Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 Adam Smith, Capabilities Theorist, in the First Edition of the Theory of Moral Sentiments James E. Alvey Since World War II, mainstream economics has been dominated by what may be called “engineering”. It has deliberately distanced itself from ethics. One ethical approach to economics, the Capabilities Approach, has been developed from the late 1970s by Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum. We investigate whether this ethical approach can be traced back to Adam Smith, the founder of modern economics. It focuses on the first edition of Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759). The first conclusion is that the Capabilities approach to economics does stretch back from Sen, at least to Smith. The second, tentative, conclusion is that Smith shows it may be possible to combine “engineering” and ethical approaches to economics. Field of Research: Economics (All Other Economics Topics) JEL Codes: A12, B31, B41 1. Introduction A frequent concern that has been raised about mainstream economics is its lack of ethical awareness (see Fullbrook 2007, Chs 51-5; Alvey 2011, pp. 1-5). Nevertheless, some contemporary economists, such as Amartya Sen (the Nobel Laureate in economics), have seen the problem, provided a critique of the mainstream view, and proposed constructive alternatives. Most importantly, along with Martha Nussbaum, Sen has established an ethical approach to economics: the Capabilities approach (see Nussbaum 2011). This paper is devoted to economic methodology and the history of economic thought. First, it sets out a new methodological framework, which builds on the work of Sen and Nussbaum. Second, it uses this ethical approach to undertake analysis in the history of economic thought: examining the first of the two books written by Adam Smith, the founder of modern economics (Sen 1987, p. 2; see pp. 21-2). The Theory of Moral Sentiments (TMS hereafter) was his first major publication. The aim of the paper is to establish whether the Capabilities approach to economics stretches back to Smith and he can be viewed as part of the ethical tradition of economics. The paper is structured as follows. A brief literature review on “ethics and economics” and Smith‟s methodological views is provided in Section 2. Section 3 sets out the Capabilities methodological framework. Section 4 states what “data” was used i.e. the text of the first edition of the TMS. Section 5 uses the framework from Section 3 to re-examine the “data” in Section 4. The paper concludes in Section 6. 2. Literature Review Despite criticisms from various sources, it is clear that a considerable gap has opened up between economics and ethics (see Sen 1987; Alvey 2011, pp. 5-9). Sen is correct, however, in viewing economics as having throughout its history both an ______________________________________________ Dr James E. Alvey, Senior Lecturer, School of Economics and Finance, Massey University, Palmerston North, New Zealand. Email: J.E.Alvey@massey.ac.nz Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 ethical tradition as well as an “engineering” tradition (Sen 1987, pp. 4-7, 78). What has happened is that the “engineering” tradition has displaced the ethical tradition (with a few exceptions). With which tradition does Smith align? Throughout the time since Smith died (1790), many topics related to Smith have now been treated extensively in the secondary literature. Numerous disputes have arisen about how to interpret his various concepts and works (see Sen 1986b). Other disputes concern whether his writings are consistent throughout his lifetime (Raphael and Macfie 1976, pp. 19-25; Montes 2004, pp. 15-56). For the purpose of this paper, pending further research, I simply assert the consistency of his thought and work. Perhaps due to his wide acceptance as the founder of modern economics, some have presented Smith as a general equilibrium theorist (Hollander 1973). Sen (1987, p. 8) views general equilibrium theorizing as “engineering”. Inevitably, viewing him as an engineer, tends to align Smith with the modern, “scientific,” positivistic, methodology and the assumption that all human motivation is self-interested. Campbell (1971) and Raphael (2007) see even the TMS as an empirical (rather than normative) work. The same, of course, applies to his second book, the Wealth of Nations (Smith 1976 [1776]). Some commentators have noted Smith‟s rejection of the positive-normative dichotomy but condemned him for doing so (Hutchison 1988, p. 363). With regard to human motivations, Stigler (1971) and Coase (1976) claim that self-interest dominates Smith‟s work. Cropsey says that everything is directed either to self-preservation or to pleasure maximization in Smith (Cropsey 1957, pp. viii, 3-4 (and note 4), 15-6, 29 c.f. p. 72). By contrast, some writers have included Smith within the ethical tradition of economics. For example, Young (1997) has shown that Smith rejected the positivenormative dichotomy and wrote in the ethical tradition of Aristotle. Fitzgibbons (1995), Hanley (2009), and Fricke (2013), find ethical motivations in Smith. Muller (1995) and Fitzgibbons (1995) argue for an ethical understanding of social achievement in Smith. Previously, I have shown that Smith‟s early works (those written before the TMS) are consistent with the ethical tradition in economics (Alvey 2014b; 2014c). Sen frequently cites Smith in his work (Sen 1986b; 2009 throughout) and asserts that the latter inspired him in his development of the Capabilities approach (1987, p. 46 n.). Nevertheless, he never attempted a comprehensive examination of Smith from the Capabilities perspective. This paper represents a step towards filling this gap. 3. The Methodology This section presents Sen‟s Capabilities approach, a new “ethics and economics” methodological framework. For more details, see Alvey (2014a; 2015). Sen rejects the standard metrics of well-being: utility and opulence (1987, pp. 45-7). He argues that these measures, as well as national accounting aggregates, such as GNP and GNP/head, are reductionist and misleading for policy purposes (Sen 1999, pp. 46-51). An alternative approach is required: a range of metrics is required to capture the complexities of human welfare. First, Sen asserts that “ethical deliberations” are relevant “to actual human behaviour” (1987, p. 4). It is on the foundation of ethical motivations that many other parts of Sen‟s work are built. Second, the starting point for Sen‟s view of well-being is the concept of functionings. Functionings “can vary from the most elementary ones, such as being well-nourished …, to quite complex and sophisticated achievements, such as having self-respect” (Sen 1992, p. 5; see 1993, pp. 36-7). “A functioning is an achievement, whereas a capability is the ability to achieve” (Sen 1986a, p. 48). The standard example that Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 Sen provides to distinguish capabilities from functionings is fasting (1986a, p. 49; see 1993, p. 45). Even if the “achieved functionings” of “the rich person fasting” is the same as the poor person starving, they “differ in their capabilities” (Sen 1993, p. 45). In short, the capabilities approach is concerned with “a person‟s ability to do valuable acts or reach valuable states of being”, even if they choose not to achieve them (Sen 1993, p. 31). Human capabilities are the true goals. Third, given this understanding of functionings and capabilities of individuals, we can turn to achievements within the society. Notions of distributive justice arise (Sen 1987, pp. 32-3). For Sen, social achievement represents some benchmark of acceptable performance for the society in terms of delivery of functioning achievements. Fourth, Sen incorporates his own version of “agency” into his work. Agency includes the virtue of practical reason: the agent forms “goals, commitments, values, etc” and acts to fulfil them (Sen 1987, p. 41). Sen lists a range of subjects which may form part of agency goals: achievements for one‟s family, community, class, party, or some other cause (1987, p. 43). Another aspect of agency is responsibility for one‟s own actions (Sen 1985, p. 183). Fifth, for Sen, freedom is valuable but complex (Sen 2002, pp. 7, 9). First, freedom is “valued” as a means to “achievements”, such as well-being, and “because of its own importance” (Sen 1987, p. 60; 1993, p. 39; 2009, p. 18). Second, although one can refer to freedom in general, one can also consider various types of freedom e.g. personal liberty, political freedom, etc. (Sen 2000, pp. 5-6 and throughout; 2002, pp. 413, 598). Sixth, Sen also recognises rights to some degree. Again, he claims that rights have both an instrumental value and an importance for their own sake (Sen 1987, pp. 4751, 56-7, 70-2, 74-8). To summarize, Sen‟s Capabilities metaframework consists of three tiers. The first tier refers to the motivations of individuals. We can distinguish between three broad categories of motivations: “the ethics-related view of motivations,” self-interested motivations, and malevolent motivations. In the second tier there are various considerations: functionings/capabilities, freedom, rights, and human agency. The top tier is social achievement. In On Ethics and Economics the concept refers to distributive justice with respect to capabilities. It is better, however, to view social achievement as a depiction of the achievements, agencies, freedoms, and rights of various individuals within the society. Numerous ethical judgments are required e.g. the choice of items evaluated, the weighting given to each item, and the proportion of the population required for success. 4. The Data The first edition of the TMS (1759) is examined in detail below. For background on the TMS, see Alvey (2015b; 2015c). 5. The Findings The Capabilities framework was used to re-examine the first edition of the TMS. (All citations below are from Smith 1992 [1759].) The chief findings are summarized below. First, Smith argues that there is evidence for the providential care of Nature (p. 168 n.). Not only does Nature demonstrate benevolent design throughout but Smith claims to have discovered that there are five or six natural ends for human beings (Alvey 2003, pp. 1, 32-5, 275-83 and throughout). Human beings desire “self- Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 preservation and the procreation of the species” (p. 168n.; see pp. 191-2). We humans desire these ends but nature directs us to these ends by means of instincts (p. 168n.). In addition, Smith explicitly attributes another three ends to nature: order, happiness, and perfection of the species (p. 168n.; see pp. 238, 284-5, 290; see Alvey 2003 throughout). I have also suggested that freedom may constitute an implicit sixth end of nature for Smith (Alvey 2003, pp. 35, 58-9, 69). This discussion has implications for functionings and social achievement. Second, Smith has a complex view of human motivations. There is some evidence that Smith views humans as directed only to self-preservation or pleasure maximization (pp. 12, 168n., 181-2, 191-2, 504). In several places, however, Smith rejects those who try “deducing all our sentiments from certain refinements of selflove” (p. 14; see pp. 14-5, 441-54, 492-7). There is stronger evidence for Smith adopting arguments along the “ethics and economics” interpretation. Humans are social beings. Smith‟s references to the fellow-feeling with other humans are ubiquitous (pp. 3, 5-6, 8, 11, 14, 35, 199). He actually begins the TMS with a claim about fellow feelings (p. 1). Humans have a “strong fellow feeling with the injuries done to their brethren” (p. 69). Fellow-feeling flows outwards and inwards. Due to our social nature and the socialization processes, we inevitably become empathetic towards other humans. We are spontaneously affected by someone else‟s misery and we “almost involuntarily… fly to his assistance” (p. 74). Third, Smith reveals important insights into his views of human functionings. 1) Consider the lower functionings which arise from the first two of the fundamental ends of nature mentioned earlier. He says that the ends of self-preservation and procreation of the species are largely achieved by instincts: “Hunger, thirst, the passion which unites the two sexes, the love of pleasure, and the dread of pain” (p. 168 n.). Smith provides strong support for the ability to live a long life (p. 168 n.). It is not surprising that he condemns the “horrible practice” of exposing infants (p. 412; see pp. 409-12). If we look again at the quote concerning the role of instincts in delivering the ends of nature, we soon realize that Smith implies several more functionings: the ability to have good health, to be free from diseases, and to be well nourished and well housed (on health, see p. 97; on sickness and disease, see p. 347; on nourishment, see pp. 56, 353; on housing, see p. 353). A life without pleasure, or one dominated by pain, runs contrary to these two ends. Alternatively, one could say that Smith argues for the ability to feel pleasure and pain and have a life characterized by at least moderate pleasure. Finally, a life without sexual pleasure and offspring is deficient. Humans should be able to enjoy sexual experiences and procreate. 2) Let us now move upwards in the list of ends of nature. Order is more complex than self-preservation and procreation. It has a number of components. External order consists of defence from external attack with a view to protecting the lives of residents within the polity. Internal order includes various measures to protect residents from other residents. Elsewhere, Smith refers to a range of negative things including “anxiety, … fear, …sorrow, …danger” (p. 347). Order overcomes, or greatly limits, many of these things. Not harming our neighbours is part of justice. Justice bridges individual morality and jurisprudence. Conforming to the rules of justice is an essential aspect of individual morality. Like other aspects of morality, in Smith‟s view, the origins of the rules of justice can be traced to a series of processes related to ethical judgment. The ability to place ourselves in the situation of another in our imagination is one of these essential processes (pp. 2-4, 36-9). Without this ability, we cannot be moral beings. Over time, moral judgment is refined and comes to approximate natural justice. Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 Unlike other virtues, breaches of justice can be punished. The government attempts to create an administration of justice (through enactment of laws, and enforcement by various agencies) that approximates natural justice. Smith focusses on commutative justice. The most sacred laws of justice … are the laws which guard the life and person of our neighbour; the next are those which guard his property and possessions; and last … come those which guard … what is due him from the promises of others. (p. 184) In other words, we should have the ability to have our life and body secure from attack. (Retrospective punishment of perpetrators is a necessary condition. Nevertheless, if attacks are frequent and most people live in fear, retrospective punishment may be insufficient.) In addition, we should be able to acquire and securely retain private property and possessions. Finally, commercial law should develop in step with the material conditions in order to secure an expanding range of contractual arrangements. In other words, we should be able to enter securely into market transactions. 3) At the highest level are functionings associated with the ends of “happiness and perfection of the species”. Not surprisingly, Smith has in mind here a wide range of abilities. Consider emotional attachment to others and friendship as requirements for happiness. It is a dreadful situation to be living “where there is nobody to care for them, or enquire after them” (p. 179; see p. 369). The same can occur in the midst of society. The poor are often ignored, even when they are visible in society (pp. 110-1). Being isolated, ignored, or the object of hatred by everyone else (or not having one‟s sentiments shared by anyone else) is a miserable condition (pp. 59, 138, 140, 179, 185-6, 369). In short, Smith also stresses the ability to befriend others and be befriended by others (see pp. 2-5). Human perfection includes the development of processes for sophisticated ethical judgment and action in accordance with this standard throughout one‟s lifetime. Understanding the range of human virtues beyond justice (e.g. generosity) is difficult. Acting in accordance with these virtues is even more difficult. Over the course of one‟s lifetime ethical judgment and action merge into issues of character. The theoretical case of” the solitary”, who grows up without meeting any other human, shows that morality is a social product. Many aspects of morality require the ability to harmonize our sentiments with others (pp. 31, 37). Smith also stresses the importance of human reasoning (pp. 9-10). This is an underappreciated aspect of his work that returns to play an important role in the Wealth of Nations. In short, Smith has a rich notion of human functionings. Just as important as functioning achievements is the absence of impediments, including poverty (see pp. 398-402). Fourth, Smith endorses various aspects of agency, freedom, and rights. With respect to agency, he makes accountability a key part of human life (p. 257; see p. 539). He also stresses the importance of avoiding dependency (p. 56). Other aspects of agency have been captured already under various functionings. Concerning freedom, Smith asserts the importance of personal autonomy (p. 56). With regard to rights, he also endorses some vague notion of fundamental duties and rights (pp. 232-3, 242; see p. 234). Fifth, Smith gives us considerable insight into his view of social achievement. He tells us that human beings “stand in need of each other‟s assistance” and can live “only in society” (p. 188). Not all societies are equal, however. Smith describes and ranks three possibilities. The “most comfortable” is: Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 Where the necessary assistance is reciprocally afforded from love, from gratitude, from friendship and esteem, the society flourishes and is happy. All the different members of it are bound together by the agreeable bands of love and affection, and are … drawn to one common centre of mutual good offices. (p. 188; see pp. 188-90) The second best society is where “no one … in it should owe any obligation, or be bound in gratitude to any other”; it is like a group of “merchants” subsisting “from a sense of its utility” alone (p. 189). This is the image of commercial society. The final scenario is not really society at all. It is when all “are at all times ready to hurt and injure one another” (p. 189). The “bands” of society are broken “asunder” (p. 189). Overall, the first scenario is characterized by beneficence, the second by justice and the third by injustice (p. 190). Human beings want to share their sentiments with others but, if this is not possible, you look upon others as “beasts” (p. 191) or strangers. While the ideal may be unattainable, a moderate degree of harmonization of the sentiments is necessary for the “harmony of society” or social stability (p. 38). Another aspect of social achievement is moral improvement. Smith implies that economic development leads to this improvement (pp. 397-412). In their inability to secure life (p. 410) and emotional development, societies at the hunting stage of history were profound failures. “Civilized” societies (i.e. those at the commercial stage) had achieved better results in these areas. Many of the points made above are consistent with what was discovered in Smith‟s early writings (see Alvey 2014b; 2014c). This points towards his consistency over a longer time horizon. Two main conclusions can be made. First, ethical concerns are important in framing Smith‟s thoughts in the first edition of the TMS. Various components of the Capabilities framework can be found in this work. Smith can be seen as a contributor to the ethical tradition stretching forwards to Sen‟s Capabilities approach. He was a rich contributor to the ethical branch of economics. The second conclusion is provisional, depending on further research demonstrating that his views were largely consistent during his lifetime. If this assumption holds, to the extent that Smith contributed to the “engineering” tradition in his Wealth of Nations, he may be a model of how to combine work in the two traditions of economics (see Sen 1987, pp. 6-7). 6. Conclusion This paper uses a new, Capabilities methodology which builds on the work of Sen. The framework was used to investigate the extent to which Adam Smith integrated ethics and economics in the first edition of the Theory of Moral Sentiments. The first conclusion is that Smith did integrate ethics and economics. He was an early Capabilities theorist who endorsed many capabilities. The Capabilities approach to economics is more than just a contemporary fad, it is embedded in the founder of modern economics. The history of economics is a rich source for Capabilities theorists. A second, tentative, conclusion can be made, assuming the consistency of Smith‟s views over time. Smith may be an exemplar of how to combine the “engineering” and ethical traditions in economics. It need not be one or the other. Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 References Alvey, J 2003, Adam Smith: optimist or pessimist? Ashgate, Aldershot. Alvey, J 2011, A short history of ethics and economics: the Greeks, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham. Alvey, J 2014a, „A new framework for ethics and economics‟, Discussion Paper 14.01, School of Economics and Finance, Massey University, Palmerston North, New Zealand. Alvey, J 2014b, „Ethics and economics in Adam Smith‟s very early works, lectures, and correspondence, part I‟, Discussion Paper 14.02, School of Economics and Finance, Massey University, Palmerston North, New Zealand. Alvey, J 2014c, „Ethics and economics in Adam Smith‟s very early works, lectures, and correspondence, part II‟, Discussion Paper 14.03, School of Economics and Finance, Massey University, Palmerston North, New Zealand. Alvey, J 2015, „A new framework for ethics and economics‟, The Journal of Social Science, no. 79, pp. 123-42. Campbell, T 1971, Adam Smith’s science of morals, Rowman and Littlefield, Totowa, NJ. Coase, R 1976, „Adam Smith‟s view of man‟, Journal of Law and Economics, vol. 19, no. 3, pp. 529-46. Cropsey, J 1957, Polity and economy, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague. Fitzgibbons, A 1995, Adam Smith’s system of liberty, wealth, and virtue, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Fricke, C 2013, „Adam Smith: The sympathetic process and the origin and function of conscience‟, in C Berry, M Paganelli, & C Smith (eds.), The Oxford handbook of Adam Smith, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp.177-200. Fullbrook, E 2007, Real world economics, Anthem Press, London. Hanley, R 2009, Adam Smith and the character of virtue, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Hollander, S 1973, The economics of Adam Smith, University of Toronto Press, Toronto. Hutchison, T 1988, Before Adam Smith: the emergence of political economy 16621776, Basil Blackwell, Oxford. Montes, L 2004, Adam Smith in context, Palgrave Macmillan, Houndmills. Muller, J 1995, Adam Smith in his time and ours, 1st Princeton paperback printing with corrections and a new preface, Princeton University Press, Princeton. Nussbaum, M 2011, Creating capabilities, Belknap Press, Cambridge, Mass. Raphael, D 2007, The impartial spectator, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Raphael, D & Macfie, A 1976, „Introduction‟ and „Appendix II‟, in A Smith (D Raphael and A Macfie [eds.]), Theory of Moral Sentiments, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 1-52, 383-401. Sen, A 1982, „Rights and agency‟, Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 11, no. 1, pp. 3-39. Sen, A 1985, „Well-being, agency and freedom: The Dewey lectures 1984‟, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 82, no. 4, pp. 169-221. Sen, A 1986a, „The standard of living‟, in S McMurrin (ed.), Tanner lectures on human values (vol. VII), University of Utah Press, Salt Lake City, pp. 1-51. Sen, A 1986b, „Adam Smith‟s prudence‟, in S Lall and F Stewart (eds.), Theory and reality in development, Macmillan, London, pp. 28-37. Sen, A 1987, On ethics and economics, Basil Blackwell, Oxford. Sen, A 1992, Inequality reexamined, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. Proceedings of World Business, Finance and Management Conference 14 - 15 December 2015, Rendezvous Grand Hotel, Auckland, New Zealand ISBN: 978-1-922069-91-7 Sen, A 1993, „Capability and well-being‟, in M Nussbaum & A Sen (eds.), The quality of life, Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp. 30-53. Sen, A 1997, „Economics, business principles and moral sentiments‟, Business Ethics Quarterly, vol. 7, no. 3, pp. 5-15. Sen, A 1999, Commodities and capabilities, Oxford India paperback, Oxford University Press, New Delhi. Sen, A 2000, Development as freedom, Anchor Books, New York. Sen, A 2002, Rationality and freedom, Belknap Press, Cambridge, Mass. Sen, A 2009, The idea of justice, Belknap Press, Cambridge, Mass. Smith, A 1976 (1776), An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, R Campbell and A Skinner (eds.), Oxford University Press, Oxford. Smith, A 1992 (1759), The theory of moral sentiments, exact reprint of the 1st edition, Risen, Kyoto. Stigler, G 1971, „Smith‟s travels on the ship of state‟, History of Political Economy, vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 265-77. Young, J 1997, Economics as a moral science, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham.