is no different from an appreciation of the work in K* (the non-excluded sub-category), then we really only appreciate x in K*. This minimal requirement is not met by the category of art. Works of art are never appreciated in a category including all works of art; there is always a systematic exclusion of some works of art. ‘Sneakin Around’ may be appreciated in the category of blues or in the category of songs, but it is not appreciated in a category that includes all ceramics and landscapes, for instance. The exclusions are systematic in the sense expressed by the principle above. Consider the hypothesis that we appreciate ‘Sneakin Around’ in the category made up of all works of art. So appreciated, we hear it as having certain features. Now consider the subcategory of art made up of music: when we appreciate it in the category of music, we hear it as having the same features as before. The features we hear it as having are not determined by the features of ceramics or landscapes. Applying the above principle, it follows that, contrary to hypothesis, we do not appreciate ‘Sneakin Around’ in the category of art made up of all works of art. Why, then, do we think that we ever do appreciate works of art in the category of art comprising all works of art? Notice that we correctly appreciate works across the boundaries of the familiar categories of art. We might see, for example, how the design of a Jerry Garcia necktie resonates with the mood of his music, so that we appreciate the tie in a category with the music. Evidently, correct appreciations need not remain within the bounds of familiar art forms like painting and music. As long as we always appreciate works in some category of art, we might conclude from cases like the Jerry Garcia tie that we sometimes appreciate works in the widest category of art made up of all art. 101 The mistake is in thinking that we are stuck with the familiar categories and that we cannot correctly appreciate works in unfamiliar categories that cross art forms and are more specific than the category made up of all art. Nothing in fact prevents the correct appreciation of works in categories of art that are projected on the fly. Jerry-Garcia-like-concoctions is such a category. We do not appreciate the Jerry Garcia tie in the category made up of all works of art, including poetry, dance, and chado. Walton’s framework explains why this should be the case. A category of art has standard, contra-standard, and variable features, and Walton’s second thesis says that the appreciation of a work in a category is sensitive to the membership of the category because it is sensitive to what features are standard, contra-standard, and variable in the category. What non-aesthetic standard, contra-standard, and variable features characterize the category of art comprising all works of art? We do not appreciate works of art in the category of art whose membership is all works of art. So there is nothing it is for a work to have value as art if the value of a work as art is the value it appears to have when it is correctly appreciated in the category comprising all works of art. Art as Achievement The second model takes inspiration from the fact that art works are achievements whose value is realized in how they came to be. This applies to any artifact, from scotch tape to the writings of David Lewis, to van Gogh’s paintings, though different kinds of value accrue to these different kinds of achievement. Assume, in general, that an item’s value as a member of a kind is its value as the product of an achievement of that kind. For example, the value of a song as a work of music is its value as a musical achievement. On this model, V is a value of an art work as art = V is a value of the work as the product of an artistic achievement. 102 An analysis along these lines is encouraged by developments in aesthetics which foreground the role of artistic acts in understanding art works (e.g. Currie , Davies ). Nobody denies that making a work of art is often an achievement, but it does not follow that it is often an artistic achievement. An achievement is an act and any act of making a work of art falls under many descriptions. It might fall under such descriptions as: getting a good price from the dealer, using up the last of the cadmium yellow, and having provided a distraction from the bothersome roommate. If none of these is an artistic act which can be an artistic achievement, then the question arises: under what description is the act of making a work of art an artistic act? Moreover, not every instance of successfully engaging in an activity under a description is an achievement under that description. Making it down the bunny hill is an achievement for me but not for an Olympic skier. More importantly for present purposes, doing something difficult and novel may not be an achievement if it is not a goal within the relevant practices or traditions. Having managed with enormous effort to breed a very large dog is no achievement in the breeding of toy spaniels. That practice or tradition sets (or includes) standards that govern which ways of engaging in the activity of breeding spaniels are achievements. Therefore, a supplementary question is: what practice or tradition is that of making art? An achievement-based theory of artistic value depends on a theory of what makes an act artistic and a theory of what practice or tradition sets the standards for artistic achievement. The strategy is to model what we need on a representative account of achievement in specific art forms – musical or pictorial achievement, for example. Wollheim’s () account of ‘thematizing activities’ is representative (Currie is an alternative). A work of art is intelligible as a product of an activity under a description according to which behaviours that were otherwise unintentional are intentional, with the result that we come to see how an inert material carries meaning. When a work is made intelligible in this way, the activity is a ‘thematizing activity’. Painting is a 103 thematizing activity because a painting is intelligible as the product of an activity of marking up a surface to support seeing– in. Accordingly, an achievement in painting is one realized by marking up a surface to support seeing–in. Likewise, writing music is a thematizing activity wherein inert materials (soundspace structured by tone, metre, and timbre) come to carry meaning. A musical achievement is one realized by making the tone, metre, and timbre properties of sounds come to carry meaning. From here it is a short step to a partial account of the practices and traditions of painting and music: these express standards which can be met by some of what is to be achieved through the thematizing activities of painting and music. This picture of thematizing activities delivers a plausible theory of what it is to value a painting as a painting. The value of Van Gogh’s Sunflowers as a painting is its value as an achievement of painting – an achievement in the handling of the materials of painting to carry meaning. Making Sunflowers is not a thematizing activity under such descriptions as getting a good price from the dealer, using up the last of the cadmium yellow, or having provided a distraction from that bothersome Gaugin. Under these descriptions, his achievement is not a painterly achievement and none of the values that Sunflowers realizes as a product of these achievements are its values as a painting. The value of a work as art is its value as the product of an artistic achievement only if making art is a thematizing activity, but art is not a thematizing activity. There is art. Artists make it. What they do when making art is often an achievement of some kind. However, it is not an artistic achievement, because there is no description under which their activity is a thematizing activity of making art. The reason is that the artist has no inert materials that she can make to carry meaning except the materials of some art form or genre. The only resources for thematizing are those of music, painting, chado, and the like. There are no resources for thematizing over and above these that could covert making a painting to making art. Take Sunflowers. It is a work of art. Van Gogh made it. Moreover, his making it was a pictorial achievement, for it was realized by engaging in a thematizing activity of depiction where 104 he made the inert materials of depiction bear meaning. Yet he had no artistic materials that he could make to bear meaning except the materials of depiction. What he did falls under no description of a thematizing activity of simply making art that is not identical to a description of the thematizing activity of making art of a particular kind, namely painting. Moreover, there are practices and traditions of painting and music, but there are no practices or traditions of making art over and above these. This fact explains why there is no history, anthropology, or sociology of art: every social scientific hypothesis about art is actually a hypothesis about painting, music, epic, melodrama, or some other kind of art. Making art is not a thematizing activity, so works of art are not products of artistic achievement in the way that paintings are products of pictorial achievement. There is nothing it is for a work to have value as art as long as the value of a work as art is its value as a product of artistic achievement. Deflationary Artistic Value Walton’s and Wollheim’s discussions of categories of art and the activity of painting represent two ways to model value as art on value in more specific art kinds. The problems scaling these models up to apply to all art do not turn on the details of either discussion: they threaten alternative versions of the same models. Nor do they offer much hope of a third model. The media, traditions, and practices associated with specific art kinds ground the distinctive values realized by works in those kinds. Art as a whole has no associated medium, tradition, or practice. Why not embrace this result? According to a deflationary theory of artistic value, the value of a work as art is its value as a song, painting, serving of o-cha, or the like. That is, V is a value of an art work as art = V is a value of the work as a K, where K is one of the art forms, genres, or other familiar art kinds. Since value as art is not being modelled on value as a K, scruples about deriving a theory artistic value from a theory of art do not 105 block theories of value as a K derived from theories of K. Hence the deflationary theory of artistic value may be stated: V is a value of an art work value as art = V is a value realized by φ where φ is what makes the work a K and where K is one of the art forms, genres, or other familiar art kinds. Some who have pondered the nature of artistic value have hinted at just such a theory (e.g. Stecker : ; Carroll : –). Moreover, it is certainly in tune with the spirit of the buck passing theory of art (though it is not entailed by it). Since the goal is to say what makes a value an artistic value and not merely a value in art, the challenge for the deflationary theory is to safeguard a distinction between artistic value and mere value in art, such that not all values in art turn out to be artistic values. Indeed, the ultimate challenge is to correctly divide artistic values from mere values in art. As Gaut put it, ‘art critical evaluations are as such aimed at the evaluation of art qua art, that is, not art as an investment, as a social symbol and so on, but at establishing the value of art as art’ (: ). Painted on a very large oak panel, the weight of a Tintoretto is a demerit from a transportation point of view, but that is hardly an artistic flaw, whereas a Rembrandt’s evoking compassion through its representation of its subject matter is an artistic merit. Deflationism implies that all and only values of a painting or story as art are values of the painting as a painting or of the story as literature. Is it true that value as a member of an art kind lines up in this way with value as art? Deflationism implies that artistic value is widespread. Artistic techniques like depiction and storytelling are used outside art. Pictures are used to illustrate anatomy for surgeons and stories are told in philosophy papers. So deflationism implies that the pictorial value of the surgeon’s anatomical atlas is an artistic value and that Bernard Williams’s essay ‘Against Utilitarianism’ has artistic merit realized through some compelling storytelling. However, these are welcome implications. We should expect to find artistic value outside art if the techniques of art are borrowed in non-art contexts. The trouble is that features that make a work a member of an art form or genre may well be features that realize prototypical 106 non-artistic values. A picture may have prurient value precisely because of what it enables us to see in it. It may have pecuniary value just for the precious metals, jewels, and pigments out of which it is made and in virtue of which it carries meaning (as in the medieval use of pigments ground from semiprecious lapis lazuli to depict the cloak of the Virgin Mary). Its scale may be a factor in its decorative value (as in airport art). Its depictively expressing certain thoughts may realize some propaganda or marketing value (as is alleged by psychoanalytic art critics). In each case, a value realized by pictorial means is a central case of a value that is not characteristically artistic. Deflationism crowns as artistic values many values in art that are prototypes of nonartistic value. Is there a bullet to bite? Critical practices are not sacrosanct; they are open to revision, especially in light of compelling theoretical considerations (Davies ). A deflationist might argue that the discovery that some prototypical non-artistic values are in fact artistic values argues for nothing more than a revision of the critical practices that determine what values are prototypically artistic and non-artistic. It is no objection to deflationism that it redraws the boundaries demarcating characteristically artistic values from values in art that are not artistic. However, deflationism implies more than some gerrymandering; it entirely erases the boundary between artistic value and mere value in art. What value in art is not, according to deflationism, an artistic value? What value is not realized in some work through some such means as depiction or storytelling? Without some principled way to distinguish some values as characteristically artistic, the deflationary theory collapses into the trivial theory of artistic value. The only bullet to bite is to accept the trivial theory and concede that there are many values in art, none characteristically artistic, except aesthetic value. There is nothing it is to have artistic value distinct from aesthetic value, stronger than mere value in art if artistic value just is the aggregate of pictorial value, musical value, and other such values. A Hybrid Approach 107 There is no artistic value that is stronger than value in art yet distinct from aesthetic value. This negative thesis suggests a positive lesson. The value of works of art is not exclusively aesthetic, and the many values in art include the values of art works as paintings, songs, and melodramas. Thus the aesthetic value of a work may be realized by features that make it a song or a melodrama. A hardy hybrid of deflationism gives due weight to aesthetic value. It identifies a work’s artistic value with its aesthetic value as a painting, song, melodrama, or the like. That is, V is an artistic value of a work = V is an aesthetic value of the work as a K, where K is an art form, genre, or other art kind. This theory has several advantages over pure deflationism and the trivial theory. It delivers a conception of artistic value stronger than mere value in art. It does not imply a conception of aesthetic value as realized in works typed as art, but only as typed more specifically. Therefore, unlike the trivial theory, it makes room for the pluralism debate room to play out, albeit within a somewhat different framework. The question is not whether cognitive and moral values in art works are artistic values but whether they interact in significant ways with aesthetic value (Lopes ). Incidentally, this framing of the pluralism debate is less radical than may appear if some parties to the debate implicitly operate with an aesthetic theory of artistic value (e.g. Gaut ). Finally, whereas deflationism and the trivial theory take the bite out of the argument from indiscernibles, the hybrid theory represents it as compelling. Appeals to an overarching notion artistic value recall the intense search, especially in the nineteenth century, for an equally overarching theory of aesthetic value as realized by any kind of art work (Schaeffer ). Both may be doomed for the same reason: they seek the value of works typed as art, when nothing has value typed as art. The remedy is to develop more specific theories of aesthetic value as realized by works of in the individual art forms (plus non-art artifacts and bits of nature). 108 What need have we for attributions of artistic value when we have characterized the values in a work, including its aesthetic value, and the values it realizes as a painting, as Baroque art, and as a still life? Why not explain apparent attributions of artistic value as attributions of other and more specific kinds of value? PART II Beyond Bricolage Some activities are arts and some are not. Among the arts we find music, poetry, and landscape architecture but not chess, philosophy, or mountain climbing. At the boundary lie some seemingly close pairs: dance but not ice dance, novels but not biographies, East Asian calligraphy but not paper making, mime but not clowning, sculpture but not body building, grand opera but not World Cup soccer, installations but not department store window displays. Following in the footsteps of early modern art theorists, who wanted to know what makes some activities arts (see Chapter ), Wollheim asked ‘why certain apparently arbitrarily identified stuffs or processes should be the vehicles of art’ ([], ). This he called the ‘bricoleur problem’. It probably has no satisfying theoretical answer. Two Options Beyond Art In the decades since Wollheim gave its name, the bricoleur problem has had little or no attention from philosophers. By , theories of art, fortified by Danto’s () and Mandelbaum’s () defences against anti-essentialism, had stolen the limelight. Recall that a theory of art states what it is for an item to be a work of art: x is a work of art = x is…. We would expect to find a solution to the bricoleur problem not in a theory of art but rather in a theory of the arts, which states what makes an activity an art form: K is an art = K is…. The hard cases set us in search of a theory of art by feeding into arguments which turn on the possibility that any given work of art may have an indiscernible twin that is not art. This hypothetical scenario concerns individual works, not entire art 110 forms. Moreover, having assumed that an art is an activity whose products are works of art, some might have expected to extract a theory of the arts from a theory of art. However, both reasons for putting the bricoleur problem on the back burner are compromised by the buck passing theory of art. The buck passing theory of art is a theory of art – it states what makes an item a work of art – but it is not directly informative. The theory is: x is a work of art = x is a work of K, where K is an art Taken on its own, the theory is uninformative at two levels in particular, and it passes the buck at two levels too. Starting at the surface, the right hand side of the theory does not seem to provide an analysis of an item’s being a work of art in terms that are more basic and perspicuous than those appearing on the left hand side. Thus the theory immediately raises two questions: what is an art? and what makes x a work of K? Answers to these questions are to be found in a theory of art and in theories of the individual arts. The latter comprise a set of theories, one for each art, each fitting the schema, x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is…. They will tell us what makes a work a painting, a song, or a performance of the chado. So far this buck passing is not especially deft. It simply balances the books: the right hand side of the theory is short on more basic and perspicuous terms and so they are borrowed from the theories to which the buck is passed. To be deft, passing the buck must be informative at a deeper level. We expect an informative theory of art to address certain needs (see the Introduction). It should contend with the hard cases. It should engineer some foundations for empirical art studies. It should anchor art criticism. Buck stopping theories of art meet these needs or, as a fall back, explain why they need not be met. The buck passing theory of art does neither, and in that sense it is uninformative. Yet it deftly passes the buck with the promise that 111 each of these needs can be met by the theories to which it passes the buck. Part I outlined how passing the buck promises to pay off with respect to each of these needs. Chapter argued that buck stopping theories of art cannot contend with the hard cases because they represent an impasse over them. The buck passing theory of art proposes that a theory of art or theories of the arts can effectively attend to the hard cases. Chapter adds that the hard cases are better understood as putting pressure on the folk concept of the arts as a whole or on the folk concepts of the individual art forms than on any folk concept of an art work. Moreover, social scientific hypotheses do not implicate a concept of art that requires a buck stopping theory of art. Any heavy lifting that is done in empirical art studies falls to a concept of the arts or to concepts of the individual arts. Finally, Chapter argues that art criticism is not anchored in distinctive evaluations of works as works of art. It is anchored in aesthetic and other evaluations of them as belonging to more specific kinds of art. These conclusions admittedly have the look of promissory notes, and the case for the ultimate informativeness of the buck passing theory of art must wait upon the notes’ being paid off. Payment in full requires not merely a theory of the arts or a framework for theories of the individual arts. These must be shown to address the needs that sent us looking for a theory of art. The bricoleur problem has been sitting for some time on the back burner; the buck passing theory of art compels us to ask whether it can stay there. It cannot as long as we need an informative theory of the arts and as long as an informative theory of the arts is one that solves the bricoleur problem. The next two sections argue that the prospects for a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem are grim. It will follow that if the problem stays on the back burner, then it is only because a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem is not needed. Theories of the individual arts can address the explanatory needs that buck stopping theories of art undertook to serve. 112 Theories of the Arts and the Bricoleur Problem Wollheim’s bricoleur problem colourfully expresses what sparked interest in developing a theory of the arts during the early modern period. Historians like Kristeller (–) and Shiner () have documented a lengthy and gradual reconceptualization of human activities that was finalized in the mid-eighteenth century. For the first time, a group of activities, with painting, sculpture, architecture, music, and poetry at its core (and several others towards its periphery), were seen as species of a genus to be sharply distinguished from activities belonging to other newlyformed genera – the sciences, the applied sciences, the crafts, and the liberal arts or humanities (see Chapter ). This reorganization was not unreflective; it came about partly as a result of a search for a theory of the arts, a statement of some features that unify the arts and distinguish them from non-art activities. Batteux () is credited with formulating the first such theory, and it was a success in so far as it fixed the extension of the arts as the common ground over which subsequent theories were to contend. But although the genus of the arts was now well established, no theory of the arts ultimately proved satisfactory. Indeed, the obstacles to a theory are probably greater now than they were in the eighteenth century. The glaring new development is the hard cases, which scotch any hope of deriving a theory of the arts from a theory of art. As we saw in Chapter , this derivation depends on the bridging assumption that an art is an activity whose products are works of art. Given a theory stating what features make paintings and songs works of art, we can say that an art is an activity outputting works with the features in question. Unfortunately, however, the dispute between traditional and genetic conceptions of the features in question has stalled at an impasse (see Chapter ). Consequently, a theory of the arts should be formulated independent of a theory of art: such is the advice of the buck passing theory of art. It does not follow that a theory of the arts must be cut from entirely new cloth. A traditional theory of the arts that echoes a traditional theory of art will take what makes an activity an art to 113 always include some exhibited features. For example, it might propose that an art is an activity which serves an aesthetic function. Notice that it need not imply that every product of the activity serving this aesthetic function has the same exhibited feature – it need not endorse the bridging assumption. Thus it need take no stand on the hard cases. By the same token, a genetic theory of the arts that echoes a genetic theory of art might propose, for example, that an art is an informal institution of a certain kind. If it does not imply the bridging assumption, then it does not imply that what makes every item a work of art is its institutional genesis. It also stands neutral on the hard cases. As a matter of fact, Dickie () pairs his institutional theory of art with an institutional theory of the arts. A work of art is ‘an artifact of a kind created to be presented to an artworld public’ by an artist – that is, ‘a person who participates with understanding in the making of a work of art’ (Dickie , ). The idea is that the act of making a work of art is partly constituted by the fact that it is made by someone playing the role of artist for others playing the role of audience. Making art is not like kissing: whereas the behaviour involved in kissing is kissing no matter who does it, the behaviours involved in making art works are not making art works unless they are done by and for individuals playing roles within the art world. That is Dickie’s considered statement of the institutional theory of art. Appended to it is the proposition that the art world is made up of several ‘art world systems‘ – that is, the individual arts (Dickie , ; see also Dickie , ). In other words, each art features its own artist and audience roles as well as its own supplementary roles (Dickie , ). Strictly speaking, the role of artist is a role type which is played by painters, set designers, choreographers, among others, and the role of audience is a role type played by those who ‘participate with understanding’ in each of the arts. The institutional theory of the arts is this: an art is a practice in which artists (persons who participate with understanding in the making of works of art) make works of art to be presented to an art world public. There are several such practices. What makes them arts is that they instantiate this institutional structure. 114 Consider one of the closely matched pairs that traverse the boundary between the arts and non-art activities: ballet and ice dance. Suppose that ballet is an art but ice dance is not. According to the institutional theory of the arts just sketched, what makes ballet an art is that it is an art world system wherein certain individuals play the role of artist by participating with understanding in the making of ballets to be presented to those playing the role of ballet audience. Although ice dances are made by choreographers, dancers, costume designers, and lighting designers whose behaviours are intrinsically similar to those playing the artist role in dance, these individuals do not play the artist role. That is why ice dance is not an art. Notice that this theory of the arts does not solve the bricoleur problem – except perhaps by rejecting it. The bricoleur problem is to identify a difference between the ‘stuffs or processes’ of ballet and ice dance to explain why the former and not the latter has been invested with institutional trappings of an art world system. Dickie () acknowledges what is implicit in the comparison of ballet with ice dance, namely that there are many ‘systems’ for making and presenting artifacts that are not art world systems, though they are very similar in their intrinsic character to art world systems. Dickie weighs the proposal that the art world comprises a ‘limited number of protosystems plus any other systems which developed historically from these in a certain manner’ (, –). He rejects this proposal as postponing the problem: we will want to know why the protosystems count as art. No doubt we will also want to know how to understand in what ‘manner’ an art world system can develop historically from a protosystem, since non-arts can develop historically from arts. In the end, Dickie bites the bullet: it is arbitrary what activities are art world systems. There is no deeper explanation of what makes ballet an art than the fact that it has in fact acquired the right institutional structure (, –). This is not an objection to the institutional theory of the arts. A theory of the arts is not obliged to answer the bricoleur problem if that problem has no solution. The institutional theory of the arts implies that it has no solution. 115 In a fresh approach to theories of art and the arts, Iseminger () marries an institutional theory of the art world to the claim that the art world serves an aesthetic function. First, following Dickie, Iseminger holds that the art world is an informal institution or practice in which people play certain roles and engage in various activities that are partly constituted by those roles (Iseminger , –). Iseminger does not explicitly follow Dickie in taking the art world to be a type of practice that is instanced through the more specific practices of each of the arts. However, since he gives no reason against an institutional theory of the arts, his framework is easily enhanced to include the theory that an art is an art world system – an activity with the institutional structure of the art world. Second, following Beardsley, Iseminger wishes to acknowledge an important connection between art and the aesthetic. He argues that, (F) the function of the art world is to promote aesthetic communication. This is a contingent fact about the art world and so is not part of what makes some practices art world practices. An art world practice may persist as such although it has ceased to promote aesthetic communication (Iseminger , ). Presumably the same goes for each of the arts, which contingently have the function of promoting aesthetic communication. This summarizes only some of Iseminger’s discussion. He fashions a theory of art to fit his theory of the art world (though it does not evade the impasse – see Lopes c). Given some additional assumptions, this theory of art delivers an aesthetic theory of artistic value. Moreover, to round things off, he crafts an original and powerful theory of aesthetic appreciation (see Chapter ). For present purposes, however, (F) is enough. It suggests the following: (F*) the function of an art is to promote aesthetic communication. This is not a theory of the arts since it is at best a contingent fact about them, but perhaps it solves the bricoleur problem? 116 Seeing what this suggestion comes to requires an examination of the arguments for (F) and (F*), and that calls in turn for accounts of ‘function’ and ‘aesthetic communication’. These should be read reasonably broadly. ‘Aesthetic communication’ is bringing about states of affairs with the intention that they be objects of aesthetic appreciation (, ). As already noted, Iseminger plugs into this a powerful and original theory of aesthetic appreciation. Set that aside for the sake of breadth. After all, we usually know aesthetic appreciation when we see it even if we cannot define it. That leaves ‘function’, and there are a several theories of function to choose from, though all agree that the attribution of a function to an item is supposed to explain some of its features. The attribution of a ‘systemic function’ to an item describes the contribution the item makes to maintaining a capacity of a system to which it belongs (Cummins ). For example, the heart has the systemic function of pumping blood because pumping blood is its contribution to the organism’s capacity to respirate. Marx famously attributed a systemic function to art when he claimed that it expresses and reinforces certain interests within the economic base of a society. The attribution of an ‘etiological function’ to an item specifies what the item does that caused it to be selected for in the past (e.g. Millikan ). For example, pumping is blood is what hearts do that caused them to be favoured by natural selection. Glenn Parsons and Allen Carlson apply etiological functions to artifacts: an artifact has an etiological function, F, just in case the artifact is currently manufactured and distributed because its recent ancestors performed F, thereby causing their success in the marketplace (, ). According to Iseminger, if something is good at doing that it was designed and made to do, then doing that is its ‘artifactual function’ (, ; see also Tolhurst ). Most artifacts are designed to perform several functions, and these functions often nest: when an item does F by doing G, then its doing F is nested in its doing G. The artifactual function of an item is a non-nested function. Iseminger argues that the art world’s non-nested artifactual function is to promote aesthetic communication. 117 History shows that the art world was designed and made to promote aesthetic communication. Citing Kristeller (–), Iseminger observes that the eighteenth century saw the formation of the modern system of the arts, wherein ‘painters, poets, and composers were eventually largely persuaded to see themselves as engaged in different branches of the same business’ (, ). The writings of Batteux () and others express the common understanding of those engaged in it that mission of this business was to be the promotion of aesthetic communication. Iseminger adds that the art world is good at promoting aesthetic communication. It is better at promotion aesthetic communication than any of the competition (Iseminger , -). Government and business are barely contenders; religion, political activity, and advertising have had their moments but they are unreliable as mechanisms for aesthetic communication; and practices of nature appreciation lack the versatility and range of the arts as sources of aesthetic appreciation. In addition, the art world is better at promoting aesthetic communication than anything else it does (Iseminger , –). For example, it is not a dependable route to wealth, power, or social status, and it does not perform well as a sphere for religion, politics, or philosophy. These are delicate empirical observations. Just as delicate would be the kinds of observations that would warrant the conclusion that promoting aesthetic communication is the art world’s etiological function. Even granted that the art world does in fact promote aesthetic communication, the question remains whether this is responsible for its continued existence over the centuries. Parsons and Carlson sensibly remark that ‘given the variation in art and art practices over time and in different cultures and groups, it seems likely that different kinds of artworks have survived for quite different kinds of reasons’ (, ). The delicacy of these operations is a challenge for anyone who seeks to show that promoting aesthetic communication is a contingent function of the art world. The challenge for those who seek a solution to the bricoleur problem is somewhat different. The suggestion is that an activity is fit to be an art world system 118 just in case it has the function of promoting aesthetic communication. The problem with this suggestion is that if the arts have this function then so do many activities that are not arts. Aesthetic communication is practically ubiquitous. As Iseminger admits, a case can be made that industrial design, cooking, and gardening have the function of promoting aesthetic communication (, -, ). Most consumer products are created in partly with an eye to their aesthetic impact: automobiles, bicycles, laptop computers, stovetops, kitchenware, clocks, pens, children’s toys… the list is very long. The function of these items to promote aesthetic communication is non-nested, at least in two obvious respects. An item’s doing F is nested only if it does F by doing G. Obviously consumer items function to generate a profit, but they do not function to promote aesthetic communication by functioning to generate a profit. The same goes for such ‘utilitarian’ functions as transportation, surfing the web, cooking, tracking the time, signing cheques, and entertaining: it is not only by performing these functions that consumer products promote aesthetic communication. The problem cannot be pinned on the artifactual conception of function. If artistic practices survive because of their aesthetic function, so do any design practices. If artistic practices contribute to a larger aesthetic system, so do any design practices. Remember the paired activities listed at the beginning of the chapter: dance and ice dance, novels and biographies, East Asian calligraphy and paper making, mime and clowning, sculpture and body building, grand opera and World Cup soccer, installations and department store window displays. It is hard to believe that an empirical case can be made that only the first member of each pair has the artifactual, etiological, or systemic function of promoting aesthetic communication. The prospects for a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem do not look rosy. Concept and Contestation Theories of art are driven by the challenge posed by the hard cases. Maybe the search for a theory of the arts is driven not only by the initial formation of the modern system of the arts but also 119 by revisions to that system since the eighteenth century, especially during the past few decades. The eighteenth century core – painting, sculpture, architecture, music, and poetry – has expanded enormously. The novel is an early addition and recent contenders include photography, the movies, earthworks, installation art, happenings, computer art, jazz, popular music, video games, and comic books. The admission of every one of these activities (including the novel) into the arts club was controversial. One might think that a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem is implicit in adjudicating these controversies. Chapter distinguished between a theory of art, which states what makes any item a work of art, and an explication of the workings of the folk concept of art, which pinpoints the features by means of which we recognize works of art. Having the concept need not consist in knowing the theory. Likewise, a theory of the arts is one thing and a concept of the arts is another. A concept of the arts figures in reasoning about and reliably detecting activities that are arts, but it need not consists in knowing a theory of the arts. Thinkers might in fact exercise a concept of the arts even if there is no true, non-trivial theory of the arts. What might be implicit in the initial formation of the modern system of the arts and in its subsequent reformations is a concept of the arts. That concept was expressed by Batteux () in the form of a theory, but that theory was soon shown to be inadequate, without perturbing the concept or its remarkably rapid promulgation among the folk. Still, the modern system of the arts has been updated over the years. Activities not previously recognized as arts were tested and found to be arts. How was this test carried out? It may seem that in the answer lies an explication of the concept of the arts. It may also seem that in this explication lies a solution to the bricoleur problem. Wollheim divided potential solutions to the bricoleur problem into two kinds: one may say why certain ‘stuffs or processes’ are the vehicles of art either when there are no arts or when ‘certain arts are already going concerns’ ([], ). Only the latter is part of a ‘serious or interesting inquiry’; it is ‘determined by the analogies and disanalogies that we can 120 construct between the existing arts and the art in question’ ([], ). Therefore, the idea might be that the analogies and disanalogies express a concept of the arts. Here, in other words, is a methodology for investigating the concept of the arts. Examine the details of the debates about the admission of new activities into the domain of the arts. These debates have been and are being settled. If they are being settled in a principled way, then it is by appeal to features that we take to be reliable indicators that an activity is an art. Maybe they are the very features that make an activity an art. At the least we get a description of the concept of art and perhaps we get a theory of the arts. There is reason to think the plan too optimistic: it assumes that the analogies and disanalogies that push us towards or away from acknowledging a new art form are global rather than local. Global analogies are features which the activity under scrutiny shares with all other arts and global disanalogies are features its shares with no other arts. Local analogies are features it may share with some other arts, local disanalogies being features it does not share with some other arts. Only global analogies and disanalogies express a concept of the arts. If disputes about the art status of certain activities revolve only around local analogies and disanalogies, then they are not a good source from which to extract a picture of the concept of the arts. The activities whose status as arts has received by far the deepest and most sustained treatment are photography and the movies. By far the most compelling case against their art status is mounted by Roger Scruton (). Scruton’s top-level argument is this: . cinema is an independent art form only if it is a representational art, . cinema is a representational art only if photography is a representational art, and . photography is not a representational art, . so cinema is not an independent art form. 121 The conclusion of this argument allows that cinema is recorded theatre, yet not an art form in its own right. A corollary of the argument is that photography is not an independent art form either, given a variant on (), namely that photography is an independent art form only if it is a representational art. Premise () expresses the thought that movies could be an art in their own right only by exploiting the technology of photography. Thus the key premise is () and Scruton floats several arguments for it, which have been targeted by those who wish to defend the art status of photography and cinema (esp. Lopes , Abell , Gaut ). For present purposes, note that the argument – and premise () in particular – does not implicate a theory or concept of the arts in general. It appeals instead to a narrower conception of the representational arts, one which nobody would think to use to revoke the artistic credentials of architecture, abstract sculpture, or pure music. Moreover, nobody who rejects Scruton’s skepticism about movies and photography would think to defend their art status by likening them to architecture, abstract sculpture, or pure music. The narrower the basis for coming to a decision about a candidate art form, the more secure the decision. We should expect to see disputes about earthworks, installation art, and happenings focus on their analogies and disanalogies to a small number of established arts. The relevant analogies are not likely to connect them to poetry and music, for example. The point is even clearer when it comes to the recognition of art forms considered ‘low brow’. It is enough to tie jazz and popular music to serious classical music and to tie comic books to other narrative and pictorial arts. Video games are an interesting case: their art status is often established by stressing their connections to cinema (Tavinor , Gaut ) but they can also be viewed as the popular counterpart of avant-garde computer art (Lopes b). Reasoning inductively, the more we find that disputes about the art status of various activities appeal to analogies and disanalogies that hold only among subsets of the arts, the less reason we have to believe that a concept of the arts can be extracted from these disputes. Indeed, this was Kristeller’s assessment, that ‘the system of the fine arts is hardly more than a 122 postulate and most of its theories are abstracted from particular arts, usually poetry, and more or less inapplicable to the others’ (–, ). Beyond the Arts It is time to stop and take stock. There is hope for a viable theory of the arts – Dickie’s institutional theory of the arts is one example. However, the prospects for a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem are dim. Moreover, the evidence is that our working concept of the arts does not rely on a solution to the bricoleur problem either. After all is said and done, the arts might truly result from bricolage, wherein a choice of materials is largely accidental and depends on what happens to lie close at hand. What follows is that the prospects for an informative theory of the arts are thin if an informative theory of the arts is one that solves the bricoleur problem. It would be nice, then, to leave the search for a theory of the arts on the back burner. That remains an option so long as theories of the individual arts are informative. Pursuing this option frees us to be agnostic about any theory of the arts. Can theories of the individual arts take over the explanatory tasks that buck stopping theories of art have been expected to serve? Can they come to grips with the hard cases? Do they supply the conceptual foundations of empirical art studies? Do they anchor practices of art criticism? These are questions for the next four chapters. They are put on the agenda not only by the buck passing theory of art but also in recognition of the dismal prospects of a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem. At the same time, these dismal prospects suggest an opportunity from which theories of the individual arts may profit. Without denying that there is a distinction between the arts and non-arts, reason recommends keeping an open mind about whether that distinction tracks a solution to the bricoleur problem. That is, there may be no informative, general answer to the question why certain apparently arbitrarily identified stuffs or processes should be the vehicles of art. To repeat, this agnosticism does not entail skepticism about the boundary between the arts 123 and the non-arts. It more modestly warrants proceeding on the assumption that, as we gird our loins to devise theories of the individual arts, there may be something to learn about those nonarts that, like the arts, also engage us in appreciation. Maybe there is something to learn about dance from ice dance, novels from biographies, East Asian calligraphy from paper making, mime from clowning, sculpture from body building, grand opera from World Cup soccer, and installations from department store window displays. The class of appreciative kinds extends far beyond the arts. Design, interior decoration, food, wine, clothing and personal adornment, quilts, television, dog breeding, circuses, games, sports: it is hard to know what to exclude. Noting the heterogeneity of the arts themselves, Zangwill recommends that we try to understand them alongside ‘everyday creative activities such as industrial design, advertising, weaving, whistling, cake decorating, arranging and decorating rooms, religious rituals, and fireworks displays’ (, ; see also Walton ). Zangwill’s proposal seems a worthy heuristic. An objection to this heuristic is dampened by keeping in mind the need for agnosticism about a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem. The objection is that the heuristic blurs the boundary between the arts and non-arts so as to distort our understanding of appreciation outside the realm of the arts. The objection is worth worrying about. Whatever the epistemic contours of the concept of the arts – whatever we take to be the reliable indicators that an activity is an art – there is no question that the concept’s application has an honorific impact. Calling an activity an art singles it out as somehow important, serious, especially worthy of attention. As a result, it can be tempting to smuggle into the arts those activities that are deemed important, serious, and worthy of attention. For example, Kevin Melchionne convincingly argues that interior design aims to ‘create an environment that facilitates domestic practice while at the same time making the environment worthy of aesthetic attention and admiration’ (, ). The ‘domestic practice’ that can be made worthy of attention and admiration is the routine stuff of everyday life in a space – cooking, cleaning, playing, 124 reading, sleeping, and the like. Interior design can ‘refine and intensify experiences already available to us in everyday life’ (Melchionne , ). So far, so good, but Melchionne goes a step further, characterizing ‘the ordinary process of inhabiting our homes’ as an artistic practice, an ‘art of domesticity’ that is practiced on a daily basis (, ). Melchionne might be right about an art of domesticity: the task at hand is not to decide what activities to list alongside poetry and dance as arts. Rather, the issue is the wisdom of the methodological heuristic of studying the arts as appreciative kinds alongside appreciative kinds that are not arts. In Everyday Aesthetics Yuriko Saito () describes our understanding of the appreciation of non-art as dominated by an ‘art-centred aesthetics’. Not much weight falls on the ‘aesthetic’, which Saito defines as ‘any reactions we form toward the sensuous and/or design qualities of any object, phenomenon, or activity’ (, ???) – that is as much of a placeholder as ‘appreciation’. As Saito observes, aesthetic appreciation pervades everyday life: most of us attend to our personal appearance almost daily: choosing what to wear and what sort of haircut to get, cleaning and ironing clothes, and deciding whether or not to dye our hair or try some kind of ‘aesthetic rejuvenation’ treatment or body decoration. These decisions and actions are primarily, if not exclusively, guided by aesthetic considerations (, ???). Nor do we check these considerations at the boundary of the personal: as citizens, we find ourselves forming opinions on societal debates primarily based upon aesthetic reasoning. Examples range from supporting the rehabilitation of a brownfield, criticizing the design of a proposed building, opposing the construction of a wind farm or a cell phone tower, to condemning graffiti while welcoming a mural and objecting to the appearance and location of a billboard (Saito , ???). 125 Once the everyday appears on the philosopher’s radar as a target of appreciation, it tends to be viewed in relation to art. Fretting about how the arts differ from the non-arts is matched, once some feature of everyday life is recognized as a target of appreciation, by fretting over whether or it is art. Saito argues that the art-centred approach distorts our understanding of everyday appreciation. No surprise: the argument calls on twins cases. A paradigm example of everyday appreciation is cooking and eating food, but Rirkrit Tiravanija’s artistic practice famously includes creates gallery installations made up of nothing more than his cooking food to be eaten by gallery visitors. The appreciation involved in eating curry at home and eating curry cooked by Tiravanija in a gallery in the West Village are not the same. What Tiravanija does makes the everyday into something extraordinary. Therefore, to understand our appreciation of the everyday in its own terms, it is essential to resist ‘making the ordinary extraordinary and rendering the familiar strange’ (Saito , ???). The lesson is that while one earns a bit of stature for food by advancing it as an art form, the endeavor is apt to divert attention from the interesting ways in which the aesthetic importance of foods diverges from parallel values in art… the fact that these features count against something being an art object does not mean that they are aesthetically uninteresting, insignificant, or irrelevant (Saito , ???). An art-centred approach to appreciation is partial and incomplete. Not having a solution to the bricoleur problem does not erase the boundary between the arts and the non-arts. Following Dickie, one might deny that a theory of the arts should even attempt to solve the bricoleur problem. This fact should serve as a reminder to heed Saito’s warning. It is one thing to view the arts as kin to appreciative kinds that are not arts and it is another to treat nonarts as arts. Without a theory of the arts that solves the bricoleur problem, the attempt to artify non-art is a dubious proposition. Unfortunately, Saito plays into this herself by listing some characteristics of the arts, leaving it open to others to defend an 126 art-centred approach to appreciation by objecting that the list fails to police the boundary separating art from non-art (Dowling ). Agnosticism requires an open mind about similarities and differences across the boundary. A final note. The arts are activities that involve the intentional production of artifacts and events by human agents, and so are many non-art appreciative kinds. However, some non-art appreciative kinds do not involve the intentional production of artifacts and events by human agents. Why not view the arts as appreciative kinds of this widest sort? There has been intensive study of natural objects, events, and settings as targets of appreciation (see Parsons ). Other targets of appreciation include bodily events like ‘being in the room you are in right now, with its particular visual features and sounds; sitting the way that you are sitting, perhaps crookedly in an uncomfortable chair; feeling the air currents on your skin’ (Irvin a, see also Irvin b). The point is not that these stuffs and processes are vehicles for art; like each art, they afford appreciation each in their own way. The buck passing theory of art sends in search of an informative theory of the arts or informative theories of the individual arts. The prospects do not seem good for a theory of the arts that illuminates what we care about. It is time to see what can be learned by developing a framework for theories of the individual arts as appreciative kinds. Appreciative Kinds and Media Theories are useful in so far as they give us some insight into phenomena that we care about, and the buck passing theory of art is indirectly informative, referring us to theories of the individual arts for the insight we seek. A theory of art is hardly a prerequisite for getting on with work on the individual arts and indeed philosophers have proposed partial or complete theories of painting (e.g. Wollheim 1987, Lopes 2005), movies (e.g. Carroll 1996a, Gaut 2010) music (e.g. Levinson 1990), dance (e.g. Beardsley 1982), theatre (e.g. Hamilton 2007), poetry (e.g. Ribeiro 2007), and literature (e.g. Lamarque and Olsen 1994, Stecker 1996). Success in these endeavours may seem to be enough to clinch the case for the buck passing theory of art. However, truth be told, theorizing about the individual arts has often proceeded with a buck stopping theory of art in the background. Absent such a theory, it is fair to ask what is the framework within which theories of the individual arts are to be developed. Ultimately, such a framework should indicate how these theories can be informative in a way that satisfies the demands traditionally placed on theories of art. Framework The great advantage of the buck passing theory of art for those who are interested in theories of the individual arts is that it does not require them to be uniform. That is also its great challenge. Each art is different from its sister arts. This datum is represented in the fact that the schema for theories of the individual arts, x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is… is to be completed differently for every art. A theorist of music, for example, need not be looking over her shoulder at theories of painting or poetry. Yet, as nobody denies, if an item is a work in an art form then it is a work of art. More strongly still, what makes an item a work of 128 art and what makes an item a painting, song, or dance number are not unrelated. A dance number is a work of art partly in virtue of facts that make it a dance number, and what makes a song a piece of music factors into what makes it a work of art. Given the stronger claim, if a buck stopping theory of art says that, 1. x is a work of art = x is F and if a theory of an art says that, 2. x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is G then it follows that, 3. x is a work of K = x is G and x’s being G is part of what makes it F. This result quite considerably constrains the theory of any art form, by ruling out many theories of the art. The buck passing theory of art does not imply (3). The buck passing theory is that, x is a work of art = x is a work of K, where K is an art. This proposition conjoined with (2) delivers a variant on (3) that is identical to (2), namely, 3*. x is a work of K = x is G and x’s being G is part of what makes it a work of K. The second half of the conjunction in (3*) is otiose and its elimination results in (2). The practical upshot is that the specific features of each art form – the ones in virtue of which it differs from its sister arts – need not be represented in a theory of that art as realizing a feature it shares in common with its sister arts. There are plenty of similarities among the arts, but these similarities need not be built into what makes each art the art that it is. That is an advantage of the buck passing theory of art for theorizing about the individual arts. 129 Is this silver lining on a cloud under which we must now labour? Presumably the point of developing theories of the arts was to understand how items in those arts came to be works of art by exploiting the specific features of each art. Thus a theory of music was expected to say what makes songs by Henry Purcell and Leonard Cohen works of musical art, as a theory of photography was to bring out what makes the productions of Diane Arbus and Jeff Wall works of specifically photographic art. According to the buck passing theory of art, this cannot be the point of theories of the individual arts. But unless we have some idea of what tasks we expect theories of the arts to perform, how can we devise theories the truth of which we can measure? To see the force of the question, consider a version of Weitz’s (1956) ‘open concept’ argument adapted to the individual arts. In fact, as Meskin (2008) acutely observes, Weitz himself endorses the adaptation when he asserts that ‘every sub-concept of art’ – from the novel to painting – is an open concept (1956: 32). Chapter 2 interpreted Weitz as giving two arguments from the claim that art is an open concept to the conclusion that there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of art. The first argument, the creativity argument, is either unsound or circular, and there is reason to think that the second argument also begs the question (see Chapter 2 for details). However, the second argument has a methodological dimension that is useful in thinking about the question above. The argument contrasts concepts which are either ‘empiricallydescriptive’ or ‘normative’, on one hand, and concepts that, on the other hand, are closed by stipulation ‘for a special purpose’ (Weitz 1956, 32). Adapting the argument to painting, for example: . if painting is an open concept then there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of painting, and . if the application of concept of painting calls for a decision on our part, then it is open, and . the concept of painting is empirically-descriptive or normative only if the application of the concept of art calls for a decision on our part, but 130 . the concept of painting is empirically-descriptive or normative, . so there is no correct, complete, non-trivial theory of painting. Premise (4) implies that painting is not closed by stipulation for a special purpose: any attempt to close the concept by stipulation fails to elucidate ‘the actual employment of the concept… the conditions under which we correctly use it or its correlates’ (Weitz 1956, 30). Meskin (2008) attributes a normative flavour to Weitz’s argument: we should not close the concept of painting if doing so leaves a remainder, excluding some uses of the concept of painting. Setting aside any structural difficulties (see Chapter 2), the argument embeds a methodological assumption, namely that a theory of painting must elucidate the concept of painting in its many and diverse uses. It must be extracted from our classificatory practices, which are highly variegated. The method is analysis of the folk concept of painting. Given this method and the disorderly folk use of art form concepts, it is perfectly sensible to doubt that correct, complete, non-trivial theories of many, if not all, of the arts lie over the horizon. This methodology is not the only option. Theories must be informative, but their informativeness need not come from elucidating folk concepts. One might reasonably suspect that only history, sociology, and psychology can make much progress with such a task. Instead, theories of the arts, like theories of art, might be informative, firstly, in so far as they ground art form concepts employed in scientific studies of the arts and, secondly, in so far as they ground evaluations of works as belonging to the arts. There are hypotheses about painting, music, and poetry that are generated in art history, musicology, and literary studies, but also the psychology and anthropology of visual art, music, and verse. Theories of painting, music, or poetry might be closed for the ‘special purpose’ of integrating and elucidating these technical concepts. This is one way for philosophy of art to contribute to empirical inquiry (Bergeron and Lopes 2011). Its contributions are bound to be piecemeal, since art studies are themselves piecemeal 131 (musicologists are not anthropologists of dance even if they sometimes pool what they know). The rest of this chapter sets out a framework for developing theories of the arts as categories which figure in the appreciation of works of art, where appreciation is a cognitive process involving the ascription of value, typically as a result of classification and interpretation. In this framework, art forms are appreciative kinds, and the notion of an appreciative kind is the framing device that replaces the concept of art. As we learned in Chapter 6, the arts make up a small subset of the appreciative kinds. Note that this last point about the domain of appreciative kinds combines with the methodological point that the task is not to analyze folk concepts – indeed, theories of appreciative kinds may not line up perfectly with folk concepts. Theories of the individual arts might not, in particular, follow the (vague and disorderly) boundaries marked by the folk concepts of painting or dance, for example. Those folk concepts may not track our actual appreciative practices, and appreciative practices are always open to correction. Reverse Engineering Judith Jarvis Thomson’s Normativity (2008, 19–33) draws a set of distinctions that are implicit in some discussions of art appreciation (e.g. Lopes 2005, 2008b). None of them are at all controversial, nor do they imply any of the theses in Thomson’s book that have drawn heavy fire. They may be taken as fundamental. Without them, it is easy to miss what we are looking for in an account of appreciative kinds. First, some evaluations are made true by the fact that an item is good as a K or for a K or, in Thomson’s official jargon, qua K. For example, being good qua toaster consists in toasting well, being good qua seeing eye dog consists in serving well in assisting disabled people to navigate their environment, being good qua tennis player consists in playing tennis well. The kinds toaster, seeing eye dog, and tennis player are what Thomson calls ‘goodness-fixing kinds’. By stipulation, a kind is a goodness-fixing 132 kind just in case what it is for an item to be a K sets the standard that a K has to meet if it is to be good qua K. Toasters, seeing eye dogs, and tennis players are functional kinds in the sense that what it is to be a member of the kind is to have a certain function. Thus to be good qua member of the relevant kind is to perform that function well. A goodness-fixing kind need not be a functional kind. Thomson’s example is beefsteak tomatoes. They do not make up a functional kind, for ‘there is nothing they do about which it could be asked whether or not they do it well’, yet tomatoes that are ‘large at maturity while nevertheless tasting good’ are good qua beefsteak tomatoes (Thomson 2008, 20). Other goodness-fixing kinds that are not functional kinds are the kinds tiger and human being. As these examples indicate, goodness need not be fixed in a goodness-fixing kind by a function performed by members of the kind. Not all kinds are goodness-fixing kinds. A pebble is a small stone smoothed by erosion, but that does not fix any standard that a pebble has to meet to be good qua pebble, so there is nothing it is for an item to be good qua pebble. A pebble may be good in some respect or other, but not qua pebble. Thomson argues that acts, events, and facts are not goodness-fixing kinds. Chapter 5 concluded that there is nothing is it for an item to be good as art. Restating that conclusion, art is not a goodness-fixing kind. Second, not all goodness is fixed by a goodness-fixing kind: the goodness of an item need not consist in its meeting a standard fixed by a kind. Some of Thomson’s examples: being good for England, being good to use in teaching elementary logic, being good to look at, being good with children (2008, 27). These are instances of ‘being good-modified’. Since acts are not a goodnessfixing kind, morally good acts are not acts that are good qua acts. Instead, ‘morally good’ is a good-modifier (Thomson 2008, 80). Another good-modifier is ‘aesthetically good’. There is no kind such that what it is to be a member of that kind fixes what it is to be aesthetically good. Third, an item might be good-modified for a K. This is not the same as the compound property of being good-modified and a K. Someone might be good to look at and also an athlete, whereas to 133 be good to look at for an athlete is to be good to look at, adjusting for how good athletes are to look at. Likewise, a six-year-old boy might be good at doing crossword puzzles. He would be a crossword prodigy. However, his being good at doing crossword puzzles for a six-year-old child does imply that he is a prodigy – he might not even be as good at doing crosswords as someone who is good at doing crosswords for a New Yorker. To take an example from the arts, a work might be a thriller movie and it might be gripping without being gripping for a thriller movie. Finally, an item might be a good K for a K*, where K is a goodness-fixing kind but K* is not. An Apple II might be a good computer for a computer made in 1980, a movie might be a good thriller for a Hitchcock movie, and a boy might be a good composer for a six-year-old child. Again, these are not compound properties like those of being a good computer and being made in 1980 (not just a classic of its era), being a good thriller and being made by Hitchcock (maybe not his best stuff), or being a good composer and being a six-year-old child (a prodigy). In sum, Thomson distinguishes four ways in which an item may be good in some respect: being good qua K, being goodmodified, being good modified for a K, and being good qua K for a K*. This list fleshes out but is not entailed by the disputed thesis that nothing is good except in some respect. Needless to say, the examples are just examples and quibbles about their classification as examples of one case rather than another do nothing to disturb these distinctions. The task at hand is to sketch a framework for arriving at theories of the art forms, each one filling in the schema, x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is…. The idea is to take that schema as a special case of the more generic schema, x is a K, where K is an appreciative kind = x is…. With that in mind, how do Thomson’s distinctions bring us closer to a framework for theories of appreciative kinds, including the arts? 134 In most cases, our understanding of what it is for an item to be a K keeps pace with our understanding of how to evaluate the item in a way that is sensitive to its being a K. That is certainly true of the kinds tennis player, toaster, six-year-old child, and composer. The fact that someone does not know how to evaluate an item as a toaster counts as strong evidence against their knowing what a toaster is. Someone’s not knowing how to adjust for the fact that a logic proof is done by a six-year-old child is strong evidence against their knowing what it is to be a six-yearold child. Many cases that provoke serious inquiry are not like this. In these cases, our understanding of what it is for an item to be a K significantly lags our understanding of how to evaluate the item in a way that is sensitive to its being a K. (Again, having a concept does not require knowing a theory.) The arts are paradigm examples of this. Anyone who listens to music is fairly well skilled at judging it, though few can even being to say what it is for an item to be a work of music. That is why books like Daniel Levitin’s This Is Your Brain on Music (2006) are so peculiarly instructive: they dispel mysteries that cloud over the most familiar phenomena. Homo sapiens is first of all Homo valorens. This fact is a convenient methodological toe hold. So long as our evaluations of items in appreciative kinds are reliable, they are a source from which to extract the nature of the kinds in question. Stipulate that, K is an appreciative kind if and only if is there is a property of being good qua K, or being good-modified for a K, or being good qua K* for a K. That is, in appreciative kinds, K, what it is to be a K fixes the standard for being a good K, or inflects what it is to be goodmodified for a K, or guides any adjustments for the fact that an item is a K when judging it against the standard for being good qua K*. We can reverse engineer from facts about appreciation of items in appreciative kinds to the nature of the kinds themselves. Doing so does not require that all appreciative kinds be goodness-fixing kinds. Nor does it require that the appreciative 135 kinds that are invariably goodness-fixing kinds be function kinds: some are obviously not. It sets aside for separate treatment what it is for an item to be aesthetically good, if ‘aesthetically good’ is a goodness-modifier. At the same time, it allows what it is to be a K to play a role in what makes it the case that an item is aesthetically good for a K. If art forms are appreciative kinds, then it allows for the hybrid theory of artistic value ventured at the end of Chapter 5. Beyond Media Bashing What it is for a work to belong to an art form is traditionally cashed out, at least in part, with reference to the art form’s characteristic medium. As Dickie put it, ‘making art has had at its center working with a medium. Learning to be an artist has meant learning to work in some medium or other – paint, stone, words, tones’ (1984, 61). However, most art theorists nowadays dissent, and Carroll (1985, 2003, 2008) is their leading philosophical champion, urging us to ‘forget the medium!’ Taking the dissenters’ concerns seriously steers us towards a moderate and viable conception of the role of media in the arts – a conception that some art scholars seek (e.g. Mitchell 2005, Smith 2006). The debate about medium is disorienting. It looks as if the players are not hitting the same ball over the same net. Those who wish to remember the medium ally themselves with Wollheim (1980[1968]) in his argument against a view that he had pinned on Croce (1922[1902]) and Collingwood (1938). Whether or not Croce and Collingwood actually endorsed the view, it was certainly in the air. For example, it is taken to task by Walter Pater in his essay on ‘The School of Giorgione’ as a, mistake of much popular criticism to regard poetry, music, and painting – all the various products of art – as but translations into different languages of one and the same fixed quantity of imaginative thought, supplemented by certain technical qualities of colour, in painting; of sound, in music; of rhythmical words in poetry. In this way, the sensuous element in art, and with it almost everything in art that is essentially artistic, is a matter of indifference (1877, 130). 136 According to the indifference thesis, the ‘technical qualities’ associated with art forms are not factors in the value of works in those art forms. No medium is an appreciative kind. Wollheim (1980[1968]) supplies the classic argument to the contrary. The imaginative activity that an artist engages in as she works is couched in a recognition of the possibilities and limitations of her medium. Thus what she achieves through her imaginative activity cannot be grasped without taking into account the ‘recalcitrance’ of the medium. In so far as the value of the work includes its value as an achievement in that medium, the medium is an appreciative kind. Media skeptics take on a purity doctrine which can be found in early modern writers (e.g. Lessing 1962[1766]) but which has far more influential backers among twentieth century art theorists, principally Clement Greenberg (1940, 1961) and Michael Fried (1967). Carroll chooses this passage from Greenberg as an example of the doctrine: a modernist work of art must try, in principle, to avoid dependence upon any order of experience not given in the most essentially construed nature of its medium. This means, among other things, renouncing illusion and explicitness. The arts are to achieve concreteness, ‘purity’, by acting solely in terms of their separate and irreducible selves (1961, 139). Although Greenberg speaks of ‘modernist’ art, Carroll treats this passage as meant to apply without restriction to any kind of art. (The criticisms of the doctrine found below do not touch upon its place in modernism.) What precisely does the doctrine say? There is no easy answer. Carroll expresses it in a dozen ways – here is a sample: [1] each art form should pursue those effects that, in virtue of its medium it alone – i.e., of all the arts – can achieve… [2] each art form should pursue ends that, in virtue of its medium, it achieves most effectively or best of all those effects at its disposal… [3] each art form should pursue only those effects 137 which, in virtue of its medium, it excels in achieving (1985, 6– 7; see also Carroll 2008, 36–7). The differences between these statements are non-trivial, and, wisely enough, Carroll does not attempt a generic formulation that accurately sums them all up. However, he does break the doctrine down into two theses (1985, 13–14). The first is a descriptive thesis and is stable across all versions of the doctrine: each art form is differentiated from the other art forms by its distinctive media. The second, prescriptive thesis varies from one version of the purity doctrine to the next. According to Greenberg, for example, works in a given art form should only be made to achieve effects unique to the art form by using the art form’s distinctive media. This prescriptive thesis is so astonishing that it is tempting to dismiss it. The proposition that some media are appreciative kinds certainly does not imply it. Perhaps the fact that K is an appreciative kind imposes the very weak collective obligation on us to create some good examples of Ks when we create Ks. That falls short of what the purity doctrine seems to require. A strong argument would be needed to show that we are under the further obligation only to create Ks that are good examples of Ks, when we create Ks. Knife makers are not obliged only to create sharp knives: there are countless respects in which knives can be good, and many are independent of their sharpness (e.g. being aesthetically good) while some are downright incompatible with it (being good for playing with). As Carroll advises, we should not let the doctrine ‘stand between us and excellence’ (1985, 14). So why think that painters are obliged only to create manifestly flat paintings? There are many respects in which paintings can be good and many are independent of their manifest flatness while some (e.g. being good illusions) are incompatible with it. Finally, it appears that the descriptive and prescriptive theses are independent, so that dismissing the prescriptive thesis does not seem to put the descriptive thesis in jeopardy – it remains an option for those who seek theories of the arts. Far from dismissing the prescriptive thesis, Carroll takes it seriously enough to reconstruct and critique the reasoning in 138 support of it. He argues that there is no good case for the prescriptive thesis because the descriptive thesis is false, and that suggests that the theses are not in fact independent, that the descriptive thesis is a premise in some reasoning for the prescriptive thesis. His ensuing critique of the descriptive thesis threatens the hope that theories of the arts can build upon ideas about media. The reasoning from the descriptive thesis to the prescriptive thesis requires some backstory about the purpose of the doctrine (Carroll 1985, 2008, 40). That purpose is to establish that new media qualify for status as arts. Thus Greenberg puts the doctrine to work in touting non-depictive painting, the art status of photography was backed in the 1930s by appeals to its pure use of its distinctive medium (e.g. Newhall 1937), and Carroll (2003) writes in reaction to a strand of film studies which promotes movies in the same way (e.g. Arnheim 1957[1932], Bazin 1967[1958–62]). If we ask, ‘why are these the arts?’ we might answer that each makes a distinctive contribution to the collection, and that is why each belongs in the collection. The reasoning from the descriptive thesis to the prescriptive thesis might be a kind of practical syllogism whose minor premise is the claim that those who work in a medium and wish to secure its standing as an art should should create works that emphasize its distinctive contribution to the arts as a whole. Viewed in this light, the prescriptive thesis is not so astonishing after all. Carroll’s reply is twofold. To begin with, he denies the premise that comes from the backstory. ‘The arts’, he writes, ‘are not systematic, designed with sharply variegated functions… there is no rationale for the system… it is only a collection’ (1985, 16–17). In effect, concern with media in the arts grows out of the search, launched by the early moderns, for a theory of the arts. Granting Carroll’s doubts about this enterprise is consistent with the previous chapter. The prescriptive thesis is safely set aside. Nevertheless, Carroll also rejects the descriptive thesis as a holdover that exerts some pull even after the purity doctrine has been repudiated. Recall that the thesis is that each art is differentiated from other arts by its distinctive media. Carroll objects that ‘we have no idea of what features of the medium are 139 important unless we have a use for the medium’ (1985, 8). The use of the medium in an art form ‘determines what aspects of the medium are relevant’ (1985, 11). But a given art form is differentiated from the other art forms by its distinctive medium only if its medium is ‘identifiable in advance of, or independently of, the uses to which the medium is put’ (Carroll 1985, 18). Therefore, art forms cannot be differentiated from each other by their distinctive media. The requirement that media be identified independently of their uses leads Carroll to identify media with material stuffs, such as paint and canvas or silver halide emulsion on cellulose strips. In a formula, medium = material. It follows that some arts, in defiance of the descriptive thesis, have no media. Literature, in particular, ‘does not appear to have a medium at all…. You might be tempted to regard words as the distinctive medium of literature. And yet, are words the right sort of thing to constitute a medium? Aren’t media, in the most clear-cut sense, physical?’ (Carroll 2003, 3). The problem is endemic if digitally encoded images, movies, and music are also media-free. Even worse, if media are material stuffs, then the material media of many arts fail to differentiate them from other arts. If plays and dances are made up of bodies and props on stage, then they do not differ from each other in respect of their media. A medium materialism clinches the case for medium skepticism, against those who side with Ruskin and Wollheim in wishing to remember the medium. It follows that Ruskin and Wollheim are right only if medium materialism is false; and if the independence requirement implies medium materialism, then it is false too. There are reasons to think both are false. One might conjecture that medium materialism is a side effect of the fact that contemporary debates about the purity doctrine are most at home in visual art theory. Appreciating a work of art generally takes into account what went into its making. In painting and sculpture, materials are exceptionally salient – it matters whether a painting is made of tempera on wet plaster or oil paint on canvas and it matters whether a sculpture is made of lime wood, marble, or bronze. 140 The salience of materials in painting and sculpture must not distract us from a more general and equally down-to-earth conception of media as ‘technical resources’ (Lopes 2004, 110). To begin with, a resource may be a material stuff, but it may be informational (e.g. a language), and events like the sounding of a c-sharp and an actor’s movement are also resources. So a resource is a generalization of Carroll’s ‘material’. In addition, resources are inert until we do something with them by using techniques. Techniques are simply procedures: they need not be ‘high tech’ – some familiar techniques applied to eggs (a resource) give us omelettes, for example. Obviously, resources afford but do not determine the techniques we can use to work with them. One resource, such as paper, affords the application of different techniques, such as drawing, printing, and composing verse. Likewise, the same technique can be used on different resources – drawing can be done with pencil on paper, with lipstick on a mirror, or vector data in a computer system. A medium is not just a resource, it is a technical resource. In a formula, medium = resource + technique. Medium materialism is a bad idea. So is the requirement that each resource be ‘identifiable in advance of, or independently of, the uses to which [it] is put’. Another conjecture is that this requirement is a legacy of the purity doctrine, which is presumably implemented as a regimen for artists to follow: ‘set aside the techniques you have learned (e.g. drawing) and look at your materials afresh… now do what expresses their nature (e.g. dripping paint)’. With the purity doctrine firmly behind us, the independence requirement is ad hoc. Some say: purify your thoughts, think only of the medium. The reaction: ‘forget the medium!’ Both sides share medium materialism and the independence requirement as common ground. The spirit of Ruskin and Wollheim lives on in a moderate conception of media that implies neither medium materialism nor the independence requirement and that is therefore at odds with Carroll’s skepticism on one hand and the purity doctrine on the other. Media in the Arts 141 According to the descriptive thesis, each art form is differentiated from the other arts by its distinctive media. That kick starts theories of the arts: each theory will identify the art form’s differentiating media. The technique of reverse engineering helps make the identification. Before going any further, care must be taken to formally disown a rather too strong reading of the descriptive thesis. According to the excessively strong reading, the descriptive thesis says that 1. each art form has some medium and no other art form has that medium. A weaker reading of the thesis says that 2. each art form has a (non-empty) set of media and no other art form has that set. Obviously (1) implies (2) but (2) does not imply (1). The proposition that each person is differentiated from all other people by their facial features does not imply that each person has a facial feature that no other person has. Think of the weak reading of the difference thesis as positing a distinctive medium profile for each art form (Fig. 3). W. J. T. Mitchell (2005, 260–1) colourfully compares media in the arts to ingredients and recipes in cooking: boeuf bourguinon and yam neua share an ingredient but differ in their ‘media’. Nothing prevents arts with different profiles from sharing some media in common; practically speaking, it is inevitable. Incidentally, the purity doctrine requires (1), but nothing more than (2) is needed to make reference to media in theories of the arts. Figure 3 is a simplification in so far as it flattens the media. In fact, they nest (Gaut 2010, 290). This is a simple consequence of the fact that media are technical resources. If language is a medium for literature then so are inscriptions, speech, and signed utterances, since they are linguistic media. Nested within the medium of imaging are drawing and photography, nested within drawing are charcoal drawing and vector drawing, and nested within vector drawing are drawing woth Adobe Illustrator and 142 drawing with Inkscape. Of course, nested media may be found scattered across the tree representing media in the arts. The task at hand is not to work out a theory of each one of the arts; it is to assemble a framework in which these theories might be developed, seeing as they are not to be developed against the background of a buck stopping theory of art. The pieces are now ready for assembly. The first is the thesis floated at the end of the first section of the chapter: art forms are appreciative kinds. The next section stipulated necessary and sufficient conditions for being an appreciative kind: K is an appreciative kind if and only if is there is a property of being good qua K, or being good-modified for a K, or being good qua K* for a K. A moderate conception of media opens up room for a weak reading of the descriptive thesis: each art is differentiated from the other arts by its distinctive medium profile. This thesis must be paired with a rich conception of media as resources and means. All three theses can be assembled into a restriction on the schema for theories of the arts: x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is a work in medium profile M, where M is an appreciative kind,… . This schema preserves the spirit Ruskin and Wollheim on art media by implying that media in the arts are appreciative kinds. However, as the ellipses signal, the schema is not fully restricted, for it leaves open whether there is more to a given art form than its medium profile. This point is taken up in Chapter 8. The framework before us provides for a coordinated top–down and bottom–up strategy in developing theories of the arts. The top–down component of the strategy is to use reverse engineering, inferring elements of a theory of an art to explain data about the appreciation of works in the art form. These data can indicate the art form’s media, since media are appreciative kinds. An example of such an inference is: 143 . a photograph’s being good qua photograph is its being good at revealing the character of a scene, . photographs reveal the character of scenes because they depict scenes, . so part of what it is for an item to be a photograph is for it to depict a scene. That is, depiction is a medium of photographic art. Of course, (1) might be false. Our access to facts about the goodness properties of works in art forms is not incorrigible. Facts about the actual resources exploited by an art form can correct mistaken appreciations. The bottom–up strategy is to take as data facts about what media are exploited as the resources of an art form. These facts can be explained by facts about art form as an appreciative kind, since media are appreciative kinds. In this way, it is possible to infer facts about the goodness properties of an art form from facts about its media. An example of such an inference is: . moving images are a medium in cinema, . moving images are a medium in cinema because, by depicting events unfolding in time, they are good for telling stories, . so being good at telling stories partly determines what it is to be good qua cinema, to be good-modified for cinema, or to be good qua K* for cinema. Of course, (1) might be false. Our beliefs about the media exploited in art forms are subject to revision under pressure from top–down inferences. The top–down and bottom–up strategies may be coordinated with the aim of reaching an informative equilibrium. At the equilibrium point, the goodness properties of an art form’s media partly determine the goodness properties of the art form itself. Carroll emphasizes that his critique of the purity doctrine brings home the lesson that it is ‘not an easy task’ to identify an art form’s media (1985, 8). The two inferences set out above are ‘potted examples’. They illustrate modes of reasoning that can be 144 used in developing theories of the arts. Putting them to work in practice would obviously mean bringing serious empirical work to bear. That this is what the framework asks is no drawback. Any framework that suggests that theories of the arts can be got by purely a priori methods is doomed to failure. Two Objections Theories of the individual arts have traditionally been worked up using a buck stopping theory of art as a framework, but that is not an option given a buck passing theory of art. So the proposal so far is that theories of the arts may be worked up by aligning facts about the appreciation of works as belonging to art forms with facts about the media that are exploited in those art forms. The proposal is expressed as a new, restricted version of the schema for theories of the arts: x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is a work in medium profile M, where M is an appreciative kind,… . It would be too much to ask for a deductive argument entailing this proposition. After all, the schema represents a methodological proposal. However, the schema does have a substantive implication, which can be tested against counterexamples. In addition, it is fair to ask whether the proposal is likely to get us as far as the competing methodology favoured by tradition and funded by buck stopping theories of art. The substantive implication is the descriptive thesis, that each art form has a medium profile. It is tempting, when viewed in the context of the debate over the purity doctrine, to object that no art form has a unique medium. The reply is that this objection assumes a strong and mistaken reading of the descriptive thesis. However, an entirely different objection comes into view when the weak descriptive thesis is contrasted not with the doctrine of medium purity but rather with the indifference thesis opposed by Ruskin and Wollheim and attributed by Wollheim to Croce and Collingwood. According to the indifference thesis, the ‘technical qualities’ of art works are not a factor in their value. 145 The artists who created the works that function as hard cases were reacting to Greenberg’s purification edicts by making works whose interest does not lie in any medium they might happen to exploit. Indeed, Cage’s 4’33” and Rauschenberg’s Erased de Kooning Drawing might be described as works without media. Croce and Collingwood are godfathers of the kind of avant-garde art making that gives us the hard cases. At any rate, the objection is that there are works of art without media. Either these belong to art forms or they do not. If they belong to art forms, then the weak descriptive thesis implied by the framework is false. That is not good news for the framework. Alternatively, if the works in question do not belong to any art form, then the buck passing theory of art is false. That is not good news for the framework either, since it will have lost its raison d’être. Either way, matters look bleak for the framework. This objection is a reminder that a rain check (issued in Chapter 1 and 3) remains to be redeemed. The buck passing theory of art does imply that every work of art belongs to at least one art form. None are free agents. But some appear to be free agents. The objection was set aside to be dealt with in Chapter 10. Now there is an additional task for Chapter 10. A case must be made not only that the apparent free agents do belong to art forms but also that they exploit the media of those art forms. A second objection demands immediate attention. A restriction has been placed on the schema for theories of the arts: a necessary condition to be met by an item that is a work in any given art form is that it be a work in a certain medium. However, there are necessary conditions and there are necessary conditions. While they may not be sufficient conditions, they are theoretically significant only when they move us closer to sufficient conditions, and not all necessary conditions are theoretically significant. The objection is that the proposed framework mandates a kind of necessary condition that is not significant. Being told that works of architecture, for example, are necessarily buildings is like being told that persons are necessarily living things. That is true but it is not much to go on. To see why it is fair to suspect the proposed framework of mandating a theoretically insignificant kind of necessary 146 condition, compare the framework to one that leans on a buck stopping theory of art. Gaut (2010, ch. 7) endorses a moderate conception of media much like the one sketched here, except in one important respect. The difference is obvious looking at three claims that Gaut defends: [] some correct artistic evaluations of artworks refer to distinctive properties of the medium in which these artworks occur… [] correct explanations of some of the artistic properties of artworks refer to distinctive properties of the medium in which these artworks occur… [] for a medium to constitute an art form it must instantiate artistic properties that are distinct from those that are instantiated by other media (, –). Works in an art form are not merely works in an associated medium. They are works that exploit a medium to realize artistic properties (and values). A buck stopping theory of art supplies an independent conception of artistic properties (and values). Technically, Gaut’s three claims are consistent with the buck passing theory of art. For example, (1) conjoined with the buck passing theory of art says that some correct evaluations of works as Ks refer to distinctive properties of the medium of K. Similarly, (3) conjoined with the buck passing theory of art says that a medium constitutes an art form, K, only if it instantiates properties of K that are distinct from those that are by other media. However, plugging the buck passing theory of art into (1), (2), and (3) robs the appeal to artistic properties of its intended function. That function is to delimit which media, of all the media exploited by works, are artistically relevant. The example Gaut gives is the compact disk. CDs are storeage media for music but they are not in any interesting sense musical media. Being stored on CD is not part of what makes an item a work of music. According to Gaut, works of art have distinctively artistic features and works in an art form have artistic features distinctive of the art form. CDs are not responsible for these features. No such move is available on the framework proposed in 147 this chapter. In principle any medium that is an appreciative kind is an artistic medium. To tackle this problem, some new resources must be brought on field. The framework so far proposed is not the whole story. Appreciative Practices What are dance, music, the movies, poetry, the chado and landscape architecture? Carroll remarks, in a Dantoesque spirit, that ‘coming to understand these concepts is an important contribution to the life of the practices in which they figure, often constitutively’ (, ). The truth in this remark is not yet accommodated by the proposal that theories of the arts be devised to fit a schema like this: x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is a work in medium profile M, where M is an appreciative kind, …. A work of poetry is not just a work in a medium, it is a product of a practice. Moreover, if Carroll is right, engaging in the practice in some way implicates a concept of poetry. Some fleshing out along these lines sharpens our pictures of the arts as appreciative kinds and it solves the problem left hanging at the end of the previous chapter. The Coffee Mug Objection Rikyu famously said that the chado is ‘nothing but / Boiling water / And making tea’. As advice for practitioners these words had a profound impact, but they obviously will not do as a theory of the art form. Worldwide tea consumption exceeds that of all other manufactured drinks, with millions of tonnes of tea leaf harvested annually. Every second of every day sees the making of tens of thousands of cups of tea. Counting all this tea-making as the performance of chado would cheat that concept of its explanatory and critical power. There is more to the chado that boiling water and making tea. What more? Switching to another hot drink, recall the coffee mug objection to the buck passing theory of art, first stated in Chapter and then reiterated in Chapter . According to the buck passing theory of art, what makes an item a work of art is its being a work of one of the arts. The objection was that ceramics is an art and the coffee mug on my desk is a work of ceramics, but, alas, it is no work of 149 art. The objection can now be refined by referring to the medium of ceramics. Ceramics is an art but the coffee mug on my desk is no work of art, though it is a work in the ceramic medium. A theory of ceramic art must distinguish a piece of bizen ware from a sample of Walmart ware. Since they are the same in respect of medium, more than the medium is needed. Generalizing, a theory of each art form must distinguish works in the art from works that are merely in associated media. Of course, it is an open question what are the arts. Ceramics might not be an art after all. It is another open question what is the medium of ceramics – it might be that Walmart ware and bizen ware do not share the same medium. A third open question is what items are works in the ceramic art form. I might be wrong about my coffee mug – perhaps it is a work of art. That these questions are open is to be expected since the framework is a methodology and the task is to test the adequacy of that methodology as far as possible without already having applied it. So choose another example if you like. The framework has to allow that sometimes not all works in a medium are works in the associated art form. The proposition that art forms are appreciative kinds bears on an answer to the coffee mug objection. An art form, K, is an appreciative kind just in case there is a property of being good qua K, or being good-modified for a K, or being good qua K* for a K. So if a piece of bizen ware belongs to the art of ceramics and a piece of Walmart ware merely belongs to the ceramic medium, then the art form and the medium are distinct appreciative kinds; and they are distinct appreciative kinds only if they differ in their goodness properties. The question of what it is to be a work of ceramic art links up to the question of what it is for a work to be good as ceramic art. This linkage should come as no surprise. Ceramic art and mere ceramics do differ in the values that they realize. The point is not that they differ in the values they realize because one is an art and the other is not – that point relies on a theory of the arts (see Chapter ). The point is more simply that they are different appreciative kinds. Often – though probably not as a matter of conceptual truth – a theory of any given art form implies that it realizes more 150 determinate values than its associated medium. A work in the medium of ceramics has scores of different kinds of goodness properties. Here are some true propositions about the coffee mug on my desk: it is good for holding hot liquids, it is good for holding pens, it is not good for use as a tennis ball, it is moderately good to look at, it goes for a good price, it is a good reminder of the time I spent in Chapel Hill, it is a good example of standardization in manufacturing processes. Each of these propositions is made true by the mug’s having certain goodness properties and what goodness properties those are takes account of the fact that it is a work of ceramics. However, only some, not all, of these goodness properties are goodness properties of the ceramic art form. Some do bridge the kinds – being good for holding hot liquids might be an example. Some do not bridge the kinds at all – being a good example of standardization in manufacturing processes is arguably not a goodness property in ceramic art. Some bridge as determinables but grade differently. For example, being good to look at for a K is a goodness property both in ceramic art and in mere ceramics, but an item that is very good to look at for a piece of ceramics might be no more than moderately good to look at for a piece of ceramic art. The upshot of these observations is that what makes a work of ceramics a work of ceramic art often makes more determinate the goodness properties pertaining to ceramic art. Provided that ceramic art is an appreciative kind, it follows that one way forward reverse engineers a conception of ceramic art from the goodness properties that pertain to it. The strategy recommended to zero in on the media associated with an art form is also available to zero in on what it is, beyond their medium, that makes items works in an art form. Art Practices Philosophers writing on art and the arts frequently insist that these are not natural kinds. An adequate description of what makes an item a work of art or a work of any of the arts must make reference to the thoughts and actions of agents. Peter Lamarque glosses the observation that literary works ‘have no 151 existence apart from the nexus of activities and judgements within which they are identified and evaluated’ by adding that they are ‘products and not just objects of critical discourse’ (, ). Davies () has argued the same for music. In general, the arts are practices. Augmenting the proposed framework for developing theories of the arts, x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is a work in medium profile M, where M is an appreciative kind, and x is a product of appreciative practice, P. What distinguishes my coffee mug from a piece of bizen-yaki is not their media, for both are ceramics, but rather the fact that they are products of different practices. The practice of bizen, and any other art practice, has some notable features. It is a social practice in the sense that engaging in the practice consists in conforming to some rules on condition that others who engage in the practice do so too (Rawls ). This is a minimal conception of a practice. The rules need not be conventions: they may not solve a coordination problem (Lewis ). Moreover, a social practice need not be institutional in the sense that to engage in the practice is, at least in part, to play one of a number of differentiated roles, where one’s playing the role depends on others playing their roles, and where some of these roles are constitutive of the practice. The practice of ceramic art may be institutional in this sense. If it is, that is a fact to represent in a theory of ceramic art. However, it would be wise to keep an open mind about whether every art is an institutional practice. Some practices are appreciative: the rules that are constitutive of an appreciative practice set a standard of goodness for products of the practice. Shetland sheepdogs are not a natural kind – they are not, in particular, a biological kind. They depend for their existence upon a practice within which they are identified and evaluated. As it happens, the rules constitutive of this practice are expressly articulated and published as the ‘breed standard’, which stipulates, for example, that shelties should have eyes of ‘medium size obliquely set, almond-shape. Dark brown except in the case of merles, where one or both may be blue or blue flecked’ (Kennel 152 Club ). To be a breeder or admirer of Shetland sheepdogs is to accept this rule as a standard of what it is to be good qua Shetland sheepdog, on condition that others engaged in the practice do so too. Not all practices are appreciative. Although constitutive rules may be described as norms, they do not always determine goodness properties. A classic example is the practice of banking. The rules of this practice make it the case that there is such a thing as a debit to an account. However, there is no property of being good qua debit. While a debit of a large sum may be less welcome to the account holder than a debit of a small sum, but it is no less good qua debit. When a practice is in fact an appreciative practice, chances are that its constitutive rules are not explicitly represented within the practice. The breed standard for the sheltland sheepdog is one end of a spectrum. At the other end are implicit rules, regularities in behaviour which are best explained as rule-following. Most if not all of the arts are appreciative practices with implicit constitutive rules. When what appear to be standards are voiced by art critics and art theorists, it is rarely to articulate what is otherwise implicit but rather to advocate a change to what is implicit. Rules of Engagement Nobody will deny that the arts are in some sense practices. The bone of contention is whether the fact that they are practices (combined with a recognition of the association with media) supplies what is needed to craft theories of the arts. According to Goldilocks objections, the rules constituting artistic practices are either too broad or too narrow to figure in theories of the arts. Here is one objection to the claim that the arts are appreciative practices. The arts have no monopoly on appreciative practices. Arguably all manufacturing practices qualify. At any rate, for many art forms there is a non-art appreciative practice centred on the very same medium. It would be a callow mistake to suppose that there is or could be no appreciative practice centred on Walmart ware. 153 The response is to mind the distinction between a theory of the arts and theories of the individual arts. Filling in the schema for a theory of ceramic art provides a representation of what it is for an item to be a work in the ceramic art form, but it is silent on what it is for ceramics to be an art form. Ceramic art and ceramics are both appreciative kinds, and a theory of each represents what makes them different appreciative kinds, but it does not represent what makes one of them an art form. For that, a theory of the arts is needed. The point is subtle enough that we should guard against a tempting mistake in reasoning. The fallacy hinges on thinking that a representation of what makes an item a work of ceramic art rather than ceramics is a representation of what makes ceramics an art. The same fallacy helps boost the appeal of another objection, that the rules constituting the practices of the arts are far too general to distinguish works in the arts from works in non-art practices. Once we have made the rules of ceramic art explicit, we will see that they are so general that they apply to much else besides ceramic art. Moreover, the same might turn out to be true for some, many, or all of the other arts. This bleak possibility cannot be excluded a priori, but it is fair to ask what reason there is to be pessimistic. Well, the objection packs considerable punch as long as an art practice is meant to be characterized so as to reveal what makes it an art practice. It is hard to imagine constitutive rules common to the practices of ceramic art and dance that are not also rules blinding the appreciative practice of non-art ceramics. The problem with this objection is that it conflates what is required for a theory of each of the arts with a theory of the arts, wherein the arts are distinguished from the non-arts. The reply to the objection is that a theory of an art may bring out the specific rules constituting the practice without regard to the arts as a whole. In presenting his theory of literature, which nicely fits the framework proposed here, Lamarque writes that the rules must be ‘specific enough to capture a substantial, recognizable, conception of literature,… yet not so specific that they apply only to some, not all, forms of literature’ (, ). These are the only 154 constraints that govern the project of developing a theory of literature. Indeed, although Lamarque regularly describes his task as developing a theory of literature ‘as art’ and although he comes close to reasoning fallaciously when he also says that his task is to say what it is for literature to be an art form (e.g. , ), he never attempts to test his theory of literature for its generalizability to other arts. If its failure to generalize is no mark against it, it is a theory of literature and not part of a theory of the arts. The framework proposed here accommodates a requirement that the rules constitutive of a practice should be specific enough to determine the specificity of the practice itself. Another objection tugs in the opposite direction. According to this objection, it will turn out that there are no rules general enough to be constitutive of the whole of an art. The point can be expanded in different ways. Identifying art practices with critical traditions, one might argue that there are different critical traditions within which works are situated, though they belong to the same art form. For example, modernist painting as understood by Greenberg and his followers is allied to critical practices at odds with those governing the practice of s conceptual art. Alternatively, one might argue that sub-arts such as poetry and the novel are practices but not sub-practices of a more generic literary practice. The reply to this objection has two parts. To begin with, keep in mind that a theory of anything, including an art form, is not worth working towards unless it is informative. The fact that a theory is informative is a reason to retain the theory and revise a folk concept, when they do not line up. It might be a discovery that there is no art of literature if we come to understand more by relinquishing our folk concept of literature as comprising both poetry and the novel. The objection assumes that theories of the arts must vindicate folk concepts of the arts. Making this assumption misses an opportunity for discovery. In cases where a theory of an art provides no reason to revise the folk concept in question, there must have been a discovery that what appear to be disparate practices represented by different critical traditions are really of a kind. To achieve such a discovery requires detailed empirical study of the practices in question. 155 Lamarque’s () discussion of literature is an excellent model. Having directed intense attention upon a wide variety of literary works and critical stances, he discerns what he maintains to be a generic literary practice. Although its rules of engagement cannot be stated as a succinct set of propositions and his full account extends over many pages, here is his summary of the practice of literary reading: inevitably this will involve an examination of the formal ‘devices’, conventional or unconventional, general and specific, that allow the artefact to ‘hang together’, through which its subject is expressed and its themes developed. It will involve exploring how parts cohere with the whole, how linguistic means further aesthetic ends. It will also use interpretation to assign symbolic, figurative, or thematic significance to the work’s elements. As every work has a subject, be it a story told or an emotion expressed, attention will be directed to the subject content itself, what it is, what connections might be drawn inside and outside its ‘world’, what its characters, incidents, or setting are like; but it is a common mark of literature (as opposed to ‘genre’ fiction or popular verse) that interest goes beyond such subject details, inviting readers to reflect on thematic ideas that both bind together and transcend the immediate subject portrayed (, -). According to Lamarque, such a practice embraces various critical stances and types of literary expression. The complexity of art practices makes subtle work of elucidating their constitutive rules. It helps to keep in mind that K is an appreciative kind just in case there is a property of being good qua K, or being good-modified for a K, or being good qua K* for a K. A rule might fix what it is to be good qua K. Take the rule that literary readers are to reflect on thematic ideas as they are expressed by subject matter. If part of what makes a work a work of literature is that it is a product of a practice governed by this rule, then literature is a goodness-fixing kind wherein part of what it is to be good qua literature is to afford such reflection. If it is a rule of the practice of Chinese painting that its audience is to 156 include the formal qualities of linguistic characters as part of the work, then those qualities figure into what it is to be aesthetically good-modified for Chinese painting. Finally, if it is part of the practice of ceramic art that its products be destined for display in glass cases, then there is a distinct property of being good qua cooking vessel for a work destined for display in a glass case – a pot might be very good qua cooking vessel for a work of ceramic art and yet turn out not to be at all good qua cooking vessel. Art practices may but need not determine goodness-fixing kinds and they may but need not determine properties of being aesthetically good-modified. Carroll’s observation that engaging in an art practice implicates a concept of the art does not entail that the concept in question is a folk classification. Having the concept may consist in mastery of the rules constitutive of the practice, and since these are generally implicit, they need not line up with a folk classification. Coming to understand these implicit rules might well contribute to the life of the art practices which they constitute. Media in Practice Without reasons to believe that the rules that constitute artistic practices are either too monolithically broad or too tied to narrow traditions to contribute to theories of the arts, Goldilocks objections deserve the brush off. A final worry concerns the apparent lack of a connection between the two elements making up the proposed schema for theories of the arts – that is, between media on one hand and appreciative practices on the other. The worry is the flip side of the coffee mug objection, which exploits a continuity of media between ceramics and ceramic art. Imagine a ceramic artist with certain avant-garde ambitions. She decides that it is time to dissociate ceramic art from its material basis, its alliance to arts like the chado, and its historical origins in such everyday activities as drinking hot liquids. Using instead Lucy Lippard’s () ideas about the dematerialized art object, she proceeds to create works of ceramic art that leave out the ceramics – no clay, no glaze, no firing. For example, one of these is entitled All the Pots I Did Not Throw on September , , and 157 that title and what it evokes in the context of ceramic art is all there is to the work. All that remains is the practice and its constitutive rules. Faced with such a scenario, two responses are available. One might concede the scenario’s coherence: the practice of ceramic art might make a decisive break with ceramics and leave its medium behind – in the dust, as it were. Since the medium turns out to be inessential to the practice, the practice might be identical to a practice that was once associated with an entirely different medium and has been similarly dematerialized – painting for example. In that case, painting and ceramic art might be one and the same art form. Enough has now been said to sketch an alternative response to the scenario. The alternative is not merely to insist that the medium is constitutive of the art form, for that is to concede that the practice of ceramic art might be continuous with an art practice that has nothing to do with ceramics. The better response is to deny that the practice of ceramic art can be characterized independently of the medium of ceramics. This denial can be implemented by amending the schema for a theory of the arts: x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is a work in medium profile M, where M is an appreciative kind, and x is a product of M-centred appreciative practice, P. A theory of ceramic art built on this framework implies that to try to make works that are products of the practice of ceramic art but that are not in the medium of ceramics is to fail to engage in that practice and hence to fail to make works of ceramic art. Which alternative is appropriate? On one hand, centring an art practice on media helps to strike the balance of specificity and generality that is needed in a theory of an art form. Lamarque could hardly describe the practice of literary reading in anything but empty terms without referring to the media of literature. On the other hand, it is a tenet of writing on late modern art as early as Lippard () that its use of any medium is purely opportunistic. Since this tenet must be taken seriously and not dismissed out of hand, a full assessment of the two alternatives 158 must wait upon a study of late modern art – art that is reported to have done just what we imagined our ceramic artist to have done. That is part of the task of Chapter . Meanwhile, there is an independent reason to favour restricting the art practices that figure in theories of art to those that are centred on the medium. A look at this reason also brings out what it is for an art practice to be medium-centred. Two Norms of Appreciation A practice is constituted by rules or norms and a medium-centred appreciative practice is one which is constituted in part by a norm that concerns the medium whose exploitation is what makes items works in the appreciative kind. The norm in question must be a general one – one that is part of any appreciative practice. Walton’s classic ‘Categories of Art’ () suggests such a general norm. As we saw in Chapter , Walton argues that the aesthetic properties that are work has is determined by two factors (see also Laetz ). The first is the category of art to which it belongs. Since any given work belongs to indefinitely many categories (Guernica is both a painting and a guernica), it is further determined by the category in which it is correct to view it. Thus the aesthetic properties of Guernica are the properties it seems to have when viewed as a painting, since it is a painting and since it is also correct to view it as a painting. Thus a norm governing the aesthetic appreciation of works of art is: view a work in a category in which it is correct to view it. Some extend this norm to the aesthetic appreciation of non-art. Thus Budd writes that ‘if you aesthetically appreciate a natural object as an instance of natural kind K, and it is not of kind K, then your appreciation is, in that respect, malfounded’ (, ). Carlson () argues that since whales are not fish an appreciation of a whale as a fish is inadequate. Presumably the norm can also be generalized beyond the aesthetic. The general norm would be: appreciate an item for what it is. Grounding this norm is the principle that 159 an appreciation of an item as a K is adequate only if the item is a K. An appreciation of an item that violates this condition is inadequate in the sense that it is not true to the item. We should appreciate an item for what it is. Not everyone buys in. Reflecting on his appreciation of the grandeur of a blue whale, Carroll writes, ‘I may be moved by its size, its force, the amount of water it displaces, etc., but I may think that it is a fish’ (, ). Indeed, the point may be put rather more strongly. Carroll may be moved by the size and force of a whale because he thinks that it is a fish. After all, the whale is orders of magnitude larger and stronger than fish and it is not grander than other sea mammals to the same degree. All the same, Carroll insists that his appreciation is not inadequate. The standard argument for the norm that Carroll rejects is an argument from objectivity. The classic statement of the argument is once again Walton (). The aesthetic properties an art work seems to have depend on the category of art in which it is viewed. Guernica seems ‘violent, dynamic, vital, disturbing’ when viewed as a painting but it seems ‘cold, stark, lifeless, or serene and restful, or perhaps bland, dull, boring’ when viewed as a guernica (Walton : ). For any art work and any aesthetic property, F, there is some category of art in which it appears F. However, category-relative viewings of works do not allow ascriptions of aesthetic properties to be mistaken ‘often enough’ (Walton : ). Walton’s solution is to claim that it is correct to view a work in some categories and incorrect to view it in others. It is correct to view Guernica as a painting and it is not correct to view it as a guernica. So Guernica is dynamic, not serene. Some appreciations are mistaken: those that ascribe properties a work seems to have only when it is viewed as a K and it is incorrect to view it as a K. Walton’s argument generalizes beyond the aesthetic appreciation of works of art. For many (maybe all) ascriptions of goodness properties to an item, there is (likely) to be an appreciative kind, K, such that the ascription is not mistaken when the item is appreciated as a K. Guernica is serene when appreciated as a guernica, for example. Our appreciations are not 160 mistaken ‘often enough’. The solution is to restrict adequate appreciation: one adequately appreciates something as a K only if it is a K. Hence the injunction to appreciate items for what they are. Rejecting this norm leads to a choice. One option is to accept that our appreciations are not mistaken often, or ever. The other is to find another norm. Note that Walton does not claim that category-relative interpretations never allow ascriptions to be mistaken. The weaker ‘often enough’ hints that there is already room for error in category relative appreciation. There is room for error about the category itself. Suppose that Munro judges a dog to be too short. Posh objects that the dog is a shetland sheepdog, not a collie, and although it is short for a collie, it is a good height for a shetland sheepdog. ‘No’, replies Munro, ‘it’s too short for a sheltie’. Either Munro or Posh is mistaken about the ideal height of shetland sheepdogs. Or suppose that Rosalind remarks that Guernica is restful. You might think that she takes her philosophy a little too seriously, and has started to view Guernica as a guernica. However, she reads your mind and hastens to add, ‘and I mean that it’s restful as a painting’. If she is wrong, she is not wrong in viewing Guernica as a painting, because it is a painting and it is correct to view it as a painting. She is wrong about the expressive properties of paintings in general – perhaps she has seen a biassed sample. An alternative to the directive to be true to the item is to be true to the kind. That is, when you appreciate an item as a K, do not misunderstand what it is to be a K (Lopes b). This norm is grounded on the principle that, an appreciation of x as a K is adequate only if it does not depend counterfactually on any belief that is inconsistent with the truth about what it is to be a K. This principle says that the adequacy of an appreciation is threatened when several conditions are met. First, the appreciation counterfactually depends on a belief: it would not have the content it has were it not for a certain belief. Second, that belief very is inconsistent with some truth about the Ks. Third, the 161 relevant truth about the Ks is a truth about what it is to be a K. Adequate appreciation must be theoretically kosher. Someone’s appreciating a whale as a fish does not violate this norm. Carroll might have a degree in marine biology; he might know that whales are mammals and not fish. Both norms are modest, setting low benchmarks for adequate appreciation. One might think that many appreciations are inadequate although they violate neither. However, the task at hand is not to compose a complete epistemology of appreciation. The task is rather to locate a norm that makes art practice a medium-centred practice. Either of our two norms will do that job. One is to be true to the item; the other is to be true to the kind. According to one analysis of what it is for a practice to be medium-centred, an art practice, P, is M-centred if and only if it is a constitutive norm of P not to appreciate a work as a work in M unless the work is a work in M. According to an alternative analysis, an art practice, P, is M-centred if and only if it is a constitutive norm of P not to appreciate a work as an M if that appreciation counterfactually depends on any belief that is inconsistent with the truth about what it is to be a work in M. Of course, a third analysis of medium-centred art practices has it that they incorporate both norms. However, the argument from objectivity supports either norm and not both. Moreover, either one norm or the other appears not to be in place in some art practices . Some art practices involve the deliberate and knowing appreciation of non-Ks as Ks. For example, it is part of the practice of landscape architecture that we are to appreciate some landscapes as paintings – not simply as scenes that can be viewed two-dimensionally but as telling stories in the way that images do. There are also cases where we () appreciate a non-K as a K and where () our appreciations counterfactually depend on false beliefs about the Ks, but where it is reasonable to expect that we 162 will correct () and not (). Ancient Greek and Roman sculpture was painted and inlaid. The discovery during the renaissance of ancient marbles that had lost their paint and inlay over time established the false image we have of ancient sculpture as pure marble or bronze, and that set the standard for modern sculpture. As a result, our appreciation of the Charioteer of Delphi as Greek sculpture counterfactually depends upon a false belief that Greek sculpture is naked stone or metal, and it is to that extent inadequate. Armed with better knowledge of the ancient world, we might appreciate the Charioteer as Greek sculpture, where glass eyes were common. Alternatively, we can appreciate it as belonging to the kind whose standard was set in the renaissance. We opt for the latter since we would lose too much by opting for the former. The appreciation of photographs seems to involve systematic misunderstanding of the nature of the medium, with serious consequences for appreciation. Barbara Savedoff argues that we appreciate photographs for their power ‘to make even the most familiar objects appear strange’ (, ). This power requires that we have a confidence in the veracity of photographs that ‘allows our faith in the documentary character of photography to be inappropriately transferred to the way things appear within the photograph’ (Savedoff , ). Our seeing photographs as ‘objective records of the world… has a far-reaching influence on interpretation and evaluation’ (Savedoff : ). As Savedoff puts it, perhaps photographs cannot be correctly understood as possessing a special documentary status; nevertheless, that is how they are experienced…. And insofar as [this] is necessary to a well-grounded evaluation and understanding of the photographs that we have been considering, it must be reflected in the critical principles we bring to bear (, ). Yet if our trust that photographs cannot lie depends on a misunderstanding of the nature of photographic technology, then photographic appreciation violates the injunction to be true to the medium. 163 Appreciations can go astray because they do not conform to the norms governing our appreciative practices. They can also go astray because those practices are inadequate and should be revised. Art practices are not sacrosanct. The proposed framework represents this fact by requiring art practices to be mediumcentred. Strategic Priorities, Again Time to pause and take stock. The fact that they provide ready resources for developing theories of the individual arts is a mark in favour of buck stopping theories of art. Yet the buck passing theory of art does not leave us empty handed. Taking advantage of the method of reverse engineering, a conception of what it is for a work to belong to an art form can be built from an independent conception of a medium profile together with a set of practices centred on that medium profile. These materials are sufficient in principle to answer the coffee mug objection and its analogues in the other arts. Moreover, this approach to theories of the individual arts has an edge on approaches that start with buck stopping theories of art. In the first place, a buck stopping theory of art does not deliver theories of arts for free. It also requires that we do the kind of work that has been done in these past two chapters. Take Beardsley’s theory of art as an example: a work of art is ‘something produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to satisfy the aesthetic interest’ (, ???). As we saw in Chapter , this theory of art implies a Beardsleyan theory of any given art form only with the help of a bridging assumption. Let φ label what makes any item a work of art and let ψ label what makes any item a member of an art. Since an item is a work of art partly in virtue of facts that make it a product of some art, K, a general bridging assumption might be this: if x is a work of K, where K is an art then x is φ partly in virtue of being ψ. 164 Substituting in, we get: if x is a work of K, where K is an art then x is something produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to satisfy the aesthetic interest partly in virtue of being ψ. That does not take us very far unless something can be said about how being a member of K helps a work satisfy the aesthetic interest. Bringing in the framework developed in these two chapters gives us a useful bridging assumption: if x is a work of K, where K is an art then x is something produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to satisfy the aesthetic interest partly in virtue of its taking advantage of K’s medium and medium-centred practices. This assumption conjoined with Beardsley’s theory of art is a machine for churning out theories of the individual arts. It outputs this, for example: if x is a work of ceramics, where ceramics is an art then x is something produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to satisfy the aesthetic interest partly in virtue of its taking advantage of the ceramic medium and ceramic’s mediumcentred practices. This is true, if the bridging assumption and Beardsley’s theory of art is true. However, it is hardly informative to those who want to know what is ceramic art. They will ask for information about the medium and the relevant practices. Starting with a buck stopping theory of art brings us right back to where we are now anyway. That leaves us at a strategic wash: whether we start with a buck stopping or a buck passing theory of art, we are end up framing out theories of the arts. Another point gives buck passing theories of art the edge. Buck stopping theories of art found theories of the arts only if they imply a substantive unity across the arts. Beardsley’s, for example, says that what makes any item a work in any art form its its appeal to the aesthetic interest. Perhaps the arts are a mixed bag. If they are not, that is a result 165 that must be won through the hard work of examining each of the arts in their own terms. Finally, developing theories of the arts with a buck passing theory of art takes off the table what makes each art an art. It takes off the table a theory of the arts. All that is required is the claim that the arts are appreciative kinds. The arts belong in a very large company – a company that includes natural objects and settings, what are often set apart as crafts, products of industrial design, and much else besides. We can be secure in the knowledge that the arts keep such (good!) company – even if we suspect that their own clique is not much more a matter of convenience. In its broad strokes, the framework for developing theories of the arts is now in place and it nowhere requires a buck stopping theory of art – a buck passing theory of art is all we need. However, one part of the framework merits a closer look. Appreciative kinds are kinds with characteristic goodnessproperties, and these include but are not restricted to the property of being aesthetically good. Yet aesthetic goodness is (at the very least) a prominent and important kind of goodness that finds its realization in (at the very least) a great many works of art. Aesthetic Appreciation Few deny some important connection between art and the aesthetic. To acknowledge a connection, even a deep one, is not yet to subscribe to an aesthetic theory of art that takes a work’s aesthetic credentials to be what makes it a work of art. The frescos of Piero della Francesca, the compositions of Thelonious Monk, the landscape of the Taj Mahal, and the short stories of Alice Munro are works of art. Whatever makes them so, they all realize exceptional aesthetic value – it is for this that we cherish them. A discussion of art that leaves out aesthetic appreciation can only disappoint. Chapter stipulated that generic appreciation is a cognitive process that includes an ascription of value, which typically results from classification and interpretation. Presumably in aesthetic appreciation the evaluation ascribes an aesthetic value, a property of being aesthetically-good-modified whether simpliciter, qua K, or for a K. The task of this chapter is to take steps towards an account of specifically aesthetic appreciation that can contribute to the framework for developing theories of the arts. The Aesthetic in Art and Beyond Chapter suggested that it may not be prudent to seek a theory of aesthetic appreciation of works typed as art. It does not follow that it is not prudent to seek a general theory of aesthetic appreciation. Carroll colourfully grumbles that the aesthetic has a ‘way of spreading once it’s turned loose’ to populate a domain of ‘aesthetic what-nots’ (????). Some such what-nots are: aesthetic properties, aesthetic values, aesthetic experience, aesthetic attention, aesthetic attitude, aesthetic judgement, aesthetic concepts, aesthetic pleasure, and aesthetic appreciation. However, the fact that ‘aesthetic’ is a promiscuous modifier is not by itself cause for complaint. The moral and the perceptual are equally promiscuous. We do of course have grounds for complaint if, at the end of the day, the aesthetic what-nots are not reducible to a small set of relatively more basic aesthetic what-nots. Two candidates 167 dominate the current literature. The majority hold that a state of mind – usually an experience – is more basic than other aesthetic what-nots (e.g. Beardsley , Dickie , Levinson , Walton , Budd , ch. , Stecker , Iseminger , ch. , Goldman ). The minority position is that properties or values are more basic than other aesthetic what-nots (e.g. Sharpe , Carroll , Carroll , Shelley ). The presumption that an aesthetic appreciation involves an attribution of aesthetic value is consistent with the positions of both the majority and the minority. An advantage of the buck passing theory of art is that it frees us to consider theories of aesthetic appreciation independently of theories of art. An aesthetic theory of art must strike a balance between two conditions. On one hand, it should invoke an independent conception of the aesthetic, not one that implies the very theory by which it is invoked. It asks a theory of the aesthetic to stand on its own feet. On the other hand, the concept of the aesthetic that it invokes should help to correctly carve out the domain of art. The invoked concept should not generate counterexamples to the invoking theory. Balancing these conditions constrains and so can exert a distorting force on theories of aesthetic appreciation. A blatant example is the ninetieth century appeal to beauty, at least according to Danto’s history (). Danto writes that ‘it was long assumed that works of art constituted a restricted and somewhat exalted set of objects that everyone would be able to identify as such’ (, ). Given an aesthetic theory of art, it was natural to explain art’s exalted status by identifying aesthetic value with an exalted conception of beauty as bearing high moral and even cognitive weight (Danto , – and Shiner , –, –). Thus near the end of the long nineteenth century, G. E. Moore identified ‘the pleasures of human intercourse and the enjoyment of beautiful objects’ as ‘by far the most valuable things we can know or can imagine’ (, ). Moore did not think he was being provocative – he went on to add that probably nobody ‘will think that anything else has nearly so great a value’ as ‘personal affection and the appreciation of what is beautiful in Art or Nature’ (, ). Bell, a member of Moore’s circle, confessed 168 to being ‘tempted to believe that art might prove the world’s salvation’ (, ???). In Danto’s history, the avant-garde sets out to wreck this marriage of art to beauty by creating works that offer anything but the enjoyment of beauty. Mediated by an aesthetic theory of art, bad ideas about art may be projected onto the aesthetic, and they may continue to attach to the latter even once cleansed from the former. Here again is Danto: ‘I regard the discovery that something can be good art without being beautiful as one of the great conceptual clarifications of twentieth century philosophy of art…. That clarification managed to push reference to aesthetics out of any proposed definition of art’ (, ). In this passage, Danto identifies aesthetic value with beauty and indeed with the exalted conception of beauty. He forgets that this identification is a product of the exalted idea of art and should fall as it falls. The palpable hopelessness of the exalted idea of art does not by itself push aesthetics out of any theory of art. (Nor does it rule out less exalted conceptions of beauty – e.g. Nehamas .) Once the demands of the highfalutin theory of art that Danto discusses have been shrugged off, the identification of aesthetic value with beauty is hardly mandatory. Already in the eighteenth century, some understood the aesthetic with reference to the sublime as well as to beauty (Burke ). Many now consider aesthetic value to be realized by way of any of a number of thicker merits or demerits, such as being graceful, shocking, and balanced or insipid, didactic, and incoherent (Sibley , Sibley , Zangwill a). Perhaps not all of these are compatible with beauty. A work’s aesthetic power may consist in its being disturbing and ugly, for example. The options are best kept open for now. Another dead horse is flogged by Carroll (, see also Carroll ). Carroll argues that the western tradition since the early modern period is dominated by a characterization of aesthetic value as realized in experiences of disinterested pleasure. He also conjectures that the dominance of this characterization results from the consolidation of the modern system of the arts in the eighteenth century (see Chapter ). That is, works of art, 169 understood as works prized exclusively for the intrinsically valuable experiences they encourage, can be thought to stand apart, virtually automatically, from all the other arts – such as agriculture, rhetoric, and engineering – since the other arts are valued primarily for their utility and not the sake of the intrinsically valued experiences they engender. If aesthetic experience is the mark of Art, properly so called, and aesthetic experience is divorced from serving any ulterior purpose, then Artworks, properly so called, thereby have no essential truck with any aims, interests, or purposes other than that of providing intrinsically valued experiences (Carroll , ). So the tremendous authority wielded by the theory of aesthetic experience as disinterested pleasure was backed by the theory of art that invoked it. Needless to say, this theory of art is a non-starter. There are works of art whose aesthetic value is inextricably bound up with their ‘utility’. The cathedral at Chartres, for example, or Eero Saarinen’s tulip chair. Surely Stephen Davies is right that ‘a beautiful chair is one having features that make it graceful and stylish and, at the same time, comfortable to sit on, stable and supportive of the back’ (, ). Moreover, aesthetic experience is ubiquitous. Assuming that clothing design is not an art, the iconic dresses made by Chanel in the s are nevertheless beautiful. If their beauty is bound up with their ‘utility’, then they furnish another example of the inadequacy of the theory of aesthetic experience as disinterested pleasure (see Parsons and Carlson ). The same goes if their beauty does not consist in a disposition to evoke disinterested pleasure. And if their beauty is independent of their utility and consists in a disposition to evoke disinterested pleasure, then the proposed theory of art is inadequate. Theories of the aesthetic can be pulled off course by the weight imposed upon them by theories of art. It would be rash to conclude that no aesthetic theory of art is correct, but it would be wise to keep in mind that a correct aesthetic theory of art requires a correct theory of the aesthetic as it is distinctively realized in the 170 individual arts and as it is found beyond the realm of art altogether. The Aesthetic in the Twins Arguments While the theories of aesthetic value arraigned by Danto and Carroll now boast few fans, contemporary thinking about the aesthetic is profoundly shaped by the twins arguments. Since the s, these arguments have functioned as fulcrums to leverage theorizing about art, and their workings include theories of the aesthetic. Thus the canonical version of the twins argument laid out in Chapter assumes that, A. if the features that make an item a work of art are aesthetic, then the features that make an item a work of art are among or supervene on its perceptible features. What this assumption comes to is sharpened by the additional assumption that, A. if the features that make an item a work of art are among or supervene on its perceptible features, then no work of art is perceptually indiscernible from a twin item that is not a work of art. Since some works of art have perceptually indiscernible non-art twins, it follows that the features that make an item a work of art are not aesthetic. That was Danto’s () landmark argument. Its axiological spinoff begins with a similar pair of assumptions. First, V. if the value of a work of art is wholly aesthetic, then its value supervenes on its perceptible features, and, second, V. if the value of a work supervenes on its perceptible features, then no work differs in value from an indiscernible twin. Since some works of art differ in value from their perceptually indiscernible twins, it follows that the value of a work of art is not wholly aesthetic. Setting aside whether each of these arguments, 171 taken as a whole, ultimately holds up, notice that each one is launched by a theory of the aesthetic – a theory of aesthetic properties in the case of (A) and a theory of aesthetic value in (V). The view of the aesthetic embodied in (A) and (V) implies that aesthetic properties and values are perceptual. Such a theory enjoys wide currency. Levinson, for example, holds that aesthetic properties are higher-order ways of appearing that depend on and emerge out of lower-order ways of appearing, where these are looks and sounds and the like (, –). An interesting example of a view of aesthetic value as perceptible in a literal sense is that assumed by Parsons and Carlson () in their defence of functional beauty. Having defined an item’s functional beauty as its ‘looking fit for function’, they assume the burden of explaining what it is for an item’s being fit for function to be ‘translated’ into its look or sound. ‘It is not’, they write, ‘that we see beauty, and then assess how well that beauty fits with function. If things are functionally beautiful, then knowing the function is what allows observers to see the beauty in the first place’ (, ). If the twins arguments deserve to be taken seriously – and they do – then it is only because (A) and (V) are either true or ring true. If they are not true, then they are nearly true. Perhaps they are so nearly true as to save the soundness of the twins arguments; perhaps they are not (Shelley ). Neither alternative is enough by itself to vindicate an aesthetic theory of art; putting theories of art to the side, two questions make a good start on a theory of aesthetic appreciation, as that phenomenon figures in contemporary thinking. Are (A) and (V) true? If not, what theory of aesthetic appreciation gives them the ring of truth? Beyond Perception The old chestnut in discussions that reach this point is that Baumgarten ([]) named the field of aesthetics by defining it as the science of sensible knowledge. According to Binkley’s influential diagnosis of where he thought aesthetic theories of art go wrong, ‘Baumgarten’s “science of perception” is a moribund 172 enterprise…. Yet a survey of contemporary aesthetic theory will prove that this part of philosophy still accepts its raison d’être to be a perceptual entity – an appearance’ (, ). In order for the twins arguments to reach the conclusions that they reach, (A) and (V) must identify perceptible features with features ‘discerned through the senses’ (Danto , ). One might well ask what else they could be. Theorizing without an explanandum in view is a treacherous business, even if theories help bring explananda into view. Iseminger singles out the following fact for explanation: aesthetic appreciation of an item requires an experience of the item (, ). He is not alone (e.g. Sibley , Pettit , Mothersill , Eaton ; cf. Budd , Livingston , Meskin ). Wollheim agrees that aesthetic judgements ‘must be based on firsthand experience of their objects’ (, ) and Alan Tormey puts it that ‘we require critical judgements to be rooted in “eyewitness” encounters’ (, ). Each immediately follows up by remarking on what they take to be a consequence of the claim. Wollheim adds that aesthetic judgements are not ‘transmissible from one person to another’ and Tormey that ‘the epistemically indirect avenues of evidence, inference, and authority that are permissible elsewhere are anathema here’. The thesis that aesthetic appreciation requires ‘first hand experience’ or an ‘eye-witness encounter’ has come to be called the ‘acquaintance principle’. The question is how to interpret the principle. Tormey draws an epistemic lesson from the principle, and the principle is frequently interpreted as implying that aesthetic testimony is weak (e.g. Hopkins , Budd , Livingston , Meskin ). For sake of simplicity, define testimony as communication from one person to another, wherein the testifier asserts something she believes. A testifier’s asserting a belief usually entitles her audience to that belief. Most of us have title to believe only through testimony that Socrates was Athenian and that brown is dark orange. Aesthetic testimony is a communication which consists in the testifier asserting an aesthetic judgement, and Tormey denies that it provides much title to belief. My assertion that the hybrid teas I just planted are elegant gives you little right to join in my judgement. The 173 explanation is that aesthetic judgement requires ‘first-hand experience’. Critics of the acquaintance principle sometimes deny that aesthetic testimony is weak in this way; and there are at least some domains of aesthetic discourse where it seems not to be (Laetz ). Fortunately, there is no need to take sides in the debate on aesthetic testimony (for that see Lopes a). There are independent reasons to downplay the epistemic interpretation of the acquaintance principle. First, there is a gap between the claims that aesthetic judgement is ‘based on first-hand experience’ and the claim that aesthetic testimony affords little or no title to aesthetic judgement. After all, perceptual belief is based on first-hand experience but perceptual testimony affords title to perceptual belief. You are entitled to believe that my cat is brown when I assert my perceptual belief that she is brown. Evidently, we cannot take aesthetic judgement to be ‘based on first-hand experience’ in just the way that perceptual belief is based on first-hand experience. The challenge remains to say what is meant by the principle that aesthetic judgement is ‘based on first-hand experience’. The idea that this might be understood in plainly perceptual terms – terms friendly to (A) and (V) – does not pan out. Second, the epistemic interpretation is too narrow. The acquaintance principle is supposed to be general, applying to all aesthetic appreciation, including the aesthetic appreciation of literature. We must read for ourselves before we judge, just as we must see or listen for ourselves. Yet most literary works have no perceptible properties. The epistemic interpretation of the acquaintance principle does not solve this puzzle. The options are either to seek an interpretation of the acquaintance principle that makes sense of its application to literature or, desperately, to deny that most literary works can be objects of aesthetic evaluation (e.g. Zangwill ). An important, obvious, yet neglected lesson is this. Barring desperate measures, a theory of aesthetic appreciation must make sense of the aesthetic appreciation of items without perceptible features – most works of literature, for a start. Danto takes Hume to task for speaking of beauty in literature: he tells us that Hume 174 must have really been thinking of ‘literary excellence, superiority, and depth’ and should have distinguished ‘between aesthetic beauty and what we might call artistic beauty’ (, –). Why assume that Hume did not have a perceptual conception of aesthetic value inconsistent with (V)? For example, Francis Hutcheson outlined a conception of aesthetic appreciation intended to cover intellectual objects such as mathematic theorems as well as sensuous objects like paintings (Shelley ; see also Iseminger ). A final and (as it will turn out) useful problem facing the epistemic interpretation of the acquaintance principle is that it is too broad. Classic statements of the principle come with a qualification. Thus Tormey grants that ‘reproductions or representations’ such as photographs and drawings ‘may, for critical purposes, be adequate surrogates for the object of critical judgement’ (, ). The qualification is sensible. Images are important vehicles for communicating information, including information about the aesthetic qualities of things, and people routinely make aesthetic judgements on the basis of images of scenes or objects (cf. Stock , –). Photographs and drawings are used to convey the aesthetic qualities of all kinds of consumer goods. We may not trust what we see in advertising images, but not all mass media images are geared to advertising. Consider travel reporting, as distinct from travel advertising. Many people make and then act on aesthetic judgements by looking at images in travel guidebooks and newspaper travel sections. The same goes for clothing and flower catalogues, architectural drawings, and on-line personals. Images also play a key role in communicating the aesthetic qualities of art works. When painting moved out of church and palace into the secular public space of the art museum, it also moved onto the printed page, first through engraving and then through photography and now Google Images and ARTstor. Paintings and sculptures, especially canonical or famous ones, are more often seen depicted than face-to-face. Is it going out on a limb to add that we often judge these works via images of them? Could these images be the exception to the rule that aesthetic testimony is weak? Not unless the use of images to transmit 175 aesthetic judgements from person to person is a form of aesthetic testimony. But images cannot be vehicles for aesthetic testimony. The claim is not that images are never used to assert. Believing that Josh is taller than Brian, I show you a picture of them, which I sincerely take to be accurate, with the intention of getting you to believe that Josh is taller than Brian – and I take responsibility for my action. In general, images can be used in acts of assertion as vehicles that depict what is asserted (Novitz , Eaton , Korsmeyer , Lopes , ch. ). The reason images cannot be vehicles for aesthetic testimony is that testimony involves ‘bare’ assertion. When I tell you that the butter is in the fridge and you accept my testimony, my reasons for my belief may become your reasons, but you do not have cognitive access to my reasons because I do not assert them. If I assert my reasons along with my belief that p, then your title to believe that p derives from your accepting my stated reasons for p and not from my bare assertion that p. However, images never figure in acts of bare assertion as to the aesthetic qualities of things. I cannot show you a picture of my tea roses that depicts their elegance without also depicting some of the features that seem to make them elegant. I cannot even show you a picture that depicts a simple elegant line without depicting some of the features that seem to make it elegant. There is no bare depiction of aesthetic features, so there is no bare assertion of aesthetic judgements via depiction. If I show you a photograph of my tea roses and you judge that they are elegant, then you so judge because you seem to see what makes them elegant, not merely because you rely on my say-so. Since images cannot figure in aesthetic testimony, they cannot supply an exception to the rule that aesthetic testimony is weak. Yet they are an exception to the acquaintance principle. So the acquaintance principle should not be interpreted epistemically, as a claim implying the weakness of aesthetic testimony. For the record, none of the reasons to downplay the epistemic interpretation of the acquaintance principle decisively defeat it. They leave wiggle room. But they are enough to warrant a search for a better interpretation. They also provide some hints towards a better interpretation. ‘First-hand experience’ is not just perception 176 by means of the senses. Imperceptible items may be objects of aesthetic appreciation. Aesthetic judgement is not transmissible by words but it is transmissible by images, or ‘surrogates’ more generally. Aesthetic Acquaintance ‘One cannot’, according to Binkley, ‘communicate Mona Lisa by describing it’ (, ). Alexander Nehamas elaborates that ‘nothing a critic ever says about a work can show how it will effect me when I am exposed to it directly’ (, ). These observations echo the principle that aesthetic judgement must be ‘based on first-hand experience’ but they seems less to be getting at an epistemic fact that a fact about the transmission of mental states. Suppose that transmission is a content-preserving relation between representations. Philip Pettit writes that ‘the state one is in when… one sincerely assents to a given aesthetic characterization is not a state to which one can have nonperceptual access’ – it is ‘essentially perceptual’ (, ). This claim about access is considerably stronger than any claim about entitlement. When the transmission of an aesthetic judgement is blocked, the result is not merely that the person on the receiving end makes a judgement to which he is not entitled. He is not in a position to make the judgement at all. Representational states are transmitted from one person to another only with the help of artifactual representations, such as sentences and images. Thus transmission can be analyzed as a relation that obtains between the cognitive state of a transmitter and an artifactual representation only when the artifactual representation is understood by the receiver. As an approximation: R is transmitted by R only if full grasp of R is a state R whose content includes the content of R. This is only a partial analysis, but it is enough for an account of what it is for types of states to be transmissible. A type of cognitive state is transmissible by a given type of artifactual representation just in case representations of that type transmit 177 states of that type. By this analysis, many types of cognitive state are transmissible by any type of artifactual representation. A perceptual belief that mondo grass is black is transmissible by my saying ‘mondo grass is black’ because your grasp of this sentence consists in having a thought whose content includes that of the perceptual belief. But I have a choice of media and I can show you a picture of some mondo grass instead. Understood in this way, transmission is non-epistemic: you might believe that mondo grass is black, or imagine it, wish it, or even doubt it. Perhaps aesthetic judgements are only transmissible by certain types of representations. How so? Remembering my walk along the Nakasen-do, I judge that it is beautiful, I tell you so, and you grasp the thought expressed by my words, but your thought differs in content from my judgement because the content of my judgement is ‘essentially perceptual’ and the content of your thought is not. Since your thought does not have the same type of content as my judgement, my judgement is not transmitted to you. Yet when I convey what I judge by showing you a photograph of the Nakasen-do, your grasp of the photograph is a state which has the same type of content as my judgement, so aesthetic judgement is transmissible via images. An extreme proposal is that aesthetic features are essentially perceptual in the sense that they are ineffable, they cannot be conceptualized or named. As Michael Tanner expresses the view, aesthetic judgements ‘must be based on first-hand experience… because one is not capable of understanding the meaning of the terms which designate the properties without the experience’ (, ). This kind of view has called some fire down upon the acquaintance principle (e.g. Livingston ). Materials for a moderate alternative come from contrasting depiction with description, if aesthetic judgements are transmitted by images and not words. As we have seen, there is no bare depiction of aesthetic features, whereas there is bare description of aesthetic features. Describing a line as graceful represents gracefulness without representing non-aesthetic features of the line, but no image depicts a line as graceful without depicting some non-aesthetic features that seem to make it graceful. 178 Indeed, the line’s grace is not depicted in addition to depicting non-aesthetic features that seem to make it graceful. There is no more to depicting the line as graceful than depicting non-aesthetic features that seem to make it graceful. Thus the only explanation for an image’s failing to depict a line’s grace is that it fails to depict some non-aesthetic features that would seem to make it graceful. By contrast, no description of a work’s non-aesthetic features implies a description of its aesthetic features (Sibley ). So there is always something more to describing a line’s grace than listing the non-aesthetic features that seem to make it graceful. Although ‘the line fits the equation y(x + a) = a’ may describe a line as having the very feature responsible for its grace, the sentence fails to describe the line as graceful. Of course, some descriptions represent the line’s grace as determined by the nonaesthetic features that make it graceful: ‘the line is graceful because it fits the equation y(x + a) = a’. Again, however, with the image, there is nothing more to depicting the line as graceful than depicting its shape. Some representations have inseparable content: R represents x as F inseparably from its representing x as B = R represents x as F by and only by representing x as B. An image depicts a line as graceful by and only by depicting it as having certain non-aesthetic features. In general, aesthetic features are depicted by and only by depicting certain non-aesthetic features. The aesthetic content of depictions is inseparable. By contrast, the aesthetic content of descriptions is not inseparable. Aesthetic features are never described by or only by describing non-aesthetic features. My saying ‘the Saarinen chair is beautiful because its floral geometry so surprisingly fits it to its purpose’ describes the chair as beautiful and also describes a non-aesthetic feature that makes it beautiful, but the beauty is not described by and only by describing its geometry and its function. Frank Sibley touched on a similar point, but mistakenly took it to suggest that inseparable content distinguishes aesthetic judgement from ordinary perceptual experience. He wrote that, if a man were not in a position to see or discern that a line had such and such a curve… he could not conceivably tell that the 179 line was… graceful…. One sees the grace in that particular curve. And if one cannot clearly see or discern the determinate character or properties which are responsible for the merit-term ‘P’ being applicable, one cannot discern that ‘P’ applies (, ). Sibley then attempted to draw a contrast with seeing the brightness of a highway sign. Suppose that speckled signs look brighter than signs with uniform colours, and a given highway sign looks bright because it is speckled. From a distance, one sees the sign’s brightness without seeing its speckling, so seeing the brightness is separable from seeing the speckling that makes for the brightness. Sibley inferred that its inseparable content marks aesthetic judgement apart from ordinary perceptual experience, which has separable content. Grasping why this inference is too hasty drives home an important point about inseparable content. One sees the sign’s brightness without seeing its speckling, but it does not follow that the brightness is represented inseparably. The sign looks uniformly coloured from a distance, and experience may well represent the sign’s brightness by and only by representing its uniform coloration. Perhaps we do see the sign’s brightness by and only by seeing other features that seem to make it bright, albeit not always the features that actually make it bright. It would be too much to expect that when a state represents x as F inseparably from its representing x as B, the representation of x as B is in fact responsible for the representation of x as F. The highway sign’s speckling and not its uniform colour is responsible for its looking bright, but experience may represent its brightness inseparably from its uniform colour. Inseparable aesthetic content is no different. From a distance, the scene in Georges Seurat’s Bathers at Asnières looks calm and dreamy. Moreover, we see this calm dreaminess by and only by seeing the scene’s flat and uniform coloration. Of course, this is an illusion. The calm dreaminess is achieved not through flat and uniform coloration but rather through saturated hues laid down in dots which are visible only from up close. Moving in close, we are 180 surprised to learn what features are actually responsible for our seeing the scene as dreamy. A little jargon helps track the distinction that is now in hand. Let ‘aesthetic judgement’ name a mental state that ascribes an aesthetic value inseparably. Let ‘aesthetic belief’ name a mental state that ascribes an aesthetic value separably. Aesthetic judgements are not transmissible in words; aesthetic beliefs are. (This suggests a hypothesis. We systematically confuse aesthetic belief and aesthetic judgement and hence the non-transmissibility of aesthetic judgement with the weakness of aesthetic testimony. Distinguishing aesthetic judgement and belief might help to sort out the problem of aesthetic testimony, for that problem concerns whether accurate aesthetic descriptions warrant aesthetic belief. See Levinson , –, Lopes a.) A Theory of Aesthetic Appreciation Correctly interpreted, the acquaintance principle represents a truth about aesthetic judgement. One can say a lot about the Mona Lisa, but a description is no substitute for an encounter the painting, either face-to-face or through a suitable surrogate. The explanation is that aesthetic judgement represents the Mona Lisa’s value inseparably; this is how it is that aesthetic judgements are ‘essentially perceptual’ or ‘based on first-hand experience’. Combining this result with the stipulated generic theory of appreciation, here is a theory of specifically aesthetic appreciation: an aesthetic appreciation of an item is a cognitive process that includes an aesthetic judgement of the item. Typically the judgement that is part of an aesthetic appreciation results from acts of classification and interpretation and it may also yield pleasure – these may be ingredients in the process of appreciation – but the essential ingredient is aesthetic judgement, where an aesthetic judgement of an item is a mental state that represents the aesthetic value of the item inseparably from the non-aesthetic properties that seem to realize that value. This theory of aesthetic appreciation explains why the acquaintance principle, correctly interpreted, is true. It implies that a description of an item is not enough to afford an aesthetic 181 appreciation of the item. Aesthetic judgement is not transmissible by words. At the same time, a face-to-face encounter with the item is not required: certain kinds of memories and artifactual representations of an item may mediate an aesthetic appreciation of it. The theory also accommodates the aesthetic appreciation of literary works and other works whose aesthetic value is not realized by perceptible features. The paradigm of inseparable content is provided by judgements that represent aesthetic values of an item by and only by representing its apparent perceptible features. However, the definition of inseparable content abstracts from the perceptual paradigm: R represents x as F inseparably from its representing x as B = R represents x as F by and only by representing x as B. The aesthetic values of a story or poem are represented inseparably from the semantic and prosodic properties that realize them when they are represented by and only by the experience of reading the story or the poem. If the reader will forgive an example in ill taste…. Pride and Prejudice and Zombies by Seth Graeme-Smith and Jane Austen is a witty mashup. More than four-fifths of the text is original Austen, into which is interpolated deadpan descriptions of stupid and insatiable brain-eating zombies and the zombie-fighting Ninja prowess of the Bennett sisters. Some of the wit comes from the martial arts spin given to the Austen’s treatment of courtship and the blurring of line between silly girls and zombies, especially in contrast with the black-belted Bennett girls. Some of the wit is meta-textual, for the interpolations ‘cannibalize’ Austen’s text in a variety of ways. It is possible to go on describing what makes the book a witty mashup, and exensive description might just convince you of the book’s merits. However, those merits, if they are merits, are represented inseparably from the story itself when you read it, starting from the opening sentence, ‘It is a truth universally acknowledged that a zombie in possession of brains will be in want of more brains… ’. Making a full case for this theory of aesthetic appreciation would require another book. The theory appears at first glance to 182 be logically consistent with a number of other theories (e.g. Budd , Iseminger , Lopes , ch. , Shelley , Shelley MS) and it also appears to be inconsistent with others, notably hedonistic theories, which take pleasure to be essential to aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic value (e.g. Beardsley , Beardsley , Walton , Levinson ). A full case would include a demonstration that the theories it is inconsistent with are inadequate and that it is to be preferred over any theories it is consistent with, unless it entails or is entailed by them. All this must await another occasion. For now, what matters is how the theory contributes to a framework for developing developing theories of the arts. According to the proposed framework, the arts are appreciative kinds. That is, K is an appreciative kind if and only if is there is a property of being good qua K, or being good-modified for a K, or being good qua K* for a K. Since aesthetic appreciations attribute aesthetic values, this framework applies to works in an art form only if they are objects of aesthetic appreciation. So does the framework apply to arts like literature, which are made up of non-perceptible works? Not if (V) is true, given the proposed theory of aesthetic appreciation plus a plausible assumption. This assumption is that the non-aesthetic properties that are represented inseparably from an item’s aesthetic value are among the properties upon which that value supervenes. That is, in general, if an aesthetic value, V, is accurately represented inseparably from determinable properties B, then being V supervenes in part on being B. In other words, what makes something graceful or beautiful is not some grand illusion – it is the curve of the line, the light in the eyes, the choice of words. So if literature is an art made up of nonperceptible works and if these are objects of aesthetic appreciation, then their aesthetic value does not supervene even in part on perceptible properties. This result is inconsistent with (V). As long as (V) is true, there is no room in the proposed 183 framework for aesthetic appreciation as it pertains to arts made up of non-perceptible works. Therefore, as long as literature is an art and as long as literary works bear aesthetic value, the theory of aesthetic appreciation on offer here improves on (V). Not only is it inconsistent with (V) but it also explains why (V) rings true. It rings true because perception is a paradigm of inseparable representation. More importantly, it fits nicely into the framework for developing theories of the arts. This is because it does not rule out that there is a property of being aesthetically-good-modified for a work of literature. On the contrary, such a property is a value that is represented in our reading of the work in a way inseparably from the apparent semantic and prosodic features of the work that realize it. These are features that the work has because it is a work of literature, so the fact that they realize certain aesthetic values points to the nature of literature. The same goes for the other arts. The fact that a work is aesthetically good for a K points to what it is to be a K. Moreover, if part of what makes it the case that a work belongs to an art form is that it realizes aesthetic value, then there is a property of being aesthetically good qua K. What makes a K aesthetically good qua K is what makes it a K, so again its aesthetic goodness points to the nature of Ks. A rather motley collection of theses go by the name of ‘formalism’, though the theses so named are not logical kin (e.g Zangwill , Nanay MS). Here is yet another expression of formalism: some goodness-aesthetically-modified simpliciter is realized by some works of art, w, though it is neither goodness qua K nor goodness-aesthetically-modified for a K, where w is a K. Is this true? It does not matter for present purposes, for the values in question give us no information about the nature of any art form. Everywhere Aesthetics Giving up on (A) and (V) is not the end of the twins arguments. If, as the arguments assume, aesthetic properties are predominantly understood nowadays as perceptual or 184 supervening on perceptual properties, then the arguments may send us back to the drawing board to rethink the aesthetic. However, updated theories of the aesthetic might also plug into the twins arguments. Aesthetic properties and values are ubiquitous. They are found in natural objects – a theory of the aesthetic that can say nothing about the beauty (and ugliness) of the human body had better have powerful compensating virtues. Having acquired a sensibility that is tuned into the aesthetic values in natural objects, human beings can only be expected to want to make things with the same kinds of properties and also to take advantage of the features of the things they make to realize aesthetic values that cannot be found in nature. No rule channels this desire into the realm of art. Almost anything that is the product of human creativity is an opportunity to add to the stock of aesthetic value in the world. A great deal of the time, the opportunity is not wasted. Art furnishes but a corner of our aesthetic environment. A good theory of aesthetic value must accommodate this ubiquity. The theory of aesthetic value modelled in (V) fails this standard because it limits aesthetic values to the perceptual domain. The theory of aesthetic appreciation as involving the cognitive representation of aesthetic values inseparably from the non-aesthetic features imposes no such limitation. It is consistent with a theory of aesthetic value which explains its ubiquity. If this is a merit of the theory, it also puts it within reach of updated twins arguments. It makes it very unlikely that there aren’t some works of art that have aesthetic – but not necessarily perceptual – twins. This is the deep power of the twins arguments. The challenge to aesthetic theories of art is sometimes said to be this: there is non-aesthetic, indeed even anti-aesthetic art. Examples tend to be works that denigrate beauty but there may be works of art that scorn, or at least turn their backs on, any aesthetic value whatsoever. Grant the point. It is not in the final analysis the most compelling interpretation. The challenge to aesthetic theories of art is this: a work of art may have a non-art twin though both have plenty of aesthetic value. Thus Danto () admires the obviously powerful aesthetic merits of the 185 Brillo boxes – the items found in the grocery store – while denying them status as art. The challenge is that an aesthetic theory of art must either accept them as art or downplay their aesthetic qualities. Fancy aesthetic theories of art do not take the aesthetic qualities of a work to suffice in making it a work of art. Thus the challenge may be restated: what makes Warhol’s Brillo Boxes art, if it is art, apart from the aesthetic properties that it shares with the Brillo boxes? One traditional answer is that Warhol’s product was made primarily with an intention to have these properties or, by having them, to bring about some state. The man who designed the Brillo box was an abstract expressionist painter and it strains credibility that his intentions were not aesthetic. Another traditional answer is that art works have special aesthetic properties. But what fences them in to the art world? Whatever they are, can they not find their way into the toolkits of those making non-art? None of this amounts to a anything close to a decisive refutation aesthetic theories of art. However, it is important to appreciate how tough a challenge is posed to any aesthetic theory by the twins arguments. Aesthetic theories of the arts are not in the same boat. An aesthetic theory of an art form, K, states that at least part of what makes an item a K is that it realizes aesthetic value by taking advantage of its medium, and in accordance with its constitutive norms. There may be many artifacts in the same medium that are not works in the art form: they are not made as part of the relevant practice. Nothing could be in the same medium and part of the same practice yet not A work in K. The twins arguments can gain no ground on theories of the arts. Those theories have resources to fend them off. Art, by contrast, has no constitutive medium and no constitutive practice. The buck passing theory of art lets us have our cake and eat it. We can develop aesthetic theories of the arts (though they are not the only option). At the same time we can take the twins arguments very seriously indeed. Can we ignore the hard cases? Not at all. To them it is time to return. Much Ado About Art This book is committed to a vision of the philosophy of art as genuinely attentive to and even inspired by significant events in the history of art, especially during the past century. Although some of the most interesting work in the discipline pursues this same vision by developing buck stopping theories of art, it would be a serious mistake to think that buck stopping theories provide the only tool by means of which philosophers may grapple seriously with recent triumph and turmoil in the art world. The buck passing theory of art also equips us to represent recent history in an illuminating way, and perhaps it does a better job at this than its competition. Hard Cases and Free Agents The function of any theory is to do some work, and work requires resistance. Chapters and argue that a principal source of resistance for buck stopping theories of art is the hard cases. Resistance to the buck passing theory of art comes from works of art that in Chapters and were called ‘free agents’. Since these works are in fact, if not by necessity, the same works as the hard cases, one might wonder whether the effort of stopping up one gopher hole has been wasted, as the self same gopher pops up nearby. The first order of business must be to clarify the relationship between hard cases and free agents. Doing that takes a step towards a better understanding of a prominent strand of recent art. Examples of hard cases pepper previous chapters. The touchstones have been Duchamp’s Fountain, Warhol’s Brillo Boxes, and Cage’s ’”. Beyond these, Christo’s wraps, Williams’s ‘This Is Just to Say’, Nichols’s ‘Cold Mountain’, Rauschenberg’s Erased de Kooning Drawing, Barry’s Inert Gas Series, and Vautier’s Regardez moi cela suffit je suis art have also been mentioned. Meanwhile, the literature reaches out further yet to acknowledge Mary Jane Jacobs Culture in Action initiatives, John Baldessari’s Everything Is Purged from This Painting but Art, and Christine Kozlov’s ‘movie’ entitled Transparent Film #. It is important to 187 register that these works are not concoctions of the philosophical imagination; they really exist. Existence is hard to quibble with; the issue is how to classify these items in an illuminating and useful way. The Introduction and Chapter stipulated to a technical definition of the hard cases that recruits them to a precise philosophical task: they are items whose status as works of art is controversial and contested, making them test cases for buck stopping theories of art. Calling Cage’s piece or Kozlov’s reel of transparent film a ‘hard case’ is neutral on whether or not it is a work of art. Furthermore, hard cases need not be borderline or marginal; it is not some vagueness that makes them controversial. Theories according to which they are not works of art may imply that they are clearly – even paradigmatically – not art, and theories that take them to be works of art may imply that they are central cases of works of art. The buck passing theory of art is neutral on the hard cases, as it refers them elsewhere, to theories of the individual arts (or possibly to a theory of the arts as a whole). Indeed, the theory implies neither that the hard cases are central nor that they are marginal; it treats the question of their centrality or marginality as not terribly meaningful. The idea is not, however, to sweep the hard cases under the carpet. The fact is that the hard cases have fuelled the development of buck stopping theories of art, and those theories are supposed to be informative in so far as they deal adequately with the hard cases. That goes not only for genetic theories that are inspired by the hard cases but also for traditional theories that downplay the hard cases as outliers in thirty thousand years of human art making that should not be given too much weight in theory-building. Since the hard cases do grip us, the buck passing theory of art is not a live option unless it enables us to contend with them in a serious manner. To answer the ‘informativeness challenge’, the buck passing theory of art must accomplish two tasks. First, it must represent the hard cases as posing a puzzle that calls upon philosophy for a response. It cannot brush off the hard cases – that would be taking sides. Second, it must propose a theoretical tool for dealing with the hard cases that has rosier prospects than buck stopping theories of art. 188 The buck passing theory of art says that what makes an item a work of art is a matter of its meeting two conditions: it belongs to a kind and that kind numbers among the arts. An item is a work of art only if it is a product of some art kind. The question of what makes Fountain a work of art, if it is one, is replaced with a different question, of what makes it a sculpture – or a member of some other art kind. The new question leaves room for puzzlement. If Fountain is a work of art then maybe it is a sculpture? But then it is puzzling what make things sculptures… so perhaps it belongs to some other art form? Which one? Likewise, if Transparent Film # is a work of art then presumably it is a movie? But does it really have what it takes to be a movie? Perhaps it belongs to some other art form? Which one? The buck passing theory of art takes the hard cases seriously – as posing a puzzle that calls upon philosophy for a response – by interpreting the puzzle as a puzzle about their membership in art kinds. Moreover, the task of saying what makes an item a sculpture or a song or a poem or a dance is in principle more tractable than saying what makes it a work of art. The buck passing theory of art does not require that theories of all of the arts draw upon the very same resources. It allows for a mix of traditional and genetic theories of different arts, for example. It also recommends a bottom-up approach: start with empirical facts about the specific media and practices of the art, as these figure in appreciation of works in that art. Start, in other words, with the hypotheses and generalizations of art history and theory; of the sociology and anthropology of art; and of developmental, cognitive, and social psychology. What it is to be an art practice is implicit in empirical research about art works and their appreciation. Observation is theory-laden so that a change of theory can make a difference to empirical research, and the buck passing theory of art has a revisionist edge in so far as standard art history shares philosophy’s understanding of the hard cases as test cases for theories of art. Thierry de Duve (, ) makes a point of the fact that the earliest incarnation of Dickie’s institutional theory of art coincided with the appearance of Joseph Kosuth’s ‘Art after Philosophy’ ([]). Just when Dickie was inspired by certain works which he saw as undercutting traditional 189 theories of art, Kosuth’s essay seemed to voice the agenda of an important body of artistic work and its associated discourse. According to Kosuth, this work distills art to its essence, namely to express the proposition that ‘art is the definition of art’ and to ‘inquir[e] into the foundations of the concept “art”’ ([], –). Whatever the exact meaning of these dicta, they were surely meant to encapsulate the idea that certain art works put in play theories of art by demanding a theory of art that sends traditional theories of art packing. An adaptation of traditional theories is not in the cards: the hard cases embody art in its purest form and an entirely new kind of theory is needed to represent them as central cases and not as products of an experimental fringe. What, for example, would be a central case of a work of art for a genetic theory but Duchamp’s Fountain? The details of the reasoning articulated by Kosuth and his peers clearly echo the philosophical arguments that put theories of art in play. Citing the authority of Fountain, Kosuth argues that ‘aesthetics… are conceptually irrelevant to art’ ([], ). Presumably the thought is either that Fountain has no aesthetic qualities yet it is a work of art or else that it does not differ in its aesthetic qualities from an ordinary urinal and yet it is a work of art. Either way, the elements are in place to construct the canonical version of the twins argument (see Chapter ). Both versions of that argument hinge on there being art works with perceptually indiscernible non-art twins (the canonical version additionally assumes that aesthetic features of works are perceptual). Unsurprisingly, then, Kosuth also argues that ‘art’s viability is not connected to the presentation of visual (or other) kinds of experience’ ([], ). He remarks, for example, that there are ‘a vast quantity of similar looking objects or images’ affording similar ‘visual/experiential “readings”’ but ‘one cannot claim from this an artistic… relationship’ ([], ). Thus far philosophy of art goes hand in hand with the explicitly expressed self-understanding of at least one art movement. (It is worth pausing to remark how closely Danto’s vision of this body of work matches its own self-understanding, since Danto has so powerfully shaped the way philosophical theories of 190 art are framed. He argues in Transfiguration of the Commonplace that the philosophical question of [art’s] status has almost become the very essence of art itself, so that the philosophy of art, instead of standing outside the subject and answering it from an alien and external perspective, became instead the articulation of the internal energies of the subject… artworks have been transfigured into exercises in the philosophy of art (1981, 56). Following up in The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art, he writes that ‘the objects approach zero as their theory approaches infinity, so that virtually all there is at the end is theory, art finally having become vaporized in a dazzle of pure thought about itself’ (, ).) Suppose we accept at face value the body of art world discourse which Kosuth exemplifies. (What is to be gained by interrupting this cheerful display of amity between art and philosophy?) Works like Everything Is Purged from This Painting but Art and Transparent Film # were made to function as test cases for buck stopping theories of art. Undoubtedly, they cannot be appreciated fully without acknowledging this fact. The buck passing theory of art never denies that the hard cases are hard cases, but it does recommend against the kind of theorizing that they invite. However, the theory is not entirely revisionist, since it recommends a theoretical approach that reflects a theme developed by Kosuth and others. Kosuth borrows for an epigraph to his essay a line from Donald Judd, his fellow artist and manifesto writer: ‘everything sculpture has, my work doesn’t’ ([], ). The aesthetic and perceptual features of the works that Kosuth has in mind are irrelevant to their status as art, and that is because their material features are irrelevant to their status as art. As long as the medium of a work has to do with its material makeup and defines the kind of art it is, this is art of no particular kind. Among the philosophers, Binkley most clearly sees that the hard cases challenge traditional, aesthetic theories of art by 191 challenging the principle that ‘media are the basic categories of art… and each work is identified through its medium’ (, ). His argument is, in brief, that the aesthetic properties of a work are indeterminate until we specify which of its non-aesthetic properties are relevant to appreciation. The non-aesthetic properties of physical materials are organized by convention into media, so that ‘by being told which medium a work is in, we are given the parameters within which to search for and experience its aesthetic qualities’ (, ). The thought is that the hard cases undermine traditional aesthetic theories of art by weakening the regime of media upon which aesthetic appreciation depends. As Binkley puts it, ‘art has become increasingly non-aesthetic in the twentieth century, straining the conventions of media to the point where lines between them blur. Some works of art are presented in “multi-media”, others (such as Duchamp’s) cannot be placed within a medium at all’ (, ). He concludes that ‘art need not be aesthetic’ (, ). Among art theorists, de Duve () gives the view trenchant expression in his reading of the significance of Duchamp’s Fountain. This is ‘neither a painting nor a sculpture, nor, for that matter, a poem or a piece of music. It doesn’t belong to any of the arts. It is either art at large or nothing’ (, -). The same goes for any readymade, which is ‘not painting, not sculpture and not something interspecific straddling both’ (, ). It is generic art, made by a generic artist, who is an ‘artist at large’ and not ‘a painter, or a sculptor, or a composer, or a writer, or an architect’ (, ). Notice that these writers seek to represent what is puzzling about certain works not by characterizing them as hard cases that test buck stopping theories of art but rather as free agents that test the reduction of art to the arts. A free agent is a work of art that does not belong to an art. If Kosuth, Binkley, and de Duve are correct, then artists have made works that are hard cases by making works that are free agents. No wonder the hard cases happen to be coextensive with the free agents. However, the free agents do not figure as free agents in the twins arguments, which never mention media or art forms. Nor do theories of art contend with the hard cases as free agents: no 192 traditional theory insists that works of art have media and belong to art forms and only Binkley defends a genetic theory by arguing that having a medium and being in an art form is inessential to art. In sum, works like Brillo Boxes and ’” throw a gauntlet down at philosophy’s feet that is not met by drawing pistols over buck stopping theories of art. The buck passing theory of art does not let the gauntlet lie, for it implies that there can be no free agents. It represents the free agents as a theoretical challenge. The theory is informative if it sheds new light on the alleged free agents. Viability: The Methodology Since free agents are works of art that seem to belong to no art kind, they are potential counterexamples to the buck passing theory of art. The theory is not viable if we sometimes cannot pass the buck because there is nowhere for it to go. Worse, if the objection succeeds, then it shows the need for a buck stopping theory of art. The answer to this objection very much turns on a methodological stance that has come into view at several points so far and that will return us in the next section to the history surveyed in the previous section. Given Brillo Boxes, there are four options (see Chapter ). The item is not a work of art, or it is a work of art and it belongs to a familiar and traditionally enfranchised art form, or it is a work of art that pioneers a new art form, or it is a work of art, pure and simple – a free agent. While the buck passing theory of art might seem at first glance to be trivial, it does in fact undertake the following commitment. It rules out the fourth option – it implies that there are no free agents – and thereby undertakes the responsibility of showing which one of the other options is appropriate for Brillo Boxes and its kin. Indeed, the first option is also ruled out, not as a matter of logic but as a matter of advantage. The point of the buck passing theory of art is to sidestep the impasse over buck stopping theories of art and we do not make much progress if the buck passing theory reroutes us back into the impasse. That leaves the middle two options – to 193 assign any alleged free agent either to a traditional or an emerging art. The viability of the buck passing theory of art requires considerable resilience from both of the middle options. Some reasons to regard an art work as a free rider are in fact reasons to find it a home in an enfranchised art kind. The enfranchised art kinds are what they are, but we may understand them imperfectly, with the result that we fail to recognize some of their members. Brillo Boxes may question the art of painting from the inside, so that it succeeds in its own terms only if it is a painting, even as it fails to fit our concept of painting. Its failing to fit our concept of painting, when it is a painting, brings us round to a concept of painting that better represents the possibilities of the art form. Likewise, some reasons to regard an art work as a free agent are reasons to credit it with expanding the modern system of the arts. Photography, film, video, computer art, and street art have solid credentials as recent additions to the arts, and the number of new arts continues to grow. The hypothesis that an alleged free rider pioneers an art form might also allow us to to understand it in its own terms, as a work of art that pushes the boundaries of the arts beyond Batteux’s legacy. Neither move requires a solution to the problem that vexed Batteux and the early modern art theorists. That problem was to come up with a theory of the arts, which states what makes any kind an art kind. Technically, the middle options require that the free agents meet two conditions. First, each free agent belongs to a kind. Second, that kind numbers among the arts. Since the prospects of a theory of the arts are not good, not much weight should be put on what makes that kind an art kind. Someone might well grant that a work belongs to a kind and yet insist that it is a free agent because that kind is not an art. Good luck to them! If that is the objection to the buck passing theory of art, it is not decisive. (See Chapter for a full defence of this position.) The bar that an item must clear in order to count as a genuine free agent must be set neither too high nor too low. It would certainly set the bar far too high to insist that a free agent belong to no kind except art. Fountain is, after all, a urinal; a Brillo Box is a box; and ’” is an event. That much has to be common ground 194 and it would be too much to ask anyone to deny it who wishes to make the case against the viability of the buck passing theory of art. Here is where the framework sketched in Chapters to comes in handy. While the buck passing theory of art does not entail that framework, that framework does provide a neutral benchmark for free agency. The framework is, x is a work of K, where K is an art = x is a work in medium profile M, where M is an appreciative kind, and x is a product of an M-centred appreciative practice. Assume, then, that a work is a free agent only if there is no such K to which it belongs. Of course, one might propose a different framework, so long as it does not set the bar for free agency too low. Anyone who alleges that a work is a free agent because it fails a more restrictive framework must provide a good argument for the proposed framework that is independent of their advocacy of free agency. Otherwise the reply on behalf of the buck passing theory will be that the proposed framework begs the question. We must guard against works that seem to be free agents only given overly restrictive frameworks. To take one example, Rosalind Krauss observes that ‘the very idea of the artist's invention of a medium… will undoubtedly make us nervous. A medium is… a shared language developed over centuries of practice so that no individual initiative, we would think, can either organize new sources of its meaning or change established ones’ (, ). Krauss is quiet right to reject this conception of an art kind as having a long history. There are new arts and they are sometimes invented by individuals or small groups of individuals. Taking the framework as read, in the absence of an alternative to it, an item is a genuine free agent only if it is not the product of an M-centred practice. The presumption is that case for free agency is to be securely anchored in empirical studies of the arts. This is not to say that empirical research directly confirms or disconfirms the existence of free agents, in the way that experimental physicists run experiments to look for the Higgs boson posited by theoretical 195 physics. As already noted, it is not existence but classification or correct description that is tricky: the problem is not whether Inert Gas Series exists but whether it belongs to an art, if it is a work of art. Historians and other empirical art scholars seem to speak of works as free agents, but the question is how to interpret their claims from a theoretical perspective. The avowals of critics are theory-driven and sometimes the wrong theory is at the helm. That is where philosophy has a contribution to make. That is, the presumption is that philosophy’s contribution consists in providing a framework of theories that are logically interconnected so as to display, in an illuminating manner, the conceptual resources that are implicit in the best empirical hypotheses and explanations. Putting it colloquially, philosophers must articulate what is doing the work in empirical research. Theories of art and the individual arts model technical concepts that are implicit in empirical research about art works and their appreciation. To be blunt about what this means, theorists should not privilege intuitions purporting to reveal the application conditions of folk concepts of art or the individual arts. For one thing, folk intuitions about free agents are not pre-theoretical; they are shaped by background theories of art, and the evidence is that folk concepts of art are feral descendants of a technical concept of art (see Chapter ). To consult folk intuitions under these circumstances is to get at technical matters indirectly, over a notoriously unreliable channel. In addition, intuitions are uninformative unless tested in very thickly described scenarios. One might ruminate, from the armchair, whether there could there be a work of art not belonging to any art. Who knows what any answer to that question means? An answer becomes meaningful only when there is enough detail about what an art is and about the case in question to see whether the latter falls under the former. The situation is hardly improved by asking ‘could there be a work of art that is not the product of a medium-centred practice, where a medium is an appreciative kind?’ Try that in a survey at the mall – or in the seminar room – and the answers will tell you nothing. 196 The safe bet is that once a scenario is so thickly described that it is probative, we are doing serious empirical research. Let there be no misunderstanding. Philosophers are not well equipped to undertake empirical art studies. These pages do not attempt to amass empirical evidence in defence of the buck stopping theory of art. They sketch a theoretical framework that is in some ways implicit in and in other ways helpfully revisionary of the best empirical understanding of the alleged free agents. What is an art work? The buck passing theory of art answers that it is a member of an art kind. That is an invitation to further research framed by the proposal that an art kind is an appreciative kind that figures in a medium-centred practice. The objection is that some works are better understood as free agents. The reply is that understanding these works as members of art kinds better brings out what is radically revolutionary about them and also what it is in them that is connected to tradition and the rest of art. The Post Material Condition The buck passing theory of art refers us to theories of the individual arts on the expectation that what appear to be free agents actually belong to established or pioneering art kinds. Given the framework for developing theories of the arts, one way to stand up for genuine free agents is to argue that they are not products of M-centred practices because they have no media. As the slogan has it, they inhabit a ‘post-medium condition’ (Krauss ). The problem is that this case for free agency implies an unacceptable conception of art media. The fundamental questions concern what media are and how they figure in making each art what it is, and some features of contemporary art only impugn obviously untenable answers to these questions. For example, Binkley describes some twentieth century art woks as a toppling tradition either because they are ‘multi-media’ or because they ‘cannot be placed within a medium at all’ (, ). More recently, Krauss stresses the significance of art which ‘jettisoned the use of a specific medium in order to juxtapose image and written text within the same work. The now- 197 fashionable possibility of installation art followed in the wake of this dispatch of the medium’ (, xiii). However, multimedia is not new – witness opera and manuscript illumination – and so it is better to understand each art not as having a single, unique medium but rather as having a ‘medium profile’, often combining several media (see Chapter ). Chapter also proposed an account of media as ‘technical resources’, resources that are accessed through sets of techniques. If every work of art is an artefact, then every art work results from applying some technique or other to some or other resource. Cage did not do nothing with nothing in making ’” and, as de Duve describes them, Duchamp’s machinations in the making of Fountain were supremely effortful, elaborate, and sophisticated. Yet this is not enough to conclude the defence of the buck passing theory of art against free agency. One might accept that all works of art are made from something by some means and nevertheless deny that every art work has an art medium. The American Heritage Dictionary, a drop of whiskey (for mental lubrication), and a Visconti pen might be used to find, assemble, and record words in the making of a poem, but they are not part of the medium profile of poetry. Not all means are art media. The fact that Cage and Duchamp went busy about making ’” and Fountain is not yet proof that these works have media. What is needed is the claim that Cage and Duchamp were working in practices that are medium-centred in the sense that they cannot be fully characterized except with reference to media. To say that not all media are art media is to say that not all media centre art practices. Works like ’” and Fountain are free agents because they are not made using media that centre art practices. The objection from free agency to the buck passing theory of art is now hull’s up. The reply begins with the thought that to see whether an apparent free agent has a medium, it is crucial to examine the practice of which it is a product and hence also its historical context and problematic. A look at empirical studies of works like Fountain, ’”, Inert Gas Series, and Transparent Film # may suggest why they pioneer new arts. Historians have a named art movement that seems to subsume works of the kind that are candidates for free agency. That 198 category is conceptual art, and it is sufficiently well established as a category of art that its critical writings have been gathered together in a canon (Alberro and Stimson ), it has been introduced to a wider public under the name of ‘conceptual art’ (Godfrey , Wood ), and it has even been studied as a distinctive phenomenon by philosophers (Goldie and Schellekens ). For now, it should be left open whether every alleged free agent is a work of conceptual art – to assume otherwise may beg the question against free agency. No matter, for conceptual art developed around an aspiration to free agency, and so it makes for a useful case study that may generalize. That is, a look at the medium profile of conceptual art, which is alleged not to have any medium at all, may indicate how to think about the medium of other kinds of alleged free agent. According to standard taxonomy, typical or classical conceptual art comprises readymades, performances, documentation, and word-based art made during the late s and early s (e.g. Godfrey , ). It is to be distinguished from other avant-garde movements, such as arte povera and Fluxus, which sought not to dispense with media altogether but rather to hybridize them and bring them down to earth. Even so, according to standard art history, these movements share a common origin as repudiations of mid-century modernist art theory as represented by the writings of Greenberg (, and also Fried ). As we saw in Chapter , Greenberg (was thought to have) held that each art is specified by a unique medium and works in that art are properly appreciated only for their medium-specific features. ‘The arts,’ he wrote, ‘are to achieve concreteness, “purity”, by acting solely in terms of their separate and irreducible selves’ (, ). Hybridization and the adoption of non-traditional media is one response to these doctrines; another is to attempt to do entirely without media. Now consider how this attempt is described by conceptual artists at the time. Kosuth has already been quoted: ‘art’s viability is not connected to the presentation of visual (or other) kinds of experience’, though, he added, ‘this may have been one of art’s extraneous functions in the preceding centuries’ ([]: ). Sol LeWitt offered that ‘when words such as painting and 199 sculpture are used, they connote a whole tradition and imply a consequent acceptance of this tradition, thus placing limitations on the artist who would be reluctant to make art that goes beyond the limitations’ ([]: ). About the same time, Ian Burn wrote that ‘for painting to be ‘‘real’’, its problems must be problems of art. But neither painting nor sculpture is synonymous with art, though they may be used as art’ (Burn []: ). The first issue of Art – Language proclaimed the movement’s target to be the idea that ‘the making of a traditional art object (i.e. one judged within the visual evaluative framework) is a necessary condition for the making of art’ (Art–Language []: ). ‘Art’ in these passages can only shorten ‘visual art’ (or the art form that has traditionally gone by that name). It is patently untrue to say that anyone ever thought that art in the generic sense, which includes all of the arts, is essentially visual; the propositions that art need not be visual and that it exceeds the bounds of painting and sculpture are completely obvious and uninformative as long as music and literature count as arts. What is happening is that early conceptual artists are engaged in a practice which they see as standing up to a Greenbergian conception of visual art as specified by and to be evaluated only in terms of visual effects. Therefore, let is grant that some works of conceptual art have no visual features whatsoever and most make use of visual media that do not centre the relevant practice (see Currie , Hopkins ). Works of art that do not belong to a practice that is centred on a visual medium may yet belong to some other medium-centred practice (indeed, a work that has a lot of features in common with paintings and sculptures may yet be a work in some other art form). It is a platitude that in conceptual art ‘the idea is paramount and the material form is secondary, lightweight, cheap, unpretentious and/or “dematerialized”’ (Lippard , vii). And it is a short step from this platitude to the claim that the core medium of conceptual art is something like language or a set of ideas, especially ideas about art. There may be more to its medium profile, but this is its core. Binkley wrote that some artists ‘might opt for articulation of a semantic space… so that artistic meaning 200 is not embodied in a physical object or event according to the convention of a medium’ (, ). The step is short but not immediate, for language and ideas might be used in making art without centring the practice of conceptual art. They centre the practice if it cannot be fully characterized without reference to them. More particularly, they centre the practice if that practice includes at least one of two general norms, as well as some number of specific norms on how language and ideas are to be used in the practice (see Chapter , pp. –). One general norm would be that we are not to appreciate an item as a work of conceptual art unless it does use language and ideas. Another general norm would be that we are not to appreciate an item as a work of conceptual art if that appreciation counterfactually depends on beliefs that are inconsistent with the truth about what it is for a work to use language and ideas as a medium. It is, of course, an empirical – that is, socio-historical – question whether either or both of these norms governs practices of conceptual art appreciation. So is it a mistake to appreciate ‘Salt Peanuts’ as performed in by Dizzy Gillespie and His All-Stars as a work of conceptual art that is up to the same tricks as Barry’s Inert Gas Series? Would such an appreciation licence quizzical looks and perhaps even correction? Or is it a mistake to appreciate Barry’s Inert Gas Series as a failed piece of conceptual art because one supposes that the ideas it manipulates must be inscriptions, as in Baldessari’s Everything Is Purged from This Painting but Art? Would it be in order to correct someone who so appreciates the Baldessari, explaining to them that linguistic inscription is one among many resources for the kind of work Baldessari is doing. Insisting that these works are genuine free agents comes with a cost: we must give up on conceptual art involving a use of certain materials that we must get right in successful appreciation. One reason to distance conceptual art from any thought of its being centred on a medium is that media were traditionally taken as foci of aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic appreciation was traditionally taken to be perceptually mediated. The anti-aesthetic character of conceptual art is an attempt to shield it from being understood through aesthetic experience, and the attempt may 201 succeed so long as appreciation is identified with aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic appreciation is taken to be a mode of perception. However, one might think that appreciation attributes many varieties of goodness to works of art and aesthetic appreciation is not essentially perceptual and applies to literature and theories as much as to paintings (see Chapters and ). A broad theory of appreciation provides tools to get a grip on the core media of conceptual art as implicated in norm-governed appreciations. Granted, the proposition that the core medium that centres the practice of conceptual art is ‘something like language and ideas’ is vague. However, further precision is not to be obtained a priori, but rather by engaging in empirical research. For example, there is evidence, already mentioned, that the ideas that are materials for conceptual art characteristically explore the nature of art. Perhaps the medium profile of conceptual art incorporates thematic resources – doctrines of the modern system of the arts, midcentury modernism, and indeed the philosophy of art since Weitz. That hypothesis would, at any rate, appear to explain many features of conceptual art production, not least what is said by practitioners and historians (and also some philosophers). This is, to repeat, an empirical hypothesis and not a conceptual truth. No further precision is required to make that case that we cannot recruit free agents from the corpus of conceptual art. Here is the argument. Conceptual art can supply free agents only if it is not a medium-centred practice. It has no medium that centres a practice if media are material stuffs and events. However, media may include conceptual and symbolic resources and techniques. Many features of conceptual art are explained on the hypothesis that it is centred on language and ideas as its medium. That is, many features of the alleged free agents are explained on this hypothesis. This argument to show that we cannot recruit free agents from the corpus of conceptual art is important because conceptual art works seem to aspire to free agency. The present task has been to look closely at conceptual art to learn how to discern a mediumcentred practice where none appears to be. However, this does not complete the defence of the buck passing theory of art against 202 the viability objection. One might still wonder whether a case study of conceptual art generalizes to every alleged free agent. Art-As-Art As a Kind of Art Many alleged free agents can be identified as works of conceptual art, but the reasoning of the previous section may suggest what to look for in locating free agents roaming beyond the domain of conceptual art. These works would be products of a practice that embodies the two norms, but where these norms are generic norms governing every kind of art. Works of this kind are free agents because they are purely generic works of art belonging to no specific kind of art. Duchamp’s Fountain is arguably such a case. The reason is not that it antedates conceptual art proper by several decades. It is sometime necessary and generally legitimate to appreciate precursors of a kind as works of the kind, and Fountain is either conceptual art or a precursor of it. Rather, the argument would be that conceptual art evolved as a specific art kind out of purely generic art works. There is a strand in de Duve’s authoritative commentary on Fountain that takes literally the assertion that the work is ‘neither a painting nor a sculpture, nor, for that matter, a poem or a piece of music. It doesn’t belong to any of the arts. It is either art at large or nothing’ (, -). The literal reading adds that it is not conceptual art either. As an aside, it is interesting to note that critics who take this line about Fountain tend to waver, even in the space of a couple of sentences. For all his rigour, de Duve writes that ‘readymades… are “art” and nothing but “art”. Whereas an abstract painting reduced to a black square on a white background is art only when you accept seeing it as a painting, a urinal is a sculpture only when you accept seeing it as art. Otherwise it simply remains a urinal’ (, , emphasis added). Or again, he write that ‘a new “species” of art is born, for which the risk of confusion with nonart is greater than ever before’ (, ). Part of a full understanding of Fountain should explain this wavering in thinking about it. 203 Returning to the literal reading, the claim would be that Fountain does not even have language and ideas – even ideas about art – as its medium. Of course, it is made using ideas, just as it is made of porcelain slip, but these are no more its medium than is the porcelain. It is a product of a practice not centred on any medium profile. As de Duve puts it, the practice is governed by the following norm: ‘do whatever so that it be called art. But make it such that, through what you will have made… you make it felt that this something was imposed on you by an idea of the anything whatever that is its rule’ (, ). That is, after Duchamp, anything can be used to make an item a work of art, where what is used to make a work of art is not what makes the item a work of art. de Duve proposes that what makes the item a work of art is something like a baptism in which is it named ‘art’ (, ff). Simply asserting that Fountain is pure generic art will not suffice to establish the reality of free agency, but the idea of purely generic art does seem to be implicit in a widely accepted approach to the work by de Duve, and many others. Here is a small taste. A remarkable feature of pure generic art is that it has arisen only out of the visual arts and nowhere else. ‘No musician’, according to de Duve, ‘would claim that what he or she is doing is “art” and nothing but “art”’ (, ; see also ). The explanation of this fact is that the doctrines of modernism pulled far more strongly upon visual art than any of the other arts, so that ‘painting gradually became more and more regulated by the idea of its own specificity, or purity, or autonomy’ (de Duve , ). Having already stripped away figurative depiction, any hint of representation, and the even figure–ground relation, the logical next step was to excise media entirely (see de Duve , ). The result is, apparently, the making of works that are not specific to any art form because what makes them art is what makes anything art. It is this history of Fountain that plausibly implicates a concept of pure generic art populated by free agents. The viability of the buck passing theory of art is saved if this history may be interpreted without appeal to a concept of pure generic art that is no specific kind of art. One alternative interpretation is as follows. Fountain is part of the modernist 204 project of reducing art to minimal constitutive elements – to the basics, as it were. Perhaps, indeed, what make Fountain art is its being art without a medium. However, the result is a work that belongs to a specific art form – call it ‘art-as-art’ (after Reinhardt [], ). Fountain and other works of art-as-art are aptly described as ‘generic’ in the sense that what makes an item a work of art-as-art is not a specific set of resources and techniques. However, they are unlike any dances, songs, paintings, conceptual art works, poems, and buildings in an important respect: what makes an item a work of art-as-art is not a specific set of resources and techniques. This fact individuates art-as-art as a specific art form. Putting the proposal in terms of the framework for theories of the arts, art-as-art is centred on a medium profile that is empty. Two interpretations of the history are now on the table. A troublesome interpretation puts the buck passing theory of art in jeopardy by opening the door to free agents. The alternative saves the theory by point to the flexibility of the framework for theories of the arts. Is there any reason to favour the latter over the former? There are several. To begin with, the troublesome interpretation is not mandatory. One might reasoning that it is: what makes Fountain a work of art is nothing more than what makes any given item a work of art; and if what makes Fountain a work of art is part of what makes every item a work of art, then it is generic art and not a specific kind of art; so Fountain is pure generic art, not a specific kind of art. The first premise of this argument is tendentious, projecting what is true of Fountain onto art works that were probably not made as art – Beowulf, for example, or a mask by Kwakwaka’wakw carver Jim Howard in the nineteenth century (see Chapter ). Setting aside this objection to the opening premise of the argument, let us grant it along with the second premise, which captures what the history suggests. The question is whether the second premise can be unhooked from the conclusion by denying the third premise, namely that if what makes Fountain a work of art is part of what makes every item a work of art, then it is generic art and not a specific kind of art. Why should that be true? It does not in general follow from the fact that an item only 205 has features that are common to all species of a genus that it belongs to no species of the genus. It might be explanatory to distinguish the simple F things from the F-and-G things and the Fand-H things. It is useful in several ways to interpret Fountain as art-as-art. It should be expected that an art practice would emerge, given suitable conditions, with a null medium. That is the limiting condition of the framework for theories of art, and art explores to its limits. If Fountain is not art-as-art, something is, or very probably will be. Moreover, we should predict that there would be some confusion – or a deliberate playfulness – over the distinction between being generic and not specific, on one hand, and being specific in a non-specific way, on the other. Finally, the proposal that Fountain is art-as-art locates it within a practice governed by the appreciative norms centred on an empty medium profile. Is it a mistake to appreciate a Brancusi Bird as having no medium in the way that Fountain has no medium? Is it a mistake to appreciate Fountain in the belief that what makes something art-as-art is its pokes fun at abstract sculpture? Affirmative answers to these questions indicate that art-as-art fits the framework for theories of the arts and thereby makes explicit the norms that govern our appreciation of Duchamp’s readymade. The hypothesis that, if it has no medium, Fountain is a work of art-as-art is a reasonable one. It serves the standard history at least as well as the hypothesis that it is a free agent. The claim that there are genuine free agents is not incoherent and the counterclaim that apparent free agents are either works of conceptual art or art-as-art is also coherent. Both claims do justice to the historical facts. Since we are at a wash, some metatheoretical advantages of the latter become relevant. If there are free agents, then we need buck stopping theories of art, and they stand at an impasse. As a result, pursuing buck stopping theories of art is not likely to shed light on the free agents – traditionalists will hotly dispute de Duve’s account of Fountain, thus denying Fountain is art, and geneticists will reply that Fountain is art so a genetic theory of art is needed. Meanwhile, if Fountain is art-as-art and genetic factors make it so, it does not follow that we are committed 206 to a genetic theory of music or dance. Is that sufficient reason to heave to and impress Fountain as art-as-art? All else being equal, the theories to choose are the most explanatory ones. We should not allow free agency to tie our hands in understanding the stunning variety of practices that are the arts. Works Cited Abell, Catharine. . Cinema as a Representational Art, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Alberro, Alexander and Blake Stimson, eds. . Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology. Cambridge: MIT Press. Artinfo. . Europe Rules That Dan Flavin and Bill Viola Artworks Are Not Art, Artinfo. http://www.artinfo.com/news/ story/. Art–Language. []. Introduction, in Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology, ed. Alexander Alberro and Blake Stimson. Cambridge: MIT Press. Arnheim, Rudolf. []. Film as Art. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Barnes, Annette. . Definition of Art, in Encyclopedia of Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Batteux, Charles. . Les Beaux-arts Reduits à un Même Principe. Paris: Durand. Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. []. Aesthetica. Hildesheim: G. Olms. Bazin, André. [–]. What Is Cinema? trans. Hugh Gray. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Beardsley, Monroe. . Aesthetic Experience Regained, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . The Aesthetic Point of View, Metaphilosophy : – . ——— . In Defense of Aesthetic Value, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association : –. ——— []. Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism, nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett. ——— . Redefining Art, in The Aesthetic Point of View, ed. Michael Wreen and Donald Callen. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ——— . What Is Going on in a Dance? Dance Research Journal : –. ——— . An Aesthetic Definition of Art, in What Is Art? ed. Hugh Curtler. New Haven: Yale University Press. Bell, Clive. . Art. London: Chatto and Windus. 208 Bergeron, Vincent and Dominic McIver Lopes. . Aesthetic Theory and Aesthetic Science: Prospects for Integration, in Aesthetic Science: Connecting Minds, Brains, and Experience, ed. Steven Palmer and Arthur Shimamura. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Binkley, Timothy. . Piece: Contra Aesthetics, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Blocker, H. Gene. . Is Primitive Art Art? Journal of Aesthetic Education : –. Bourdieu, Peirre. . Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste, trans. Richard Nice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Budd, Malcolm. . Values of Art. London: Penguin. ——— . The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . The Aesthetics of Nature, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society : –. ——— . The Acquaintance Principle, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Burke, Edmund. . A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful. London: R. and J. Dodsley. Burn, Ian. []. Conceptual Art as Art, in Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology, ed. Alexander Alberro and Blake Stimson. Cambridge: MIT Press. Carlson, Allen. . Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Objectivity, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Carroll, Noël. . The Specificity of Media in the Arts, Journal of Aesthetic Education : –. ——— . Art and Interaction, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . Beauty and the Genealogy of Art Theory, Philosophical Forum : –. ——— . Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— a. Defining the Moving Image, in Theorizing the Moving Image. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 209 ——— b. Moderate Moralism, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Philosophy of Art. London: Routledge. ——— . Art and the Domain of the Aesthetic, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . On Being Moved by Nature: Between Religion and Natural History, in Beyond Aesthetics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— . Aesthetic Experience Revisited. British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Forget the Medium! in Engaging the Moving Image. New Haven: Yale University Press. ——— . Aesthetic Experience, Art, and Artists, in Aesthetic Experience, ed. Richard Shusterman and Adele Tomlin. London: Routledge. ——— . The Philosophy of Motion Pictures. Oxford: WileyBlackwell. Choi, Jinhee. . Bibliography, in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Collingwood, R. G. . The Principles of Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Croce, Benedetto. []. Aesthetic: As Science of Expression and General Linguistic, trans. Douglas Ainslie. New York: Noonday. Crow, Thomas, . Modern Art in the Common Culture. New Haven: Yale University Press. Cummins, Robert. . Functional Analysis, Journal of Philosophy : –. Currie, Gregory. . An Ontology of Art. London: Macmillan. ——— . A Note on Art and Historical Concepts, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Visual Conceptual Art, in Philosophy and Conceptual Art, ed. Goldie, Peter and Elisabeth Schellekens. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— . Actual Art, Possible Art, and Art’s Definition, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Danto, Arthur C. . The Artworld, Journal of Philosophy : –. 210 ——— . Transfiguration of the Commonplace. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ——— . The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art. New York: Columbia University Press. ——— . After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ——— . Art and Meaning, in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. ——— . The Abuse of Beauty. Chicago: Open Court. Davies, David. . Art as Performance. Oxford: Blackwell. ——— . Medium in Art, in Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, ed. Jerrold Levinson. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Davies, Stephen. . Definitions of Art. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ——— . Themes in the Philosophy of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— . Aesthetic Judgments, Artworks, and Functional Beauty, Philosophical Quarterly : –. Dean, Jeffrey. . The Nature of Concepts and the Definition of Art, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. de Duve, Thierry. . Kant after Duchamp. Cambridge: MIT Press. Dickie, George. . The Institutional Conception of Art, in Language and Aesthetics, ed. Benjamin Tilghman. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas. ——— . Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ——— . The Art Circle. New York: Haven. ——— . Evaluating Art. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. ——— . Art and Value. Oxford: Blackwell. ——— . The Triumph in Triumph of the Will, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Dowling, Christopher. . The Aesthetics of Daily Life, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Dummett, Michael. . Seas of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 211 Dutton, Denis. . Mythologies of Tribal Art, African Arts : –. ——— . But They Don’t Have Our Concept of Art, in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. ——— . The Art Instinct: Pleasure, Beauty, and Human Evolution. New York: Bloomsbury Press. Eagleton, Terry. . Marxism and Literary Criticism. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Eaton, Marcia. . Truth in Pictures, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . A Sustainable Definition of Art, in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. ——— . Merit, Aesthetic and Ethical. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fodor, Jerry. . Déjà Vu All Over Again, in Danto and His Critics, ed. Mark Rollins. Oxford: Blackwell. Freeland, Cynthia. . But Is it Art? New York: Oxford University Press. Fried, Michael. . Art and Objecthood, ArtForum : –. Gaut, Berys. . ‘Art’ as a Cluster Concept, in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. ——— . Art, Emotion, and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— . A Philosophy of Cinematic Art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Godfrey, Tony. . Conceptual Art. Oxford: Phaidon. Goldie, Peter and Elisabeth Schellekens. eds. . Philosophy and Conceptual Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goldman, Alan. . Aesthetic Qualities and Aesthetic Value, Journal of Philosophy : –. ——— . The Experiential Account of Aesthetic Value, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Gombrich, E. H. . The Story of Art. London, Phaidon. ——— . Art and Illusion. London: Phaidon. 212 Greenberg, Clement. . Towards a Newer Laocoon, Partisan Review : –. ——— . The New Sculpture, in Art and Culture. Boston: Beacon Press. Halliwell, Stephen. . The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Hamilton, James. . The Art of Theater. Oxford: Blackwell. Hanslick, Eduard. [] On the Musically Beautiful: A Contribution Towards the Revision of the Aesthetics of Music, trans. Geoffrey Payzant. Indianapolis: Hackett. Heerman, Victor. . Animal Crackers. Hollywood: Paramount. Hegel, G. F. W. []. Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T. M. Knox. New York: Oxford University Press. Hilpinen, Risto. . On Artifacts and Works of Art, Theoria : –. Hopkins, Robert. . Beauty and Testimony, in Philosophy, the Good, the True, the Beautiful, ed. Anthony O’Hear. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— . Aesthetics, Experience, and Discrimination, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . Speaking Through Silence: Conceptual Art and Conversational Implicature, in Philosophy and Conceptual Art, ed. Goldie, Peter and Elisabeth Schellekens. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hutcheson, Francis. . An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue. Irvin, Sherri. a. The Pervasiveness of the Aesthetic in Ordinary Experience, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— b. Scratching an Itch, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Iseminger, Gary. . The Aesthetic Function of Art. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Jacobson, Daniel. . Ethical Criticism and the Vice of Moderation, in Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Matthew Kieran. Oxford: Blackwell. Jenkins, Carrie. . The Rules of Flirtation, The Philosophers Magazine : –. 213 Kant, Immanuel. []. Critique of the Power of Judgement, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kennel Club. . Shetland Sheepdog Breed Standard. www.thekennelclub.org.uk/item/. Kennick, William. . Does Traditional Aesthetics Rest on a Mistake? Mind : –. Kieran, Matthew. . Revealing Art. London: Routledge. Kivy, Peter. . Philosophies of Arts. New York: Cambridge University Press. Korsmeyer, Carolyn. . Pictorial Assertion, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Kosuth, Joseph. []. Art after Philosophy, in Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology, ed. Alexander Alberro and Blake Stimson. Cambridge: MIT Press. Krauss, Rosalind. . Perpetual Inventory. Cambridge: MIT Press. Kristeller, P. O. –. The Modern System of the Arts, Journal of the History of Ideas : – and : –. Laetz, Brian. . A Modest Defense of Aesthetic Testimony, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . Kendall Walton’s ‘Categories of Art’: A Critical Commentary. British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Lamarque, Peter. . The Philosophy of Literature. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. ——— . Précis of The Philosophy of Literature, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— and Stein Haugom Olsen. . Truth, Fiction, and Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lessing, G. E. []. Laocoon, trans. E. A. McCormick. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. Levinson, Jerrold. . Defining Art Historically, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Refining Art Historically, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . The Concept of Music, in Music, Art, and Metaphysics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. 214 ——— . Pleasure and the Value of Works of Art, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Extending Art Historically, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . What Is Aesthetic Pleasure? in The Pleasures of Aesthetics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ——— . Aesthetic Properties, Evaluative Force, and Differences of Sensibility, in Aesthetic Concepts: Essays After Sibley, ed. Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— a Hume’s Standard of Taste: The Real Problem, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— b. The Irreducible Historicality of the Concept of Art, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Aesthetic Properties, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume : –. Levitin, Daniel. . This Is Your Brain on Music: The Science of a Human Obsession. New York: Dutton. Lewis, David. . Convention. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. LeWitt, Sol. []. Sentences on Conceptual Art, in Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology, ed. Alexander Alberro and Blake Stimson. Cambridge: MIT Press. Lind, Richard. . The Aesthetic Essence of Art, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Lippard, Lucy. . Six Years: The Dematerialization of the Art Object from to . New York: Praeger. Livingston, Paisley. . On an Apparent Truism in Aesthetics, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Longworth, Francis and Andrea Scarantino. . The Disjunctive Theory of Art: The Cluster Account Reformulated, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Lopes, Dominic McIver. . The Aesthetics of Photographic Transparency, Mind : –. ——— . Digital Art, in Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information, ed. Luciano Floridi. Oxford: Blackwell. 215 ——— . Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— a. Art Without ‘Art’, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— b. Conceptual Art Is Not What It Seems, in Philosophy and Conceptual Art, ed. Peter Goldie and Elizabeth Schellekens. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— c. Critical Notice of The Aesthetic Function of Art by Gary Iseminger, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research : –. ——— a. Nobody Needs a Theory of Art, Journal of Philosophy : –. ——— b. True Appreciation, in Photography and Philosophy: New Essays on the Pencil of Nature, ed. Scott Walden. Oxford: Blackwell. ——— a. Aesthetic Acquaintance, Modern Schoolman, Special Issue on Varieties of Perception, : –. ——— b. A Philosophy of Computer Art. London: Routledge. ——— . The Myth of (Non-Aesthetic) Artistic Value, Philosophical Quarterly .: –. ——— forthcoming. Feckless Reason. Mandelbaum, Maurice. . Family Resemblances and Generalizations Concerning the Arts, American Philosophical Quarterly : –. Margolis, Eric and Stephen Laurence. . Concepts: Core Readings. Cambridge: MIT Press. Matthews, Robert. . Traditional Aesthetics Defended, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Maynard, Patrick. . The Engine of Visualization: Thinking Through Photography. Ithaca: Cornel University Press. Melchionne, Kevin. . Living in Glass Houses: Domesticity, Interior Decoration, and Environmental Aesthetics, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Meskin, Aaron. . Aesthetic Testimony: What Can We Learn from Others about Beauty and Art? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research : –. ——— . From Defining Art to the Defining the Individual Arts: The Role of Theory in the Philosophies of Arts, in New 216 Waves in Aesthetics, ed. Kathleen Stock and Katherine Thomson-Jones. London: Palgrave Macmillan. Millikan, Ruth Garrett. . Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge: MIT Press. Mitchell, W. J. T. . There Are No Visual Media, Journal of Visual Culture : –. Moore, G. E. . Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Moravcsik, Julius. . Art and ‘Art’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy : –. Mothersill, Mary. . Beauty Restored. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nanay, Bence. MS. Neo-formalism. Nehamas, Alexander. . Only a Promise of Happiness: The Place of Beauty in a World of Art. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Newhall, Beaumont. . Photography: A Short Critical History. New York: Museum of Modern Art. Novitz, David. Pictures and Their Use in Communication. The Hague: Nijhoff. ——— . Art by Another Name, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. Parsons, Glenn. . Aesthetics and Nature. London: Continuum Press. ——— and Allen Carlson. . Functional Beauty. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pater, Walter. . The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry. London: Macmillan. Peacocke, Christopher. . A Study of Concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press. Pettit, Philip. . The Possibility of Aesthetic Realism, in Pleasure, Preference, and Value, ed. Eva Schaper. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Putnam, Hilary. . The Meaning of Meaning, in Language, Mind, and Knowledge, ed. Keith Gunderson. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Rawls, John. . Two Concepts of Rules, Philosophical Review : –. 217 Reber, Rolf. . Art in Its Experience: Can Empirical Psychology Help Assess Artistic Value? Leonardo : –. Reinhardt, Ad. []. Art as Art, in Art as Art: The Selected Writings of Ad Reinhardt, ed. Barbara Rose. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Ribeiro, Anna Christina. . Intending to Repeat: A Definition of Poetry, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Rush, Michael. . New Media in Late Twentieth Century Art. New York: Thames and Hudson. Saito, Yuriko. . Everyday Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Savedoff, Barbara. . Transforming Images: How Photography Complicates the Picture. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Schaeffer, Jean-Marie. . Art of the Modern Age: Philosophy of Art from Kant to Heidegger, trans. Steven Rendall. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Scruton, Roger. . Photography and Representation, Critical Inquiry : –. Sharpe, R. A. . The Empiricist Theory of Artistic Value, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Shelley, James. . The Problem of Non-Perceptual Art, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Aesthetics and the World at Large, British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— . Against Value Empiricism in Aesthetics, Australasian Journal of Philosophy : –. ——— MS. Why Aesthetic Judgments Should Be True. Shiner, Larry. . The Invention of Art: A Cultural History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sibley, Frank. . Aesthetic Concepts, Philosophical Review : –. ——— . Aesthetic and Nonaesthetic, Philosophical Review : –. ——— . Particularity, Art, and Evaluation, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume : -. Smith, Murray. . My Dinner with Noël; Or, Can We Forget the Medium? Film Studies : –. 218 Sparshott, Francis. . A Measured Pace: Toward a Philosophical Understanding of the Arts of Dance. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Stecker, Robert. . What Is Literature? Revue Internationale de Philosophie : –. ——— . Artworks: Definition, Meaning, Value. University Park: Penn State University Press. ——— . Is It Reasonable to Attempt to Define Art? in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Stock, Kathleen. . The Role of Imagining in Seeing-in, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Tanner, Michael. . Ethics and Aesthetics Are – ? in Art and Morality, ed. José Luis Bermúdez and Sebastian Gardiner. London: Routledge. Tavinor, Grant. . The Art of Videogames. Oxford: WileyBlackwell. Tatarkiewicz, Wladyslaw. . What Is Art? The Problem of Definition Today, British Journal of Aesthetics :–. Thomasson, Amie. . Artifacts and Human Concepts, in Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation, ed. Eric Margolis and Stephen Laurence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Thomson, Judith Jarvis. . Normativity. Chicago: Open Court. Tolhurst, William. . Toward an Aesthetic Account of the Nature of Art, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Tormey, Alan, . Critical Judgments, Theoria : –. Vogel, Susan Mullin. . Baule: African Art, Western Eyes. New Haven: Yale University Press. Walton, Kendall. . Categories of Art, Philosophical Review : –. ——— . Review of Art and the Aesthetic by George Dickie, Philosophical Review : –. ——— . How Marvelous! Towards a Theory of Aesthetic Value, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. ——— . Aesthetics – What? Why? and Wherefore? Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. 219 Weitz, Morris. . The Role of Theory in Aesthetics, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism : –. Wollheim, Richard. []. Art and Its Objects, nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— . Art and Evaluation, in Art and Its Objects, nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— []. Minimal Art, in On Art and the Mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ——— . Painting as an Art. London and New York: Thames and Hudson. ——— . The Core of Aesthetics, Journal of Aesthetic Education : –. ——— . Why Is Drawing Interesting? British Journal of Aesthetics : -. Wolterstorff, Nicholas. . Art in Action. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. Wood, Paul. . Conceptual Art. London: Tate. Yanal, Robert J. . The Institutional Theory of Art, in Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, ed. Michael Kelly. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zangwill, Nick. a. The Beautiful, the Dainty, and the Dumpy. British Journal of Aesthetics : –. ——— b. The Creative Theory of Art, American Philosophical Quarterly : –. ——— c. Groundrules in the Philosophy of Art, Philosophy : –. ——— . Aesthetic/Sensory Dependence, British Journal of Aesthetics : -. ——— . Feasible Aesthetic Formalism, Noûs : –. ——— . In Defence of Moderate Aesthetic Formalism, Philosophical Quarterly : –. Ziff, Paul. . The Task of Defining a Work of Art, Philosophical Review : –.