WHAT LOGICALIZATION CAN TEACH US ABOUT THE ORIGINS OF LANGUAGE R.E. JENNINGS Abstract. Language is, to observation, primarily a physical, biological phenomenon rather than a semantic one. We are accustomed to being told that language should not be regarded as a technology, yet the study of logicalization, the process by which natural languages evolve their connective vocabulary from lexical items, looks like nothing so much as a series of technological innovations on a minute scale, that is, innovations by which pre-existing physical sub-devices are exploited for the production of novel effects. Any attempt to construct from even a detailed understanding of logicalization a way of approaching larger questions of language origins must pay close attention to the evolutionary changes in the scale at which these innovations are to be looked for. At later stages they represent relatively small changes to a large and complex structure; at the earliest stages ancestral innovations would have represented relatively large-scale changes to small and comparatively simple structures. In a physical account of logicalization, meanings are treated as physical rather than semantic types, in particular, types of neural effects accessible to the processes of speech production. But the short-term evolutionary facts of the case require that such types be regarded as species, that is, as unions of populations temporally ordered by an engendering relation, and sharing with organic species the features that (a) they are non-classical sets, and that (b) every member of such a species has ancestors that are not members of the species. Ultimately the phylum of effects that we are prepared to regard as pre- or proto-linguistic effects finds its ancestry in a class of exploitations of wholly non-linguistic effects. Arguably some gestural vestiges of these very early exaptations persist in human practice. 1. The Origins of this Essay The main illustration of this paper, the connection of language origins with throwing, was and remains a methodological illustration rather than an hypothesis. The subject of the illustration, pointing, arises mainly from an evening graduate seminar on language run jointly by David Hamlyn and Peter Winch at Birkbeck College in 1966. There we considered the view that language is learned through pointing, and the difficulty for that view that pointing was already a complexly linguistic act. By contrast, the content of the illustration arose naturally from a biological representation of meaning introduced as a vehicle for explaining the phenomenon of logicalization: the historical process by which languages evolve their connective vocabulary from lexical vocabulary, mainly from that of physical relationships. The gist of that representation is this: Let a meaning be a physical type characterizable in the language of a neuro-functional theory of the relevant structures of the brain; in particular, let it be a type of neural effect accessible Key words and phrases. language, logicalization, evolution, technology. 1 2 R.E. JENNINGS to the structures controlling speech production. Then even as much as we know about logicalization forces us to regard such a type as a species, that is, as a union ∪P of a set P of populations of effects, temporally ordered by an engendering relation, earlier populations engendering later ones. Like the members of organic species, every member of a meaning has ancestors that are not members of that meaning. Now on such a representation what holds for species holds for genera and higher-order taxonomic divisions. In particular the phylum of linguistic effects has ancestral phyla that are non-linguistic effects–which is perhaps to say little more than that all linguistic beings have non-linguistic ancestors. It is the “little more” that gives interest to the application of a theoretical idiom conceived in minutiae of linguistic change to the largest linguistic change of all. But as regards the illustration, if pointing is already a richly linguistic act, what were its nonlinguistic forbears and how were its effects engendered by theirs? In general, philosophy students, attracted to big questions rather than to little ones, become restive under a regimen of detail. So the illustration, although (or perhaps because) they invariably prefer to hear it as a speculation, redeems a trimester of tedium, and gives them something sensible to write about. That seemed to be, through a number of offerings of the logicalization course, the principal role of “the story of pointing”. It was the more general methodological questions that it raised that piqued my curiosity about language origins; it was a remark of Deacon’s ([2], 52) that convinced me, so to speak, that God was an Anglican. Deacon refers to . . . a number of other theories that view language origin as secondary to some more specialized adaptation, e.g., lateralized tool manufacture and use (Doreen Kimura), accurate stone throwing (William Calvin), etc. (my emphasis) Someone, I supposed, who actually knows something about the subject has come to the conclusion that my illustration suggested. Perhaps the general theoretical framework can find an application here. 2. Language and Technology It is widely protested that language cannot be regarded as technology, because language constitutes too large and too significant a portion of what we are to be usefully thought of merely as an instrument. One might as well say that digestive enzymes are technology because we use them in our gastro-intestinal tract to assimilate protein. To be sure, we can learn techniques of effective speaking, but speaking itself is not (ontogenetically) acquired as a technique for doing something. A feral child that has not developed language does not in general acquire it later, as she might acquire techniques of donning clothes. There does seem, however, to be some connection at an evolutionary level, between our ancestors’ having become technological and their having become linguistic. Derek Bickerton: . . . if any species is to behave like ours, it needs . . . the physical capacity to manufacture a wide range of artifacts–something that our remote ancestors already had in the form of prehensile hands with a powerful grip. It may well be that, without some such morphological advantage, even a species with language might not succeed in radically restructuring its behavior. It may even be that the complex reasoning processes we now deploy in language could WHAT LOGICALIZATION CAN TEACH US ABOUT THE ORIGINS OF LANGUAGE 3 not have arisen had they not been derived in some fashion from equally complex technological processes that we mastered first. . . For our purposes, it is enough to note the interdependence of language and technology in radical behavioral change. ([1], 173) Bickerton goes on: Since the power to conceive logically precedes the power to create, we may therefore assume that a radical improvement in conceptual power (such as might result from the development of protolanguage into language) logically preceded a radical improvement in artifacts, rather than vice versa. Certainly all the technological advances of recorded history have had not one iota of effect on the structure of language. Ibid A deeper reason for avoiding the language of technology in an explanatory theory of language is that the term technology is not well-defined. People who speak of technology in connection with the phylogenetically early stages of language development among hominids often have in mind predative and agrarian technologies, the development and use of weapons, missiles, the production and use of fire, the subordination and selective breeding of other animals, the refinement of crop types, agriculture and so on. Asked for a general account of what technology is, they give no reply. Fair enough: their purposes do not require it. But since ours do, it will be as well to try to say at least sufficiently much about it to explain why the topic is being raised at all. The fact of the matter is that we haven’t said what language is either, and we might very well use enzymes as artificial aids to digestion, enzymes produced by methods that everyone would agree were technological. (Come to that, we might also use language, in ways that everyone agreed were technological, to open a door, or start a car, or run a bath.) But in neither the case of language nor the case of technology should we expect to be able to provide a defining set of severally necessary and jointly sufficient conditions. In the case of language we have given the reasons, and corresponding considerations apply to technology. In introducing the notion of linguistic effects, we observed that the set of linguistic effects is a non-classical set. Every linguistic effect has non-linguistic ancestors, since every linguistic agent has clearly non-linguistic ancestors. Between those and our later, clearly linguistic ancestors there must have been ancestors who were linguistic to some unclear degree or other, and the effects of their vocal practices can presumably be said also to be linguistic to some degree or other. There is no point in supposing otherwise, even if the steps that led from the one to the other were in important respects incremental. We can adopt the same liberal attitude to the development of technology. Some effects are technological effects, that is, produced by technological means, and others not. We can find clear enough examples to illustrate the difference. But every technological effect is engendered by earlier effects, and in the ancestral of that relation will be effects that are not technological. In the ancestral of the species of technological effects will be species that antedate all species of technological effects. Again, without repeating the case, it is reasonable to speak of degrees of technologicality if only to accommodate the transition from our pre-technological to our technological ancestors. Purely for local purposes, let us suppose that we can identify language with some set of linguistic effects, and technology with some set of technological effects. It is 4 R.E. JENNINGS natural to take the question about the nature of language or technology to require us to distinguish between current or recent activities or capacities that are regarded as linguistic or technological from those current or recent activities or capacities that are not. If then we are to speak, diachronically, about the set of all linguistic effects or the set of all technological effects, we will need special notation to remind us that that is what we are talking about. I introduce the following convention. Suppose that “label” names a particular set, S of co-special items, that is, members of the same species. And suppose that these items are the product of evolution, that is, that they were engendered by previous items, that these previous items were engendered by still previous items, and so on, until, tracing the ancestry far enough we find ancestors that, for whatever purpose, we do not regard as being of the same species. Let S 0 be the closure of S under the engendered-by relation for that species. That is, (a) S ⊆ S 0 and ∀m ∈ S 0 , if S 00 is the set of items that engendered m, then S 00 ⊆ S 0 . Then we adopt “label ” as the name of the portion of S 0 ⊇ S that takes our interest. By this convention, if we apply the label “language” to a set of clearly linguistic effects, and we apply the label “technology” to a set of clearly technological effects, then “language ” and “technology ” will label portions of the corresponding closures of these sets of effects under their respective engendered-by relations. In practice we needn’t quite regard these sets as closed under the engendering relation, only as including sufficiently much of the domain of the relation as to enable us to trace the evolutionary emergence of language on the one hand and technology on the other. If we are to understand the set of linguistic (technological) effects diachronically, then we will not imagine there to have been a first linguistic (technological) effect, since the set of such effects is non-classical. Membership in such a set, like membership in a biological species, takes a value in the closed unit interval. For such a set we ought properly to abandon the two-valued idiom of e ∈ S 0 and e0 ∈ / S 0 in favour of the more general idiom of 0 0 0 ≤ ∈ (e0, S ) ≤ ∈ (e, S ) ≤ 1. The adoption of the language of non-classical sets puts us at odds with the language of closure under engendered-by, since that closure must take us to effects properly outside the sets that interest us, hence the use of “label ” as the name of a portion of S 0 . The notation is not intended to overcome a difficulty of mathematical imprecision–it is intentionally imprecise–but rather one of physical imagination. It reminds us that the relationships we are trying to think about are somewhere near the 0-end of the sets of technological and of linguistic effects. The question that I want to raise here is not about the relationship between language and technology as Bickerton understands that question, but about the relationship between language and technology . To put the matter another way, if we can label the earliest considered class of items pre-, the next earliest proso-, the next proto- and so on as our knowledge of Greek enables us, the question is more like: what is the connection between pre-technology and proso-language or between proso-technology and proto-language? The difficulty is that the best set of such prefixes that we can manage will not do justice to the fine-grainedness of their co-evolution at the earliest stages. Let us suppose that pre-technological hominids scavenged large game, but lacked the means of killing it themselves. In eating flesh made available through accident, they were exploiting incidental non-technological effects of natural occurrences. (It doesn’t matter for the illustration that they might also, perhaps even mainly, scavenged the victims of quicker and more adept hunting species.) We may imagine WHAT LOGICALIZATION CAN TEACH US ABOUT THE ORIGINS OF LANGUAGE 5 them coming upon animals that had fallen off cliffs, or upon animals unto which bits of cliffs had fallen. Then an early step toward a technological replacement for this rather haphazard and unreliable arrangement would be to take steps to increase the probabilities of such events, say by panicking herds and loosening rocks. By gradual refinements, relatively fresh large game protein is made available by means that are undeniably technological, albeit at a very primitive level of technology. The point that such a story is intended to illustrate is that, in its earliest stages, technological innovation imitates nature, reproducing the incidental effects of natural events by more or less the same proximal means observed in nature, but at relatively more convenient times and intervals. Subsequent refinements reduce the amount of effort expended to the same effect and perhaps generalize the method, enabling an expanded field of deployment, and freeing the technology from the haphazard and varied particularities of its original application. But technological interventions, besides having anticipated outcomes, like naturally occurring events, also have incidental effects. And since the now-refined, to some extent ritualized technological intervention has a familiar practiced regularity, so too do its outcomes have noticeably refined incidental characteristics. And these too can be reliably reproduced for their own sake if there is some benefit to be had from them. So technological advance engenders further technological advance, with later generations requiring, in general, greater resolving power of discernment for their discovery, and finer motor control in the refinements of their exploitation. Into all of this we must add the effects of the transmission of the practice to new generations of practitioners with variations due to initially misapprehended purpose and modifications imposed by juvenile musculation and altered social arrangements. 3. Grammaticalization Now linguistic change, and particular, the process of grammaticalization, bears some of these marks of technological progress. Lexical uses have anticipated, and exploited but also incidental effects. Grammaticalization is a process by which these incidental effects are exploited, isolated and refined. Consider the grammaticalized uses of various forms of the verb go as verb endings (Latin) and auxiliaries (English) in future tense formations. Compare 3.1 I am going to visit Aunt Sally as an explanation of motion toward Aunt Sally 3.2 I’m gönna be sick in the absence of any motion and in the presence of other cues as a warning of imminent upheaval. The second use, that of the progressive future, has evolved from the first use, which reports motion and its end. But it would not have done so if the first use did not incidentally give generally reliable grounds for the anticipation of whatever was given as the end of motion. It is that incidentally created anticipation that enables the successful refined use of the form in the noticeable absence of any motion at all, and eventually even in the presence of motion. Even in an in-flight conversation, I’m going to be married need not be taken as an explanation of the current journey. Parallel remarks would apply to the prosodically distinguished, logicalized use of the string 3.3 Martyn swims as well as Robyn 6 R.E. JENNINGS The discretely-valued, conjunctive X ϕ’s as well as Y has evolved from the persisting smoothly-valued use that reports comparable ϕ-ing ability. However, it would not have done so but that almost all instances of the older use reliably ground the anticipation that both of the comparands ϕ. The pattern is widely repeated: (1) α-use of vocable-string S has a main effect, e and (among others) an unavoidable subsidiary effect, e0 . (2) S is used in circumstances that nullify effect e, but not e0 . (3) S acquires a prosodic or other variant β-use, S 0 which has effect e0 but not e, even when circumstances would not nullify e. The crudity of the use, admittedly a fine-grained crudity, is strikingly present in one form or another virtually everywhere in language. The surprise of its ubiquity must be a common experience for anyone studying these matters for the first time. As many people are taught by their early training to see in the world the beauty of a divine creation, they were also taught by their literary training to revere their language almost as an holie thing. But where we have learned to see elegant concision, the study of linguistic change shows us a Rube Goldberg world of unlikely improvisations and recycled spare parts of long disused machinery and antique devices cobbled together. It would be to decidedly odd effect that I asked of a guest recently ensconced in my favourite armchair whether she is capable of being comforted. Yet there is nothing odd in the effect of my asking whether she is comfortable–and no insult in my asking whether the chair beneath her is comfortable.1 There suddenly is a murky cluttered landscape of ramshackle, makeshift and forgotten purpose where before we thought we saw fixed order. The change of attitude is Galilean. The immutable crystalline spheres are become messy collocations of stuff from somewhere else. Now, rhapsodies aside, none of this implies that human language itself in its present highly evolved state should be understood as a kind of technology; nevertheless, some central kinds of linguistic innovations look like nothing so much as relatively small-scale technological innovations (and, considering the present state of nano-technology, not, comparatively, so small-scale as all that.) In retrospect, it seems no small feat to distill an expression of futurity from an expression of motion and end. Yet linguistic interaction seems to have done it by the use of the language of motion without accompanying motion, leaving only what had been incidentally present in the earlier use as its product. It is the similarity of these linguistic changes to small-scale technological innovation that prompts the question as to the connection between language and technology . Do all linguistic effects have technological but pre-linguistic ancestors, that is, ancestral effect-types in the intersection of language and technology whose memberships in the set, T of technological effect-types must be assigned a markedly higher value in the unit interval than their memberships in the set L of linguistic effecttypes? Is there an effect-type e such that ∈ (e, T ∩ L) = ∈ (e, T ) × ∈ (e, L) ∈ (e, L)? 1Here is an exercise: write a long book demonstrating the truth of this paragraph and citing only vocabulary and constructions from this essay as examples. Let one of the chapters concern the use of English verbs of vision. WHAT LOGICALIZATION CAN TEACH US ABOUT THE ORIGINS OF LANGUAGE 7 Any proposed answer must be hypothetical, but we can give one that will at least illustrate the sort of candidate we have in mind, leaving aside questions of plausibility and means of confirmation. What would the marks of such an item be? In the following partial list, we must remember that e is itself a non-classical set. (1) We would expect events of type e to be the incidental effects of some common physical activity. (2) We would expect these effects to have been effects in linguistic ancestors. (3) We would expect them to have neural and perhaps larger physical component effects. (4) We would expect them, in the earliest instances, to reproduce effects of a type e0 that are also reliably produced naturally, that is, other than as incidental outcomes of technological interventions. (5) We would expect the susceptibility to e0 effects to be an inherited trait, present in some form from early infancy. (6) We would expect the physical intervention that produced incidental eeffects to engender a refined physical intervention type that produced descendent e-effects without the effects to which earlier ones were incidental. (7) We would expect to find descendants of those e-effects in every descendent language , and so, given the specifications of the search, in virtually every current human language. The qualification that the effects should reproduce naturally occurring (e0 ) effects amounts to the supposition that some inherited biological propensity was available for simple technological exploitation. The proposed candidate propensity is the tendency to track motion, that is the tendency to detect sudden motion within the visual field and to adjust focus, eye and head motion to maintain a visual fix on a moving object both when it is continuously and also when it is only intermittently visible. In the adopted language of effects, the reliable (e0 ) effect is the effect on a subject of an object moving within the field of vision. The descendent effect is the tracking effect of a missile moving within the field of vision. Simply, the tendency to track moving objects in general implies a tendency to track thrown objects. It is the tendency to track thrown objects that this illustration takes as technologically exploitable, since throwing an object reliably produces the effect, and incidentally directs attention to whatever the object was thrown at. So the technological effects are the general effects of missile-throwing and the incidental effects are the effects on those present, namely that they visually track the missile and thereby focus upon its target, which for the sake of the example, we can assume is prey. There is at this stage in the development a reliable means of drawing attention to any feature whether prey or no, namely tossing a missile at it. And that new technology is likely to be learned by children in the course of their learning missile technology more generally. However, there is no need to waste missiles to draw attention to a feature, since companions will tend visually to pick up the trajectory of a missile even when they have only intermittent visual contact with it, it is sufficient to go through the motions of throwing. Thus what was mere incidental effect of a technology having one purpose has become the central purpose of a new descendent technology incapable of achieving the main effect of its immediate ancestor. Freed from the old end, the motions of throwing can be refined so as unambiguously, and more efficiently to achieve the new, and to achieve it, should the situation demand, more discreetly. For the purpose, the important elements of the motions 8 R.E. JENNINGS are the direction and terminal position of the arm and hand. Incidental features of throwing, such as the extension of the forefinger, which had provided a useful spin to the projectile and precisely controlled its release, might be retained for sighting along, but a gesture would adequately serve the function that was greatly reduced in the flamboyance and vigour of its execution retaining only the extension of the arm in a particular direction and with its particular final position. The result is a low-energy action which is in certain visual respects like throwing, but which will not be taken for throwing, an action that will, however, retain effects that have been engendered by effects of throwing. Specialized variations of the action would mimic certain features of the ancestral action, for example, one which propels the hand forward in a roughly parabolic trajectory, thereby adding the effect of anticipated distance to that of anticipated direction. Another that combines an arm motion having the character of throwing with forward movement of the thrower in the same direction would have the effect of inducing companions to follow. And so on. If throwing were the technological ancestor of pointing, if the early elements of pointing were elements of disarmed or ineffectual instances of throwing, the development of the former from the latter would have had some of the important marks of grammaticalization, which places vocables of the language (such as have, going, to, follows, from and so on)in environments (such as I am going to stand here until I have demonstrated that P follows from Q) that render their lexical loading inert, that is, environments in which they cannot have an earlier causal significance, cannot have some neural effects that at an earlier stage they could not have been used without. But linguistic practices generally include a variety of iterable devices for doing just that to any sufficiently small portion of the language, as a temporary expedient for particular purposes. One such device is quotation, in which strings of vocables, with undisturbed syntax, can be moved about safely with none but a select and relatively passive set of reactive neural systems engaged by their utterance. Mimicry is another. Here an ensemble of cues–some linguistic possibly, some not–that are associated with one source is presented unmistakably by another. And both quotation and mimicry can be iterated. We can mention the mention of a string; we can mimic mimicry and so on. So strings and presentations can be stripped even of the secondary neural effects left to them in first-order quotation and mime. All such practices involve partial imitation. But once we have the knack of noticing them, a limitless variety of such activities presents itself in this light, among these, the creation of poetry. Consider Dylan Thomas’ They shall be one with the man in the wind and the west moon in which the effect (whatever it is) is achieved by transposition of the elements of the comparatively banal They shall be one with the man in the moon and the west wind. We have relatively easy investigative access to such relatively short term evolutionary linguistic developments as grammaticalization, though we do not yet have a sufficiently general understanding of their neural dimension. But processes like grammaticalization are processes that themselves have an evolutionary history. An historico-linguistic study of classical Latin would perhaps show its perfect and future verb endings to be grammaticalized forms of earlier verbs of possession and motion toward, and we might conclude that much the same exaptations as have occurred in English occurred in Latin. But since, like us, the ancient Latins had non-linguistic ancestors, there must have been much earlier stages in the ancestry of Latin in which the elements available for grammaticalization were themselves WHAT LOGICALIZATION CAN TEACH US ABOUT THE ORIGINS OF LANGUAGE 9 less evolved. After all, if the activities sufficiently early in the ancestry of language were themselves non-linguistic, it follows that the grammatical distinctions of language themselves evolved. So the earliest ancestors of grammaticalizations were themselves not grammaticalizations, but the products of some ancestral process to which their ancestors were susceptible. The two millennia that separate us from Cicero are insufficient to reveal much difference in the character of long-term linguistic descent. But it is a fair guess that a comparison with Indo-European or ancient Hebrew would show more. We can therefore speak of grammaticalization , that is, the process of grammaticalization together with the catalogue of ancestral processes that engendered it as a process of linguistic change. We cannot say with any certainty that human languages of, say, 100,000 years ago had grammatical categories corresponding to those of any present-day language. But we can say with assurance that however many categories they had, and whatever their character, the items within those divisions had the uses they had because of the uses that ancestral items had had within the divisions, whatever they had been, of ancestral languages. It is tempting, perhaps to suppose that in the behaviours of sufficiently early ancestors, there was but one undifferentiated grammatical category that could not even be seen as such save by reference to descendent distinctions whatever they were. But the illustration suggests a somewhat different picture: that at a sufficiently early stage, the grammatical, or rather grammatical , distinctions were confused, in the best sense, with distinctions among actions more generally. The idea is compatible with the notion of a relatively sudden development of distinctly linguistic complexity, and in fact, taken together with what we can readily infer in broad terms about grammaticalization, would go some way toward explaining such a quick development were there independent evidence that one had occurred. For even the development of species of pointing as grammaticalized , disarmed forms of throwing would create a suddenly enormous linguistic market for a lexicon of nominal-like items beyond those already available through disarming mimicry of distinguishing sounds. We need only suppose a growth in the resolution of the distinctions represented within this early member of the genus lexicon to find as well a slower accumulation of outworn vocables, those representing superseded duller distinctions available for recycling as general verb-predicate-like items, that is, available for a kind of grammaticalization that, though still generalized,is closer to our normal understanding of the process. Now this is far from presenting a hypothesis about changes in language being brought about by changes in technology. Nor does it claim a relationship between grammaticalization and the development of syntax. But it does suggest a common ancestry and early separation of the processes by which language and technology evolved. And it can be understood as an illustration of a possible relationship between grammaticalization and syntax . If a hypothesis lurks here it is a methodological one: deliberations about early evolutionary linguistic developments can benefit from a consideration of very early processes in the genus, grammaticalization . References [1] Bickerton, Derek. Langusge and Species. University of Chicago Press. Chigago, 1990. [2] Deacon, Terrence. Brain-Language Coevolution in [3], 49–83. [3] Hawkins, John A. and Murray Gell-Mann editors. The Evolution of Human Languages: Proceedings of the Workshop on the Evolution of Human Languages, Held August, 1989 in Santa 10 R.E. JENNINGS Fe, New Mexico. Proceedings Volume XI, Santa Fe Institute Studies in the Sciences of Complexity. Addison-Wesley. Reading, Massachusetts, 1992. —————————————————————Laboratory for Logic and Experimental Philosophy, Simon Fraser University, Burnaby BC, Canada V5A 1S6 E-mail address: jennings@sfu.ca