The Context of Ideology: Law, Politics, and Empirical Legal Scholarship Carolyn Shapiro 1 In their confirmation hearings, Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Sotomayor both articulated a vision of the neutral judge who decides cases without resort to personal perspectives or opinions, in short, without ideology. At the other extreme, the dominant model of judicial decisionmaking in political science has long been the attitudinal model, which posits that the Justices’ votes can be explained primarily as expressions of their personal policy preferences, with little or no role for law, legal reasoning, or legal doctrine. Many traditional legal scholars have criticized such scholarship for its insistence on the primacy of ideology in judicial decisionmaking, even as empirical legal scholarship has grown in significance and influence in the legal academy. Recently, however, empirical scholars and traditional legal academics have begun to engage in serious discussions with each other about how to think about and evaluate the balance between law and ideology and about how to harness the powerful tools of quantitative analysis to study such questions. In this Article, I offer several contributions to this discussion. First, the Article evaluates current efforts by empirical scholars to identify the ideological character of cases. These efforts generally assume that the ideological character of a case can be determined by reference to a single liberal-conservative spectrum, and they generally presume that all or most cases present only a single issue. Through a recoding and quantitative analysis of a random sample of recent Rehnquist Court cases, as well as through a qualitative analysis of many of the cases, I establish concretely some of the limitations of these efforts. Specifically, I demonstrate that these approaches are indeterminate and oversimplified, and often prevent scholars from identifying cases in which the Justices face issues that pull them in different ideological directions. At the same time, however, I identify their strengths, particularly the strengths of approaches that leverage information derived from the Justices’ actual voting patterns. 1. Assistant Professor of Law, Chicago-Kent College of Law; Affiliated Scholar, American Bar Foundation. For comments and discussion at various stages of this project, thanks are due to Joshua Fischman, Joshua Karsh, David Klein, Robin Lenhardt, Gregory Mitchell, Mark Rosen, Matthew Sag, Christopher Schmidt, and David Schwartz. I am also very grateful to Paul Edelman, David Klein, and Stefanie Lindquist for sharing their data with me, and to Matthew Sag, Andrew Martin, and Joshua Fischman for answering my questions about their work. Exceptional research assistance was provided by Jerry Thomas. Thanks also to Tom Gaylord for his superb library assistance. 43 80 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Finally, I propose a new approach for empirical scholars interested in studying the role of ideology in Supreme Court cases. Rather than starting with the assumption that ideology is the most important factor in Supreme Court decisionmaking, my approach focuses on just how important ideology was to the Justices in a particular case. Measuring ideological salience, I argue, would allow empirical scholars to study the empirical question of when and how ideology – and other factors – affects decisionmaking. Doing so would also open the door to a wide variety of important and interesting research questions. Most importantly, this approach would allow empirical scholars to engage with more traditional legal academics in the important normative debates about when and how ideology should play a role in the work of the Supreme Court. I. INTRODUCTION ......................................................................................... 81 II. CODING CASE IDEOLOGY ........................................................................ 85 III. OUTCOME CODING ................................................................................. 91 A. How It Works and How It Doesn’t ................................................... 91 1. The Supreme Court Database .................................................... 91 2. Challenging the Database’s Issue and Ideology Codes.............. 94 B. The Recoding Project ....................................................................... 97 1. Quantitative Analysis ............................................................... 100 Table 1: Ideology Coding for 95-Case Sample in U.S. Supreme Court Database and Recoding Project ............... 101 Table 2: Factors Tested for Effect on Likelihood of Mixed Ideology in Recoded Cases......................... 103 2. Qualitative Analysis ................................................................. 104 IV. BEHAVIORAL CODING .......................................................................... 111 A. A First Approach ............................................................................ 111 B. A Refinement: Identifying When There Are More Dimensions ...... 120 V. IDEOLOGICAL SALIENCE AND IDEOLOGICAL LEGITIMACY: A WAY FORWARD? ................................................................................ 126 A. Defining Terms ............................................................................... 126 B. Is Measuring Ideological Salience Possible? ................................ 129 1. Possible Indicators of Ideological Salience ............................. 129 a. Distance from the Court’s Median. ................................... 129 b. Disordered Voting ............................................................. 130 c. Vote Margin. ..................................................................... 130 d. Other Possible Variables. .................................................. 131 2. Challenges in Using the Indicators .......................................... 131 C. Learning from Ideological Salience ............................................... 133 VI. CONCLUSION ........................................................................................ 134 APPENDIX A ................................................................................................ 136 Cases in Recoding Sample (Chronological Order) ............................. 136 APPENDIX B ................................................................................................ 139 Cases in Recoding Sample by Ideological Salience ............................ 139 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 81 I. INTRODUCTION Does ideology have a role to play in the work of the Supreme Court? Chief Justice Roberts suggested that it does not when, during his confirmation hearings, he described the judicial role as one of a neutral umpire “call[ing] balls and strikes.”2 In Justice Sotomayor’s more recent confirmation hearings, she partially accepted this metaphor (although she said it is an “imperfect” analogy) and consistently rejected the notion that, as a Supreme Court Justice, her personal experiences or perspectives would have a legitimate – or even an inevitable – role to play in her work.3 These statements reflect a view – widely expressed in public debates over judicial confirmations – that law and legal reasoning can and will provide an objectively correct answer to even the most difficult cases if only the judge is willing to put aside his or her personal preferences and opinions – his or her ideology. At the other extreme, the dominant model of Supreme Court decisionmaking in political science has long been the attitudinal model, which posits that the Justices’ votes can be explained primarily as expressions of their personal policy preferences, with little or no role for law, legal reasoning, or legal doctrine.4 More recent and nuanced attempts to describe judicial ideology – attempts that focus not on case outcomes (as the attitudinal model does) but rather on which Justices are in the majority and dissent in each case – likewise fail to identify an explicit role for legal reasoning, precedent, or case facts. For these scholars, judging on the Supreme Court is presumptively about politics or ideology.5 2. Nomination of Judge John G. Roberts, Jr. to Be Chief Justice of the Supreme Court: Panel One of a Hearing of the S. Judiciary Comm., 104th Cong. (2005) (statement of Judge John Roberts). 3. Nomination of Judge Sonia Sotomayor to Be Associate Justice of the Supreme Court: Panel One of a Hearing of the S. Judiciary Comm., 106th Cong. (2009) (statement of Judge Sonia Sotomayor). 4. See generally JEFFREY A. SEGAL & HAROLD J. SPAETH, THE SUPREME COURT AND THE ATTITUDINAL MODEL REVISITED (2002). 5. The attitudinal model’s chief competitor in political science, the strategic model, does not dispute that the Justices seek to implement their policy preferences but theorizes that, for strategic reasons, Justices may not vote (or write) in perfect accord with those preferences. See generally LEE EPSTEIN & JACK KNIGHT, THE CHOICES JUSTICES MAKE (1998). Rather, they behave strategically to try to get a result as close as possible to their preferred outcome but within the constraints imposed by needing agreement among colleagues and (sometimes) by concerns about the response of other governmental actors. Id. at 1. While somewhat more nuanced than the attitudinal model, the strategic model likewise assumes that the Justices are primarily motivated by ideological considerations, not law. See generally id. Of course, these models are not the only ways that political scientists think about judicial decisionmaking. See, e.g., Cornell W. Clayton, The Supreme Court and Political Jurisprudence: New and Old Institutionalisms, in SUPREME COURT DECISIONMAKING: NEW INSTITUTIONALIST APPROACHES 15-41 (Cornell W. Clayton & Howard 44 82 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Despite their limitations, these approaches to studying the ideology of Supreme Court cases and Justices are prominent in the burgeoning field of empirical legal scholarship in part because they are conducive to large-scale quantitative analysis. They also are good examples of two significant limitations of much empirical legal scholarship. First, as already mentioned, they at best ignore and at worst reject any role for law in Supreme Court judging. And second, they presume that the ideological nature of each case can be characterized along a single liberal-conservative dimension. As a result, these approaches generally offer no way to evaluate the possibility that a particular case might involve multiple issues or concerns that pull the Justices in different directions and that require them to balance competing interests and priorities. As a result of these and other deficiencies, some might dismiss the project of quantitative analysis as, at best, too reductive to be useful, and indeed some legal academics have criticized empirical legal scholarship for such flaws.6 This Article, however, proceeds from the premise that the tools of quantitative analysis can enrich the longstanding public and academic debates about ideology and judging by offering important information about what the Justices actually do. For example, quantitative analysis might allow us to evaluate the ways in which Justices vote in cases that turn on issues of procedure. Do the votes vary systematically depending on the underlying issues in the cases, and, if so, how? Quantitative analysis of such questions can help scholars avoid basing broad conclusions about the respective roles of ideology and law on a handful of high-profile but unrepresentative cases – a danger to which both traditional legal scholarship and public debate are particularly susceptible. In order to answer such questions, however, we must refine the way empirical scholars identify the ideological nature of cases, Gillman eds., 1999); Howard Gillman, What’s Law Got to Do with It? Judicial Behavioralists Test the ‘Legal Model’ of Judicial Decision Making, 26 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 465 (2001); Mark J. Richards & Herbert M. Kritzer, Jurisprudential Regimes in Supreme Court Decision Making, 96 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 305 (2002); Herbert M. Kritzer & Mark J. Richards, Jurisprudential Regimes and Supreme Court Decisionmaking: The Lemon Regime and Establishment Clause Cases, 37 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 827 (2003); Stefanie A. Lindquist & David E. Klein, The Influence of Jurisprudential Considerations on Supreme Court Decisionmaking: A Study of Conflict Cases, 40 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 135 (2006). 6. See, e.g., FRANK B. CROSS, LAW IS POLITICS (forthcoming 2009) (manuscript at 9-10) (prepared for presentation at the “What’s Law Got to Do With It?” Conference, Indiana University, 2009); Harry T. Edwards & Michael A. Livermore, Pitfalls of Empirical Studies That Attempt to Understand the Factors Affecting Appellate Decisionmaking, 58 DUKE L.J. 1895 (2009); Brian Z. Tamanaha, The Distorting Slant in Quantitative Studies of Judging, 50 B.C. L. REV. 685 (2009); Gregory C. Sisk, The Quantitative Moment and the Qualitative Opportunity: Legal Studies of Judicial Decision Making, 93 CORNELL L. REV. 873 (2008). 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 83 making possible acknowledgment and empirical assessment of the cases’ legal content. Fortunately, traditional legal academics, who generally engage in qualitative analysis of cases and doctrines, and empirical legal scholars, who use large-scale quantitative techniques, have recently begun to engage in serious discussions with each other about how to think about and evaluate the balance between law and ideology.7 What is missing in many of these discussions, however, is an effort to use the tools of quantitative analysis to engage with actual cases at a level of detail that allows for more nuanced understandings of the interactions between law and politics (or policy, or ideology) and of the interactions among different areas of law and between law and other considerations. There are notable and creative exceptions to this trend, but those works generally focus on particular questions or areas of the law, such as workplace law, tax law, or intellectual property.8 In this Article, in contrast, I engage with a cross-section of cases in order to struggle with and evaluate methods of identifying or describing ideology and the role it plays in the cases. And I conclude that quantitative scholars must think about how to identify the ideological valence of Supreme Court cases in entirely new ways. Specifically, I argue that rather than assuming that the ideological character of cases is the cases’ most important aspect, we should evaluate whether and to what extent ideology plays a role. The Article proceeds in four substantive parts. Part II provides the basic context of the inquiry into attempts to identify the ideological character of Supreme Court cases. In this Part, I explain some of the reasons scholars want to characterize the ideological nature of cases, and I describe and critique in general terms the two most common approaches: Outcome Coding, which assigns a liberal or conservative label to each case depending on its outcome, and Behavioral Coding, which focuses on the voting patterns of the Justices. Part III carries the critique of Outcome Coding a step further. In this Part, I discuss the widely used U.S. Supreme Court Database, which as- 7. Two recent conferences illustrate this development. In March 2009, Indiana University at Bloomington hosted an interdisciplinary conference entitled “What’s Law Got to Do With It?” The proceedings of that conference will be published in a volume forthcoming from the Indiana University Press. In February 2009, the Duke Law Journal hosted a symposium entitled Measuring Judges and Justice, 58 DUKE L.J. 1173 (2009). 8. An outstanding recent example is James J. Brudney & Corey Ditslear, The Warp and Woof of Statutory Interpretation: Comparing Supreme Court Approaches in Tax Law and Workplace Law, 58 DUKE L.J. 1231 (2009). In this fascinating article, following up on their previous work focusing on workplace law, the authors examine the ways in which the Justices’ use of legislative history and canons of statutory construction compare in workplace law and tax law. See id.; see also, e.g., Matthew Sag et al., Ideology and Exceptionalism in Intellectual Property: An Empirical Study, 97 CAL. L. REV. 801 (2009); Nancy Staudt et al., The Ideological Component of Judging in the Taxation Context, 84 WASH. U. L. REV. 1797 (2006). 45 84 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 signs either a liberal or a conservative ideology code to every Supreme Court case since 1953 and which is the primary source of evidence for the attitudinal model. Part III also presents an in-depth recoding, discussion, and analysis of a random sample of 95 cases decided by the last Rehnquist natural court.9 This recoding vividly demonstrates how a presumption that each case involves only one issue, coupled with binary liberal/conservative outcome codes, masks important information about the cases’ ideological and legal content and context. As a result, the Database’s ideology coding involves subjective and unarticulated decisions, leading to great indeterminacy. In fact, for more than a third of the recoded cases, under the Database’s basic protocols, the ideological nature of the cases could have been coded as either liberal or conservative, depending on what issue the coder assigned to the case. Through a qualitative analysis of these cases, Part III also identifies particular types of cases in which the Justices must reconcile competing priorities and issues – ripe areas for future research. Part IV details current efforts to use Behavioral Coding to identify the ideological nature of particular cases. Behavioral Coding infers the ideological character of cases from the voting patterns of the Justices. In this Part, through a qualitative analysis of some of the recoded cases, I examine some of the strengths and weaknesses of these approaches. For example, I demonstrate some of the limitations of relying on a methodology that promises more precision than it can actually provide and that elides the reality that the Justices often face cases that present multiple and competing issues. I also discuss, however, some of the benefits of leveraging information provided by the Justices’ actual voting patterns. Finally, in Part V of the Article, I propose a new way for quantitative scholars to think about the role ideology plays in Supreme Court cases. Specifically, I suggest that rather than focusing – as most empirical scholars do – on the ideological position of a case (liberal or conservative), we should look at the extent to which the case in fact had ideological salience to the Justices themselves. This proposal capitalizes on the insight – often pointed out by traditional legal scholars and acknowledged by some quantitative scholars – that many cases, even at the Supreme Court level, do not have a particularly strong ideological component. If we can separate cases that the Justices treated as largely non-ideological from those cases that were ideologically salient, we can begin to analyze what influences the Justices’ decisionmaking 9. The term natural court refers to the Supreme Court during a period in which there are no personnel changes. Saul Brenner, The New Certiorari Game, 41 J. POL. 649, 653 (1979). The last Rehnquist natural court lasted from the beginning of October Term (OT) 1994 through OT 2004 – a total of 11 years. It is sometimes referred to as the Rehnquist 7 natural court, as it is the seventh natural court of Chief Justice Rehnquist’s tenure. HAROLD J. SPAETH, THE ORIGINAL UNITED STATES SUPREME COURT JUDICIAL DATABASE 1953-1997 TERMS 30 (2008), available at http://www.cas.sc.edu/poli/juri/allcourt_codebook.pdf [hereinafter Codebook]. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 85 in different circumstances. We can address such questions as when and how law dominates, when and how ideology does, and whether other factors might explain the Justices’ votes and opinions. In this Part, I identify and discuss a number of factors likely to be useful in identifying ideological salience. In Part V, I also describe some of the important benefits that a focus on ideological salience would bring to empirical legal scholarship. For example, it would allow quantitative scholars to investigate whether, how, and why judicial behavior varies depending on the ideological salience of a case. A focus on ideological salience would also allow quantitative scholars to consider why some cases have higher ideological salience than others and to identify and study changes over time in the types of cases that are ideologically salient. Perhaps most importantly, a focus on ideological salience would open the door to more meaningful normative discussions between traditional legal academics and empirical scholars about the appropriate role of ideology in Supreme Court judging. The truth about the roles of ideology and law in the work of the Supreme Court undoubtedly lies somewhere between the two extremes of the neutral umpire and the lawless ideologue, both as an empirical and normative matter. As Judge Posner explains, all judges, but especially appellate judges and even more especially Supreme Court Justices, can and must sometimes decide cases with reference to their perspectives, politics, experiences, and intuition.10 This is because the law itself leaves areas of uncertainty – what Posner calls “open areas” – in which judges must exercise discretion, weigh competing interests, and make policy judgments.11 If we want to talk about whether we think the Justices get the balance between law and ideology right, then we have to know what balance they are in fact striking, when they allow ideology to dominate, and how other factors influence their decisions. II. CODING CASE IDEOLOGY The role of ideology in the work of the Supreme Court, as well as of lower courts, has long been of interest to scholars. However, “judicial ideology” is not a self-defining term, nor is there consensus about what, precisely, it means.12 “Ideology” could refer to a desire for 10. RICHARD A. POSNER, HOW JUDGES THINK 81-87, 269 (2008). 11. Id. at 81-121. See also Joshua B. Fischman & David S. Law, What Is Judicial Ideology, and How Should We Measure It?, 29 WASH. U. J.L. & POL’Y 133, 13841 (2009) (making the same point and noting that, in many contexts, use of judicial discretion is mandated by the law). 12. See generally CROSS, supra note 6; LAWRENCE BAUM, LAW AND POLICY: MORE AND LESS THAN A DICHOTOMY (forthcoming 2009) (prepared for presentation at the “What’s Law Got To Do With It?” Conference, Indiana University, 2009); Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 137-38. 46 86 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 a particular policy outcome – a world characterized by less environmental degradation, or of less regulation, or of greater or lesser levels of immigration. Alternatively, the term “ideological” could describe a tendency to favor or disfavor certain types of parties – criminal defendants, police officers, corporations, members of ethnic or religious minorities, the disabled, and so forth. Indeed, the breadth of the concept of “ideology” even makes it possible to speak of both political ideology and legal ideology. To say that a certain type of judicial behavior is “ideological” need not mean that it is ideological in a political sense . . . . [A]djudication driven by ideas about the role of law and the responsibilities of judges might by contrast be characterized as both “legal” and “ideological” in character.13 Due to this range of possible meanings, some scholars have defined ideology in functional terms. “Ideology” could, for example, refer to “an overarching framework of beliefs, with sufficient consistency among constituent belief elements that knowledge of an individual’s ideology allows for prediction of his or her views on related topics.”14 Still other scholars think of ideology in more purely political terms, distinct from legal or jurisprudential philosophy: some judges are liberal, others conservative.15 For the purposes of this Article, a working understanding of what is meant by judicial ideology falls somewhere between these latter two ideas. Judicial ideology here refers to judges’ extralegal “beliefs and intuitions,”16 which can and often do form a general framework or orientation influencing decisionmaking, frequently but not always correlating to more general understandings of political ideology. To understand the significance of this working definition as a practical matter, it is helpful to consider some of the kinds of questions that scholars interested in judicial ideology have asked. Some have focused on the relationship between judges’ or Justices’ political orientations when appointed and the way that they vote once on the bench. For example, if certain Justices were described by newspaper editorials as very liberal (or conservative) before they were confirmed,17 or if those Justices were appointed by a Demo13. Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 138. 14. Sag et al., supra note 8, at 804. 15. SEGAL & SPAETH, supra note 4, at 86 (“Simply put, Rehnquist votes the way he does because he is extremely conservative; Marshall voted the way he did because he was extremely liberal.”). 16. POSNER, supra note 10, at 79. 17. This measure is known as the Segal-Cover scores and has been widely used because it is a measure of a Justice’s ideology that is completely independent of any votes the Justice makes on the Court. Jeffrey A. Segal & Albert D. Cover, Ideological Values and the Votes of U.S. Supreme Court Justices, 83 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 557, 559-61 (1989). Of course, it also is unable to capture any changes or evolution in the Justice’s views once confirmed. Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 173. Judicial 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 87 cratic (or Republican) President, can we then predict how they will vote?18 In some cases? In cases involving certain legal issues only? In all cases? Other scholars have attempted to answer questions about judicial ideology by looking at the Justices’ behavior on the bench. If we know that Justice X rarely votes in favor of criminal defendants, what (if anything) does that tell us about how Justice X is likely to vote in intellectual property cases, for example, or First Amendment cases?19 Or if two particular Justices generally vote together and often are the only two in dissent in certain types of cases, can we make predictions about how they might vote in other categories of cases? All of these questions require researchers to have not only some information about the Justices’ ideological orientations – whether gleaned from newspaper editorials, party of appointing President, or voting patterns – but also information about the ideological nature of the Justices’ votes, opinions, or holdings. Put concretely, if we want to know if Justices appointed by Democratic Presidents generally vote more liberally than Justices appointed by Republican Presidents, then we need to be able to evaluate whether particular votes or opinions are more liberal or more conservative than others. It is this question – how we should identify (or, in the language of empirical legal studies, “code”) the ideological nature of cases (“case ideology”) – on which this Article focuses. The two primary approaches to coding case ideology focus on the votes and/or outcomes in cases and not on the content of the opinions. Some scholars assign an ideology code to the case outcome (or the outcome for which a Justice voted). Outcome can be defined by a variety of factors, such as which party wins, whether a statute is upheld or struck down, or the type of claim at issue, but, crucially, it is (in theory) independent of information about which Justices vote which way. So, for example, the U.S. Supreme Court Database assigns a liberal code to case outcomes (or votes) in favor of criminal defendants. I refer to this kind of coding as “Outcome Coding.” Other scholars look at the voting patterns of the Justices over time with reference to each other and derive ways of describing case ideology from those voting patterns. Although these approaches often use highly sophisticated statistical methods, we can begin our discussion of them with a conceptual description. Knowing nothing about a case other than that Justices Scalia, Thomas, and Rehnquist were in the majority and that Justices Souter and Stevens were in dissent, most observers likely assume that the outcome of the common space scores, another widely used measure of judicial ideology, have some of the same strengths and weaknesses. These scores rely on ideology measures of the appointing President as well as of a judge’s home state senators at the time of appointment where those senators are of the same party as the President. Michael W. Giles et al., Picking Federal Judges: A Note on Policy and Partisan Selection Agendas, 54 POL. RES. Q. 623 (2001). 18. Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 166-72. 19. See, e.g., Sag et al., supra note 8 (evaluating whether judicial ideology predicts votes in intellectual property cases); Nancy Staudt et al., supra note 8. 47 88 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 case is conservative. This assumption arises from information we have about the Justices’ behavior on the bench rather than from any identification of the case outcome itself, from any other characteristics of the case, or, for that matter, from information about how the Justices were expected to vote by editorialists or their appointing Presidents.20 I will refer to this kind of coding as “Behavioral Coding.”21 These approaches share several important limitations.22 First, they both focus on the votes and/or outcomes in cases and not on the content of the opinions. As a result, factors such as legal reasoning, precedent, and case facts play no explicit role in describing the ideological character of the case, nor is there an attempt to account for law, jurisprudential approaches, or institutional concerns as constraining, channeling, or motivating forces.23 Second, implicit in these approaches is an assumption that the Justices generally vote sincerely, not strategically, or that we can legitimately treat those votes as sincere even if the Justices do vote strategically.24 And third, these approaches all assume that there is a single dimension – liberal to conservative – along which all cases’ ideological character can be measured. In fact, for the Outcome Coding used in the U.S. Supreme Court Database, not only is the ideology coding unidimensional, but it is also binary – either liberal or conservative.25 The recent Voting Rights Act case, NAMUDNO v. Holder,26 provides a useful example of the complications inherent in trying to identify a case’s ideological character while operating within these limitations. In NAMUDNO, a small Texas municipal district wanted to avoid the restrictions of Section 5 of the Voting Rights Act.27 Section 5 requires voting districts in certain parts of the country, including Texas, to obtain “preclearance” from the U.S. Department of Justice before making any changes that affect vot- 20. In fact, a measure like party of appointing President would not help here, as all five Justices mentioned were appointed by Republican Presidents. 21. Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 176-83 (describing “behavioral measures” of judicial ideology). When describing the coding of cases, Fischman and Law refer to this kind of coding as “agnostic coding” because it “does not require the researcher to make a subjective assessment of the direction of each outcome.” Id. at 162. 22. I discuss here three significant structural limitations. These and other limitations are discussed in more detail infra, Parts II & III. 23. See id. 24. Political scientists often distinguish between sincere and strategic voting. Sincere voting means that judges vote their ideological preferences regardless of the effect that it will have on the final result. Strategic voting occurs when judges alter their votes or other actions in some way to achieve a result closer to their preferences than would occur if they voted sincerely. See, e.g., EPSTEIN & KNIGHT, supra note 5. 25. Codebook, supra note 9. 26. Nw. Austin Mun. Util. Dist. No. One v. Holder, 129 S. Ct. 2504 (2009). 27. Id. at 2505 (the particular statute can be found at 42 U.S.C. § 1973c). 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 89 ing.28 Some otherwise covered states and political subdivisions are able to “bail out” of Section 5’s requirements by making certain showings in a special three-judge district court.29 That court held in NAMUDNO, however, that, under the statutory definition of “political subdivision,” the municipal district was not eligible to bail out.30 In the Supreme Court, the voting district argued that it should be allowed to bail out of Section 5’s requirements (or, rather, that it should be allowed an opportunity to show that it could meet the requirements to bail out).31 In the alternative, it argued that Section 5 was unconstitutional.32 The Supreme Court had upheld identical and near-identical language in earlier incarnations of the Voting Rights Act as legitimate exercises of Congress’s power to enforce the Fifteenth Amendment.33 In NAMUDNO, however, the voting district argued that, under the factual circumstances when the law was reenacted in 2006, Congress exceeded its Fifteenth Amendment power.34 After oral argument, it seemed overwhelmingly likely that there were at least four votes (Chief Justice Roberts and Justices Alito, Scalia, and Thomas) for holding Section 5 unconstitutional, with a likely fifth vote from Justice Kennedy.35 But when the opinion was announced on June 22, 2009, to much surprise,36 the vote was eight to one in favor of a reading of the statutory text that declared that all covered voting districts, including NAMUDNO itself, are eligible for bail-out.37 Because it held for the voting district on the statutory claim, the Court said that it need not and should not decide the constitutional question.38 Only Justice Thomas, concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part, reached the constitutional issue and would have struck down the statute.39 Not only did Justices Alito and Scalia join the majority, but the opinion itself was written by Chief Justice Roberts.40 Perhaps 28. 42 U.S.C. § 1973c (2006). 29. Id. 30. Nw. Austin Mun. Util. Dist. No. One v. Mukasey, 573 F. Supp. 221, 232 (2008). 31. NAMUDNO, 129 S. Ct. at 2510. 32. Id. 33. Lopez v. Monterey County, 525 U.S. 266 (1999); City of Rome v. United States, 446 U.S. 156 (1980); Georgia v. United States, 411 U.S. 526 (1973); South Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383 U.S. 301 (1966). 34. See NAMUDNO, 129 S. Ct. at 2510. 35. See, e.g., Dahlia Lithwick, The Supreme Court Breakfast Table: Roberts, Then and Now, SLATE, June 22, 2009, http://www.slate.com/id/2220927/entry/222105 2/. 36. Id. 37. See NAMUDNO, 129 S. Ct. 2504. 38. Id. at 2513. 39. Id. at 2517 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (arguing that the doctrine of constitutional avoidance is inapplicable in the circumstances of this case). 40. See generally id. 48 90 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 just as surprising, the four most liberal members of the Court – Justices Breyer, Ginsburg, Souter, and Stevens – all joined Chief Justice Roberts’s majority opinion in full, despite the opinion’s skeptical language about the constitutionality of the law,41 and none of them wrote separately. Speculation has run rampant about what happened after the oral argument. Many people presume that there was some kind of compromise.42 For the conservatives, the opinion allowed the plaintiff voting district to avoid the requirements of Section 5 and raised explicit concerns about the law’s constitutionality. For the liberals, the statute remains intact, and Congress has the opportunity to resolve the constitutional concerns itself by amending the law, thereby avoiding a constitutional precedent restricting congressional power with respect to civil rights. There is little question that NAMUDNO raised politically and ideologically salient questions of government treatment of race and of federal authority over functions, like running elections, that are traditionally within the purview of the states. The post-oral-argument predictions presumed, based in large part on their questions and demeanor at oral argument, that the four most conservative Justices would vote to strike down Section 5.43 If we focus only on outcome, then would we say that the majority opinion is liberal because it did not do so or conservative because it did not uphold Section 5? Would we say that it is conservative because it allowed for the possibility that the voting district could bail out of Section 5’s requirements or liberal because to do so the district must establish a track record of undertaking measures designed to ensure minority voters equal access to the polls? If we take a more behavioral approach, we might assume that, because the liberal Justices joined the majority opinion, the opinion should be characterized as relatively liberal – but the behavioral approach does not allow us to take into account the opinion’s language voicing serious doubts about Section 5’s constitutionality. Nor does it allow us to account for the possibility of strategic voting and opinion writing. And finally, we miss, through these approaches, any analysis of the legal reasoning, such as the majority’s use of the constitutional avoidance doctrine, or any way to consider what (if anything) the quality or nature of that reasoning tells us about the ideological and/or strategic nature of the Justices’ votes. Neither Outcome Coding nor Behavioral Cod- 41. See, e.g., id. at 2512 (discussing “federalism concerns” inherent in federal control over state-run elections, differentiation between states “despite our historic tradition that all the States enjoy equal sovereignty,” and race-consciousness required to comply with Section 5) (internal quotation marks and citations omitted); id. at 2513 (noting that the “Act’s preclearance requirements and its coverage formula raise serious constitutional questions”). 42. See, e.g., Linda Greenhouse, The Supreme Court Breakfast Table: There’s Always Another Day, SLATE, June 22, 2009, http://www.slate.com/id/2220927/ entry/2221036/; Lithwick, supra note 35. 43. Lithwick, supra note 35. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 91 ing adequately describes the ideological valence of the case and the interaction between ideology and other considerations. III. OUTCOME CODING A. How It Works and How It Doesn’t 1. The Supreme Court Database The most famous and widely used source of Outcome Coding for Supreme Court cases is found in Harold Spaeth’s U.S. Supreme Court Database (the “Database”).44 The Database is the primary source of evidence for the attitudinal model, but it is ubiquitous in all kinds of empirical legal scholarship on the Supreme Court. As one scholar puts it, “‘There is little doubt that today [the] U.S. Supreme Court Judicial Data Base is the greatest single resource of data on the Court; there are virtually no social-scientific projects on the Court that fail to draw on it.’”45 The Database’s own new website proclaims itself “the definitive source for researchers, students, journalists and citizens interested in the U.S. Supreme Court.”46 Unfortunately, however, scholars often use the Database without careful consideration of its significant limitations and its appropriateness for their purposes.47 To identify the ideological character of cases, the Database codes virtually every case as having either a liberal or a conservative outcome.48 Some of the limitations of this approach are obvious and fairly well recognized. A binary, liberal-versus-conservative coding system masks all kinds of subtleties: some cases are more liberal (or more conservative) than others;49 some 44. The Database is available for free public download at http://scdb.wustl.e du/index.php [hereinafter Database]. See also www.cas.sc.edu/poli/juri/ sctdata.htm. 45. Michael Heise, The Past, Present, and Future of Empirical Legal Scholarship: Judicial Decision Making and the New Empiricism, 2002 U. ILL. L. REV. 819, 848 (2002) (quoting Lee Epstein, Social Science, the Courts, and the Law, 83 JUDICATURE 225, 225 (2000)). 46. See Database, supra note 44. 47. See generally Carolyn Shapiro, Coding Complexity: Bringing Law to the Empirical Analysis of the Supreme Court, 60 HASTINGS L.J. 477 (2009). 48. Codebook, supra note 9. Likewise, it codes every vote as having a conservative or liberal orientation. Id. I will refer primarily to case outcomes in the text, but the same analysis and critiques apply to the Database’s coding of individual votes. 49. See, e.g., Shapiro, supra note 47, at 486-87 & n.43 (citing Frank B. Cross et al., Warren Court Precedents in the Rehnquist Court, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 3, 4 (2007)) (“[T]he binary outcome coding cannot measure whether a particular opinion is moderately liberal (or conservative) or more extremely ideological.”); Michael J. Gerhardt, Attitudes About Attitudes, 101 MICH. L. REV. 1733 (2003) (reviewing objections to the attitudinal model and Spaeth and Segal’s responses). 49 92 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 issue areas (such as civil rights) may be more suitable to being characterized as liberal or conservative than others (such as patent law);50 and some cases involve more than one issue to which an ideology code could be attached.51 It is this last point – the possibility of more than one issue actually being present in a case – that the Database’s design and coding protocols render particularly problematic. Each case receives a code reflecting the case’s “issue,” and the coding protocols for the Database explicitly presume that most cases can and should be coded with a single issue.52 Once a case’s issue is identified, an issue area code is assigned. Assigning issue area codes is mechanical: each issue code is assigned to one of thirteen issue areas.53 Those issue area codes are crucial for determining the ideology of the case. The ideology coding protocols are different for different issue areas and focus either on which party prevails or on what type of ruling was issued on a particular claim.54 In the criminal procedure issue area, for example, when the prevailing party in a case is a criminal defendant, the case is coded as liberal; 50. See William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, Rational Judicial Behavior: A Statistical Study (August 28, 2009) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1126403 (changing ideology codes within certain issue areas to “indeterminate” due to dissatisfaction with the liberal versus conservative options in those issue areas). For examples of efforts to address inadequate ideology coding in particular issue areas, see Michael S. Greve & Jonathan Klick, Preemption in the Rehnquist Court: A Preliminary Empirical Assessment, 14 SUP. CT. ECON. REV. 43 (2006) (explaining that the Database does not adequately assess the ideological orientation of cases involving federal preemption of state law); Nancy Staudt et al., supra note 8 (developing a separate ideology coding regime for tax cases in part due to dissatisfaction with the Database in this area of law); Sag et al., supra note 8 (developing a different approach to identifying the ideological nature of intellectual property cases). 51. See, e.g., Greve & Klick, supra note 50, at 79; Ernest A. Young, Just Blowing Smoke? Politics, Doctrine, and the Federalist Revival After Gonzales v. Raich, 2005 SUP. CT. REV. 1, 1-3; Shapiro, supra note 47, at 521; Anna Harvey & Michael J. Woodruff, Confirmation Bias in the United States Supreme Court Judicial Database 3 (2009), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id =1393613. See infra text and notes 64-69 for an in-depth discussion of Anna Harvey and Michael Woodruff’s analysis of the scope of this problem. 52. Shapiro, supra note 47, at 491-92. The coding protocols do allow for cases to have multiple issues assigned to a single case. Id. at 492. Only about 8.6% of the orally argued cases in the Database (1953-2005) have more than one issue code. Id. at 491-92 & n.74. In addition, a case’s issue is defined not as its legal issue but as the public policy context of the case. Id. at 488-91. 53. The issue areas are Criminal Procedure, Civil Rights, First Amendment, Due Process, Privacy, Attorneys, Unions, Economic Activity, Judicial Power, Federalism, Interstate Relations, Federal Taxation, and Miscellaneous. SPAETH, Codebook, supra note 9, at 42-52. The coding protocols require the coder to identify the issue code for the case. Id. at 42-43. The issue area is then automatically assigned by the computer. Id. at 82. 54. Id. at 53-55. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 93 when the criminal defendant loses, the case is coded as conservative.55 In the economic activity area, if economic regulation is invalidated, the case is coded as conservative; if it is upheld, the case is coded as liberal.56 Individual Justices’ votes are also classified using the same protocols but with a focus on the party or claim for which the Justices voted.57 Because the Database’s ideology protocols vary with issue area, in some cases, the choice of issue area determines the ideology code. Schenck v. ProChoice Network of Western New York58 is such a case.59 In Schenck, abortion protesters brought a First Amendment challenge to an injunction restricting their activities.60 Votes for the abortion protesters and their First Amendment rights were coded as conservative – because the issue identified was abortion.61 But if the issue identified had been the First Amendment, the votes for the protesters, as claimants of First Amendment rights, would have been classified as liberal.62 Spelling out these protocols forces us to recognize that what looks on the surface like a completely objective system – look at the issue area and figure out which party prevailed – in fact masks subjective decisions about how to characterize a case. This does not mean that those decisions are necessarily “wrong.” Consider Schenck: most observers would agree, I think, 55. Id. at 53-54. 56. Id. at 54. 57. Id. at 61-67. 58. 519 U.S. 357 (1997). 59. Another prominent example is Gonzalez v. Raich, 545 U.S. 1 (2005), in which a liberal vote for the supremacy of federal law was also a conservative vote against legalizing medical marijuana. See also Shapiro, supra note 47, at 492; Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 161-63; Young, supra note 51, at 11. 60. Schenck, 519 U.S. at 361-62. 61. See Shapiro, supra note 47, at 480. 62. A disclaimer about terminology is appropriate here. As others have complained, see, for example, Ernest Young, Judicial Activism and Conservative Politics, 73 U. COLO. L. REV. 1139, 1189-90 (2002), the Database’s identification of which case outcomes are conservative (versus liberal) is, in some contexts, contestable, outof-date, or even offensive. Most contemporary conservatives would bristle at the notion that a decision in favor of a cross-burner should be seen as conservative because the decision is in favor of a racist. Likewise, many conservatives today would be quite reluctant to accept automatic descriptions of all pro-First Amendment decisions as “liberal.” See infra note 78. A similar critique of the Database’s protocols can be made from the left. Many liberals would not accept the notion, for example, that a vote against a criminal defendant should automatically be seen as a conservative vote. Nonetheless, throughout my discussion of the Database and its coding protocols in both Part II and Part III, I will, by necessity, refer to case outcomes or votes in the Database’s terms. This use of terminology should not be taken to mean that I am attributing particular views to all (or any) conservatives or liberals. The same of course is true when I refer to liberal or conservative views even outside the context of the Database. 50 94 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 that in our current political context the votes for the abortion protesters were votes for the more conservative outcome, while the votes against the protesters were for the more liberal outcome. (This is true even though the votes for the protesters were also votes for more expansive First Amendment rights, a position traditionally deemed liberal.)63 But making such an assessment requires the coder to, sub silentio, locate the case in a broader political and social context, which is not always easy to do. 2. Challenging the Database’s Issue and Ideology Codes Recent scholarship has begun to explore the extent to which the Database systematically selects one type of issue code over another – and therefore one type of ideology code over another. This scholarship is useful both for noting the indeterminacy of the Database’s coding protocols and for understanding the nature of the unarticulated criteria that go into the coding decisions. In a recent working paper, for example, Professors Anna Harvey and Michael Woodruff convincingly demonstrate that the way the Database identifies issues – and hence ideology – varies over time and correlates to the ideological reputation of the Court that decided each case.64 Harvey and Woodruff focus on cases that involved constitutional challenges to federal statutes and that were decided between 1953 and 2002.65 Under the Database’s coding protocols, they note, most such cases can be given either an issue code that focuses on the constitutional question (for example, the First Amendment or due process) or one that focuses on the substantive area that the statute regulates (for example, economic activity).66 Moreover, some of these issue areas are oriented so that within those areas decisions to strike down statutes are coded as “liberal” – vindicating a person’s constitutional rights, for example – while other issue areas would code the same decision as “conservative” – anti-regulation. As a result, the issue coding decisions with respect to constitutional challenges have systematic implications for the ideology coding in such cases. 63. Cf. Lee Epstein & Jeffrey A. Segal, Trumping the First Amendment, 21 WASH. U. J.L. & POL’Y 81, 91 (2006) (arguing that, over time, liberal Justices have become increasingly willing to allow other interests to predominate over First Amendment interests). But see Shapiro, supra note 47, at 507-08 (pointing out the ways in which Epstein and Segal’s analysis is faulty due to its reliance on the Database’s coding). 64. Harvey & Woodruff, supra note 51, at 14; see also Anna Harvey, What Makes a Judgment “Liberal?” Coding Bias in the United States Supreme Court Judicial Database 8 (2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1120970 (arguing that decisions about issue and ideology coding may be affected by the coder’s knowledge of which Justices are in the majority and which are in dissent). 65. See generally Harvey & Woodruff, supra note 51. 66. See id. at 6-10. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 95 Through statistical analysis of the cases involving constitutional challenges, Harvey and Woodruff establish that the Database systematically identifies issue codes leading to liberal outcomes for cases decided by the relatively liberal Warren and Burger Courts and vice versa for the conservative Rehnquist Court.67 Harvey and Woodruff attribute their findings to confirmation bias: the coder knows, for example, that the Rehnquist Court is conservative, and so the coder is more likely to select an issue code resulting in a conservative outcome.68 As a result, they argue, conclusions drawn about, for example, the ideological nature of cases decided by these different Courts may be circular and unreliable.69 There are, however, other explanations for Harvey and Woodruff’s striking and fascinating findings, and those explanations require thinking about ideology in more contextual ways. Take one of their prominent examples, Lopez v. United States.70 In Lopez, a convicted criminal challenged the constitutionality of a statute criminalizing possession of a gun within a certain distance of a school.71 Lopez’s argument – which likely looked like a long shot when it was first made – was that the statute in question exceeded Congress’s regulatory authority under the Commerce Clause.72 In a 5-4 decision, the Supreme Court agreed with him.73 As Harvey and Woodruff point out, if coded as a criminal procedure case – which is possible under the Database’s protocols – the case would result in a liberal ideology code because it was decided in favor of a criminal defendant.74 But since it was coded as a federalism case, it received a conservative ideology code because it limits the regulatory power of Congress.75 Harvey and Woodruff suggest that the decision to code Lopez so that it received a conservative ideology code is the result of confirmation bias.76 But this line of argument assumes that we should assess ideology by reference to the same aspects of a case in 1995 as in 1965, regardless of what other legal or political issues are present in the case and regardless of broader historical and political contexts. In other words, at some historical moments, 67. In fact, they find that every single case in which the Warren Court struck down a statute is coded for liberal ideology. Id. at 11. 68. Id. at 10-14. 69. I use the term “unreliable” in its ordinary, descriptive sense, not in the technical statistical sense of repeatedly reaching different results or observations. Cf. Shapiro, supra note 47, at 481 n.16. 70. 514 U.S. 549 (1995). 71. Id. at 551-52. 72. Id. at 552. 73. Id. 74. See Harvey & Woodruff, supra note 51, at 16-17. 75. Id. at 16. Lopez also was coded as a case involving economic activity. Id. Because the case struck down a regulatory statute, under the Database’s decision rules, it is coded as a conservative outcome. Id. at 16-17. 76. See id. at 17-18. 51 96 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 the Justices’ focus may be more clearly on congressional power issues, for example, while at other times they may be paying more attention to criminal law and procedure. More generally, underlying Harvey and Woodruff’s analysis is an assumption that ideology is always relevantly identified by reference to the same aspects of an opinion – either the nature of the statute struck down or the nature of the constitutional challenge, but not both. Different areas of the law (or, for that matter, of policy) are not deemed to interact, influence, or trump each other. But does anyone really doubt that Lopez was a conservative decision? True, it vacated a criminal conviction, but that was unquestionably the least salient aspect of the case to the Justices and to the opinion-reading public. It was the implications of both the holding and the Court’s reasoning for congressional power in all kinds of contexts – criminal and otherwise – that alarmed liberals and pleased conservatives.77 The criminal context of the case was largely irrelevant to these concerns. In fact, the conservative majority’s willingness to vacate a criminal conviction and overturn a criminal statute (albeit one relating to guns) could be seen as an indication of just how salient the conservative aspect of the opinion was to the Justices in the majority. More importantly, seen in the context of the many other Rehnquist Court cases restricting congressional power, Lopez was part of a larger conservative project, just as expansive readings that vindicated constitutional rights were part of a larger project of the Warren Court. Part of the challenge empirical legal scholars face in gaining respect within the legal academy is rooted in such realities – realities that are elided by the Database, unnoted by most people who rely on its coding, and ignored by the kinds of “objective” coding regimes with which Harvey and Woodruff experiment. Put bluntly, coding regimes that might identify Lopez as a liberal case will not and should not be taken seriously by legal scholars.78 Ultimately, what Harvey and Woodruff’s work may establish is that – at least sometimes – the Database’s issue and ideology coding is driven not so much by confirmation bias, as they hypothesize, but by an assessment of the most politically salient aspects of the case in the context of the time and the particular Court’s overall agenda. To the extent that the Database gets those 77. Cf. Baum, supra note 12, at 5 (citing Paul J. Wahlbeck, The Life of the Law: Judicial Politics and Legal Change, 59 J. POL. 778 (1997) (noting that “judges actually might have limited interest in who wins and loses a specific case and much greater interest in the broader policy implications of court decisions than are captured in doctrine”). 78. I do not mean to suggest that miscoding the occasional case – even an important case like Lopez – necessarily renders the Database and work relying on it unreliable. To the extent that such miscodings are randomly distributed and are not too ubiquitous, the problems they present will not affect conclusions drawn from large-N statistical studies. Moreover, in fairness to Harvey and Woodruff, I do not believe that they are claiming that Lopez is a liberal case. They use it as an example of the systematic differences in coding among different eras of the Supreme Court. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 97 assessments “right,” it is because of unarticulated decisions and criteria, such as the decision not to code Lopez as a liberal criminal procedure case or to code Schenck as an abortion case. The unarticulated nature of these assessments means that, at best, scholars are deprived of the opportunity to analyze the way the Justices’ votes and opinions are affected by the interaction of different legal and political issues arising in a single case.79 The appropriate response, it seems to me, is to find ways to explicitly account for both the context of the cases and the content of the opinions. Doing so requires moving away from binary, liberal-versus-conservative coding and from assumptions that most cases can be described by reference to a single issue or issue area. B. The Recoding Project Part of any assessment of the limitations of the Database’s coding must concretely examine ways in which the coding is incomplete or inaccurate. To do so here, I build on my prior efforts to evaluate the limitations of the Database. In a previous article, Coding Complexity: Bringing Law to the Empirical Analysis of the Supreme Court, I recoded a random sample of 95 cases – 10% of the cases decided by the last Rehnquist natural court (“Rehnquist 7”)80 – in an effort to establish the extent to which the Database accurately provides information about law. Through this Recoding Project, I concluded that a significant amount of information about law goes unreported in the Database, in large part due to the presumption that most cases can and should be coded with a single issue.81 Notably, out of the 95 cases in my sample, the Database coded 94 of them as involving only a single issue area and coded only one case as having two issue areas.82 In contrast, once recoded, the mean number of issue areas per case was 2.4, and only six cases had a single issue area.83 In other words, the Database failed to identify more than half of the issue areas identified by the Recoding Project. Coding Complexity focused on the Database’s limitations only with respect to information about law, and my primary goal in that article was to evaluate how and whether empirical scholars interested in law could use the 79. At worst, of course, the Database systematically gets these assessments wrong, leading to misleading data and conclusions based on that data. Cf. Harvey & Woodruff, supra note 51, at 20 (arguing that the Database’s ideology coding biases have led to inaccurate assessments of the extent to which the Court is constrained by Congress). 80. The sample was computer generated. See Shapiro, supra note 47, at 511 n.175. 81. See id. at 528-29. 82. Id. at 514-15. 83. Id. Only about 5.12% of Rehnquist 7 cases are coded in the Database as having more than one issue (and some of those cases have only one issue area). Id. at 516 & n.187. 52 98 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Database.84 Therefore, although I noted that the Database’s coding of outcome ideology relies on the issue areas coded, I did not evaluate the extent to which the issue areas that the Database fails to identify in fact affected its ideology coding. Here, I address that question: since the Database’s ideology coding is directly related to the issue area codes, how would ideology coding vary for the many cases that, once recoded, have additional issue area codes?85 In other words, using the Database’s basic ideology protocols but my more complete issue coding, do we see any significant differences or inconsistencies in the ideology coding? To investigate this question, I returned to the recoded cases from Coding Complexity. I used the ideology coding protocols set out in the Database’s codebook, applying them to each issue that I had coded86 rather than to the case as a whole. Several caveats are worth mentioning. First, because the Database’s issue coding is designed to identify the public policy context of a case, not the case’s legal issues, comparing my legal-issue based ideology coding to the Database’s public-policy based coding is, arguably, comparing apples to oranges. I accounted for this problem by reviewing the cases to ensure that the public policy context was captured by the issue coding, and I concluded that only three cases in the sample involved public policy contexts not accounted for by their recoded legal issues.87 As a result, the Database’s ideology coding protocols were generally applicable to the legal issues that I identified. 84. Id. at 488. 85. I am indebted to Gregory Mitchell for suggesting this line of inquiry. 86. I did the ideology coding more than a year and a half after I did the issue coding. 87. Those three cases are Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W. N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997), Clinton v. Jones, 520 U.S. 681 (1997), and Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003). Schenck is the First Amendment challenge brought by abortion protesters. 519 U.S. 357. There is no legal issue related to abortion in the case. See id. Virginia v. Black is also a First Amendment case in which the nature of the “speech” – cross burning – has a significant public policy context in its own right. 538 U.S. 343. Finally, in Clinton v. Jones, Paula Jones’s lawsuit against President Clinton, see 520 U.S. 681, the partisan political context is not encompassed by the issue codes. For these cases, I did not add any issues to my issue coding, but I did account for the larger public policy context in the ideology coding. Because Schenck and Black were already coded as having mixed ideology, nothing changed in their coding. For Clinton v. Jones, however, I changed the liberal ideology code to a mixed code. See note 94 and accompanying text for an explanation of mixed ideology codes. My conclusion that public policy context was almost always accounted for in the issue coding is consistent with my findings in Coding Complexity that, in general, at least one of my issue area codes matched the Database’s. Shapiro, supra note 47, at 517. Interestingly, despite the protocol requiring coding of the public policy context and not legal issue, Schenck is the only one of the three cases for which the Database actually identifies the public policy context as the case’s issue. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 99 Nonetheless, in a few situations, the protocols did not speak directly to the types of issues presented. For example, the coding protocols provided that cases decided in favor of voting rights plaintiffs should be coded as liberal, making no distinction between minority plaintiffs alleging that their voting rights had been violated and white plaintiffs alleging racial gerrymandering. When appropriate, I updated the protocols accordingly.88 In addition, in the Recoding Project for Coding Complexity, I created some issue areas that did not exist in the original Database in order to more accurately describe the cases’ legal issues.89 As a result, I had to make some changes and additions to the ideology coding protocols to accommodate these new issue areas. I tried, however, to hew as closely as I could to the Database’s protocols. For example, in my issue area “employment,” which encompasses the Database’s “unions” issue area but is much broader, I continued the Database’s practice of coding a case conservative if it was proemployer and vice versa.90 Finally, unlike the Database, which codes outcome on the basis of which party or claim prevailed in the entire case,91 I coded the outcome of the cases on an issue-by-issue basis. For example, if a habeas petitioner were to win on a procedural claim but lose on the merits of his ineffective assistance of counsel claim, the Database would likely assign that case a conservative code – the final outcome is in favor of the government and against the criminal defendant. Coding by issue, however, required me to evaluate how each issue was decided, even if the resolution of that issue did not affect the case’s final outcome. So my hypothetical habeas case would get a liberal code for the procedural issue and a conservative code on the merits. Before describing the results of this recoding and comparing them to the Database’s original coding, however, it is worth reiterating why I undertook the project. My purpose is not simply to show that the Database’s ideology coding protocols are indeterminate and dependent upon subjective issue coding – although there is strong evidence for that proposition in my recoding and in the work of Harvey and Woodruff, among others.92 The purpose here is to use an intensive look at the 95 cases in my sample to begin a discussion of how and whether we can better evaluate a case’s ideological character, what we mean when we talk about a case’s ideology, and what we are missing under current measures of case ideology. I do not claim that my approach 88. In fact, I discovered that, in some instances, including the racial gerrymandering cases, Spaeth himself had, sub silentio, updated the protocols, coding conservative votes in favor of the plaintiffs in those cases and vice versa. 89. See Shapiro, supra note 47, at 511-12. 90. This approach is also consistent with the Database’s overall economic activity protocols, which also overlap with my employment issue area. 91. Codebook, supra note 9, at 58-59. 92. Harvey & Woodruff, supra note 51; Young, supra note 51, at 9-10; Shapiro, supra note 47, at 493; Paul H. Edelman & Jim Chen, The Most Dangerous Justice Rides into the Sunset, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 199, 207 (2007). 53 100 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 to coding legal issues, coupled with the Database’s ideology protocols, is the best way to identify the ideological nature of cases.93 Rather, this approach gives us an initial purchase on the nuanced and textured nature of ideological and legal decisionmaking in a cross-section of cases and a way to evaluate at least some of the substantive limitations of binary, liberal-versus-conservative coding. 1. Quantitative Analysis Once I completed the outcome recoding of my 95-case random sample, I compared my ideology codes to the Database’s. Out of the 95 cases in the dataset, the Database assigns 47 of them a conservative ideology code and 45 of them a liberal ideology code. Three cases received both liberal and conservative ideology codes; that is, the Database itself gave three cases what I call “mixed ideology codes.”94 Where the Database’s ideology codes were in complete agreement with mine, I designated the case a match. Sixty cases, including the Database’s three mixed ideology cases, were matches. Under my recoding, there were an additional 35 cases that had mixed ideology codes – both liberal and conservative codes – for a total of 38 or 40.0%.95 Were all the cases from the last Rehnquist natural court (“Rehnquist 7”) to be recoded, there is a 95% chance that between 30.0% and 50.0% of them would have mixed coding.96 In other words, from about one-third to one-half of Rehnquist 7 cases would be coded as having both liberal and conservative ideology. The Database, however, identifies a grand total of only 93. I doubt very much that it is. See infra Part V. 94. Those cases were Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W. N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997), which received a mixed ideology code because the Court upheld part of the injunction against the abortion protesters and struck down part of it; Kolstad v. American Dental Ass’n, 527 U.S. 526 (1999), in which the Court unanimously allowed punitive damages under Title VII but, in a 5-4 vote, restricted the circumstances under which they could be awarded; and Green Tree Financial Corp. v. Randolph, 531 U.S. 79 (2000), in which the Court decided two entirely distinct questions, each of which received its own issue and ideology code. For further discussion of these cases, see infra Part III.B.2. 95. There were no cases in which I coded only the opposite ideology code from the Database. All of the cases either matched the Database’s coding or resulted in mixed ideology coding. 96. Unanimous cases are often omitted from analyses that focus on the ideological orientation of the cases and votes on the theory that these cases are legally easy and that ideology plays little or no role in them. I think that this approach is very problematic, but I did think it was likely that unanimous cases might reflect greater multidimensionality – hence more mixed ideology codes – because different Justices might find different aspects of the same case more salient than other Justices. However, there was barely any change when I removed unanimous cases from the sample. Among the non-unanimous cases in the sample, 37.7% have mixed ideology coding, with a 95% confidence interval of 25.2% to 50.2%. THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 2010] 101 10 such cases for the 11 years of that natural court – about 0.01% of the cases in the Database. These findings alone raise significant questions about any study that rests too much weight on the binary, liberal-versus-conservative coding of the Database, and they suggest that in many cases even the most ideologically driven Justice must prioritize some aspects of a case over others. Table 1: Ideology Coding for 95-Case Sample in U.S. Supreme Court Database and Recoding Project U.S. Supreme Court Database Recoding Project Conservative Only: Number of Cases 47 Liberal Only: Number of Cases 45 Mixed Ideology: Number of Cases 3 27 30 38 In addition to compiling these descriptive statistics, I performed a (logit) regression analysis to investigate factors that made it more likely for a case, once recoded, to have mixed ideology codes. I hypothesized that recoded cases with issue areas that are not generally seen as particularly ideologically fraught – areas like economic activity, judicial power, and matters of government structure and operations97 – would be more likely to have mixed ideology. My reasoning was that it is likely – or even, as Harvey and Woodruff demonstrate, highly probable – that the economic, governmental, or judicial issues often point in different ideological directions from constitutional or civil rights issues that might appear in the same cases.98 Under the same reasoning, I also tested whether cases identified in the Database as involving civil liberties99 were particularly likely to have mixed ideology once recoded. 97. Here, I included cases with issue areas of federalism, federal government, and state and local government. Federalism, of course, was a much contested area during the Rehnquist Court. See, e.g., Kathleen M. Sullivan, From States’ Rights Blues to Blue States’ Rights: Federalism After the Rehnquist Court, 75 FORDHAM L. REV. 799, 799 (2006) (noting that “the Rehnquist Court dramatically revived the structural principles of federalism as grounds for judicial invalidation of statutes”); id. at 800 (noting that these decisions “sharply divided the Court, typically eliciting 5-4 divisions among the Justices and vigorous dissents”). 98. My previous work indicated that issues involving judicial power and the structure and functioning of government are particularly likely to go uncoded in the Database, in contrast with, for example, the sexier issues of civil rights or criminal procedure. Shapiro, supra note 47, at 518-21. For this reason, I focused on the recoded issue areas here. 99. I grouped together cases that the Database codes as involving criminal procedure, civil rights, due process, First Amendment, or privacy. Cf. Lee Epstein et al., The Supreme Court During Crisis: How War Effects Only Non-War Cases, 80 N.Y.U. 54 102 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Here, I thought we might see more mixed ideology codes because the civil liberties aspect of the case would likely have dominated the coding in the Database, leaving out other, less “sexy,” issue and ideology codes. I suspected that vote margins would be related to whether a case had mixed ideology. Cases with broad agreement among Justices who are often at odds ideologically might involve multiple issues, some perhaps more salient to liberal Justices and others more salient to conservative Justices. If that were so, then we might expect to see that unanimous cases or cases with wide vote margins (e.g., 8-1) are more likely to have mixed ideology. On the other hand, I thought we might see the opposite effect. To the extent that unanimous or lopsided cases are the legally “easy” cases in which ideology is not salient, the Justices might join cases that, superficially, appear to point in the opposite direction of their usual predilections. I similarly identified cases in which the lower courts were in disagreement, thinking that such disagreement might signal multidimensionality in issues that would make it more likely that we would see mixed ideology. Finally, I included a variable to indicate how far to the right or left the median Justice in the majority is100 as a way of controlling, to some degree, for the overall ideological orientation of the opinion independent of any outcome-related coding. Interpreting the results of this quantitative analysis must be done with caution. The sample size is quite small,101 and, although there are many potential explanatory variables, I was not able to include them all in the regression.102 My results, which are discussed below and summarized in Table 2, are best understood, therefore, as providing some guidance for future investigation, not as definitively explaining the mixed ideology codes. As expected, recoded cases that included a government, judicial power, or economic activity code were more likely to have mixed ideology than those that did not, but there was no statistically significant effect for cases that the Database coded as involving civil liberties. There was also no statistically significant effect for unanimous cases or for the size of the vote margin. On the other hand and to my surprise, I found that a split of authority in the lower courts made mixed ideology coding less likely. I am unsure how to explain this last result. My measure for how far to the right or left the court majority was, based on the median Justice in the majority, was borderline L. REV. 1, 43-44 (2005) (defining civil liberties cases as including the same five issue areas as well as the “attorneys” issue area). 100. For this variable, I used the Martin-Quinn score of whichever Justice was the median of the majority. See Part IV, infra, for an explanation of Martin-Quinn scores and the significance of the score of the median Justice of the majority. 101. It is at the very low end of the appropriate sample size for a logistic regression. See J. SCOTT LONG & JEREMY FREESE, REGRESSION MODELS FOR CATEGORICAL DEPENDENT VARIABLES USING STATA 77 (2d ed. 2006). 102. I could not include some variables because those variables did not have enough variation in the sample. In addition, due to the small sample size, I had to restrict the number of explanatory variables in the regression. See id. at 131. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 103 statistically significant (p>.052)103 and suggested that, the further to the left the majority was, the less likely the case was to have mixed ideology coding. Again, I am unsure how to explain this result, but it suggests that Justices on the right and left may treat multidimensional cases differently. This finding obviously warrants future research and investigation. Table 2: Factors Tested for Effect on Likelihood of Mixed Ideology in Recoded Cases Factors Tested Economic Activity Issue Area in Recoded Cases Judicial Power Issue Area in Recoded Cases Government Issue Area in Recoded Cases Civil Liberties Code in Original Database Vote Margin Position of Median Justice in Majority Split of Authority Lower Courts in Effect Found Mixed ideology is more likely. Mixed ideology is more likely. Mixed ideology is more likely. No effect found. Statistical Significance p>.01 No effect found. Mixed ideology may be more likely the further to the left the median Justice in the majority. Mixed ideology is less likely. None p>.052 p>.01 p>.01 None p>.05 I also wanted to investigate whether cases that the Database coded as liberal were more or less likely to have mixed ideology once recoded than were cases that it had coded as conservative.104 The evidence here is not conclusive, but it is concerning. When I added the Database’s issue coding to the model, it approached statistical significance (p>.088). In other words, the analysis suggested but did not establish that, all else equal, cases identified as liberal in the Database are more likely to have mixed ideology coding once recoded than are cases originally identified as conservative.105 Further research – with larger datasets – is needed to determine if such a skew is in fact 103. The traditional cut-off for statistical significance is p>.05. The p-value tells us the likelihood that a particular variable actually has the effect identified by the statistical analysis. At p>.01, we can say that there is a 99% likelihood that the variable has the identified effect. At p>.05, we can say there is a 95% likelihood. 104. For this regression, I dropped from the sample the three cases that the Database identifies as mixed. 105. The results also suggested – again without statistical significance – that the tendency was less pronounced in cases to which the Database assigns a civil liberties issue area than in other cases. 55 104 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 present in the Database and, if so, to investigate its implications, which could be extraordinary. 2. Qualitative Analysis The qualitative analysis of the mixed ideology cases begins with the three cases that the Database itself codes as having mixed ideology: Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of Western New York, 106 Kolstad v. American Dental Ass’n,107 and Green Tree Financial Corp. v. Randolph.108 The Database characterizes two of those cases, Schenck and Kolstad, as “split decisions,” meaning that each party prevailed in part. In Schenck, the Court upheld part of the injunction restricting abortion protesters’ activities (coded as liberal) and struck down part of it (coded as conservative).109 In Kolstad, the Court held unanimously that Title VII plaintiffs can receive punitive damages (coded liberal), but, over a partial dissent by four Justices, it imposed a fairly restrictive test for determining when such damages are warranted (coded conservative).110 Green Tree Financial, the third case that the Database codes as both liberal and conservative, is the only case in my sample to which the Database assigns two issues areas: economic activity and judicial power. In Green Tree Financial, the Court answered two distinct questions.111 The first question was whether a district court’s “order compelling arbitration and dismissing a party’s underlying claims is a ‘final decision with respect to arbitration’ within the meaning of . . . the Federal Arbitration Act . . . and is thus immediately appealable pursuant to that Act.”112 Presumably because of the centrality of this jurisdictional question to the case, the Database gives the case a judicial power issue area code. And since the Court concluded (unanimously) that the answer was yes – it was a final order, and so there was appellate jurisdiction113 – the case received a liberal code with respect to judicial power.114 106. 519 U.S. 357 (1997). 107. 527 U.S. 526 (1999). 108. 531 U.S. 79 (2000). 109. Schenck, 519 U.S. at 361. 110. Kolstad, 527 US. at 527. 111. Green Tree Fin., 531 U.S. at 82. 112. Id. (citing 9 U.S.C. § 16(a)(3)). 113. Id. at 89. 114. Under the coding protocols, cases decided in favor of federal court jurisdiction should be coded as liberal. Codebook, supra note 9, at 54-55. Jurisdictional or procedural issues that must be decided before the Court can consider the merits are sometimes called threshold issues, and some scholars systematically identify them separately from the underlying merits issues. Although the Database does identify the issue separately in Green Tree Financial, the protocols do not require that it systematically does so, and in many other cases it does not. See, e.g., Yamaha Motor Corp., 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 105 The Court then went on to consider the second question: the enforceability of the arbitration agreement. The agreement at issue in the case did “not mention arbitration costs and fees,” and the plaintiff argued that it was therefore “unenforceable because it fail[ed] to affirmatively protect [her] . . . from potentially steep arbitration costs.”115 Here, the Court held that the agreement was not automatically unenforceable for that reason and, in a 5-4 vote, ruled against the plaintiff because she had failed to provide any evidence of the arbitration’s actual cost burdens.116 Presumably because the case involved a dispute between a mortgage holder and borrower, the Database assigns it an economic activity issue area. And for a holding like this one, in favor of the large company and against an individual (or potential class of individuals), the coding protocols dictate a conservative ideology code.117 Each of the three original mixed-ideology cases has a different kind of structure with respect to its issue and ideology coding. Schenck involved application of the same body of law – the First Amendment and precedent construing it – to a multi-faceted factual situation – the injunction against the abortion protesters.118 The Court reached different conclusions with respect to different aspects of the factual situation (the injunction), but it did not purport to announce any new legal rules.119 In Kolstad, on the other hand, the Court decided a pure legal question in favor of the plaintiff – and by extension in favor of all Title VII plaintiffs – but it did not go as far in favor of the plaintiff as it could have.120 Both of these cases, to the extent that they can be explained ideologically, suggest that the Justices do not vote in purely binary, liberal-versus-conservative terms. Rather, these cases might be described as falling somewhere on a spectrum. I call cases like Schenck “Tug-of-War Cases” because they involve two clearly defined interests (abortion rights and the First Amendment) that, in the factual context of the case, point in opposite ideological directions under the Database’s protocols.121 In Tug-of-War Cases, the decision as to which issue area to identify will determine the ideology code. These are the kinds of casU.S.A. v. Calhoun, 516 U.S. 199 (1996) (coded by the Database as an economic activity case with no reference to the jurisdictional issue that the Court also decided). 115. Green Tree Fin., 531 U.S. at 82. 116. Id. at 91-92. This portion of the opinion was 5-4. See id. Although the dissenters agreed that the arbitration agreement was not automatically unenforceable, they would have remanded to the lower court “for closer consideration of the arbitral forum’s accessibility.” Id. at 93 (Ginsburg, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). 117. Codebook, supra note 9, at 54. My description of the reasons that the Database codes Green Tree Financial as it does is educated speculation. 118. See Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W. N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997). 119. See generally id. 120. See generally Kolstad v. Am. Dental Ass’n, 527 U.S. 526 (1999). 121. See supra note 62 for a disclaimer and discussion about liberal and conservative labels. 56 106 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 es that Harvey and Woodruff identify as problematic for the Database. In contrast, Kolstad is what I call a “Spectrum Case.” Spectrum Cases are those in which, while there may well be more than one issue or issue area, they run ideologically in the same direction; a vote for the plaintiff is considered a liberal vote in Kolstad under both civil rights coding and economic activity coding.122 Green Tree Financial, on the other hand, is a Tug-of-War Case, but, unlike Schenck, it involves two distinct legal questions, each coded in the Database and decided (according to the Database’s protocols) in different ideological directions. Green Tree Financial’s two distinct legal issues challenge not only the widespread assumption of unidimensionality but also the underlying presumption that the Justices simply vote their policy preferences without regard for law.123 In Green Tree Financial, the Justices who voted against the plaintiff on the merits could have reached the same result – a loss for the plaintiff – if they had held that there was no jurisdiction. Moreover, if they were trying to reach a conservative bottom line, such a holding would have had much more impact, as it would have prevented lower appellate courts from ever reviewing dismissals of plaintiffs’ claims pursuant to the Federal Arbitration Act. Nonetheless, they joined their liberal colleagues in finding such dismissals reviewable in the federal appellate courts.124 The Justices’ behavior in Green Tree Financial therefore suggests that, assuming they were simply voting their policy preferences, they had different ideological preferences with respect to different issue areas. If so, there is no unidimensionality with respect to judicial ideology, at least in this case. On the other hand, if their ultimate policy preference was to promote arbitration (as indeed they suggest in the opinion),125 then their failure to vote against the plaintiff on jurisdictional grounds suggests that they were constrained in some way, perhaps by their reading of the law, or that they were concerned about the consequences of the case as a legal precedent.126 If so, it is not just ideology that motivated their votes. Likewise, the Justices who dissented in Green 122. The difference between Spectrum Cases and Tug-of-War Cases is largely an artifact of the issue and ideology coding protocols both in the Original Database and in the Recoding Project. In both kinds of cases, the Justices are balancing competing interests. Spectrum Cases, however, are often identifiable only when there are separate opinions urging the Court to go further in one direction or another. Moreover, in any case, there may be additional dimensions – jurisprudential, strategic, or institutional, to name a few – that might compete with ideology as the Justices make their decisions. 123. See generally SEGAL & SPAETH, supra note 4. 124. See Green Tree Fin. Corp. v. Randolph, 531 U.S. 79 (2000). 125. The majority does not assert that this is its personal policy preference. See id. Rather, it refers to the need to support the “liberal federal policy favoring arbitration agreements.” Id. at 91 (quoting Moses H. Cone Mem’l Hosp. v. Mercury Constr. Corp., 460 U.S. 1, 24 (1983)). 126. Cf. BAUM, supra note 12, at 5. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 107 Tree Financial could have argued that all arbitration agreements that are silent as to costs are necessarily unenforceable, as the plaintiff claimed and the Eleventh Circuit held, but they did not do that either. Instead, the dissenters agreed with the majority that such agreements can, at least sometimes, be enforced.127 The Green Tree Financial opinions, like those in Schenck and Kolstad, evidence some calibration of judicial preferences that – whether ideological or not – are certainly not binary and that appear to operate along several dimensions. A review of all 38 of the mixed ideology cases in my dataset revealed that – as with Schenck, Kolstad, and Green Tree Financial – in almost every case, the mixed ideology codes revealed something substantive about the case instead of being an artifact of the coding protocols. Sometimes, of course, the mixed ideology codes identified something for which the case was not well known.128 Nor did the different ideological considerations always carry anything close to the same weight within the case.129 Nonetheless, of the 38 mixed ideology cases, I identified only two cases in which the mixed ideology code seemed a function purely of a mechanical application of the coding protocols and added no information about the ideological character of the case.130 In other words, my mixed ideology codes helped to identify cases in which the Justices in fact had to reconcile competing interests. 127. See Green Tree Fin., 531 U.S. 79. 128. For example, Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898 (1997), is known for striking down part of the Brady Bill. But in a lower-profile holding, the Court also held that the plaintiff had no standing to challenge other aspects of the law. 129. In Garner v. Jones, 529 U.S. 244 (2000), for example, the Court held that a change in Georgia’s parole board operations did not violate the Ex Post Facto Clause. However, Justice Scalia, concurring in part and concurring in the judgment, would have denied the prisoner even the possibility that on remand the lower courts might allow him to take additional discovery. See id. at 257-59 (Scalia, J., concurring in part of the judgment). The majority, while it issued a conservative decision, did not go as far as Justice Scalia. See id. at 246-57 (majority opinion). 130. In fact, those two cases demonstrate some additional weaknesses and overgeneralizations in the Database’s coding protocols. In Heintz v. Jenkins, 514 U.S. 291 (1995), the Court held that an attorney who regularly engaged in debt collection was subject to the Fair Debt Collection Practices Act. As an economic activity case (and as coded in the Database), this is a pro-consumer, liberal decision. But if coded as a decision within the attorneys issue area (or in the legal profession issue area in my recoding) as an anti-lawyer decision, it would get a conservative ideology code. The notion that pro-lawyer decisions are necessarily liberal is absurd, and I presume that this protocol arose with respect to issues related to attorneys’ fees and access to lawyers in other contexts. In Jerome B. Grubart, Inc. v. Great Lakes Dredge & Dock Co., 513 U.S. 527 (1995), the Court held that maritime jurisdiction governed litigation over the Chicago flood; as a result, the available damages were dramatically reduced. As an economic activity decision, it should be coded as a conservative, anti-tort liability decision. As a judicial power case, however, the protocols dictate that pro-federal 57 108 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Of the remaining 36 cases, five, including Kolstad, were Spectrum Cases that essentially split the baby – not going as far in one direction as the Court could have gone and issuing a holding that was, in some sense, moderated.131 In Wilson v. Layne, for example, the Court held that officers violated the Fourth Amendment by bringing reporters along for execution of a warrant, but the Court also held that the officers were entitled to qualified immunity from suit.132 The remaining 31 cases were Tug-of-War Cases. These cases involved some recurrent themes,133 some of which have been studied and others of which are ripe for more investigation: (a) Federalism and Preemption. Five cases were about whether federal regulatory structures preempted state law.134 Professors Jonathan Klick and Michael Greve have already recognized this category of cases as problematic for the Database.135 As they explain, if understood as a matter of federalism, pro-state-law, anti-federal-law votes should be coded as conservative, which is in fact how they are usually coded in the Database. But if understood as economic activity cases, the pro-regulation votes – which are also the pro-state-law votes because they are votes to uphold state regulation – should be coded as liberal and vice versa. Greve and Klick’s findings suggest that it is this second dimension – economic regulation – that is often jurisdiction holdings be identified as liberal. Ironically, this is how the Database codes the case, although I would argue that it is simply wrong and overly mechanical. 131. Garner v. Jones, 529 U.S. 244 (2000); Slack v. McDaniel, 529 U.S. 473 (2000) (resolving some procedural matters in favor of habeas petitioner and resolving others against him); Kolstad v. Am. Dental Ass’n, 527 U.S. 526 (1999); Martin v. Hadix, 527 U.S. 343 (1999) (holding that the Prison Litigation Reform Act’s limitations on attorneys’ fees applies to postjudgment monitoring performed after the PLRA’s enactment but not to such monitoring performed before its enactment even if payment was sought only post-enactment); Wilson v. Layne, 526 U.S. 603 (1999). Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003), the cross-burning case, could also be considered to fall into this category. In all of these cases, that there is a spectrum is made obvious by the presence of separate opinions, see, for example, Slack, 529 U.S. 473 (separate opinion by Justice Stevens agreeing with only part of the majority’s holding and separate opinion by Scalia agreeing with a different part), and/or by the Court’s resolution of at least two related questions, as in Wilson, 526 U.S. 603 (resolving merits of Fourth Amendment question as well as the related issue of qualified immunity). 132. 526 U.S. 603 (1999). 133. There is of course some overlap between the categories of cases set forth below, and many cases could be classified in more than one category. Some (but not all) of those overlaps are noted in the footnotes. 134. AT&T v. Cent. Office Tel., Inc., 524 U.S. 214 (1998); Am. Trucking Ass’ns, Inc. v. Mich. Pub. Serv. Comm’n, 545 U.S. 429 (2005); Mid-Con Freight Sys., Inc. v. Mich. Pub. Serv. Comm’n, 545 U.S. 440 (2005); Norfolk S. Ry. Co. v. Shanklin, 529 U.S. 344 (1996); Yamaha Motor Corp., U.S.A. v. Calhoun, 516 U.S. 619 (1996). 135. Greve & Klick, supra note 50, at 79-80. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 109 more salient to the Justices in these cases. Of my five preemption cases, only two of them were coded as economic activity cases. The other three received federalism codes. (b) Constitutional Challenges to Laws. Four cases involved constitutional challenges to state or federal regulation,136 much like the cases that Harvey and Woodruff examine.137 (c) Jurisdictional Issues. Eleven cases, including Green Tree Financial, decided whether to grant standing or jurisdiction to plaintiffs where the ideological character of the jurisdictional decision pointed in the opposite direction of the underlying claims.138 In Bennett v. Spear,139 for example, the Court held that prudential zone-of-interests standing requirements did not apply to citizen suits authorized by the Endangered Species Act, and it found that the plaintiffs in the case – ranchers and irrigation districts concerned about the economic harm they would suffer from certain actions taken by the Department of the Interior under the ESA – had sufficient injury-in-fact to satisfy Article III.140 Pro-jurisdiction, pro-standing holdings are generally seen as liberal, and indeed that is how the case is coded in the Database. But the claims that the Court allowed to go forward alleged that the Secretary of the Interior had failed to adequately consider the economic impact of his action – an anti-environmental, anti-regulation outcome. Such outcomes are generally seen as conservative. So although the Database assigns Bennett a judicial power issue area with a liberal ideology code, the case could have received an economic activity issue area with a conservative ideology code. (d) Federal Government Structure and Power. Four cases involved questions of federal government structure or power – cases that have implications for the balance of power between Congress, the courts, and the executive. Such cases can sometimes pit supposedly liberal or conservative prefer- 136. Ill. ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Assocs., 538 U.S. 600 (2003); Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., 514 U.S. 476 (1995); Buckley v. Am. Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 525 U.S. 182 (1999); Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003). 137. Harvey & Woodruff, supra note 51, at 6-8. Harvey and Woodruff examine only challenges to federal law. See generally id. 138. Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Mineta, 534 U.S. 103 (2001); Green Tree Fin. Corp. v. Randolph, 513 U.S. 79 (2000); Nelson v. Adams USA, Inc., 529 U.S. 460 (2000); Bennett v. Spear, 520 U.S. 154 (1997); Lords Landing Condo. Council of Unit Owners v. Cont’l Ins. Co., 520 U.S. 893 (1997); Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898 (1997); Suitum v. Tahoe Reg’l Planning Agency, 520 U.S. 715 (1997) (takings plaintiff); Comm’r v. Lundy, 516 U.S. 235 (1996); Celotex Corp. v. Edwards, 514 U.S. 300 (1995); Austin v. United States, 513 U.S. 5 (1994); Reich v. Collins, 513 U.S. 106 (1994). 139. 520 U.S. 154 (1997). 140. Id. at 166-68. 58 110 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 ences about deference to the different branches against preferences with respect to the underlying substantive issues.141 (e) Public Policy Contexts. There were three cases, including Schenck, in which the public policy context could be seen as more salient than the legal issues – and where the ideological orientation of the public policy context was inconsistent with the ideological orientation of the legal issues.142 These are cases in which the attitudinal model may have the most explanatory power. (f) Deference to State Decisionmakers. In four cases, the Court had to decide whether to defer to state policymakers or state courts that were asserting a relatively liberal position. In other words, as with the preemption cases, the traditionally conservative solicitude for state policymaking and sovereignty conflicted with the substantive legal issues at stake – and vice versa.143 This qualitative analysis of the mixed ideology cases illustrates why and how unidimensionality and binary ideology coding inadequately describe content of Supreme Court cases and the nature of Supreme Court decisionmaking. The Justices are not simply giving the thumbs up (or thumbs down) to favored (or disfavored) parties or claims. Instead, they are balancing sometimes powerful competing interests. What we cannot conclude from this analysis, however, is the extent to which those competing interests are perceived by the Justices in purely ideological terms – protecting women’s access to abortion versus protecting free speech, for example – or the extent to which they are perceived and resolved along other dimensions – most notably law, but also including strategic, institutional, and jurisprudential considerations. With respect to the interaction of ideology and law, Tug-of-War Cases involving questions of standing and jurisdiction and the state solicitude cases offer particularly fruitful avenues for future research. Are the Justices 141. Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 578 (2004) (holding that the government could not indefinitely detain an American citizen designated an enemy combatant without providing him a chance to contest the factual basis for the detention); Household Credit Servs., Inc. v. Pfennig, 541 U.S. 232 (2004) (applying Chevron deference to regulation promulgated by the Federal Reserve Bank and upholding regulation); Fischer v. United States, 529 U.S. 667 (2000) (holding that the federal bribery statute covered a health care provider participating in Medicare, thereby expanding the reach of federal regulation of criminal activity traditionally governed by the states); Loving v. United States, 517 U.S. 748 (1996) (holding that Congress could delegate to the President the authority to identify aggravating circumstances for the imposition of the death penalty and upholding the factors so identified). Clinton v. Jones, 520 U.S. 681 (1997), could also be placed in this category. 142. Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W. N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997); Clinton, 520 U.S. 681; City of Chicago v. Morales, 527 U.S. 41 (1999). Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003), could also be considered in this category. 143. Easley v. Cromartie, 532 U.S. 234 (2001); Abrams v. Johnson, 521 U.S. 74 (1997); Bush v. Vera, 517 U.S. 952 (1996); Ohio v. Robinette, 519 U.S. 33 (1996). The federal preemption cases can be seen as a subset of this category. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 111 voting on judicial power issues in ways that are inconsistent with their apparent preferences on the underlying merits, especially in ideologically charged areas like race and capital punishment? Do they rule in the same way on similar judicial power questions in different factual or legal contexts? How does deference to state lawmakers vary depending on the legal or factual context? These questions might help us determine how (or whether) legal doctrine interacts with ideology. IV. BEHAVIORAL CODING A. A First Approach While scholars like Spaeth, Harvey, and Woodruff attempt to identify the ideological nature of cases by reference to case outcomes, independently of the Court’s composition and how particular Justices vote, other scholars have taken precisely the opposite path. For these scholars, the ideology of a case is a function of which Justices joined the majority opinion. In a landmark article, Professors Andrew Martin and Kevin Quinn use an elegant and sophisticated methodology to assign each Justice a numeric score for each Term.144 Martin and Quinn’s model calculates the frequency with which Justices vote together, incorporating historical voting patterns as well as such information as the frequency with which a given Justice is a lone dissenter or one of two dissenters, etc.145 Based on this information, the Justices are arrayed along a single line, with new scores determined for each Term. The scores represent the Justices’ “ideal points” relative to each other, 146 and Martin and Quinn, as well as other scholars, interpret them as reflecting the ideological predilections of the Justices.147 Indeed, most observers would likely agree that the scores are consistent with where the Justices fall ideologically, at least relative to each other. For October Term (OT) 2004, for example, the last Term of the Rehnquist 7 natural court, Justice Thomas was at the far right, with a score of 4.5. Justice Stevens was at the 144. Andrew D. Martin & Kevin M. Quinn, Dynamic Ideal Point Estimation via Markov Chain Monte Carlo for the U.S. Supreme Court, 1953-1999, 10 POL. ANALYSIS 134 (2002). 145. See id. 146. Martin and Quinn claim that the scale is consistent over time and so can be used to compare Justices who never served together – like Thomas and Douglas – through the information provided by looking at the votes of the Justices who served with both. Martin & Quinn, supra note 144, at 145. See infra Part IV.A for discussion of this claim. 147. See, e.g., Lee Epstein et al., Ideological Drift Among Supreme Court Justices: Who, When, and How Important?, 101 NW. U. L. REV. 1483 (2007); Tonja Jacobi & Matthew Sag, Taking the Measure of Ideology: Empirically Measuring Supreme Court Cases, 98 GEO. L.J. 1, 3-4 (2009). 59 112 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 other extreme, with a score of -2.41. The median Justice for that Term was, unsurprisingly, Justice O’Connor, with a score of .08. The Martin-Quinn scores (which are publicly and freely available)148 are widely used for a variety of purposes. While they cannot be used as an independent variable to explain the universe of votes (because they are derived from the universe of votes), they can (arguably) be used to explain or predict votes in certain areas or on certain subjects.149 Among the advantages of the Martin-Quinn scores is that they are not binary. Instead of identifying a Justice as either liberal or conservative, the Martin-Quinn scores define a spectrum and locate Justices at various points along that spectrum. Scholars are now beginning to try to use Martin-Quinn scores to describe the ideological character of cases as well as of the Justices. In a recent article, for example, Professors Tonja Jacobi and Matthew Sag present several models of how the Martin-Quinn scores might be used to identify the ideological character of a case, taking advantage of this spectrum.150 Jacobi and Sag’s work explores a variety of theoretical models that might explain the way ideological and strategic considerations influence Justices’ voting. One possibility, which they call the Ideological Model, simply assigns every case the Martin-Quinn score of the median Justice of those who participated in the case, which, for most cases, is the median Justice on the Court for that Term.151 Yet it is obvious that not every case in a given Term has the same ideological character, and, in part for this reason, the Ideological Model is not compelling. 148. See Martin-Quinn Scores, The National Center for Empirical Research in the Law and the Institute for Quantitative Social Science, http://mqscores.wustl.edu/ (last visited on Nov. 3, 2009). 149. Andrew D. Martin & Kevin M. Quinn, Can Ideal Point Estimate Be Used as Explanatory Variables?, (Oct. 8, 2005) (unpublished working paper), available at http://mqscores.wustl.edu/media/resnote.pdf. 150. Jacobi & Sag, supra note 147, at 11-18; see also Tonja Jacobi, Competing Models of Judicial Coalition Formation and Case Outcome Determination, 1 J. LEGAL ANALYSIS 411 (2009) (laying out in detail the theoretical justifications for the models). Jacobi and Sag’s work is a particularly well-developed attempt to use the Martin-Quinn scores to identify case ideology. As such, it offers the opportunity to analyze how the strengths and weaknesses of the widely used Martin-Quinn scores affect such an effort. 151. Jacobi & Sag, supra note 147, at 15-16. This model relies on the Median Justice Theorem, which suggests that the median Justice essentially controls the outcome of all cases. See id. (citing Duncan Black, On the Rationale of Group DecisionMaking, 56 J. POL. ECON. 23 (1948), and Keith Krehbiel, Supreme Court Appointments As a Move-the-Median Game, 51 AM. J. OF POL. SCI. 231 (2007)). There are occasional cases in which one or more Justices do not participate. In such cases, the score for the median Justice may or may not be the score for the median Justice for the Court. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 113 The approach that Sag and Jacobi prefer, after assessing its descriptive power, is what they call the Strategic Model.152 In this model, the ideological nature of the case is defined as the median or, alternatively, the mean of the Martin-Quinn scores of all of the Justices in the majority.153 I will refer to the Strategic Model’s scores as Jacobi-Sag scores of case ideology, and, in the text, I will report the median score of the Justices in the majority, with the mean score identified in the footnotes.154 As an alternative to the binary, liberal-versus-conservative coding of the Database, measures (like the Jacobi-Sag approach) that rely on the MartinQuinn scores offer a number of distinct advantages. Notably, they allow for a spectrum – some cases might be more conservative (or more liberal) than others. And they do not rest on subjective assessments (unarticulated or explicit) about the most salient aspects of a case. In fact, assigning the JacobiSag score to a case requires knowing nothing at all about the case’s legal issues, case facts, or political context. Moreover, the Jacobi-Sag approach in particular can be both descriptive and informative. It arguably identifies the correct ideological direction with respect to closely decided cases in which the Court’s swing Justice sides with the liberal Justices and those in which the swing Justice sides with the conservatives. Compare, for example, the Jacobi-Sag scores for two 5-4 voting rights cases.155 In Bush v. Vera, Justice O’Connor sided with the conservative Justices to strike down the boundaries of three congressional districts on equal protection grounds.156 The Jacobi-Sag score for the case is 1.544.157 In 152. Jacobi & Sag, supra note 147, at 17-18. The theoretical framework for this model rests on the idea that Justices care both about case outcome and about the size of the majority coalition and will make strategic trade-offs between them. Id. at 1718. Jacobi and Sag also consider and reject a “Collegial Model,” which assigns each case the Martin-Quinn score of the “marginal” Justice. Id. at 16, 24, 65. In a 6-3 decision that the Database codes as conservative, for example, the case will receive the Martin-Quinn score of the most liberal Justice who joined the majority. See id. at 16. They explain the theory behind the Collegial Model but then convincingly demonstrate that it does a terrible job of describing the ideological character of decided cases. Id. at 16, 34-65. 153. Id. at 17-18. Jacobi and Sag assess whether the median or mean is a better measure and conclude that each has practical and theoretical advantages and disadvantages. Id. at 82; see also Cliff Carrubba et al., Does the Median Justice Control the Content of Supreme Court Opinions? (November 2007) (unpublished working paper), available at http://adm.wustl.edu/media/working/mjt1-5.pdf (concluding that the median Justice of the majority is a better measure of case ideology than the median Justice of the Court). 154. I figured the Jacobi-Sag scores myself based on the protocols set forth in their article. 155. Except where noted, all of the cases discussed in this Part are in my 95-case dataset. 156. 517 U.S. 952, 956-57 (1996). 157. Using the mean instead of the median, the score is 1.996. 60 114 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Easley, on the other hand, Justice O’Connor sided with the liberal block to uphold a district against a similar challenge.158 The Jacobi-Sag score is -1.518.159 The shift in these scores from the right of the Court’s median Justice (O’Connor) in Bush v. Vera to her left in Easley comports with some of what we know about the cases. Bush v. Vera has a conservative outcome, while Easley is a liberal case, as indeed they are coded in the Database. But the spectrum created by the Jacobi-Sag scores provides more information about the ideological nature of a case than does the Database. In the Database, a unanimous (or lopsided) case with a “liberal” outcome has the same ideology code as Easley, and a unanimous case with a “conservative” outcome has the same ideology code as Bush v. Vera. Yet such a unanimous case would have the Jacobi-Sag score of the median Justice on the Court. Jacobi and Sag’s use of the Martin-Quinn scores, on the other hand, allows us to distinguish meaningfully between the ideological character of cases in which the outcome closely divided the Court (like the voting rights cases) and those in which the outcome was relatively centrist, an improvement over binary, liberal-versus-conservative codes. Moreover, the Jacobi-Sag scores might help us identify when and how ideological predilections change, again without reference to subjective assessments. Specifically, the scores might demonstrate how the meaning of “conservative” and “liberal” can change over time. Take, for example, Republican Party of Minnesota v. White, a 5-4 decision striking down, on First Amendment grounds, state law restrictions on judicial candidates’ speech.160 White is coded in the Database as a liberal First Amendment decision. But because the four most liberal Justices dissented in White, the Jacobi-Sag score is comparable to the score in Bush v. Vera, the conservative voting rights case. That information can serve as a signal that, at least sometimes, what has traditionally been considered liberal (or conservative) with respect to the First Amendment may have changed or that issues other than the First Amendment have become more salient to at least some of the Justices.161 There are several specific problems with the Jacobi-Sag scores, however. First, Jacobi and Sag’s use of the Martin-Quinn scores may sometimes substantially overstate the difference between the ideological positions of cases. The focus on the median Justice in the majority may, in some kinds of cases, shift the focus away from the Justices whose votes were actually contested and therefore whose ideology is most likely to be reflected in the case. For example, in Bush v. Vera and Easley, the voting rights cases discussed earlier, the shift in one vote – Justice O’Connor’s decision to side with the liberals or the conservatives – caused a dramatic change in the Jacobi-Sag 158. 532 U.S. 234, 236-37 (2001). 159. Using the mean instead of the median, the score is -1.27. 160. Republican Party of Minn. v. White, 536 U.S. 765, 766, 788 (2002) (coded as liberal in the Database). White is not in my dataset. 161. Cf. Epstein & Segal, supra note 63, at 91. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 115 score for those cases (1.544 for the conservatively decided Bush v. Vera and -1.518 for the liberal decision in Easley). While the Jacobi-Sag measure accurately identifies the ideological direction of each case, it seems unlikely that Justice O’Connor perceived either case as being anywhere close to that ideological extreme. As in the Michigan affirmative action cases, where Justice O’Connor alone voted to uphold the law school’s affirmative action admissions program but voted to strike down the program used for undergraduate admissions,162 it is likely that she understood both cases to be close cases in which the specific facts made all the difference. Sag and Jacobi’s singular focus on the median Justice in the majority in these cases, then, obscures important information about the ideological character of the cases and may overstate the ideological distance between them.163 This criticism, put more theoretically, suggests that Jacobi and Sag’s Ideological Model may be a more accurate approach to identifying the ideological position of some kinds of cases than is their Strategic Model. The remaining three problems I will discuss all arise from Sag and Jacobi’s reliance on the Martin-Quinn scores. The first problem is that the scores provide an extraordinary degree of apparent precision – several digits beyond the decimal point. This precision arises from the sophisticated (and, for most legal scholars, incomprehensible) methodology Martin and Quinn use. Moreover, the Martin-Quinn scores are estimates, and they have their own confidence intervals around them – ranges within which Martin and Quinn calculate the actual ideal points are overwhelmingly likely to fall. The apparent precision of the scores, then, is an artifact of statistical techniques and reporting conventions. This precision, however, is not necessarily qualitatively meaningful. That is, knowing nothing else about the cases, is it meaningful to say that a case (or a Justice) with a score of 1.518 is more conservative than one with a score of 1.516? And, if not, why make the distinction? The approaches do not tell us at what point the distance between scores becomes important or useful information. While this concern may not matter when the Martin-Quinn or Jacobi-Sag scores are used for large-N empirical studies,164 it becomes more problematic, as I will explain below, if we assume that the scores are telling us something substantive about the ideological nature of particular cases relative to each other. A second problem with the Martin-Quinn scores is that while they improve on the binary, liberal-versus-conservative coding of the Database in some respects, they nonetheless assume unidimensionality.165 More concrete162. Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 244 (2003) (striking down undergraduate admissions program); Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306 (2003) (upholding law school’s admissions program). 163. I am indebted to David Klein for this insight. 164. “N” refers to the number of observations in a study. “Large-N” means that there are many observations. 165. Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 32 (noting that unidimensional ideology coding may create “distortions” that we cannot identify). 61 116 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 ly, the Martin-Quinn scores do not allow us to take into account the possibility that the Justices’ actual ideal points on the spectrum may vary relative to each other depending on the legal issues, facts, or context of the cases. One consequence of this unidimensionality is that, while Martin-Quinn scores for each Justice vary from Term to Term, it is impossible to tell what those changes mean other than that Justices vote with each other at somewhat different rates from Term to Term. In other words, the Martin-Quinn scores reflect observed voting behavior. Ascribing that behavior solely to ideological ideal points requires a significant inferential leap, but that leap is necessary if we interpret changes in Martin-Quinn scores as changes in the Justices’ ideology.166 These criticisms of the Martin-Quinn scores lead to a criticism of the Jacobi-Sag approach. Changes in the Martin-Quinn scores of the Justices from Term to Term lead to changes in the Jacobi-Sag scores for particular cases – changes that may not in fact be at all meaningful in understanding the relative ideological nature of those cases. A third and related problem with Martin-Quinn scores – and hence with the Jacobi-Sag approach – I mention with some hesitancy, as its existence and significance is disputed in the literature.167 Nonetheless, it is potentially serious. It is the dual problem of selection effects and changes in the nature of law over time. The Court, of course, has control over most of its docket, and it may well choose to hear different mixes of cases in different Terms. As a result, if the Justices’ ideal points vary with different types of cases, we might see different voting coalitions depending on the mix of cases being heard each Term, thereby causing the Justices’ Martin-Quinn scores to shift regardless of whether their ideological views have changed.168 166. This problem is sometimes called the problem of observational or behavioral equivalence. See Fischman & Law, supra note 11. See also Ward Farnsworth, The Uses and Limits of Martin-Quinn Scores to Assess Supreme Court Justices, With Special Attention to the Problem of Ideological Drift, 101 NW. L. REV. 1891 (2007) (explaining that the agreement and disagreement reflected in the Martin-Quinn scores might have nothing to do with political ideology but might instead demonstrate agreement or disagreement about law or legal reasoning). 167. See infra note 168. 168. Whether such shifts are artifacts of the mix of cases being heard or accurately reflect changes in the Justices’ actual ideal points is disputed. Compare Epstein et al., supra note 147, at 1503-04 (claiming that the Martin-Quinn scale is consistent over time and that the scores can therefore measure whether Justices’ ideal points shift or “drift”), and Jacobi & Sag, supra note 147, at 2-3 (suggesting that reliance on the Martin-Quinn scores produces “a valid and reliable mechanism of . . . comparing cases via a consistent, objective standard”) (emphasis added), with Michael A. Bailey, Comparable Preference Estimates Across Time and Institutions for the Court, Congress, and Presidency, 51 AM. J. POL. SCI. 433 (2007), Fischman & Law, supra note 11, at 153-55 (asserting that selection effects prevent the Martin-Quinn scale from accurately assessing drift), and Farnsworth, supra note 166 (same). I find very powerful the intuition behind the claim that the scores may be affected by selection effects. I am not in a position, however, to resolve the question here. On selection 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 117 Moreover, changes in voting coalitions could be affected by developments in the law. Imagine a group of Justices who constitute a majority on the Court and who consistently vote in favor of criminal defendants, expanding defendants’ constitutional rights and reading criminal and sentencing statutes as leniently as possible. Suppose that, over time, due in part to this group of Justices, criminal law in the United States shifts. Eventually, presumably, the law overall might coincide with these Justices’ ideal point(s). In fact, the law, as developed in the lower courts (or by Congress), could even trend beyond those ideal points. Then, these same Justices might begin to vote against criminal defendants in some cases. If this shift were to occur, some of our group of Justices might now find themselves voting with their colleagues who used to dissent. Because the Martin-Quinn scores arise from actual voting coalitions, the scores of our Justices would then shift in the direction of their formerly dissenting colleagues (and vice versa) – even though their actual, internal ideal points have not shifted. To understand how these concerns might affect the usefulness of the Jacobi-Sag scores in identifying case ideology, I returned to my sample of cases and identified sets of cases that dealt with similar subject matter. I conclude that the Jacobi-Sag scores may, at least sometimes, be missing the forest for the trees by, like the Database, emphasizing ideology at the expense of other significant factors in the Justices’ decisionmaking. Compare, for example, Jerome B. Grubart, Inc. v. Chicago169 and Yamaha Motor Corp. v. Calhoun.170 Both cases involve maritime law and remedies, and both were decided unanimously, although in Grubart neither Justice Stevens nor Justice Breyer took part in the decision and Justices Thomas and Scalia concurred only in the judgment.171 In Grubart, the Court held that there was federal maritime jurisdiction over tort actions against the barge company that allegedly negligently caused the Chicago flood.172 As a result of the case being litigated under federal maritime law instead of state tort law, the barge company’s liability was limited to the value of the barges and tug involved, orders of magnitude less than the actual damages suffered as a result of the flood.173 effects more generally, see Jonathan P. Kastellec & Jeffrey R. Lax, Case Selection and the Study of Judicial Politics, 5 J. EMPIRICAL LEGAL STUD. 407 (2008). Others have attempted to assess drift more directly. Professor Michael Bailey has developed measures of changes in the Court’s and the Justices’ ideology over time by analyzing what he calls “bridge observations” – cases presenting the same issue but decided at different times. Bailey, supra. 169. 513 U.S. 527 (1995). 170. 516 U.S. 199 (1996). 171. They disagreed with the test that the Court used to determine whether maritime jurisdiction applied but agreed with the result. 172. Grubart, 513 U.S. at 529. 173. Id. at 530-31. 62 118 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Yamaha was a wrongful death action brought by the parents of a girl who was killed in an accident involving a jet ski.174 The issue in the case was whether, despite uncontested maritime jurisdiction, state law remedies were available because the victim was a nonseaman.175 As in Grubart, the answer to this apparently technical question was of great substantive importance: if only maritime remedies applied, there was a possibility (albeit disputed) that the plaintiffs could recover only funeral expenses.176 The Court held, 9-0 with no separate opinions, that state law remedies were not displaced and that the plaintiffs, if successful, could recover the full range of state remedies, such as damages for loss of society, support and services, and future earnings, as well as punitive damages.177 So, is one of these opinions more conservative or more liberal than the other? One might think that the answer is clearly yes – Yamaha is significantly more liberal than Grubart because it allows for broad tort liability, while Grubart does not.178 Yet Grubart’s Jacobi-Sag score is only slightly to the right of Yamaha’s (.691 versus .577).179 Here, then, the apparent precision of the scores does not reveal anything useful about the substantive differences between the cases. In fact, the difference in the scores is largely a function of the recusal of two Justices in Grubart and the slight changes in each Justice’s Martin-Quinn scores with each Term. 174. Yamaha, 516 U.S. at 201-02. 175. Id. at 205. 176. Id. at 203. 177. Id. at 202, 216. The Court left open the question of which state law would govern. Id. at 216 n.14. The plaintiffs were residents of Pennsylvania, but the accident took place in Puerto Rico. Id. at 202-03 & n.1. 178. The Database codes Yamaha as a liberal economic activity decision and Grubart as a liberal judicial power decision, presumably because it finds federal jurisdiction. See infra note 179 for a discussion of why that coding of Grubart is meaningless. In the Recoding Project, both cases received mixed ideology codes. 179. Calculating the Jacobi-Sag score for Grubart is somewhat complicated and presents its own set of problems. Normally, the Jacobi-Sag median score for a unanimous case is simply set at the score of the median Justice of the Court. Because Stevens and Breyer did not participate, however, the median Justice on the Grubart Court is one spot to the right of the median Justice for that Term and so moves from O’Connor (.666) to Kennedy (.691) for OT 1994. On the other hand, if Thomas and Scalia are excluded from the majority since they concurred only in the judgment, the Grubart Court’s median Justice shifts back to Justice O’Connor. Another difficulty with scoring Grubart is that using the mean Martin-Quinn score causes wild fluctuations depending on whether we include Thomas and Scalia. It also is shifted substantially to the right given the lack of participation of Stevens and Breyer. If Thomas and Scalia are included, the Jacobi-Sag score is 1.169, significantly to the right of Yamaha and perhaps, in this case, the most descriptively accurate score. But if they are excluded, the score is .389 – which is actually to Yamaha’s left. Such large fluctuation in the scores is a reason to use the median rather than the mean. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 119 More significantly, the comparison of the cases calls into question the extent to which either or both cases were decided on the basis of ideology at all. Issued not even a year apart, their holdings are – if understood ideologically – difficult to reconcile, particularly as both were decided unanimously with Jacobi-Sag scores that are quite close to each other. There must be other dimensions to these cases that are captured neither by Sag and Jacobi’s ingenious but unidimensional approach nor by the Database’s ideology coding. Another pair of unanimous cases likewise raises questions about how meaningful movement along the spectrum might be and highlights again the problem of unidimensionality. In Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., the Court unanimously struck down a federal statute prohibiting beer labels from displaying alcohol content as violating the First Amendment.180 Rubin’s JacobiSag score is .666.181 In contrast, in Illinois ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Ass’n, the Court, again unanimously, rejected a First Amendment challenge to a fraud claim brought by the State of Illinois against professional fundraisers.182 The suit alleged that the fundraisers had defrauded donors “by falsely representing that ‘a significant amount of each dollar donated would be paid over to’” the charity for which they were soliciting donations, when in fact the fundraisers retained 85% of all the money they raised.183 Madigan’s Jacobi-Sag score is .227,184 suggesting that it should be considered more liberal than Rubin. Perhaps so. If understood as economic activity cases, Rubin would be seen as conservative (anti-regulation, pro-business), and Madigan would be seen as liberal. Of course the opposite is true if they are seen as First Amendment cases.185 But the only reason for the difference in their scores here is that the cases were decided in different Terms. The median Justice – O’Connor – is the same in both cases; the difference in the JacobiSag score is due to the difference in her Martin-Quinn score between OT 1994 and OT 2002. It is hard to see how this difference tells us anything meaningful about the relative ideological character of these two unanimous cases. A third First Amendment case makes the point even more starkly. In Buckley v. American Constitutional Law Foundation, Inc., the Court struck down a series of regulations that Colorado had imposed on circulators of petitions for popular initiatives.186 Colorado required that the petition circulators themselves be registered voters, that each circulator wear a badge with his or 180. 514 U.S. 476, 478 (1995). 181. Using the mean, it is .531. 182. 538 U.S. 600, 605-06 (2003). 183. Id. at 605. 184. Using the mean, it is .255. 185. The Database codes both as First Amendment cases, with the accompanying ideology codes. In other words, the Database codes the relative ideology of these cases as the opposite of the Jacobi-Sag scores. Recoded, both receive mixed ideology codes. 186. 525 U.S. 182, 186-87 (1999). 63 120 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 her name on it, and that the proponents of an initiative report the names and addresses of paid circulators and the amount paid to them.187 The Court struck down all of these requirements as violating the First Amendment.188 As to the identification badge, the vote was 8-1, with only Chief Justice Rehnquist in dissent.189 As to the other requirements, Justices O’Connor and Breyer also dissented.190 A mixed vote like this one might make assigning a Jacobi-Sag score a bit messy, but because of the way the votes are distributed, the median Justice of the majority – and therefore the Jacobi-Sag score – is the same for both the full majority (8-1) and the partial majority (6-3).191 It is -0.75. But what does it mean that the scores for both parts of the case are the same? 192 Certainly, Justices Breyer and O’Connor saw important differences in the balance of interests as between the different regulations – although they may well not have seen those differences in ideological terms. Moreover, in this case, the Justices at the far ends of the Martin-Quinn spectrum agreed with each other – Justices Thomas, Scalia, Stevens, and Ginsburg all were in the majority.193 The distribution of votes in this case suggests that an attempt to explain the case along a single dimension obscures relevant information about what led the Justices to their decisions. B. A Refinement: Identifying When There Are More Dimensions The Martin-Quinn scores are unique among attempts to measure ideology in that they are dynamic. That dynamic nature is their strength – they derive from the actual behavior of the actual Justices – but it can, as described above, create weaknesses. On the other hand, that dynamism can perhaps be exploited for even more information about the Justices’ voting behavior. Recent work identifying and measuring “disordered voting” does just that. 187. Id. at 188-89. 188. Id. at 186-87. 189. See generally id. 190. See generally id. 191. For both, the score is the mean of the OT 1998 Martin-Quinn scores of Justice Souter (-0.899) and Justice Kennedy (0.75). 192. Using the mean of the majorities here, which does cause a shift, does not seem particularly illuminating. For the 8-1 part of the decision, the mean is .284, while, for the 6-3 part, it is .424. So the decision to strike down the registered voter and ID badge provisions is scored as more liberal than the decision to strike down the disclosure requirements. Nothing in the content of the case compels or justifies this result. See generally Buckley, 525 U.S. 182. 193. Justice Thomas did not actually join the majority opinion. See generally id. at 206-15 (Thomas, J., concurring in the judgment). He concurred in the judgment, arguing for a stricter test of constitutionality than the majority used. Id. at 206 (advocating for use of strict scrutiny). 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 121 In their 2008 article, Professors Paul Edelman, David Klein, and Stefanie Lindquist (“EKL”) capitalize on the Martin-Quinn scores to explore the phenomenon of unexpected voting coalitions, or what they call “disordered voting.”194 They define a case as disordered when the Justices’ votes are not consistent with their relative positions on the Martin-Quinn spectrum.195 Buckley, with Justices Breyer, O’Connor, and Rehnquist in dissent,196 is disordered. So is, for example, a 7-2 decision where the dissenters are Justices Thomas and Stevens197 or Justices Breyer and Rehnquist198 because there are other Justices whose ideal points fall between the two dissenters in each of those cases. In contrast, a 7-2 decision with Justices Scalia and Thomas in dissent is ordered because Scalia’s and Thomas’s ideal points are next to each other at one extreme of the spectrum. EKL’s formula not only identifies when such voting occurs but also measures the extent of a majority coalition’s disorder.199 So, if Justice O’Connor is the median Justice, a 5-4 decision with Justice O’Connor in the majority along with Justices Breyer, Ginsburg, Souter, and Stevens is an ordered case, with a disorder score of 0. The same is true for a 5-4 decision with Justice O’Connor in the majority along with Justices Scalia, Thomas, Kennedy, and Rehnquist. A 5-4 liberal majority, however, where Justice Kennedy (who is the next most conservative Justice after O’Connor) votes with the liberals and O’Connor votes with the conservatives, is disordered – but only modestly so, as only Kennedy and O’Connor have switched places. It will have a fairly low disorder score. In contrast, a 5-4 decision with a majority of Scalia, Rehnquist, O’Connor, Souter, and Stevens is much more disordered and will have a much higher disorder score. 194. Paul H. Edelman, David Klein & Stefanie A. Lindquist, Measuring Deviations from Expected Voting Patterns on Collegial Courts, 5 J. EMPIRICAL LEG. STUD. 819 (2008). 195. Id. at 829. The authors calculate the Justices’ ideal points by natural court, not by Term. Id. at 829-30. For the Rehnquist 7 court, the order of Justices, from lowest ideal point (generally interpreted as most liberal) to highest ideal point (interpreted as most conservative), is Stevens, Ginsburg, Souter, Breyer, O’Connor, Kennedy, Rehnquist, Scalia, Thomas. Id. at 830 tbl.1. So a case in which Stevens, Ginsburg, and Breyer dissent, but Souter does not, will count as disordered because Souter has a lower ideal point than does Breyer. Likewise, a case in which Kennedy sides with the liberal bloc in a 5-4 vote, with O’Connor in dissent, will count as disordered. For some Terms, of course, Souter’s ideal point is higher than Breyer’s, and O’Connor’s is higher than Kennedy’s. Whether such cases should really be considered disordered is debatable. They do, however, have quite low disorder scores. See infra for a discussion of the relative magnitude of disorder scores. 196. See Buckley v. Am. Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 525 U.S. 182 (1999). 197. See, e.g., Comm’r v. Lundy, 516 U.S. 235 (1996). 198. See, e.g., Lords Landing Village of Condo. Council of Unit Owners v. Cont’l Ins. Co., 520 U.S. 893 (1997). 199. Edelman, Klein & Lindquist, supra note 194, at 825-27. 64 122 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 EKL computed disorder scores for every nonunanimous orally argued case decided by each natural court that lasted at least three terms.200 For Rehnquist 7, the natural court on which I focus, the scores ranged from 0 (perfectly ordered) to a high of 1.356.201 Specifically, EKL found that 55.56% of nonunanimous cases were ordered but that 61.52% of civil liberties cases (broadly defined) were ordered.202 EKL suggest that civil liberties cases may have a lower rate of disorder than other cases “perhaps [because the] Justices feel more strongly about civil liberties issues and are less able to put aside ideology in deciding them . . . .”203 Even in civil liberties cases, however, nearly 40% of the nonunanimous cases were disordered.204 One important benefit of EKL’s approach is that it accepts the possibility of multidimensional preferences or factors in judicial decisionmaking and begins to offer a way to identify when and how those preferences manifest themselves. If the Justices do not simply vote liberal or conservative, or move from left to right on a single line, their votes may vary with the case’s subject matter, the law, or case facts, and these changes in voting behavior may be reflected in the disorder scores. In this respect, EKL’s approach has the potential to add a richness to our understanding of judicial decisionmaking that was not previously available.205 Specifically, the disorder scores reveal some significant differences between cases that, under other approaches, are identified as having the same ideological character. Cases with the same median Justice in the majority but different voting coalitions would receive the same Jacobi-Sag score, yet they can be distinguished by disorder score. Likewise, the disorder scores can add nuance to our understanding of the ideological valence of cases identified as simply liberal or conservative in the Supreme Court Database. The disorder scores have their limitations, of course. EKL are conservative in their methodology and therefore likely to fail to identify all the cases that are indeed multidimensional. By starting with the Martin-Quinn scores, for example, EKL seem to accept the notion that, for most cases, there is a single dimension that explains the Justices’ actions, and they likewise seem to operate on the assumption that this dimension is ideology.206 But if the Justices are operating along many dimensions and are regularly weighing com- 200. Id. at 830. Unanimous cases are omitted because there can be no disorder (or order) when all of the Justices vote the same way. Id. 201. Id. at 831. My dataset contained the same range. 202. Id. at 830. 203. Id. at 843. 204. Id. at 830. 205. It is worth noting that the same logic might apply to unanimous cases as well as to any case in which typical voting partners are separated, even when the case is ordered. 206. See id. at 843. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 123 peting interests, there may in fact be more “disorder” than EKL account for.207 Nonetheless, EKL’s disorder scores may give us a window into the question of what kinds of issues, facts, or contexts are more salient to some Justices than to others. As EKL hypothesize, “We feel justified in concluding that . . . unexpected voting patterns are frequently caused by other considerations outweighing ideology in the thinking of at least some Justices.”208 So what might those other considerations be? By way of example, I focus here on Justice Breyer and his well-known pragmatism.209 I theorized that Breyer is more likely to be “out of place” (leading to a “disordered” case) when he is voting to defer to the judgments of an agency or other entity that is either expert or closer to the facts on the ground, when he is concerned about the administrability of a particular holding, or when he wants to allow government actors room to experiment. In fact, a review of the six cases in my dataset in which Justice Breyer is out of place reveals that five of them meet this description. In other words, one of the “other considerations,” as EKL put it, or one additional dimension might, for Justice Breyer, be his pragmatism.210 In Schenck, for example, Justice Breyer was the only Justice who voted to uphold the district court’s entire injunction.211 All of the other Justices voted to strike down the portion of the injunction that they construed to pro207. The term “disorder” itself implies a deviation from the normal unidimensional order. 208. Edelman, Klein & Lindquist, supra note 194, at 843. EKL do not find that multiple issue coding in the Database is more likely to lead to disordered voting. Id. at 843. They express surprise at this result because multidimensionality is the attitudinalist’s explanation for surprising votes – the Justices simply have different preferences along different dimensions. Id. Of course, the Database systematically omits an enormous amount of information about the legal issues in the cases, so reliance on its multiple issue coding to identify multidimensionality is problematic. Shapiro, supra note 47, at 503-04, 515-16. 209. Justice Breyer is explicitly and deliberately concerned about the real-world consequences of the Court’s decisions. See STEPHEN BREYER, ACTIVE LIBERTY: INTERPRETING OUR DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION 115-32 (2005). His pragmatism has not escaped the notice of commentators. A search in Westlaw’s JLR database for Breyer /s pragmati! produced 264 results (search conducted on January 1, 2010). See, e.g, Paul Gewirtz, The Pragmatic Passion of Justice Breyer, 115 YALE L. J. 1675 (2006); Cass Sunstein, Justice Breyer’s Democratic Pragmatism, 115 YALE L.J. 1719 (2006); Michael J. Zimmer, A Pro-Employee Supreme Court?: The Retaliation Decisions, 60 S.C. L. REV. 917, 924 (2009) (noting that “Justice Breyer advocates a method of statutory interpretation aimed at determining the purpose of the legislation, which is fundamentally a pragmatic approach”). 210. At other times in the country’s history, Breyer’s willingness to defer to administrative agencies and other government entities might have itself been a hotbutton issue seen in more ideological terms. 211. See Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W. N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997). 65 124 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 hibit abortion protesters to approach within fifteen feet of people entering and leaving the clinic.212 Justice Breyer, on the other hand, argued not only that the injunction did not have to be so construed but also that it should be “left [] to the District Court to resolve in the first instance any linguistic ambiguity that might create a constitutional problem.”213 He explained, The District Court understands the history, and thus the meaning, of the language in context better than do we. If the petitioners [abortion protesters] show a need for interpretation or modification of the language, the District Court, which is directly familiar with the facts underlying the injunction, can respond quickly and flexibly.214 Similar concerns arise in other cases in which he is out of place, even when he did not write the opinion himself. In Buckley, for example, Justice Breyer joined Justice O’Connor’s partial dissent.215 Both Justices would have upheld Colorado’s requirement that petition circulators be registered voters against a First Amendment challenge, in part for a very practical reason: In the past, Colorado has had difficulty enforcing its prohibition on circulation fraud, in particular its law against forging petition signatures, because violators fled the State . . . . Colorado has shown that the registration requirement is an easy and a verifiable way to 212. See id. 213. Id. at 399 (Breyer, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). 214. Id. (emphasis added); see also Nat’l Park Hospitality Ass’n v. Dep’t of the Interior, 538 U.S. 803, 817-21 (2003) (Breyer, J., dissenting) (disagreeing with the Court’s holding that plaintiffs, who wished to challenge the validity of a regulation, did not have standing and indicating that he would uphold regulation; joined by the only other dissenter, Justice O’Connor); Almendarez-Torres v. United States, 523 U.S. 224 (1998) (holding in majority opinion that statute authorizing additional prison time for certain illegal immigrants was a sentence enhancement and not a separate offense, so no mention in indictment was required; joined in majority by Justices Thomas, Kennedy, O’Connor, and the Chief Justice). But see Verizon Commc’ns, Inc. v. F.C.C., 535 U.S. 467, 539 (2002) (Breyer, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (arguing that challenged regulations were not authorized by the relevant statute; joined in part by Justice Scalia). Outside of my dataset, there are many other examples of disordered cases in which Justice Breyer is out of place that are consistent with my theory that he is motivated in part by administrative pragmatism. See, e.g., Clinton v. New York, 524 U.S. 417 (1998) (voting, in dissent and joined by Justices Scalia and O’Connor, to uphold line-item veto); Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v. Acton, 515 U.S. 646 (1995) (joining majority of Justices Scalia, Thomas, Kennedy, and the Chief Justice to hold that schools can constitutionally require athletes to submit to random drug tests). 215. See Buckley v. Am. Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 525 U.S. 182 (1999). 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 125 ensure that petition circulators fall under the State’s subpoena power.216 Likewise, in Lords Landing, Justice Breyer joined the Chief Justice’s dissent from a per curiam order to grant, vacate, and remand (GVR).217 The Court sent the case back to the Fourth Circuit for consideration of a recently decided state supreme court case, even though that case had already been presented to the Fourth Circuit on a motion to recall the mandate.218 The dissent argued not that the Fourth Circuit had reached the right result in the first place but rather that the GVR mechanism was inappropriate and confusing. The Court, the dissent said, should either set the case for argument or summarily reverse. True, this would require the investment of still more time and effort in a case that is in the federal courts only reason of diversity of citizenship . . . but it would have the virtue of explicitly telling the Court of Appeals how to dispose of the case. The Court’s decision to grant, vacate, and remand . . . on the contrary, is muddled and cryptic. Surely the judges of the Court of Appeals are, in fairness, entitled to some clearer guidance from this Court than what they are now given.219 A theory of judging that focuses only on a single dimension of ideology might conclude that Justice Breyer’s views on abortion are more liberal than any of his colleagues or that his views of the First Amendment are more conservative. But this is only one possible explanation for his votes, and it is not the most likely one. Instead, by looking at his opinions (or the opinions he joins) in the cases in which he is out of place, we can identify themes that may, at least in some cases, be more salient to him than ideological considerations220 or whatever other considerations that normally align him with particular members of the Court. The disorder scores offer a way to capital216. Id. at 220 (O’Connor, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part, joined by Breyer, J.). 217. See Lords Landing Village of Condo. Council of Unit Owners v. Cont’l Ins. Co., 520 U.S. 893 (1997). 218. See id. at 894. Normally, the Supreme Court does not GVR in light of a new legal development when the lower court has already had an opportunity to consider it. ROBERT L. STERN, EUGENE GRESSMAN, STEPHEN M. SHAPIRO, KENNETH S. GELLER, SUPREME COURT PRACTICE 318 (8th ed. 2002). 219. Lords Landing, 520 U.S. at 898 (Rehnquist, C.J., dissenting, joined by Breyer, J.) (emphasis added). 220. In some cases, of course, his ideological preferences may point in the same direction as his desire to defer to the expert or more knowledgeable government entity. See, e.g., Parents Involved in Cmty. Schs. v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 551 U.S. 701, 803 (2007) (Breyer, J., dissenting). 66 126 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 ize on the dynamic nature of the Martin-Quinn scores, one that holds the potential to begin studying the multidimensional nature of judicial decisionmaking. V. IDEOLOGICAL SALIENCE AND IDEOLOGICAL LEGITIMACY: A WAY FORWARD? A. Defining Terms Although this Article critiques many empirical scholars’ attempts to identify the ideological character of Supreme Court opinions, I do not wish to deny the significant role of ideology in judging, particularly in Supreme Court judging. To the contrary, ideology (or, to use a gentler term, policy or political judgments) inevitably plays a role in much of the Supreme Court’s work. The Supreme Court often addresses difficult and contested political questions – questions to which there is simply no objectively correct answer. Instead, there are judgments to be made. The question of whether a sitting President has immunity from suit is one such question.221 Whether or when the Constitution permits public displays of the Ten Commandments is another.222 That these cases involve political judgments does not mean that legal arguments and sources are irrelevant, of course, but it does mean both that the law in such cases is indeterminate and that the indeterminacy must be resolved by largely political judgments.223 Such political resolutions are not intrinsically illegitimate, notwithstanding Chief Justice Roberts’s and Justice Sotomayor’s claims about neutrality.224 In some cases, the Justices would not be doing their jobs if they did not make political judgments. In other words, in some cases, judging based on ideology is legitimate.225 Parents Involved, the recent case adjudicating a 221. See Clinton v. Jones, 520 U.S. 681 (1997). 222. See Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677 (2005); McCreary County, Ky. v. ACLU of Ky., 545 U.S. 844 (2005). 223. Some readers might complain that I have fallen into the trap of distinguishing between ideology on the one hand and law on the other, as if they are analytically distinct. See, e.g., BAUM, supra note 12, at 10; Stephen B. Burbank, On the Study of Judicial Behaviors: Of Law, Politics, Science and Humility, at 20, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1393362, Posner, supra note 10, at 43. These complaints are both true and inevitable. In fact, however, my goal here – consistent with these authors – is to acknowledge that ideology, especially on the Supreme Court, is a factor in the Justices’ decisions, while rejecting attempts to describe Supreme Court cases only in ideological terms. 224. See Nomination of Judge John G. Roberts, Jr., supra note 1; Nomination of Judge Sonia Sotomayor, supra note 2; see also discussion supra, Part I. 225. Some might contest this assertion, claiming, for example, that originalism and textualism can provide objective and non-ideological answers. See, e.g., Michael W. McConnell, Active Liberty: A Progressive Alternative to Textualism and Original- 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 127 challenge to the Louisville and Seattle schools’ voluntary desegregation efforts is a good example.226 Although there were legal arguments to be made, the key textual sources – both Brown v. Board of Education and the Constitution itself – failed to explicitly dictate a result.227 Ultimately, therefore, the outcome was determined by the Justices’ political judgments, informed by their value-laden understanding of the meaning of Brown.228 The case could not have been decided in the absence of these judgments. ism, 119 HARV. L. REV. 2387, 2415 (2006) (reviewing STEPHEN G. BREYER, ACTIVE LIBERTY (2005)) (arguing that textualism-originalism “is not an ideological position, but one that safeguards the distinction between law and politics” and that “in principle the textualist-originalist approach supplies an objective basis for judgment that does not merely reflect the judge’s own ideological stance”). Such an approach, however, suffers from the same hidden subjectivity as does the Supreme Court Database’s coding systems. Value judgments must still be made, but they will be masked by a veneer of neutrality. See STEPHEN BREYER, ACTIVE LIBERTY: INTERPRETING OUR DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION (2005); Thomas B. Colby & Peter J. Smith, Living Originalism, 59 DUKE L.J. 239 (2009). 226. Parents Involved in Cmty. Schs. v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 551 U.S. 701, 803 (2007). 227. See Christopher W. Schmidt, Brown and the Colorblind Constitution, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 203 (2008). 228. Chief Justice Roberts’s plurality opinion attempted to present its conclusion that race-based decisionmaking by school districts is virtually always unconstitutional as if it were required by value-neutral legal reasoning and reliance on Brown. This aspect of the opinion has been widely criticized, for example, as “disingenuous,” Joel K. Goldstein, Not Hearing History: A Critique of Chief Justice Roberts’s Reinterpretation of Brown, 691 OHIO ST. L.J. 791, 793 (2008), for “pretend[ing] . . . that invalidation of the . . . programs was compelled by . . . Brown,” POSNER, supra note 10, at 313, and for failing to discuss the factual context of Brown, “an omission [that] is historically and intellectually misleading, if not dishonest.” Vikram David Amar, The Supreme Court’s Problematic Use of Precedent Over the Past Term: Why Overruling or Refashioning May, In Some Cases, Be Better than Selective Interpretation, FindLaw, July 20, 2007, http:// writ.news.findlaw.com/amar/20070720.html. Such criticism of the opinion was not limited to those who disagreed with its conclusions. In a Harvard Law Review article, Fourth Circuit Judge J. Harvie Wilkinson, in full agreement with Chief Justice Roberts’s plurality opinion, expresses a wish that the opinion had engaged in a discussion of Brown’s meaning in historical context. J. Harvie Wilkinson III, The Seattle and Louisville Cases: There Is No Other Way, 121 HARV. L. REV. 158 (2007). He concludes, The whole sad saga of the early African American experience teaches that racial decisions by the state remain unique in their capacity to demean. To squeeze human beings of varying talents, interests, and backgrounds into an undifferentiated category of race is to submerge what should matter most about us under what should matter least. To seize upon this one proven odious criterion of judgment as the basis for preferment of some and disfavor for others, and as a potential determinant of the destiny of all, is to commit this country to the perpetuation of means employed in the 67 128 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 Arguing for the legitimacy of ideological or political considerations in judging in certain types of cases does not mean that one must accept any result in such a case as right.229 What it does mean, however, is that the most powerful arguments about the case must explicitly incorporate policy and political judgments. One can argue, for example, as Judge Posner does, that Parents Involved was wrongly decided because it prevents school districts from experimenting with the “vexing issue of race”230 or, as Justice Breyer did, that the school districts had compelling interests in considering race in school assignments, including the need to “help create citizens better prepared to know, to understand, and to work with people of all races and backgrounds . . . .”231 One can argue, as Justice Kennedy did, that we must take account of race now in order to keep it from mattering later but that the specific race-based school assignments at issue were not justified.232 Or one can argue for the colorblind Constitution, as Justice Thomas did, pointing out that “if our history has taught us anything, it has taught us to beware of elites bearing racial theories.”233 No one person can agree with all of these arguments, but we can agree that they are the kinds of arguments that are appropriate for the Justices to make in a case like Parents Involved.234 But not every case is like Parents Involved. Even in the Supreme Court, there are many cases that do not appear to have been considered by the Justices primarily in ideological terms. So this discussion returns us to the normative questions raised in this Article’s introduction: when is it legitimate for the Justices to make decisions motivated in whole or in part by ideology, and do we think that they strike the right balance between ideology and other considerations? A focus on these questions suggests that, rather than trying to identify a decision’s liberalness or conservativeness, empirical scholars might instead focus on the relative importance or salience of ideology – to the Justices themselves – in different cases.235 In so doing, empirical scholars darkest hours of its history. From this, the Fourteenth Amendment was supposed to be the instrument of deliverance. Id. at 163-64. 229. Like many other commentators, I strongly reject the plurality opinion and agree with Justice Breyer’s dissent. But a discussion of the merits of the case is beyond the scope of this Article. 230. POSNER, supra note 10, at 313. 231. Parents Involved, 551 U.S. at 843 (Breyer, J., dissenting). 232. Id. at 782-98 (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment). 233. Id. at 780-81 (Thomas, J., concurring). 234. See supra note 228 for a discussion of Judge Wilkinson’s political argument in support of the Parents Involved plurality opinion. 235. Cf. Stephen B. Burbank, On the Study of Judicial Behaviors: Of Law, Politics, Science and Humility, at 13, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract= 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 129 can move beyond the basic assumption that ideology is almost always the dominant factor in judicial decisionmaking or that it is the most important aspect of a case. Analyzing the role of ideology in such a nuanced and functional way would begin to acknowledge the complexity of judicial decisionmaking in ways that legal scholars have long called for.236 B. Is Measuring Ideological Salience Possible? However valuable the concept of ideological salience might be, it is not likely to be embraced by empirical scholars unless there are relatively objective ways to identify and measure it. In this subpart, I explore some of the factors that may help scholars do just that. The specifics here are more conceptual than functional, and I do not offer a measure that other scholars can begin to use. Nonetheless, I identify a number of objectively measureable factors that can together provide at least a partial picture of the salience of ideology in different Supreme Court cases.237 1. Possible Indicators of Ideological Salience a. Distance from the Court’s Median One lesson of Sag and Jacobi’s efforts is that the relative location of the median Justice in the majority can be a useful indicator of the ideological orientation of a case, as the comparison of the two voting rights cases showed.238 As discussed in Part IV, however, the specific Martin-Quinn scores of these median Justices, attached to each case as its Jacobi-Sag score of ideology, do not add substance to this understanding. In fact, those scores probably overstate the ideological distance between the two cases.239 But 1393362 (asserting that it is a mistake to “assume that the relationship between ‘judicial politics’ and ‘law’ is or should be the same . . . even for judges on the same court in every type of case”). 236. See, e.g., id.; Shapiro, supra note 47; Barry Friedman, Taking Law Seriously, 4 PERSP. ON POL. 261 (2006); Emerson H. Tiller & Frank B. Cross, What Is Legal Doctrine?, 100 NW. U. L. REV. 517, 522-25 (2005). 237. I do not focus here on ideological salience for each Justice. But obviously, in any given case, different Justices may rely on ideology to greater or lesser extents. 238. See Jacobi & Sag, supra note 147; see also supra Part IV.A. In those two 54 decisions, Justice O’Connor was the swing vote, and all other Justices voted with their customary blocs. So in Bush v. Vera, with a conservative majority, the median Justice is Justice Rehnquist. In Easley, on the other hand, in which the liberal bloc is in the majority, the median Justice is Justice Ginsburg. Knowing nothing else about these cases other than who the majorities’ median Justices are, we have some reasonably good information about their relative ideological orientation. See Easley v. Cromartie, 532 U.S. 234 (2001); Bush v. Vera, 517 U.S. 952 (1996). 239. See supra Part IV.A. 68 130 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 there is valuable information in the number of places the median Justice in the majority is from the median Justice on the Court. That information is not how liberal or conservative the case is, but instead is suggestive of the extent to which the Justices relied on ideology in their resolution of the case. In a unanimous case, the median Justice is the median Justice on the Court. In Bush v. Vera, in contrast, the median Justice in the majority is the third most conservative Justice, while in Easley the majority’s median is the third most liberal member of the Court. Knowing that the median Justice is as far away from the Court’s median as possible on a nine-member Court can help to orient us to the ideological intensity of the case. b. Disordered Voting As the discussion of disordered cases demonstrates, information about the relative position of the majority’s median Justice is not enough, by itself, to tell us how central ideology might have been to the decision in the case.240 A majority made up of Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justices Scalia, Thomas, Ginsburg, and Stevens has the same median Justice – Chief Justice Rehnquist – as a majority consisting of Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justices Scalia, Thomas, O’Connor, and Kennedy (the majority in Bush v. Vera). The insight that EKL capitalize on in their concept of disordered voting is that these two majorities do not strike us as having the same ideological valence – even if we know nothing else about the cases. To identify ideological salience, then, in addition to knowing how far from the Court’s median Justice the majority’s median is, we might want to know if a case is disordered and whether it is very disordered or only slightly so – information provided by EKL’s disorder scores. The scores can help identify cases that divided the Court along predictable ideological lines and cases that did not.241 Specifically, the more disordered a case is, the less likely it is to be ideologically salient. c. Vote Margin Not all ordered cases are necessarily ideologically salient, however. A case with only one or two dissenters, for example, may be a perfectly ordered case. Where Justice Stevens alone dissents, for example, there is no disorder. 240. See supra Part IV.B. 241. Disorder may not be the only way to identify the less ideologically salient cases. An ordered case is one in which Justice Thomas dissents alone. But one might wonder why Justice Scalia, his frequent coalition partner, did not join him. An ordered case is likewise one in which Justices Stevens, Ginsburg, and Souter are all in dissent, with Breyer in the majority. The same question arises – since Breyer’s ideal point is so close to Souter’s and Ginsburg’s that from Term to Term they switch places on the spectrum, does ideology explain the voting? So we might want to look at deviations not only from order but also from traditional coalitions to help us identify cases that lack ideological salience. 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 131 But if all eight of the other Justices agree on the outcome, it seems unlikely that all eight perceived the case largely ideologically. At least on the Rehnquist 7 court, generally speaking, an ordered 5-4 decision is likely much more ideologically salient than is an ordered 7-2 decision. And as others have observed, unanimous cases are particularly unlikely to have been ideological salient. In addition to a case’s disorder score, then, we might also want to look at the vote margin. d. Other Possible Variables There are other possible indicators of ideological salience. The widely used measure of salience in a more public sense – appearance on the front page of The New York Times the day after announcement – often denotes ideologically fraught decisions.242 Likewise, a Justice’s decision to read his or her dissent from the bench, especially in a close case, often signals a pitched ideological battle on the Court.243 And, of course, scholars may be able to identify other factors that should be considered. 2. Challenges in Using the Indicators There are, of course, challenges to be overcome in developing a functional measure of ideological salience. Among other things, some of the variables discussed above need to be refined. For example, EKL’s measure of disordered voting, which is based on the Martin-Quinn scores, undoubtedly suffers from the problem of artificial precision.244 Instead of relying on the specific disorder scores, then, we might want to divide the scores into categories – highly disordered, somewhat disordered, slightly disordered, etc.245 Likewise, there are important decisions to be made about how and whether to account for separate opinions like concurrences only in the judgment, which might signal ideological disagreement.246 We might also want to consider 242. Lee Epstein & Jeffrey A. Segal, Measuring Issue Salience, 44 AM. J. POL. SCI. 66, 72-73 (2000). 243. Christopher W. Schmidt & Carolyn Shapiro, Oral Dissenting on the Supreme Court (forthcoming) (working title). 244. See supra Part IV.A for a discussion of the problem of too much precision in the Martin-Quinn scores. 245. An additional consideration in using the disorder scores is that EKL calculated the scores by natural court, not by Term, and calculated them only for natural courts that existed for at least three Terms. Edelman, Klein & Lindquist, supra note 194. 246. In this Article, I have followed the convention of counting all votes for a particular outcome together. So, for example, I have counted Clinton v. Jones as a unanimous case, even though Justice Breyer concurred only in the judgment and was quite critical of the majority opinion. But this convention may not be appropriate when identifying ideological salience. 69 132 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 whether and how factors indicating ideological salience might vary in different eras of the Court. Although ideologically contentious cases have recently been decided with a 5-4 vote, for example, for some earlier eras of the Court, different vote margins might be more indicative of ideological salience. Identifying (some of) the objective indicators of ideological salience of course leaves open the question of how to use those indicators. There is no scientific way to aggregate them into a single measure of ideological salience. Nonetheless, to get a sense of whether, together, the factors described above identify cases that seem intuitively to be more ideologically driven than others, I put them together into a “salience score.” The specifics of the aggregation can be found in Appendix B. The primary guiding principle, however, was that no single variable should completely dominate. To emphasize, this method is entirely experimental, designed to evaluate qualitatively whether my general approach to identifying ideological salience is on the right track. I am not proposing a measure that scholars can begin to use. For each of the 95 cases in my dataset, I calculated a “salience score” based on the factors I identified. A list of the cases, ordered by salience score, is in Appendix B. The highest (most salient) score was 2.875, and the lowest (least salient) was -2.525. Looking at the cases with the highest scores on this measure and working down to the lowest scores, the list generally comported with my sense of which cases were the most ideologically salient. The three cases with the highest scores were Bush v. Vera and Easley, the two hotly contested voting rights cases discussed earlier, and Printz, the controversial Brady Bill case.247 All of these cases were 5-4 decisions, and all involved some of the Rehnquist 7 court’s most contested issues – issues of race and voting rights for Bush and Easley and federalism for Printz. And, as expected, unanimous cases were, for the most part, clustered at the bottom of the list, with a few high profile ones, such as Clinton v. Jones, higher up. The differences in salience scores between cases with similar subject matter were also generally consistent with what one might predict. Grubart and Yamaha, the two maritime law cases, both had very low salience scores (-2.275 and -2.525 respectively), as did Rubin and Madigan, the two unanimous First Amendment cases (both -2.525). On the other hand, Buckley, the First Amendment case challenging Colorado’s requirements for petitions on voter initiatives and in which the Court split into unusual coalitions, received a higher score (-0.465), indicating somewhat more ideological salience, but not such a high score as to suggest that ideology dominated the decision. A comparison of the scores of two high-profile War on Terror cases is likewise instructive. In both Rasul v. Bush and Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, the Court held that War on Terror detainees had the right to contest their detention.248 247. See Easley v. Cromartie, 532 U.S. 234 (2001); Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898 (1997); Bush v. Vera, 517 U.S. 952 (1996). 248. Rasul v. Bush, 542 U.S. 466 (2004); Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 502 (2004). 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 133 Although the cases were decided the same day, their voting coalitions were quite different. Rasul, which involved a foreign national detained at Guantanamo Bay, was an ordered 6-3 decision, with Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justices Scalia and Thomas in dissent. Hamdi, however, which involved an American citizen held in South Carolina, was highly disordered. Justice Thomas alone would have denied Hamdi the right to challenge his detention. Justices Scalia and Stevens dissented together, but they took the opposite position, arguing that the Court did not go far enough in asserting limits on the government’s ability to detain U.S. citizens. Based on these voting coalitions, it appears that Hamdi had less ideological salience than did Rasul. On the other hand, one would expect a case on such a divisive and high-profile subject to carry a fair amount of ideological baggage, regardless of the voting line-up. Consistent with these expectations, both cases have relatively high salience scores, but Rasul’s score (2.125) is higher than Hamdi’s (1.625). Again, I do not offer this “salience score” for scholars to begin using. It is undertheorized and unproven. Future research and experimentation is needed to make such an approach functional for researchers. Whatever its limitations, however, the approach offers the possibility of new insights into Supreme Court decisionmaking. Specifically, such an approach may well make it possible to challenge the traditional assumption of empirical scholars that ideology dominates Supreme Court decisionmaking without either abandoning the project of empirical legal scholarship or attempting to identify every non-ideological factor that the Justices might consider (a plainly impossible task). C. Learning from Ideological Salience Distinguishing between cases of high and low ideological salience opens the door to a variety of research questions through which scholars can better investigate the relative role of law, legal indeterminacy, and institutional considerations in different kinds of cases. For example, we could examine whether the Justices use different kinds of arguments in more ideologically salient cases than in less ideologically salient ones. The recent work of Professors Brudney and Ditslear – examining the Court’s use of legislative history and canons of statutory construction in the somewhat ideologically charged area of workplace law compared with the more technocratic area of tax law – certainly suggests that such comparisons would be fruitful avenues for more research.249 Identifying ideological salience also would allow us to study how the subject matter of high-ideological-salience cases changes over time. After all, one thing we learn from Harvey and Woodruff’s work is that historical context matters – and, I argue, it should matter – for evaluating the ideologi- 249. See generally Brudney & Ditslear, supra note 8. 70 134 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 cal nature of a case.250 As Professors Epstein and Segal have argued, for example, the ideological significance of the First Amendment has shifted since the days of the Warren Court.251 Today, while we continue to see contentious First Amendment cases, there are many First Amendment cases that, even when they are high profile, do not closely divide the Court (or do not divide it at all) and do not seem to fall out along predictable ideological lines. Buckley,252 Rubin,253 Schenck,254 and Madigan255 all illustrate this point. Similarly, charting shifts in ideological salience creates the possibility of studying how particular doctrines move from being controversial to being mainstream or vice versa. Identifying subject matter or cases likely to be highly ideologically salient on a particular Court might also help us study strategic behavior. Specifically, we may be able, more systematically, to identify cases, like NAMUDNO or Clinton v. Jones, that initially appear ideologically salient due to their subject matter but that end with unanimous decisions or lopsided majorities. Such cases suggest the possibility of comparing measures or predictions of ideological salience ex ante – before the decision – with measures, like the one I have proposed, that seek to identify ideological salience ex post. Perhaps most importantly, however, thinking about cases in terms of ideological salience allows us to make some normative judgments. We can focus on those cases that are ideologically salient, for example, and within that group, we can face the difficult but important question of whether the Justices’ reliance on ideology in those cases was appropriate – whether it was ideologically legitimate – and why. When and how should the Justices make political decisions? Should they adopt (or strengthen) norms of deference to the political branches when they confront such cases? How much candor about what they are doing is appropriate when they decide them? These questions are not empirical questions. But by shifting their focus to ideological salience, empirical scholars can meaningfully contribute to these important debates. VI. CONCLUSION In this Article, I have critiqued empirical scholars’ efforts to identify and assess ideology in judging. But I have also tried to build on those efforts and to propose a new way for empirical scholars to think about ideology. This new way would not give us objective and consistent measures of how far to the left or right particular cases are. Rather, it would allow us to evaluate the 250. 251. 252. 253. 254. 255. See generally Harvey & Woodruff, supra note 51. See generally Epstein & Segal, supra note 63. Buckley v. Am. Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 525 U.S. 182 (1999). Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., 514 U.S. 476 (1995). Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W. N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997). Ill. ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Assocs., 538 U.S. 600 (2003). 2010] THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 135 likelihood that ideology played a large role in a particular case, a question that has long been ignored or assumed away in empirical legal scholarship. Distinguishing between cases that are and are not ideologically salient opens the door to a whole new set of empirical questions. With that information, we can, for example, work to identify other factors and dimensions that might be of importance to all or some of the Justices. We can also evaluate and compare the roles of law and legal reasoning in ideologically salient and non-salient cases, and we might be better able to identify cases in which there is a strong likelihood of strategic behavior. Most importantly, however, identifying ideologically salient cases brings the promise of meaningful normative discussions about whether that salience and the Justices’ responses to it are appropriate. These discussions would join empirical legal scholars in important conversations with the rest of the legal academy. And perhaps these discussions could even add candor to the public debate about the role of ideology in the work of the Supreme Court. Ideally, such candor could make confirmation possible for a Supreme Court nominee who professes that ideology – or policy judgments – inevitably will play some role in his or her work, allowing the Senate and the public to evaluate the nature of that ideology and how the nominee is likely to use it. A public debate and a confirmation process that no longer require disingenuous claims of absolute neutrality would be both more honest and more democratic. Contributing to such developments is a worthy goal for empirical legal scholarship. 71 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW 136 [Vol. 75 APPENDIX A Cases in Recoding Sample (Chronological Order) L.Ed.2d cite 130/0219 130/0454 130/1024 131/0324 131/0395 131/0403 131/0532 133/0578 133/0611 134/0034 134/0577 135/0036 135/0248 135/0843 136/0347 136/0696 137/0001 137/0041 137/0055 137/0063 137/0093 137/0281 137/0945 137/0980 138/0091 138/0120 138/0162 138/0285 138/0914 139/0433 Case Name and U.S. Reports Cite Austin v. United States, 513 U.S. 5 (1994). Reich v. Collins, 513 U.S. 106 (1994). Jerome B. Grubart, Inc. v. Great Lakes Dredge & Dock Co., 513 U.S. 527 (1995). Whitaker v. Super. Ct., 514 U.S. 208 (1995). Heintz v. Jenkins, 514 U.S. 291 (1995). Celotex Corp. v. Edwards, 514 U.S. 300 (1995). Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., 514 U.S. 476 (1995). Yamaha Motor Corp., U.S.A. v. Calhoun, 516 U.S. 199 (1996). Comm’r v. Lundy, 516 U.S. 235 (1996). Norfolk & W. Ry. Co. v. Hiles, 516 U.S. 400 (1996). Markman v. Westview Instruments, Inc., 517 U.S. 370 (1996). Loving v. United States, 517 U.S. 748 (1996). Bush v. Vera, 517 U.S. 952 (1996). Bd. of County Comm’rs. v. Umbehr, 518 U.S. 668 (1996). Ohio v. Robinette, 519 U.S. 33 (1996). Babbit v. Youpee, 519 U.S. 234 (1997). Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W.N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997). Maryland v. Wilson, 519 U.S. 408 (1997). Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Doe, 519 U.S. 425 (1997). Lynce v. Mathis, 519 U.S. 433 (1997). Dunn v. Commodity Futures Trading Comm’n, 519 U.S. 465 (1997). Bennett v. Spear, 520 U.S. 154 (1997). Clinton v. Jones, 520 U.S. 681 (1997). Suitum v. Tahoe Reg’l Planning Agency, 520 U.S. 725 (1997). Lords Landing Vill. Condo. Council of Unit Owners v. Cont’l Ins. Co., 520 U.S. 893 (1997). Gilbert v. Homar, 520 U.S. 924 (1997). Mazurek v. Armstrong, 520 U.S. 968 (1997). Abrams v. Johnson, 521 U.S. 74 (1997). Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898 (1997). Jefferson v. City of Tarrant, 522 U.S. 75 (1997). 2010] 139/0702 140/0350 140/0542 140/0759 140/0875 140/0970 141/0222 142/0599 143/0818 144/0067 144/0347 144/0494 146/0236 146/0374 146/0530 146/0542 146/0561 146/0707 147/0105 147/0374 148/0373 148/0576 149/0164 149/0430 149/0590 149/0674 151/0489 151/0659 151/0820 152/0437 152/0701 152/0888 153/0027 THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 137 Buchanan v. Angelone, 522 U.S. 269 (1998). Almendarez-Torres v. United States, 523 U.S. 224 (1998). Atl. Mut. Ins. Co. v. Comm’r, 523 U.S. 382 (1998). Crawford-El v. Britton, 523 U.S. 574 (1998). Ark. Educ. Television Comm’n. v. Forbes, 523 U.S. 666 (1998). Calderon v. Ashmus, 523 U.S. 740 (1998). Am. Tel. & Tel. Co. v. Cent. Office, Inc., 524 U.S. 214 (1998). Buckley v. Am. Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 525 U.S. 182 (1999). Wilson v. Layne, 526 U.S. 603 (1999). City of Chicago v. Morales, 527 U.S. 41 (1999). Martin v. Hadix, 527 U.S. 343 (1999). Kolstad v. Am. Dental Ass’n, 527 U.S. 526 (1999). Garner v. Jones, 529 U.S. 244 (2000). Norfolk S. Ry. Co. v. Shanklin, 529 U.S. 344 (2000). Nelson v. Adams USA, Inc., 529 U.S. 460 (2000). Slack v. McDaniel, 529 U.S. 473 (2000). Beck v. Prupis, 529 U.S. 494 (2000). Fischer v. United States, 529 U.S. 667 (2000). Reeves v. Sanderson Plumbing Prods., Inc., 530 U.S. 133 (2000). Arizona v. California, 530 U.S. 392 (2000). Green Tree Fin. Corp.-Ala. v. Randolph, 531 U.S. 79 (2000). Solid Waste Agency of N. Cook County v. U.S. Army Corps of Eng’rs., 531 U.S. 159 (2001). TrafFix Devices, Inc. v. Mktg. Displays, Inc., 532 U.S. 23 (2001). Easley v. Cromartie, 532 U.S. 234 (2001). Daniels v. United States, 532 U.S. 374 (2001). Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424 (2001). Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Mineta, 534 U.S. 103 (2001). Chao v. Mallard Bay Drilling, Inc., 534 U.S. 235 (2002). Lee v. Kemna, 534 U.S. 362 (2002). United States v. Craft, 535 U.S. 274 (2002). Verizon Commc’ns., Inc. v. F.C.C., 535 U.S. 467 (2002). Alabama v. Shelton, 535 U.S. 654 (2002). Delvin v. Scardelletti, 536 U.S. 1 (2002). 72 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW 138 154/0491 154/0501 154/0588 154/0653 155/0001 155/0017 155/0164 155/0376 155/0535 155/0793 155/0933 155/0946 155/1017 156/0544 157/0112 158/0291 158/0450 158/0659 158/0764 158/0787 159/0548 159/0578 159/0643 160/0611 161/0066 161/0563 161/0651 161/0876 161/0953 162/0407 [Vol. 75 Howsam v. Dean Witter Reynolds, Inc., 537 U.S. 79 (2002). Abdur’rahman v. Bell, 537 U.S. 88 (2002). Satazahn v. Pennsylvania, 537 U.S. 101 (2003). Barnhart v. Peabody Coal Co., 537 U.S. 149 (2003). Moseley v. Secrete Catalogue, Inc., 537 U.S. 418 (2003). Boeing Co. v. United States, 537 U.S. 437 (2003). Smith v. Doe, 538 U.S. 84 (2003). Brown v. Legal Found. of Wash., 538 U.S. 216 (2003). Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003). Ill. ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Assocs. Inc., 538 U.S. 600 (2003). Inyo County v. Paiute-Shoshone Indians of the Bishop Cmty., 538 U.S. 701 (2003). City of L.A. v. David, 538 U.S. 715 (2003). Nat’l Park Hospitality Ass’n v. Dep’t of Interior, 538 U.S. 803 (2003). Stogner v. California, 539 U.S. 607 (2003). Doe v. Chao, 540 U.S. 614 (2004). Nixon v. Mo. Mun. League, 541 U.S. 125 (2004). Household Credit Servs., Inc. v. Pfennig, 541 U.S. 232 (2004). Dretke v. Haley, 541 U.S. 386 (2004). Tenn. Student Assistance Corp. v. Hood, 541 U.S. 440 (2004). Till v. SCS Credit Corp., 541 U.S. 465 (2004). Rasul v. Bush, 542 U.S. 466 (2004). Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507 (2004). Missouri v. Seibert, 542 U.S. 600 (2004). Whitfield v. United States, 543 U.S. 209 (2005). Cherokee Nation of Okla. v. Leavitt, 543 U.S. 631 (2005). Rousey v. Jacoway, 544 U.S. 320 (2005). Small v. United States, 544 U.S. 385 (2005). Lingle v. Chevron U.S.A., Inc., 544 U.S. 528 (2005). Deck v. Missouri, 544 U.S. 622 (2005). Am. Trucking Ass’ns, Inc. v. Mich. Pub. Serv. Comm’n, 545 U.S. 429 (2005). THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 2010] 162/0418 162/0982 139 Mid-Con Freight Sys., Inc. v. Mich. Pub. Serv. Comm’n, 545 U.S. 440 (2005). Medellin v. Dretke, 544 U.S. 660 (2005). APPENDIX B Cases in Recoding Sample by Ideological Salience Note on Methodology: To create these scores, I started by identifying the median Justice of the majority and calculating the number of places he or she was from the median of the Court. Taking the absolute value of that number, I subtracted the disorder score if the case was not unanimous or 1.4 if it was (just .01 higher than the highest disorder score in my sample). I also subtracted the vote margin (divided by eight), added one if the case was reported on the front page of The New York Times, and added one if a dissent was read from the bench. The guiding principles were to combine the various factors I identified, giving somewhat more weight to large disorder scores, unanimity, and majorities’ median Justices who are far from the median Justice of the Court, but without allowing any single factor to dominate. Because the disorder scores, derived from the Martin-Quinn scores, extend, in some cases, many places past the decimal, I rounded to three digits after the decimal. In my view, the particular numbers that result here are not intrinsically informative. What is more important is the order in which the cases are listed and, to some extent, the relative magnitude of the distances between them. Please note that I do not offer these salience scores as a new methodology that is ready for widespread use. To the contrary, the approach is, at this stage, experimental and unrefined, but it is a first step towards a new way for empirical scholars to assess the ideology in Supreme Court cases. Ideological Salience Score 2.875 2.875 2.875 2.625 2.125 1.875 1.875 1.875 1.875 1.875 Case Name and U.S. Reports Cite Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898 (1997). Easley v. Cromartie, 532 U.S. 234 (2001). Bush v. Vera, 517 U.S. 952 (1996). City of Chicago v. Morales, 527 U.S. 41 (1999). Rasul v. Bush, 542 U.S. 466 (2004). Daniels v. United States, 532 U.S. 374 (2001). Solid Waste Agency of N. Cook County v. U.S. Army Corps of Eng’rs., 531 U.S. 159 (2001). Brown v. Legal Found. of Wash., 538 U.S. 216 (2003). Stogner v. California, 539 U.S. 607 (2003). Kolstad v. Am. Dental Ass’n, 527 U.S. 526 (1999). 73 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW 140 1.875 1.875 1.875 1.825 1.825 1.750 1.625 1.608 1.445 1.375 1.125 1.125 1.125 1.108 1.108 1.077 0.952 0.952 0.903 0.557 0.452 0.375 0.375 0.375 0.375 0.375 0.375 0.375 0.375 0.375 0.328 0.104 -0.061 -0.171 -0.268 -0.375 -0.375 -0.375 -0.375 -0.375 [Vol. 75 Sattazahn v. Pennsylvania, 537 U.S. 101 (2003). Abrams v. Johnson, 521 U.S. 74 (1997). Alabama v. Shelton, 535 U.S. 654 (2002). Crawford-El v. Britton, 523 U.S. 574 (1998). Missouri v. Seibert, 542 U.S. 600 (2004). Small v. United States, 544 U.S. 385 (2005). Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507 (2004). Buchanan v. Angelone, 522 U.S. 269 (1998). Medellin v. Dretke, 544 U.S. 660 (2005). Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003). Garner v. Jones, 529 U.S. 244 (2000). Mazurek v. Armstrong, 520 U.S. 968 (1997). Ark. Educ. Television Comm’n v. Forbes, 523 U.S. 666 (1998). Doe v. Chao, 540 U.S. 614 (2004). Smith v. Doe, 538 U.S. 84 (2003). Till v. SCS Credit Corp., 541 U.S. 465 (2004). Devlin v. Scardelletti, 536 U.S. 1 (2002). Lee v. Kemna, 534 U.S. 362 (2002). Barnhart v. Peabody Coal Co., 537 U.S. 149 (2003). Arizona v. California, 530 U.S. 392 (2000). Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of W. N.Y., 519 U.S. 357 (1997). Tenn. Student Assistance Corp. v. Hood, 541 U.S. 440 (2004). Celotex Corp. v. Edwards, 514 U.S. 300 (1995). Bd. of County Comm’rs v. Umbehr, 518 U.S. 668 (1996). Fischer v. United States, 529 U.S. 667 (2000). Norfolk S. Ry. Co. v. Shanklin, 529 U.S. 344 (2000). Slack v. McDaniel, 529 U.S. 473 (2000). Boeing Co. v. United States, 537 U.S. 437 (2003). Martin v. Hadix, 527 U.S. 343 (1999). Deck v. Missouri, 544 U.S. 622 (2005). Beck v. Prupis, 529 U.S. 494 (2000). Dretke v. Haley, 541 U.S. 386 (2004). Almendarez-Torres v. United States, 523 U.S. 224 (1998). Maryland v. Wilson, 519 U.S. 408 (1997). Mid-Con Freight Sys., Inc. v. Mich. Pub. Serv. Comm’n, 545 U.S. 440 (2005). Abdur’Rahman v. Bell, 537 U.S. 88 (2002). Wilson v. Layne, 526 U.S. 603 (1999). Jefferson v. City of Tarrant, 522 U.S. 75 (1997). Babbitt v. Youpee, 519 U.S. 234 (1997). Whitaker v. Super. Ct., 514 U.S. 208 (1995). THE CONTEXT OF IDEOLOGY 2010] -0.375 -0.375 -0.388 -0.465 -0.580 -0.625 -0.705 -0.750 -0.942 -1.125 -1.525 -1.525 -1.900 -1.900 -1.982 -2.275 -2.400 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 141 Ohio v. Robinette, 519 U.S. 33 (1996). Nixon v. Mo. Mun. League, 541 U.S. 125 (2004). Nat’l Park Hospitality Ass’n v. Dep’t of Interior, 538 U.S. 803 (2003). Buckley v. Am. Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 525 U.S. 182 (1999). Verizon Commc’ns., Inc. v. F.C.C., 535 U.S. 467 (2002). Lords Landing Vill. Condo. Council of Unit Owners v. Cont’l Ins. Co., 520 U.S. 893 (1997). Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Leatherman Tool Group, Inc., 532 U.S. 424 (2001). Am. Tel. & Tel. Co. v. Cent. Office Tel., Inc., 524 U.S. 214 (1998). United States v. Craft, 535 U.S. 274 (2002). Green Tree Fin. Corp. v. Randolph, 531 U.S. 79 (2000). Clinton v. Jones, 520 U.S. 681 (1997). Markman v. Westview Instruments, Inc., 517 U.S. 370 (1996). Cherokee Nation of Okla. v. Leavitt, 543 U.S. 631 (2005). Chao v. Mallard Bay Drilling, Inc., 534 U.S. 235 (2002). Comm’r v. Lundy, 516 U.S. 235 (1996). Jerome B. Grubart, Inc. v. Great Lakes Dredge & Dock Co., 513 U.S. 527 (1995). Howsam v. Dean Witter Reynolds, Inc., 537 U.S. 79 (2002). Reich v. Collins, 513 U.S. 106 (1994). Bennett v. Spear, 520 U.S. 154 (1997). Norfolk & W. Ry. Co. v. Hiles, 516 U.S. 400 (1996). Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., 514 U.S. 476 (1995). Ill. ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Assocs., Inc., 538 U.S. 600 (2003). Lingle v. Chevron U.S.A., Inc., 544 U.S. 528 (2005). Dunn v. Commodity Futures Trading Comm’n, 519 U.S. 465 (1997). Nelson v. Adams USA, Inc., 529 U.S. 460 (2000). Lynce v. Mathis, 519 U.S. 433 (1997). Moseley v. V Secret Catalogue, Inc., 537 U.S. 418 (2003). Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Mineta, 534 U.S. 103 (2001). Am. Trucking Ass’ns, Inc. v. Mich. Pub. Serv. Comm’n, 545 U.S. 429 (2005). 74 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW 142 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 -2.525 [Vol. 75 Atl. Mut. Ins. Co. v. Comm’r, 523 U.S. 382 (1998). Calderon v. Ashmus, 523 U.S. 740 (1998). Household Credit Servs. v. Pfennig, 541 U.S. 232 (2004). Loving v. United States, 517 U.S. 748 (1996). Whitfield v. United States, 543 U.S. 209 (2005). Heintz v. Jenkins, 514 U.S. 291 (1995). Suitum v. Tahoe Reg’l Planning Agency, 520 U.S. 725 (1997). Yamaha Motor Corp., U.S.A. v. Calhoun, 516 U.S. 199 (1996). Inyo County v. Paiute-Shoshone Indians, 538 U.S. 701 (2003). Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Doe, 519 U.S. 425 (1997). City of L.A. v. David, 538 U.S. 715 (2003). TrafFix Devices, Inc. v. Mktg. Displays, Inc., 532 U.S. 23 (2001). Austin v. United States, 513 U.S. 5 (1994). Rousey v. Jacoway, 544 U.S. 320 (2005). Reeves v. Sanderson Plumbing Prods., Inc., 530 U.S. 133 (2000). Gilbert v. Homar, 520 U.S. 924 (1997). The Myth of the Level Playing Field: Knowledge, Affect, and Repetition in Public Debate Jeremy N. Sheff * The industrialization of the channels and scale of communication has led some well-meaning reformers to try to regulate the ability of powerful private actors to leverage economic inequality into political inequality, particularly in the area of campaign finance. Such reform efforts are ostensibly intended to further the deliberative democratic ideal of rational, informed public decisionmaking by preventing well-funded private interests from improperly influencing democratic debate and, by extension, political outcomes. This Article examines empirical findings in political science, psychology, and marketing and argues that, in the context of contemporary American society, the normative principles of deliberative democracy and formal equality operate at cross-purposes. Equalizing measures in campaign finance regulation are extremely likely to increase the divergence between actual political decisionmaking and a deliberative, informed, rational ideal by increasing the incentives for speakers to mislead and manipulate voters or by entrenching preexisting majorities. This Article argues that, rather than focusing on equality of financing, reformers would do better to think about how to ameliorate the source of non-optimal political decisionmaking: the (economically rational) political ignorance, non-rational decisionmaking, and civic disengagement of the average citizen. * Assistant Professor of Law, St. John’s University School of Law. I am grateful for helpful comments from Professors Richard Hasen, Daniel Ortiz, Ilya Somin, and Brian Tamanaha. This Article also benefited from comments at the New York City Junior Faculty Colloquium at Fordham Law School. All errors are the author’s alone. 75 144 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 I. INTRODUCTION ....................................................................................... 144 II. WHY LEVEL THE PLAYING FIELD? THE ARGUMENT FOR REFORM ....... 147 III. CAMPAIGNS, CASH, AND THE POWER OF REPETITION .......................... 150 A. Does Campaign Spending Matter? ................................................ 150 B. How Does Campaign Spending Work? .......................................... 157 IV. A RATIONALE FOR REFORM? EVALUATING EQUALIZATION PROPOSALS ........................................... 164 A. Undoing Buckley – Expenditure Limits ......................................... 166 B. Matching Funds – Raising the Playing Field................................. 168 C. Equal Dollars per Voter – Aggregation at the Expense of Deliberation................................... 169 V. CONCLUSION: EQUALITY VS. RATIONALITY ......................................... 175 I. INTRODUCTION [I]t is said that Cato contrived to drop a Libyan fig in the Senate, as he shook out the folds of his toga, and then, as the senators admired its size and beauty, said that the country where it grew was only three days’ sail from Rome. And in one thing he was even more savage, namely, in adding to his vote on any question whatsoever these words: “In my opinion, Carthage must be destroyed.” In this way Cato is said to have brought to pass the third and last war against Carthage . . . .1 Justice Holmes famously asserted that “the best test of truth is the power of the thought to get itself accepted in the competition of the market.”2 This empirical claim about the relationship between the truth of a proposition and its popular acceptance is the quintessential crystallization of a widely espoused instrumentalist account of the right to free expression. Ultimately, the free exchange of ideas is considered a means to the end of rational and optimal decisionmaking in a deliberative democracy.3 While such instrumentalist 1. 2 PLUTARCH, LIVES 383 (Bernadotte Perrin trans., Loeb Classical Library ed., 1914); see also Charles E. Little, The Authenticity and Form of Cato’s Saying “Carthago Delenda Est,” 29 CLASSICAL J. 429 (1934). 2. Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting). 3. See, e.g., ALEXANDER MEIKLEJOHN, FREE SPEECH AND ITS RELATION TO SELF-GOVERNMENT 26 (1948) (“Just so far as, at any point, the citizens who are to decide an issue are denied acquaintance with information . . . which is relevant to that issue, just so far the result must be ill-considered, ill-balanced planning for the general good. It is that mutilation of the thinking process of the community against which the First Amendment to the Constitution is directed.”). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 145 arguments have been levied against government interference in the “marketplace of ideas” for centuries,4 the industrialization of the channels and scale of communications in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries has led many to doubt the ability of laissez-faire First Amendment policy to secure its promised benefits. Reasoning backward from the ends of instrumentalist First Amendment theory, reformers argue that the ability of certain powerful private actors to manipulate the scope and content of debate requires some qualification of Holmes’s conclusion. Specifically, reformers contend that truth can only emerge from competition on a level playing field and that, left unchecked, the disproportionate wealth of certain speakers will allow them to exert a greater influence on public debate (and, by extension, public policy) than less endowed citizens and groups, in violation of the fundamental democratic principle of political equality.5 Implicit in this argument is a claim that laissez-faire First Amendment doctrine is causing our democratic processes to generate policy outcomes that are inferior to those that could be achieved through more muscular regulation of public debate.6 Modern First Amendment instrumentalists have proposed various departures from existing doctrine as a means to the end of optimal, rational, egalitarian self-government. Among the most hotly contested of these arise in the area of campaign finance law. Well-meaning reformers lament rigid constitu- 4. See, e.g., JOHN MILTON, AREOPAGITICA (1644) (“And though all the windes of doctrin were let loose to play upon the earth, so Truth be in the field, we do injuriously, by licencing and prohibiting to misdoubt her strength. Let her and Falshood grapple; who ever knew Truth put to the wors, in a free and open encounter[?] . . . This I know, that errors in a good government and in a bad are equally almost incident; for what Magistrate may not be mis-inform’d, and much the sooner, if liberty of Printing be reduc’t into the power of a few[?]”). 5. See, e.g., Jerome A. Barron, Access to the Press – A New First Amendment Right, 80 HARV. L. REV. 1641, 1656 (1967) (“The soap box is no longer an adequate forum for public discussion. Only the new media of communication can lay sentiments before the public, and it is they rather than government who can most effectively abridge expression by nullifying the opportunity for an idea to win acceptance. As a constitutional theory for the communication of ideas, laissez faire is manifestly irrelevant.”); Owen M. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, 71 IOWA L. REV. 1405, 1411 (1986) (“What is said determines what is not said . . . . [A]utonomy adds nothing and if need be, might have to be sacrificed, to make certain that public debate is sufficiently rich to permit true collective self-determination.”); Morton J. Horwitz, The Supreme Court, 1992 Term – Foreword, The Constitution of Change: Legal Fundamentality Without Fundamentalism, 107 HARV. L. REV. 30, 113 (1993) (“[T]he central practical goal of modern First Amendment history [is] the use of free speech doctrine to ‘level the playing field’ in order to provide economically or socially weak political dissidents with a chance to engage in political debate.”). 6. See Samuel Issacharoff & Pamela S. Karlan, The Hydraulics of Campaign Finance Reform, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1705, 1717 (1999) (“One common starting point for electoral reform is a claim that the current system somehow adulterates the outcomes that a purer system would produce.”). 76 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW 146 [Vol. 75 tional barriers to creative measures that would, in theory, increase the diversity of viewpoints represented in political debate while privileging no viewpoint over any other, resulting in a better-informed citizenry and, therefore, better decisionmaking, better government, and better policy. Chief among these barriers is the widely disparaged yet remarkably stable contribution/expenditure distinction of Buckley v. Valeo7 and its progeny. By attempting to place all candidates, citizens, or interests on an equal footing in terms of the amount they can spend on political campaigning, reformers hope to design a marketplace of ideas from which truth can reliably emerge victorious. This Article argues that the categorical assertion of Justice Holmes’s dissent in Abrams is indeed descriptively inaccurate, but that the relationship between popular acceptance of an idea and its truth is too complex and fraught to be reliably controlled by blunt field-leveling measures in campaign finance regulation. As a result, reform proposals tend to focus on the wrong targets, potentially exacerbating the conditions they purport to alleviate. Reformers who believe that unsound policy is being generated as a result of an improperly skewed marketplace of ideas would do better to explore the dynamics of political decisionmaking and persuasion in an effort to determine why policy outputs fall short of the perceived ideal. The political science, psychology, and marketing literatures provide helpful guidance in this regard, suggesting that finance regimes play less of a role in campaign outcomes than do background levels of knowledge and commitment. Investigation of these literatures suggests that the level playing field envisioned by instrumentalist reformers, in which all speakers or points of view have equal fiscal resources for the propagation of their arguments, is anathema to those reformers’ ultimate goals. Put simply, equality of resources is not a useful means to the end of enlightened policy in our democracy. Part II of this Article sets up the elements of the problem to be examined: whether campaign finance reforms, and particularly measures to equalize campaign expenditures, are normatively desirable from an instrumentalist point of view. Part III explores the relevant political science, psychology, and marketing literatures in an effort to explain the dynamics of knowledge, persuasion, and action in public debate, both in general and in the specific context of electoral campaigns. Part IV applies the social science findings of Part III to the questions outlined in Part II. Part IV goes on to argue that equality-minded reforms are unlikely to influence the outputs of the political process in a way that would satisfy reformers’ goals and are in fact more likely to aggravate the conditions of which reformers currently complain. Part V concludes the Article with some discussion of potential alternative means to the social ends of instrumentalist free speech policy. 7. 424 U.S. 1 (1976). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 147 II. WHY LEVEL THE PLAYING FIELD? THE ARGUMENT FOR REFORM The project of this Article is to address only one of the many instrumentalist rationales underlying campaign finance reform agendas: the political equality rationale.8 Since the Supreme Court (in)famously announced in Buckley v. Valeo its view that “the concept that government may restrict the speech of some elements of our society in order to enhance the relative voice of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment,”9 equality-based arguments in favor of campaign finance reform have been at a disadvantage relative to arguments addressing the Court-approved, anti-corruption justification for reform.10 Nevertheless, equality remains a central concern of reformers, who often either assail the Buckley rule as misguided or repackage equality 8. Other rationales include the anti-corruption rationale endorsed by the Supreme Court in Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 26-27 (1976); the “participatory selfgovernment” rationale expressed in the recent campaign finance opinions of Justice Breyer, see Richard L. Hasen, Buckley Is Dead, Long Live Buckley: The New Campaign Finance Incoherence of McConnell v. Federal Election Commission, 153 U. PA. L. REV. PENNUMBRA 31, 57 (2004), available at http://www.pennumbra.com/ issues/pdfs/153-1/Hasen.pdf; the rationale that limiting fundraising frees up candidate time for worthier democratic pursuits, see generally Vincent Blasi, Spending Limits and the Squandering of Candidates’ Time, 6 J. L. & POL’Y 123 (1997); and the antiextortion rationale that has gained attention in the wake of the sweeping deregulation of corporate political expenditures occasioned by the Supreme Court’s recent decision in Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, No. 08-205, slip op. (U.S. Jan. 21, 2010), see North Carolina Right to Life v. Leake, 525 F.3d 274, 335-36 (4th Cir. 2008) (describing a campaign by private interests to influence legislators’ behavior by threatening them with a barrage of negative advertising if they did not adopt the group’s preferred position), cited in Election Law Blog, http://electionlawblog.org/ (Feb. 4, 2010, 08:18 PDT), available at http://electionlaw blog.org/archives/015213.html; see also Yglesias (Think Progress), http://yglesias.thinkprogress.org/ (Jan. 22, 2010, 12:15 EDT), available at http://yglesias.thinkprogress.org/archives/2010/01/money-for-nothing-and-votes-forfree.php (“[A] group doesn’t actually need to spend vast sums of money to have a decisive influence on politics. It just needs to be able to credibly threaten to spend said sums.”). 9. 424 U.S. at 48-49. 10. Id. at 26-27 (finding that campaign finance regulation is constitutionally justified by the government’s interest in preventing corruption of the democratic process or the appearance thereof). But see FEC v. Mass. Citizens for Life, Inc., 479 U.S. 238, 258 (1986) (“Relative availability of funds is after all a rough barometer of public support. The resources in the treasury of a business corporation, however, are not an indication of popular support for the corporation’s political ideas. They reflect instead the economically motivated decisions of investors and customers. The availability of these resources may make a corporation a formidable political presence, even though the power of the corporation may be no reflection of the power of its ideas.”). 77 148 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 concerns as corruption concerns.11 Examples of equality-inspired proposals range from radical “equal-dollars-per-voter” voucher regimes (usually entailing explicit abrogation of Buckley)12 to more moderate (and legislatively successful) voluntary incentive-based systems of equal public financing.13 What these proposals have in common is their goal of preventing economic inequality – a natural and accepted byproduct of a capitalist economy such as ours – from being leveraged into political inequality – a normatively unacceptable condition in a purportedly democratic society like ours.14 It is not always clear from reformers’ arguments how campaign financing translates economic power into political power; indeed, the mechanism often appears to be largely assumed.15 This assumption has crept into the 11. In one such repackaged argument, Professor David Strauss has argued that corruption concerns are a byproduct of inequality concerns in an environment of interest-group politics. See generally David A. Strauss, Corruption, Equality, and Campaign Finance Reform, 94 COLUM. L. REV. 1369 (1994). 12. See generally Richard L. Hasen, Clipping Coupons for Democracy: An Egalitarian/Public Choice Defense of Campaign Finance Vouchers, 84 CAL. L. REV. 1, 42-43 (1996); Edward B. Foley, Equal-Dollars-Per-Voter: A Constitutional Principle of Campaign Finance, 94 COLUM. L. REV. 1204 (1994). 13. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Political Equality and Unintended Consequences, 94 COLUM. L. REV. 1390, 1400 (1994); see also Citizens Clean Elections Act, 16 ARIZ. REV. STAT. ANN. §§ 16-940 to -961 (2006) (establishing a voluntary system of campaign expenditure limits in exchange for public funding in elections for state office); Maine Clean Election Act, ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 21-A, §§ 1121-1128 (2006) (same). These two states, the first to adopt robust public-financing regimes for state elections, have achieved some success in expanding the circle of candidates for state office and increasing election competitiveness but have not yet seen significant declines in overall campaign expenditures or increases in voter participation. See generally GEN. ACCTG. OFFICE, CAMPAIGN FINANCE REFORM: EARLY EXPERIENCES OF TWO STATES THAT OFFER FULL PUBLIC FUNDING FOR POLITICAL CANDIDATES, GAO03-453 (2003); Kenneth R. Mayer, Timothy Werner & Amanda Williams, Do Public Funding Programs Enhance Electoral Competition?, in THE MARKETPLACE OF DEMOCRACY: ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND AMERICAN POLITICS 245 (Michael McDonald & John Samples eds., 2006), available at http://works.bepress.com/mayer /15. 14. See generally Daniel R. Ortiz, The Democratic Paradox of Campaign Finance Reform, 50 STAN. L. REV. 893 (1998) (outlining and critiquing the equalitybased objection to unregulated private financing of political campaigns). 15. Id. at 901 (“The notion that people can transform economic into political power has such great common-sense appeal that few reformers even bother to explain how it occurs. That speakers with more money can make more appeals to voters than can those with less money seems obviously to violate equality, particularly the equality of opportunity to persuade others . . . .”). This assumption has been called into question recently. See, e.g., BRADLEY A. SMITH, UNFREE SPEECH: THE FOLLY OF CAMPAIGN FINANCE REFORM 48-51 (2001) (critiquing the argument that “money buys elections” as an example of the fallacy that correlation is equivalent to causation). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 149 analysis of the Supreme Court16 and remains a background principle of debates about campaign finance reform. Professor Daniel Ortiz argues that the assumption that relative levels of campaign spending influence political outcomes “requires, descriptively, that a significant number of citizens . . . be civic slackers: voters who make political decisions in a somewhat careless way.”17 He further argues that campaign reform measures seeking to cure deficiencies in policy that result from the political participation of such “civic slackers” imply “a strong normative commitment to a particular conception of how people should vote . . . [, that is, through] the independent exercise of deliberate political judgment.”18 Professor Ortiz characterizes reformist arguments that rely on these two premises as potentially inegalitarian or elitist but encourages reformers to make them explicit.19 This Article will take the argument one step further. It will analyze, descriptively, the dynamics underlying voter decisionmaking, as understood by the social scientists who study them. Based on this analysis, it will then argue that, given the two necessary premises of reformist arguments (the descriptive belief in an uninformed, unmotivated electorate and the normative belief in the superiority of deliberative political decisionmaking), equality-based campaign finance measures are actually detrimental to reformers’ ostensible goals. Considering the importance to reformist arguments of the assumption that private campaign financing allows economic power to be translated into political power, the factual basis for the assumption has received surprisingly little scrutiny in the legal academic literature. As noted above, Professor Ortiz has exposed the basic model of the electorate necessary to uphold the assumption20 and has elsewhere noted that this “civic slacker” model is supported by empirical research.21 In a recent symposium, some of the contributors also discussed the empirical underpinnings of campaign finance regula- 16. See Austin v. Mich. Chamber of Commerce, 494 U.S. 652, 659-60 (1990) (decrying “the corrosive and distorting effects of immense aggregations of wealth that are accumulated with the help of the corporate form and that have little or no correlation to the public’s support for the corporation’s political ideas”); Hasen, supra note 8, at 58 (arguing that the only basis for Austin and similar opinions of the Court is the conclusion that allowing unlimited election-related speech by moneyed interests such as corporations or unions “would give [their] views disproportionate weight in society, and the legislature is seeking to democratize the influence that money can bring to bear upon the electoral process”). 17. Ortiz, supra note 14, at 913. 18. Id. 19. Id. at 913-14. 20. See supra note 17 and accompanying text. 21. Daniel R. Ortiz, The Engaged and the Inert: Theorizing Political Personality Under the First Amendment, 81 VA. L. REV. 1, 26-29 (1995) (noting that American voters tend to be “civic slobs,” in contrast with “the deliberate, informed civic smarty of classical democratic theory”). 78 150 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 tion in ballot measure campaigns.22 Apart from these early steps, however, the legal academy has given little attention to the two central questions begged by equality-based reformist arguments: (1) do political campaigns actually influence the outcomes of democratic processes, and, (2) if so, what is the mechanism by which they do so? These questions are of more than mere academic interest. If campaign spending does not influence campaigns in the ways reformers assume, reform measures are at best superfluous and at worst counterproductive from an instrumentalist point of view. Similarly, an understanding of the mechanism (if any) by which money translates into political outcomes would help to identify appropriate targets for regulation and avoid regulation of inappropriate ones. Thus, reformers would be well served to learn more about the relationships between campaign financing, campaign activities, and political outcomes. Some difficulty arises insofar as this learning is generally not to be found in the legal authorities that are the mainstay of traditional legal analysis, particularly in areas as enmeshed in constitutional law as the campaign finance debate. Nevertheless, the political science, psychology, and marketing literatures have all examined the relationship between information campaigns and social outcomes, and their findings bear directly on the questions that much of the debate in the legal academy has simply assumed away. Given the comparative advantage scholars in these social science disciplines enjoy in addressing these types of empirical questions, legal academics would be well served to draw on their work when considering policy changes in campaign finance.23 This Article is an effort to do precisely that. III. CAMPAIGNS, CASH, AND THE POWER OF REPETITION A. Does Campaign Spending Matter? The first question equality-minded reformers must address is whether campaign spending makes any difference in the outcome of political processes. The political science literature teems with analyses of the dynamics of voter decisionmaking and the influence of political campaigns on those dynamics. One robust and persistent finding validates the “civic slacker” 22. See generally Thomas Stratmann, The Effectiveness of Money in Ballot Measure Campaigns, 78 S. CAL. L. REV. 1041 (2005); John M. de Figueiredo, How Much Does Money Matter in a Direct Democracy, 78 S. CAL. L. REV. 1065 (2005). 23. Cf. Richard A. Epstein, Let “The Fundamental Things Apply”: Necessary and Contingent Truths in Legal Scholarship, 115 HARV. L. REV. 1288, 1291 (2002) (“The division of labor matters, and lawyers qua lawyers have no comparative advantage in doing empirical work. As such, their preferred strategy should be to rely on the empirical work done by trained social scientists, or in the alternative, to spend time and effort acquiring the expertise needed to do social science work at their level . . . . Lawyers should be able to understand, interpret, and critique the work of social scientists, not replicate it.”). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 151 view of the electorate. It is generally recognized in social science circles that American voters tend not to be especially well informed: The democratic citizen is expected to be interested and . . . to be well informed about political affairs. He is supposed to know what the issues are, what their history is, what the relevant facts are, what alternatives are proposed, what the party stands for, what the likely consequences are. By such standards the voter falls short . . . . [W]hen it comes to politics and political information, most Americans are severely malnourished. We are inattentive to most things political; we care little, know less, and participate in politics only when absolutely necessary (and often not even then). Our political views are peripatetic, hastily assembled, unconstrained by ideology, and unencumbered by data. Americans, in short, fail to meet the dictates of even the most charitable versions of democratic theory.24 The low-information condition of political decisionmaking in American democracy has attracted serious scholarly attention to questions such as the distribution of political knowledge and sophistication,25 the proper measurement of such knowledge and sophistication,26 and especially whether low 24. Paul Freedman, Michael Franz & Kenneth Goldstein, Campaign Advertising and Democratic Citizenship, 48 AM. J. POL. SCI. 723, 724 (2004) (quoting BERNARD R. BERELSON, PAUL F. LAZARSFELD & WILLIAM N. MCPHEE, VOTING: A STUDY OF OPINION FORMATION IN A PRESIDENTIAL CAMPAIGN 308 (1954)) (internal citations and quotation marks omitted). The legal academy’s awareness of voter ignorance and its implications has lagged behind the political science literature and has only begun to catch up in the past decade. See, e.g., Ilya Somin, Political Ignorance and the Countermajoritarian Difficulty: A New Perspective on the Central Obsession of Constitutional Theory, 89 IOWA L. REV. 1287 (2004) (arguing that judicial review is not necessarily countermajoritarian because legislation cannot be understood to be an expression of popular will in a democracy where the electorate is generally uninformed); Michael S. Kang, Democratizing Direct Democracy: Restoring Voter Competence Through Heuristic Cues and “Disclosure Plus,” 50 UCLA L. REV. 1141, 1145-46, 1153-54 (2003) (evaluating the implications of a low-information electorate for direct democracy); Ortiz, supra note 21, at 26-29 (noting that American voters tend to be “civic slobs,” in contrast with “the deliberate, informed civic smarty of classical democratic theory”). 25. See, e.g., Robert C. Luskin, Measuring Political Sophistication, 31 AM. J. POL. SCI. 856, 885-89 (1987) (summarizing and interpreting numerous studies of the distribution of political sophistication). 26. See generally Michael X. Delli Carpini & Scott Keeter, Measuring Political Knowledge: Putting First Things First, 37 AM. J. POL. SCI. 1179 (1993) (an influential defense of survey-based measures of political knowledge); see also Luskin, supra note 25, at 864-85 (describing various measures of political sophistication and their conceptual underpinnings); Jeffery J. Mondak, Reconsidering the Measurement of 79 152 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 voter knowledge or sophistication leads to deviation from policies or election results that would obtain under conditions of greater voter knowledge. The growing consensus is that, although heuristic cues can assist low-information voters in bringing their political decisionmaking closer to that of fully informed voters,27 persistent deviations remain.28 A related question of particular relevance to this Article is whether, given the low-information environment of American electoral politics, spending on campaign communications can affect voter knowledge, electoral or policy preferences, or voting behavior. Again, political scientists have examined this question in depth, and more recent scholarship is moving away from a long-standing dismissive view of campaigns’ capacity to alter election outcomes and toward the position that there are moderate campaign effects on voter knowledge, preferences, and even behavior.29 Campaign messages do Political Knowledge, 8 POL. ANALYSIS 57, 58-64 (1999) (critiquing popular surveybased methods of measuring political knowledge as incomplete and potentially misleading). 27. See generally, e.g., SAMUEL L. POPKIN, THE REASONING VOTER: COMMUNICATION AND PERSUASION IN PRESIDENTIAL CAMPAIGNS (1991) (arguing that voters use heuristic cues to approximate fully informed decisionmaking and that any remaining individual deviations from the informed ideal likely cancel each other out in the aggregate); see also Kang, supra note 24, at 1149-50 (arguing that heuristic cues allow voters to bring their voting behavior into line with their preferences). 28. See Patrick Fournier, The Impact of Campaigns on Discrepancies, Errors, and Biases in Voting Behavior, in CAPTURING CAMPAIGN EFFECTS 45, 45-48 (Henry E. Brady & Richard Johnston eds., 2006) (summarizing research demonstrating that low-information voters’ decisionmaking deviates from decisionmaking of better informed voters, on both an individual and an aggregate basis); see generally, e.g., Larry M. Bartels, Uninformed Votes: Information Effects in Presidential Elections, 40 AM. J. POL. SCI. 194 (1996) (describing, testing, and critiquing as descriptively inaccurate models of voter behavior – such as that advanced in POPKIN, supra note 27 – that hypothesize that low-information voters use heuristic cues to approximate fully informed decisionmaking and that remaining deviations from fully informed decisions cancel each other out); Martin Gilens, Political Ignorance and Collective Policy Preferences, 95 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 379 (2001) (finding that not only the level of general political knowledge but also the level of policy-specific knowledge has a significant effect on policy preferences, particularly but not exclusively among those with high levels of general political knowledge); Robert C. Luskin & James S. Fishkin, Deliberative Polling, Public Opinion, and Democracy: The Case of the National Issues Convention, at 10-15 (Jan. 2005) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://cdd.stanford.edu/research/papers/2005/issues-convention.pdf (describing attitude change on political issues as a result of increased information gained through a deliberative polling exercise); Ilya Somin, Voter Ignorance and the Democratic Ideal, 12 CRITICAL REV. 413, 419-31 (1998) (critiquing various arguments that shortcuts in voter decisionmaking can compensate for low levels of political knowledge). 29. See, e.g., THOMAS H. HOLBROOK, DO CAMPAIGNS MATTER? 1-19 (1996) (summarizing scholarship arguing for and against the proposition that political campaigns affect voter decisions); Daron R. Shaw, The Effect of TV Ads and Candidate 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 153 appear to increase voter information, particularly among voters with the least background political knowledge – the “civic slackers” benefit most in informational terms.30 Campaign ads also appear to affect voter attitudes toward candidates. In particular, political advertising appears to have the ability to implant emotional or affective attitudes toward its sponsors and subjects, though the positive or negative tenor of the ads can determine the polarity of these attitudes.31 Significantly, repeated exposure to a candidate’s campaign advertisements appears to moderately but consistently strengthen positive Appearances on Statewide Presidential Votes, 1988-96, 93 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 345, 345-47 (1999) (same); Shanto Iyengar & Adam F. Simon, New Perspectives and Evidence on Political Communication and Campaign Effects, 51 ANN. REV. PSYCHOL. 149 (2000) (arguing that the conventional wisdom that campaigns have negligible effects is based on methodological and conceptual errors and reviewing new research pointing to a diversity of campaign effects). 30. See generally, e.g., Freedman, Franz & Goldstein, supra note 24 (arguing that campaign television ads increase voter information, particularly among less informed voters); cf. Thomas M. Holbrook, Presidential Campaigns and the Knowledge Gap, 19 POL. COMM. 437 (2002) (finding that some campaign communications – specifically presidential debates – can reduce the information gap between highinformation and low-information voters). A slightly different view can be found in STEPHEN ANSOLABEHERE & SHANTO IYENGAR, GOING NEGATIVE: HOW ATTACK ADS SHRINK AND POLARIZE THE ELECTORATE 51-61 (1995), where the authors report experimental results showing that a single political advertisement exposure reduces the information gap between individuals more likely to be politically informed and those less likely to be informed, but that with a second exposure this gap widens to its original spread (the experiment does not test more than two exposures). The authors theorize that this result could be extrapolated to support the proposition that “the more candidates advertise, the more their message reaches only better-informed portions of the electorate,” however, their results show absolute information gains for less informed voters with repeated advertising, even though relative gains after two exposures return to pre-advertising levels. Id. at 54-55. 31. See generally, e.g., Charles Atkin & Gary Heald, Effects of Political Advertising, 40 PUB. OPINION Q. 216 (1976) (demonstrating experimentally that positively and negatively charged ads can have corresponding effects on voters’ affective responses to the subjects and, in the case of negative advertising, the sponsors of the ads); Chingching Chang, The Impacts of Emotion Elicited by Print Political Advertising on Candidate Evaluation, 3 MEDIA PSYCHOL. 91 (2001) (arguing that positive and negative print ads evoke emotions that in turn affect candidate evaluation in line with the positive or negative valence of the emotion); see also Richard R. Lau, Lee Sigelman, Caroline Heldman & Paul Babbitt, The Effects of Negative Political Advertisements: A Meta-Analytic Assessment, 93 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 851, 857 (1999) (finding based on meta-analysis of studies examining negative political ads that such ads decrease positive affect for the target of the ad but decrease it even more for the ad sponsor). But see Robert G. Meadow & Lee Sigelman, Some Effects and Noneffects of Campaign Commercials: An Experimental Study, 4 POL. BEHAV. 163 (1982) (finding that presentation of television ads did not appreciably affect voter assessment of candidate qualities along certain dimensions or their vote choice). 80 154 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 attitudes toward the candidate, though the tone of the advertisement may influence its effects.32 Despite these reported effects of political advertising, it is far less clear whether or how these effects translate into different voting behaviors or political outcomes.33 At the aggregate level, there is a fair amount of early research, particularly the work of Professor Gary Jacobson beginning in the 1970s and 1980s, suggesting that campaign spending by incumbents does not tend to increase their share of the vote, while campaign spending by challengers does.34 However, this finding has been increasingly criticized recently on several grounds. One criticism notes that, insofar as candidates can be expected to behave strategically, increases in vote share are not necessarily an appropriate measure of the effects of campaign spending on results in firstpast-the-post, winner-take-all elections, where margin of victory is far less important than victory itself.35 Another notes that empirical research underlying the finding omits key variables (such as the contested nature of a race, the relative cost of media across districts, and background partisan identifications within a district), likely skewing the results; significantly, studies that attempt to control for these missing variables find a more reliable correlation between spending and vote share.36 In short, through refinement of methodologies, 32. Atkin & Heald, supra note 31, at 225-26 & n.23 (finding that repeated advertising increases recipients’ positive affective response to the sponsor, except where the tone of the advertisement is negative); cf. ANSOLABEHERE & IYENGAR, supra note 30, at 91-94 (reporting experimental results showing that negative ads can benefit their sponsor, particularly in general as opposed to primary elections, but that this effect is heavily mediated by pre-existing party affiliation, with increased conservatism correlating to increased receptiveness to negative ads). 33. See generally James N. Druckman, Does Political Information Matter?, 22 POL. COMM. 515 (2005) (exploring the relevance of political information and communications where the effects of such information on voter behavior are unclear); cf. ANTHONY DOWNS, AN ECONOMIC THEORY OF DEMOCRACY 238-59 (1957) (arguing that voter ignorance is rational in light of the insignificance of any single vote to the outcome of an election and the costs of obtaining political information). But see MICHAEL X. DELLI CARPINI & SCOTT KEETER, WHAT AMERICANS KNOW ABOUT POLITICS AND WHY IT MATTERS 218-67 (1996) (arguing that voters’ level of political knowledge does influence their political behavior in measurable ways, with repercussions for democratic society, such that increasing voter knowledge is normatively desirable). 34. See generally, e.g., Gary C. Jacobson, Money and Votes Reconsidered: Congressional Elections, 1972-1982, 47 PUB. CHOICE 7 (1985). 35. See Alan S. Gerber, Does Campaign Spending Work? Field Experiments Provide Evidence and Suggest New Theory, 47 AM. BEHAV. SCIENTIST 541, 560-69 (2004). 36. See Thomas Stratmann, Some Talk: Money in Politics. A (Partial) Review of the Literature, 124 PUB. CHOICE 135, 136-41 (2005); see also Stratmann, supra note 22, at 1060-61; Daniel R. Ortiz, The Empirics of Campaign Finance, 78 S. CAL. L. REV. 939, 940-43 (2005); Alan Gerber, Estimating the Effect of Campaign Spending on Senate Election Outcomes Using Instrumental Variables, 92 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 155 empirical research in political science is moving from demonstrations of modest and ambiguous correlations of campaign spending to aggregate election outcomes toward more rigorous demonstrations of aggregate spending effects. However, it should be noted that the size of these effects, while statistically significant, is relatively small: one recent study concludes that $100,000 worth of television advertising at median rates corresponds with only a fraction of a percent change in vote shares in federal legislative elections.37 Despite the growing consensus in the political science community that aggregate spending effects exist, the mechanism of those effects is still an area of emerging research in the field.38 Longstanding conventional wisdom has doubted the ability of campaign communications to directly and immediately persuade voters to change their candidate preference,39 and the political science community is just beginning to seek out alternative individualvoter-level mechanisms of campaign effects. Some argue that campaigns serve primarily to energize or demobilize particular voters, and much research in the past dozen years has focused – inconclusively – on the role of negative or “attack” advertisements in this dynamic.40 Debate has also devel401, 409-10 (1998); Thomas Stratmann, How Prices Matter in Politics: The Returns to Campaign Advertising, 140 PUB. CHOICE 357 (2009) [hereinafter Stratmann, Prices]. Other studies suggest that advertising tends to persuade low-information voters more than high-information voters. See generally, e.g., Nicholas A. Valentino, Vincent L. Hutchings & Dmitri Williams, The Impact of Political Advertising on Knowledge, Internet Information Seeking, and Candidate Preference, 54 J. COMM. 337 (2004). 37. See Stratmann, Prices, supra note 36, at 368-71. 38. See, e.g., Gerber, supra note 36, at 410 n.29 (“Exactly how campaign spending leads to more votes is an ongoing research question.”); David A.M. Peterson, Uncovering the Mechanism: How Campaigns Matter and Why 3 (Apr. 20, 2006) (unpublished manuscript, presented at the annual meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association), available at http://www.allacademic.com/meta/p137445 _index.html (“We do know that campaigns matter . . . . We do not, however, know how campaigns matter; the mechanism that individuals are influenced by is unknown.”). 39. See generally HOLBROOK, supra note 29, at 1-19 (summarizing the early line of research supporting the view that individual voting behavior is determined primarily by prevailing economic conditions, party identification, and satisfaction with incumbent performance). 40. Compare generally, e.g., Stephen Ansolabehere, Shanto Iyengar & Nicholas Valentino, Does Attack Advertising Demobilize the Electorate?, 88 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 829 (1994) (reporting experimental findings that negative campaign advertisements decrease intentions to vote), with Ken Goldstein & Paul Freedman, Campaign Advertising and Voter Turnout: New Evidence for a Stimulation Effect, 64 J. POL. 721, 723-28 (2002) (finding that statistical analysis of the likelihood of exposure to negative political advertising suggests that such ads actually stimulate turnout), and Kim Fridkin Kahn & Patrick J. Kenney, Do Negative Campaigns Mobilize or Suppress Turnout? Clarifying the Relationship Between Negativity and Participation, 93 81 156 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 oped as to whether and how campaign ads might affect voters’ candidate knowledge and preferences. On this front, researchers have divided into at least two camps. One group of scholars argues that campaign advertising can indirectly influence voter decisions (and thereby, in the aggregate, election outcomes) by “priming” the electorate – setting the agenda by establishing in voters’ minds the relevance of certain criteria that are then used to measure the suitability of candidates.41 Another faction argues that campaign messages influence ultimate votes by fostering “on-line” or “running tally” updates of an overall affect-based candidate preference that persists even after the information that caused the updated preference has faded from memory.42 In AM. POL. SCI. REV. 877 (1999) (distinguishing between appropriately presented negative information and mudslinging attacks and finding that the former mobilizes while the latter demobilizes). For retrospective analyses of the debate, see, e.g., Valentino, Hutchings & Williams, supra note 36, at 338 (summarizing scholarship on both sides); Lau, Sigelman, Heldman & Babbitt, supra note 31, at 857-58 (concluding based on a meta-analysis of many reported and unreported studies that negative political ads do not appear to depress political participation). Much of the debate over these effects centers on the proper methodology for measuring voter exposure to campaign messages and the adequacy of available data sources. See, e.g., Goldstein & Freedman, supra, at 723-28 (discussing methodological issues and problems of survey data and other available data sources); Shaw, supra note 29, at 346-47 (contrasting experimental and survey methodologies for measuring campaign effects). Other research in this vein has attempted to identify whether particular campaign activities are effective in mobilizing voters to go to the polls. See generally, e.g., Alan S. Gerber & Donald P. Green, The Effects of Canvassing, Telephone Calls, and Direct Mail on Voter Turnout: A Field Experiment, 94 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 653 (2000) (testing the effectiveness of various methods of voter outreach); D. Sunshine Hillygus, Campaign Effects and the Dynamics of Turnout Intention in Election 2000, 67 J. POL. 50 (2005) (finding that advertising and personal contacts tend to increase participation by voters who did not initially intend to vote, while contacts from party and interest group organizations maintain the intent to vote among those who already had the intent to do so). 41. See, e.g., Iyengar & Simon, supra note 29, at 157 (arguing in favor of the existence of priming effects); James N. Druckman, Priming the Vote: Campaign Effects in a U.S. Senate Election, 25 POL. PSYCHOL. 577 (2004) (arguing in favor of the existence of priming effects based on a comparison of exit poll results and media campaign coverage). In the face of long standing scholarly consensus that there is no direct persuasive effect of campaigns on vote choice, the priming model can be understood as an effort to demonstrate changes in voter preferences as a second-order effect: priming is “tantamount to indirect persuasion in that altering the criteria [by which candidates are evaluated] can alter the choice.” Iyengar & Simon, supra note 29, at 157. 42. See Milton Lodge, Marco R. Steenbergen & Shawn Brau, The Responsive Voter: Campaign Information and the Dynamics of Candidate Evaluation, 89 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 309 (1995) (setting forth this model of campaign effects and voter preference formation). A related and somewhat inverted account framed in terms of learning rather than affect is described in Gabriel S. Lenz, Learning and Opinion Change, Not Priming: Reconsidering the Evidence for the Priming Hypothesis, 53 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 157 each of these areas of research, political science scholars are still in the early steps of trying to identify the mechanisms by which campaigns might influence voter beliefs, attitudes, and behavior.43 As they do so, they are beginning to explore terrain already charted (at least preliminarily) by the psychology and marketing literatures. B. How Does Campaign Spending Work? As the search for campaign effects turns to focus on more nuanced questions about voter psychology at the individual level, it is beginning to pick up on the strong role played by affective and emotional responses in judgment tasks.44 As discussed below, repetition plays a key mediating role in this relationship. The study of the relationships among affect, repetition, and judgment, first identified in the general psychology literature, has crossed over to the marketing literature, where an understanding of the psychological basis of belief, persuasion, and decisionmaking has significant practical applications. Both of these literatures, in turn, have recently begun to influence the political sphere, which over the last few decades has been cross-pollinated with the tools of psychology45 and mass marketing.46 This Section describes AM. J. POL. SCI. 821 (2009) (arguing that studies purporting to show priming effects are better explained as demonstrating the updating of voters’ policy preferences to comport with new knowledge about their preferred party’s or candidate’s position on an issue). 43. See, e.g., Peterson, supra note 38, at 6-8 (noting that studies focused on campaign effects at the level of the individual voter have generally not examined the psychological mechanism of campaign effects). 44. See generally, e.g., GEORGE E. MARCUS, W. RUSSELL NEUMAN & MICHAEL MACKUEN, AFFECTIVE INTELLIGENCE AND POLITICAL JUDGMENT (2000) (setting forth a model of political judgment and behavior based on affective responses, particularly responses to emotional states of anxiety, enthusiasm, and anger); Ted Brader, Striking a Responsive Chord: How Political Ads Motivate and Persuade Voters by Appealing to Emotions, 49 AM. J. POL. SCI. 388 (2005) (reviewing the literature on the role of affect in political judgment and behavior and arguing, based on an experimental study, that emotional cues such as music and images in political ads can cause changes in judgments of candidates and in motivation to participate in the political process); George E. Marcus, Emotions in Politics, 3 ANN. REV. POL. SCI. 221 (2000) (reviewing research into the role of emotion in political evaluation and judgment); Jack Glaser & Peter Salovey, Affect in Electoral Politics, 2 PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. REV. 156 (1998) (reviewing the state of research into the role of affect in politics and suggesting future research directions). Some of the most current research in this vein suggests that such emotional aspects of campaign messages may spur updating of voters’ “running tally” candidate preferences. Brader, supra, at 401. 45. See, e.g., POPKIN, supra note 27, at 72-95 (reviewing aspects of the cognitive psychology literature and applying it to campaign effects). 46. See generally Margaret Scammell, Political Marketing: Lessons for Political Science, 47 POL. STUD. 718 (1999) (describing the development of political marketing as a field of scholarly inquiry); HANDBOOK OF POLITICAL MARKETING (Bruce I. 82 158 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 some relevant findings in psychology and marketing that are just beginning to be explored by political scientists. Psychology researchers have concluded that choices and judgments are often made heuristically based on automatically generated valences of positive or negative affective responses.47 Put simply, we choose what we like, and only after we have decided do we retroactively try to rationalize our decision.48 Marketing researchers have similarly concluded that such affectdriven judgments are major determinants of consumer choice.49 Drawing on Newman ed., 1999) (collecting scholarship on political marketing theory and practice). 47. See Daniel Kahneman & Shane Frederick, Representativeness Revisited: Attribute Substitution in Intuitive Judgment, in HEURISTICS AND BIASES: THE PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT 49, 57 (Thomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin & Daniel Kahneman eds., 2002) [hereinafter PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT] (“Affective valence is a natural assessment, and therefore a candidate for substitution in the numerous situations in which an affectively loaded response is required.”); Paul Slovic, Melissa Finucane, Ellen Peters & Donald G. MacGregor, The Affect Heuristic, in PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT, supra, at 397 (describing the affect heuristic and the empirical data from which it is inferred); Shane Frederick, Automated Choice Heuristics, in PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT, supra, at 548, 553 (describing the use of the affect heuristic as a means of generating choices without deliberate reasoning). This author and others have previously extended cognitive psychology research into heuristic judgments based on affect to legal issues concerning advertising, trademarks, and consumer protection; much of the discussion in this paragraph and the next is duplicative of the author’s prior work. See Jeremy N. Sheff, The (Boundedly) Rational Basis of Trademark Liability, 15 TEX. INTELL. PROP. L. J. 331, 358-61 (2007) (discussing applicability of research into the affect heuristic to debates about the purpose and scope of trademark law); see also Jon D. Hanson & Douglas A. Kysar, Taking Behavioralism Seriously: The Problem of Market Manipulation, 74 N.Y.U. L. REV. 630, 732 (1999) (“[O]ur affective responses to products more often than not determine the purchasing decision, regardless of whether we experience the decision as having resulted from ‘reasons.’”). 48. See Frederick, supra note 47, at 550; see also R. B. Zajonc, Feeling and Thinking: Preferences Need No Inferences, 35 AM. PSYCHOLOGIST 151, 155 (1980) (“Quite often ‘I decided in favor of X’ is no more than ‘I liked X.’ . . . We buy the cars we ‘like,’ choose the jobs and houses that we find ‘attractive,’ and then justify those choices by various reasons . . . .”). 49. See generally, e.g., Girish N. Punj & Clayton L. Hillyer, A Cognitive Model of Customer-Based Brand Equity for Frequently Purchased Products: Conceptual Framework and Empirical Results, 14 J. CONSUMER PSYCHOL. 124 (2004) (formulating and empirically testing a model of brand equity that is dominated by affectively laden “global brand attitude” and “brand heuristic” as first- and second-level determinants, respectively, of consumer decisionmaking); Tim Ambler, Sven Braeutigam, John Stins, Steven Rose & Stephen Swithenby, Salience and Choice: Neural Correlates of Shopping Decisions, 21 PSYCHOL. & MKTG. 247, 248 (2004) (summarizing research suggesting that emotion and feelings are the primary drivers of consumer decisionmaking). But see id. at 257 (noting that brain imaging neither supported nor refuted neurophysiological predictions of one theorist of emotion-based choice). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 159 this work and supplementing it with original research, political scientists over the past twenty years have proposed and tested decisional models based on heuristic cues and affective responses.50 The growing interest in heuristics, and particularly affect, as determinants of political behavior should not be surprising in light of the lowinformation, low-attention conditions of American democratic politics. “[P]eople are not accustomed to thinking hard, and are often content to trust a plausible judgment that quickly comes to mind.”51 Affective reactions, like heuristics generally, are less cognitively demanding than logical thought processes.52 Moreover, implanting affective associations is an extraordinarily easy task.53 Such associations are also persistent: once a stimulus has been tagged with affective value, later contrary information about the stimulus’s actual semantic meaning will often be insufficient to significantly alter the affective response.54 Indeed, when we rely on any heuristic judgment in our 50. See generally, e.g., POPKIN, supra note 27; MARCUS, NEUMAN & MACKUEN, supra note 44. 51. Kahneman & Frederick, supra note 47, at 57-58 (“[P]eople initially believe whatever they are told. . . . [I]t takes some time and mental effort to ‘unbelieve’ such dubious statements.”). Cf. generally Christian D. Schunn, Lynne M. Reder, Adisack Nhouyvanisvong, Daniel R. Richards & Philip J. Stroffolino, To Calculate or Not to Calculate: A Source Activation Confusion Model of Problem Familiarity’s Role in Strategy Selection, 23 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL.: LEARNING, MEMORY & COGNITION 3 (1997) (demonstrating that people tend to retrieve answers to problems from memory rather than calculate them through logical reasoning when the problem appears familiar to them). 52. See Steven A. Sloman, Two Systems of Reasoning, in PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT, supra note 47, at 379, 380-84 & tbl.22.1, 393-94 (arguing that “associative” reasoning such as heuristic judgment is an automatic form of cognitive processing, to be distinguished from “rule-based” reasoning, which governs more formal logical analysis and requires more taxing deliberate sequential processing). But see Gerd Gigerenzer & Terry Regier, How Do We Tell an Association From a Rule? Comment on Sloman (1996), 119 PSYCHOL. BULL. 23 (1996) (critiquing Sloman’s dual-system theory on grounds of ambiguity, vagueness, and failure to consider alternative explanations of data). 53. As an illustration of our unconscious susceptibility to affective content, consider a study that showed that flashing an affectively charged image (a smiling or frowning face) for 1/250th of a second immediately prior to the display of a stimulus was enough to bias the test subject’s preference for that stimulus, even though the affectively charged “priming” cue was so brief that there was no recognition or recall of it. Slovic, Finucane, Peters & MacGregor, supra note 47, at 401 (citing P. Winkielman, R. B. Zajonc & N. Schwarz, Subliminal Affective Priming Resists Attributional Interventions, 11 COGNITION & EMOTION 433 (1997)). This effect persisted even when the stimulus was later presented with an affectively opposite “priming” cue. Id. 54. For example, in one experiment test subjects were given an affectively charged definition for Chinese pictograms, then told that those definitions were inaccurate and asked to memorize “accurate” affectively neutral definitions for the same 83 160 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 decisionmaking, as political scientists argue is the case for the majority of American voters, it takes considerable time and effort to alter those judgments based on further, more rational consideration, if we can alter them at all.55 Heuristic responses based on affect are also heavily mediated by repetition. Studies show that simple familiarity with a stimulus increases positive affective response to it.56 In other words, the more often we are merely exposed to a stimulus, the stronger our affective response to it will be and the more likely we will be to prefer it.57 This “mere exposure” effect may help to explain research findings that repetition of positive campaign messages increases positive attitude toward their sponsor58 and that increased exposure of the electorate to a candidate’s name increases that candidate’s vote share.59 It pictograms. Id. Even after the new affectively neutral meanings had been learned, the test subjects continued to exhibit the earlier affective reaction to the pictograms. Id. 55. See Hanson & Kysar, supra note 47, at 646-54 (discussing a host of empirically demonstrated phenomena illustrating the general principle that initial judgments are extremely persistent, even in the face of contradictory or ambiguous hard data). Surprisingly, attempts at rationalization may actually serve to increase confidence in a faulty intuitive judgment, a phenomenon known as confirmation bias. See id. at 64750, 660-62; Nicholas Epley & Thomas Gilovich, The Anchoring-and-Adjustment Heuristic: Why the Adjustments Are Insufficient, 17 PSYCHOL. SCI. 311, 312 (2006) (“[P]eople evaluate hypotheses by trying to confirm them.”). This dynamic is prevalent in political learning as well. Brendan Nyhan & Jason Reifler, When Corrections Fail: The Persistence of Political Misperceptions (Apr. 22, 2009) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www-personal.umich.edu/~bnyhan/nyhan-reifler.pdf (finding that voters tend to try to fit new information into their preexisting ideological views and not only discount information inconsistent with those views but actually rebel against such information, hewing to their original views even more strongly than before encountering the new information). For a general overview of the empirical and theoretical underpinnings of the confirmatory bias, see Hanson & Kysar, supra note 47, at 647-50. 56. Frederick, supra note 47, at 553-54; see also Ambler, Braeutigam, Stins, Rose & Swithenby, supra note 49, at 253-54 (discussing experimental results showing significant correlation between brand familiarity and selection of the brand and quicker decisionmaking when faced with a familiar brand than with unfamiliar brands). 57. Slovic, Finucane, Peters & MacGregor, supra note 47, at 400 (“[W]hen objects are presented to an individual repeatedly, the ‘mere exposure’ is capable of creating a positive attitude or preference for these objects.”); see also, e.g., Robert F. Bornstein, Exposure and Affect: Overview and Meta-Analysis of Research, 1968– 1987, 106 PSYCHOL. BULL. 265 (1989) (reviewing studies that document the “mere exposure effect”). 58. See supra notes 31-32 and accompanying text. 59. See generally Paul E. Schaffner, Abraham Wandersman & David Stang, Candidate Name Exposure and Voting: Two Field Studies, 2 BASIC & APPLIED SOC. PSYCHOL. 195 (1981). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 161 also suggests that the ability to repeat a campaign message or secure repeated exposure for a political candidate has real potential to skew the results of an election in favor of a campaign that leverages that ability. More generally, repetition threatens the integrity of political decisionmaking by increasing the susceptibility of low-information, low-attention voters to factual error. With all due respect to Justice Holmes, it turns out that the ability of a thought to get itself accepted in the market is not necessarily a very good test of the empirical truth of that thought. To the contrary, the acceptance of a proposition can be manipulated by processes having little or nothing to do with empirical truth, key among them repetition. Thirty years ago a group of experimental psychologists discovered that, simply by repeating a plausible proposition two or three times, they could impart to their hearers significantly increased confidence in the truth of that proposition, regardless of its actual truth or falsity.60 Since then, other psychologists have investigated this “illusory truth effect”61 and found it to be robust, though its underlying causes remain a matter of some debate.62 Not only does repetition strengthen the belief that a proposition is true, but it also strengthens the belief that the proposition is widely considered to be true.63 Such belief, in turn, reinforces belief in the truth of the proposition, as we are more inclined to believe that a proposition is true if we believe that it is accepted by a large number of people.64 Moreover, strength of belief in the truth of a proposition 60. Lynn Hasher, David Goldstein & Thomas Toppino, Frequency and the Conference of Referential Validity, 16 J. VERBAL LEARNING & VERBAL BEHAV. 107 (1977). For a more recent and rigorous demonstration of this effect, see generally Ian Maynard Begg, Ann Anas & Suzanne Farinacci, Dissociation of Processes in Belief: Source Recollection, Statement Familiarity, and the Illusion of Truth, 121 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCH.: GEN. 446 (1992). 61. This effect is referred to variously in the literature as the “truth effect,” Scott A. Hawkins & Stephen J. Hoch, Low-Involvement Learning: Memory Without Evaluation, 19 J. CONSUMER RES. 212, 215 (1992); the “reiteration effect,” Ralph Hertwig, Gerd Gigerenzer & Ulrich Hoffrage, The Reiteration Effect in Hindsight Bias, 104 PSYCHOL. REV. 194, 194-95 (1997); the “repetition effect,” Kimberlee Weaver, Stephen M. Garcia, Norbert Schwarz & Dale T. Miller, Inferring the Popularity of an Opinion From Its Familiarity: A Repetitive Voice Can Sound Like a Chorus, 92 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 821, 827 (2007); and the “illusory truth effect,” Jason P. Mitchell, Chad S. Dodson & Daniel L. Schacter, fMRI Evidence for the Role of Recollection in Suppressing Misattribution Errors: The Illusory Truth Effect, 17 J. COGNITIVE NEUROSCI. 800, 800 (2005). This Article will use the latter term to encompass all these labels. 62. For a summary of the experimental results and theories concerning the cause of the illusory truth effect, see Anne L. Roggeveen & Gita Venkataramani Johar, Perceived Source Variability Versus Familiarity: Testing Competing Explanations for the Truth Effect, 12 J. CONSUMER PSYCHOL. 81, 82-84, 90 (2002). 63. See generally Weaver, Garcia, Schwarz & Miller, supra note 61. 64. Id. at 822. Similar effects have already been analyzed with respect to the judiciary, where lopsided panel composition can induce minority conformity to a 84 162 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 – even if based solely on the sense of familiarity that results from repetition – leads us to believe that the proposition derives from a credible source,65 and, in passing along the information to others, attribution to a credible source can increase the likelihood that the proposition will be accepted and further spread.66 This potential for cascading effects is further complicated by the fact that, like affective reactions, repetition-based beliefs are easy to implant and difficult to correct. In general, the greatest increase in truth-belief comes with just two to three repetitions, after which the effect levels off.67 Unfortunately, repetition-based belief in “Proposition X” is not likely to be dissipated by simply informing the belief holder that Proposition X is false. To the contrary, such refutations, because they require repetition of the false proposition, may actually strengthen belief in the truth of Proposition X: warnings ultimately become recommendations.68 This irony is hypothesized to result from the fact that, when we are presented with new information, we record the semantic content of the information in memory separately from information about the context in which the semantic content appeared. Over time, the contextual data fades from memory at a faster rate than the semantic content, and we cannot remember anything about Proposition X other than the fact majority position. See CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DAVID SCHKADE, LISA M. ELLMAN & ANDRES SAWICKI, ARE JUDGES POLITICAL? AN EMPIRICAL ANALYSIS OF THE FEDERAL JUDICIARY 67-69 (2006). However, the original social psychology experiments demonstrating conformity effects show that such effects deteriorate significantly when the majority belief is less than unanimous. See Solomon E. Asch, Opinions and Social Pressure, 193 SCIENTIFIC AM. 31, 35 (1955). Moreover, there is significant debate in the political science literature as to whether analogous “bandwagon” effects obtain in electoral contexts. See generally, e.g., Catherine Marsh, Do Polls Affect What People Think?, in 2 SURVEYING SUBJECTIVE PHENOMENA 565 (Charles F. Turner & Elizabeth Martin eds., 1984). 65. See generally Alison R. Fragale & Chip Heath, Evolving Informational Credentials: The (Mis)Attribution of Believable Facts to Credible Sources, 30 PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. BULL. 225 (2004). 66. Norbert Schwarz, Lawrence J. Sanna, Ian Skurnik & Carolyn Yoon, Metacognitive Experiences and the Intricacies of Setting People Straight: Implications for Debiasing and Public Information Campaigns, in ADVANCES IN EXPERIMENTAL SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY 127, 151 (Mark P. Zanna, ed., 2007), available at http://sitemaker.umich.edu/norbert.schwarz/files/07_aep_schwarz_et_al_settingpeople-straight.pdf. 67. See Scott A. Hawkins, Stephen J. Hoch & Joan Meyers-Levy, LowInvolvement Learning: Repetition and Coherence in Familiarity and Belief, 11 J. CONSUMER PSYCHOL. 1, 2 (2001). 68. Ian Skurnik, Carolyn Yoon, Denise C. Park & Norbert Schwarz, How Warnings About False Claims Become Recommendations, 31 J. CONSUMER RES. 713, 713 (2005). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 163 that it is familiar.69 Familiar information is easier to process than novel information, and the experience of facile cognitive processing gives rise to a belief in the truth of the processed information.70 As a result, our belief in Proposition X can be strengthened even if the source of the proposition or the proposition itself is discredited, and, in fact, the act of discrediting over time can reinforce belief in Proposition X’s truth by force of repetition.71 For similar reasons, the mere expression of a question as to whether a proposition is true, with the passage of time, tends to be remembered as an assertion that the proposition is true.72 Accordingly, psychologists and marketing researchers alike warn that, when attempting to refute false or misleading claims, “information campaigns should focus more on what is true than on reiterating what is false.”73 There are available countermeasures besides direct questioning or refutation of a false premise that can mitigate the illusory truth effect. For example, a repetition-based belief might be successfully countered with a message that does not repeat the challenged proposition and includes features designed for especially fluent processing, such as simple, clear presentation or mnemonic devices such as rhyme or music.74 More importantly for present purposes, greater attention to the semantic content of a message and the integration of that content with other knowledge, entailing more in-depth cognitive processing than mere passive awareness, can cause hearers to resort to preexisting knowledge and beliefs in critically assessing the truth of the message, diminishing their reliance on the sense of familiarity that gives rise to the 69. Id. at 713-15. The illusory truth effect becomes increasingly pronounced as we age, both because the decay rate of contextual memory accelerates over the course of our lives and because as we get older we are more likely to believe that new information has been encountered before. Id. at 714, 722-23; see generally Sharmistha Law, Scott A. Hawkins & Fergus I. M. Craik, Repetition-Induced Belief in the Elderly: Rehabilitating Age-Related Memory Deficits, 25 J. CONSUMER RES. 91 (1998). 70. Schwarz, Sanna, Skurnik & Yoon, supra note 66, at 149-51. 71. Id. at 151-58. While it is possible to design refutations of repetition-based beliefs, the ability of such refutations to secure popular belief or to reduce belief in the refuted claim is highly contingent on the nature of the refuted claim and the relationship between the original claim and the refutation, such that refutation efforts are not guaranteed success and have the potential to backfire. See generally Gita Venkataramani Johar & Anne L. Roggeveen, Changing False Beliefs from Repeated Advertising: The Role of Claim-Refutation Alignment, 17 J. CONSUMER PSYCHOL. 118 (2007). 72. See generally Mario Pandelaere & Siegfried Dewitte, Is This a Question? Not For Long. The Statement Bias, 42 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCH. 525 (2006). 73. Skurnik, Yoon, Park & Schwarz, supra note 68, at 723. 74. See Schwarz, Sanna, Skurnik & Yoon, supra note 66, at 153; cf. Hawkins & Hoch, supra note 61, at 223 (noting that such mnemonic devices tend to cause the greatest increases of belief in simple claims). 85 164 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 illusory truth effect.75 This more attentive and engaged cognitive processing mediates the effects of repetition, such that repeating a message more than a few times can actually cause backlash in the attentive hearer, who becomes increasingly critical of, or bored or irritated with, the repeated claim.76 Psychologists have pointed out that the use of familiarity as a cue for measuring truth is a useful heuristic insofar as most of the information we encounter is true.77 But bringing the analysis back to investigation of mechanisms by which campaigns might influence voters, it becomes apparent that this intuitive judgment can be easily exploited by repeating a claim to an audience that does not expend significant cognitive effort in evaluating that claim. In such a situation, the audience is likely to reflect elevated levels of subjective belief in the truth of the repeated claim, regardless of its actual truth or falsity. Insofar as this model of exploitation is a fair description of the typical American electoral campaign, in which a primary expense is repetitive campaign advertising broadcast over various media for consumption by an unsophisticated American electorate, equality-minded reformers may have a legitimate empirical basis to be concerned about the unequal distribution of campaign funds. It is possible that a well-funded speaker could repeat an empirically false claim that supports the speaker’s preferred policy position, thereby increasing popular acceptance of the truth of the claim and making adoption of the policy position through democratic processes more likely. 78 However, even if the aforementioned findings in the psychology and marketing literatures could be extended to political campaigns – and to date they have not been in any systematic or rigorous way – it would not necessarily follow that equalization of campaign funds is either practically feasible or normatively desirable. While others have focused on the practicality of equalizing reforms,79 the next Part will assume their feasibility and discuss their desirability. IV. A RATIONALE FOR REFORM? EVALUATING EQUALIZATION PROPOSALS Part II of this Article posed two questions to test a key assumption of equality-based campaign finance reform proposals. Part III answered the first 75. See generally Hawkins & Hoch, supra note 61; Law, Hawkins & Craik, supra note 69. 76. See Hawkins & Hoch, supra note 61, at 213-14; Hawkins, Hoch & MeyersLevy, supra note 67, at 2. 77. Skurnik, Yoon, Park & Schwarz, supra note 68, at 714. 78. Indeed, Justice Stevens appeared to come close to such a realization when he recently observed that the rule of Buckley “at best, has an indirect relationship to activity that affects the quantity – rather than the quality or the content – of repetitive speech in the marketplace of ideas.” Randall v. Sorrell, 548 U.S. 230, 280 (2006) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (emphasis added). 79. See, e.g., Issacharoff & Karlan, supra note 6, at 1708-18. 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 165 question – whether political campaigns influence the outcomes of democratic processes – in the affirmative, suggesting that campaign regulation might affect electoral and policy outputs. However, the second question – how campaigns influence the outcomes of democratic processes – is far more important to evaluating the merits (as opposed to the relevance) of equalitymotivated reform proposals. The influence of campaigns on ultimate election results is, by definition, an aggregation of campaign effects on the individual level, and such effects must be understood if they are to be manipulated by regulation. The social science research discussed above – which surely does not exhaust the entire universe of possible campaign effects on the individual level – explains several documented and potential effects of campaign activities. From an instrumentalist point of view that sees public debate as a means to the end of enlightened policy, none of these campaign effects can be considered inherently undesirable, and indeed some of them must be considered inherently desirable. As noted above80 and elsewhere,81 the ideal model of deliberative, rational political decisionmaking is undermined by the empirical finding that most American voters lack sufficient information or interest to conform to that model. Yet political advertising ameliorates the informational deficiencies of the least informed portion of the electorate, at least in absolute terms and possibly in relative terms as well82 – an apparent benefit of campaign activities for democratic processes (from the instrumentalist point of view). Similarly, while repetition of campaign messages could be misused to deceive ill-informed voters into believing false propositions or forming favorable impressions of unfavorable candidates, it could also be an efficient means of perpetuating accurate information throughout an electorate without the inclination or resources to gather that information independently.83 Moreover, even where campaign effects might be manipulated at the expense of optimal political decisionmaking, remedying those manipulations through regulation may be less effective than alternative approaches. Accordingly, instrumentalist campaign reform proposals should be evaluated in light of what we know about the likely effects of their implementation in order to determine whether they are appropriate means to their stated ends. In this spirit, this Part evaluates three equality-based reform measures – expenditure limits, public matching funds, and equal-dollars-per-voter contribution limits – in light of the campaign effects described in the previous part.84 See supra notes 24-28 and accompanying text. See, e.g., Ortiz, supra note 21, at 26-29. See supra note 30 and accompanying text. See generally Kang, supra note 24. Given the limited scope of this Article, this Part will not directly examine various campaign reform proposals that are not clearly motivated by an equality rationale, even though the critiques offered in this Part could apply with considerable force to such proposals. While this limitation necessarily omits some current topics in campaign finance law, the focus of this Article is on one particular rationale underly80. 81. 82. 83. 84. 86 166 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 A. Undoing Buckley – Expenditure Limits One potential campaign finance measure would entail the abrogation of Buckley’s contribution/expenditure distinction85 and the imposition of equalizing expenditure limits on candidates and on individuals or groups seeking to influence the outcomes of political campaigns. But a regime of finite, albeit equal, resources at the campaign level is unlikely to generate the rational, informed decisionmaking that is the ostensible end of equality-minded reform. First, as noted above, because campaign activities generally have the effect of increasing the political knowledge of low-information voters, capping the level of campaign funding below levels it would achieve in the absence of such caps will likely depress voter knowledge, increasing the disparity between actual voter behavior and the normative ideal of fully informed, rational, deliberative decisionmaking. An objection may be raised that this is precisely the point of equalizing regulation in campaign finance law: insofar as the unscrupulous but wellfunded speaker can disseminate false or misleading information, the knowledge-increasing function of campaign communications threatens to undermine the deliberative decisionmaking process by infecting it with factual error. It should be clear, though, that this objection rests on dubious assumptions. First, it assumes a correlation between amount of resources and tendency to mislead – a correlation that cannot be posited a priori. Second, to the extent that the objection rests on an argument that an asymmetric ability to disseminate false or misleading information creates an incentive to do so, the underlying causal reasoning of the assumption warrants scrutiny, and in any case it would not necessarily follow that resource equalization is normatively desirable. To the contrary, the social science findings discussed above seriously undermine the claim that resource equalization will eliminate any incentive to make false or misleading claims in political communications, and the opposite could well be true. Consider that artificially low ceilings on the financial resources political campaigns can deploy place a strategic premium on campaign tactics that have the most favorable effects on the outcome of an election for the least cost. In a world where the great majority of voters do not have much background political knowledge, do not devote significant attention to politics, and rely largely on heuristic cues rather than deliberative reasoning in making ing campaign finance reform efforts rather than a detailed critique of the entire spectrum of campaign finance reform measures. 85. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 39-59 (1976) (striking the expenditure limitation provisions of the 1974 amendments to the Federal Election Campaign Act as unconstitutional restrictions on First Amendment rights to engage in political expression); id. at 23-38 (upholding the act’s contribution limits as constitutionally permissible tools to maintain the integrity of the electoral process by preventing actual or apparent improper influence of major campaign contributors over elected officials). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 167 political choices, a rational campaign with finite resources has tremendous incentives to deploy reliable and scalable tactics such as repetitive, affectladen mass advertising. Given that campaign resources are generally finite even in the absence of expenditure limits, it is unsurprising that such tactics are prevalent in modern political campaigns, to the chagrin of champions of deliberative decisionmaking. However, mandating that campaign funding be not only finite but also equal does nothing to remove this incentive and, given the difficulties in displacing affect- or repetition-based beliefs,86 may in fact strengthen it. Nor would expenditure limits provide a check on the incentive to make false or misleading assertions in campaign communications. Campaigns in a world of equal-but-finite financing would have little incentive to expend scarce resources in an attempt to refute debatable or even false beliefs generated by their adversaries’ manipulation of repetition and affect for at least two reasons. First, such efforts stand a good chance of further entrenching the belief they are intended to refute.87 Second, given the ease of implanting affect- and repetition-based beliefs and the difficulty of dispelling them,88 the cost of refuting such beliefs is extremely likely to exceed the cost of implanting them. Together, these observations suggest that deploying affect- and repetition-based campaign messages – regardless of their objective truth or falsity – would be a dominant strategy in the game of equal-but-finiteresource political campaigning, while directly responding to such messages would be a dominated strategy. Thus, rather than exposing and deterring misleading campaign communications or encouraging rational debate and deliberation on issues of public concern, equal-but-finite campaign funding is likely to turn political debate into a zero-sum contest in which campaigns race to stake out exclusive claims to rhetorical territory and issue space.89 At a deeper level, even if expenditure limits were capable of imposing perfect equality of resources for each of the various factions on an issue of public concern, they could not remedy deficiencies in political outcomes where the source of those deficiencies lies not in the balance of campaign See supra notes 54-55, 67-76 and accompanying text. See id. See id. Indeed, a similar race is the norm in consumer product marketing, where brands generally are “positioned” to create and elicit associations along semantic dimensions that are not already the subject of associations with competitive products – because any attempt to challenge a competitor’s brand associations is unlikely to succeed. See DAVID A. AAKER, MANAGING BRAND EQUITY: CAPITALIZING ON THE VALUE OF A BRAND NAME 111-12 (1991) (“A differentiating association can be a key competitive advantage. If a brand is well positioned (with respect to competitors) upon a key attribute in the product class, . . . competitors will find it hard to attack. If a frontal assault is attempted by claiming superiority upon that dimension, there will be a credibility issue . . . . Thus, an association can be a formidable barrier to competitors.”). 86. 87. 88. 89. 87 168 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 activity but in the decisionmaking processes of voters.90 In short, if the goal of reform is to bring the results of democratic decisionmaking processes into better alignment with the results of rational, deliberative, fully informed decisionmaking processes, expenditure limits are probably the wrong tool for the job. B. Matching Funds – Raising the Playing Field Another popular equalization proposal is the allocation of public matching funds to financially disadvantaged candidates, such as those available in state “clean election” statutes91 or the “fair fight funds” provision in the recently proposed Fair Elections Now Act for U.S. Senate campaigns.92 While such measures might mitigate somewhat the avoidable information-lowering effects of expenditure limits, they suffer from the same inherent weaknesses of such limits: they do little if anything to alter the incentive to deploy efficient affect- or repetition-based campaign tactics, regardless of whether such tactics mislead.93 Once again, this incentive arises from the desire to leverage scarce resources to influence the decisions of an electorate, the largest proportion of which responds more strongly and predictably to such tactics than to any others. Matching-funds measures may indeed ameliorate the problem of only the wealthiest speakers being able to use such tactics to get their message accepted throughout the electorate (and thereby to influence the political preferences and behaviors of voters). However, these measures cannot deter any speaker from propagating false or misguided beliefs throughout the electorate, or from using affect-laden appeals to influence the preferences and behavior of voters in a way that would be inconsistent with more considered, rational judgment. Indeed, providing matching funds would likely increase the ability of speakers of modest means to deploy such tactics – which there would be a strong incentive to deploy – without any assurance that the body 90. BRYAN CAPLAN, THE MYTH OF THE RATIONAL VOTER: WHY DEMOCRACIES CHOOSE BAD POLICIES 166 (2007) (“What happens if fully rational politicians compete for the support of irrational voters . . . ? It is a recipe for mendacity.”). 91. See 16 ARIZ. REV. STAT. ANN. § 16-952 (2006) (providing matching funds to qualifying candidates participating in the public funding regime who face nonparticipating opponents exceeding the regime’s expenditure limits); ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 21-A, § 1125(9) (2006) (same). 92. Fair Elections Now Act, S. 752, 111th Cong. tit. V (2009). 93. Indeed, it is conceivable that matching regimes could generate scarcity pressures similar to expenditure limits to the extent that the availability of public matching funds decreases the incentive for private citizens and interests to expend or donate money for campaign efforts (on the theory that the donation would provide no relative, as opposed to absolute, benefit to their preferred candidate or issue). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 169 of political information made available to the electorate would correlate any more strongly to objective truth.94 Thus, to the extent that informed and rational decisionmaking is a goal we want our democratic processes to serve, matching regimes offer little benefit. At best, they might provide surplus resources that would allow for the deployment of campaign tactics in addition to repetitive, affect-laden advertising, while increasing the total volume and penetration of campaign communications (and thus the total level of information among voters). Such additional forms of communication might very well have salutary effects like increasing political participation95 and could be expected to elevate total levels of political information among the electorate somewhat,96 but by themselves they offer no mechanism either to deter campaign tactics that manipulate or mislead or to bring actual voting behavior into significantly better correlation with a deliberative, rational ideal. C. Equal Dollars per Voter – Aggregation at the Expense of Deliberation One final, more radical, equality-based campaign finance reform proposal would allocate to all citizens a fixed and equal amount of money to 94. This consequence of matching regimes may be, in the language of computer programming, a feature rather than a bug. One could argue that if our political process is fated to be influenced by non-rational behavior, potentially based on false and misleading information, then the ability to manipulate and mislead should at least be equally distributed across the economic spectrum. Such equal distribution would do nothing to increase the rationality of political outcomes or to serve any other goals of the deliberative model (and would likely undermine those goals), but it could serve other purposes – particularly to the extent that one doubts the existence of some objective rational standard by which policy outcomes can be judged or views political processes as a kind of competition over economic rents. Under the assumption that the effort to influence political outcomes is simply a competition among selfinterested interest groups to secure benefits conferred by the state, allocation of such benefits according to the preexisting distribution of wealth could be considered inconsistent with encompassing notions of equality. See Hasen, supra note 12, at 14-18. As discussed below, however, this understanding of the political process is in direct contradiction with the goal of rational political decisionmaking in a democratic society with a low-information, low-involvement electorate. See infra section IV.C. 95. For example, recent experiments suggest that face-to-face campaign contact with voters increases voter turnout and does so to a greater extent than other forms of outreach such as direct mail or telephone contacts. See generally Gerber & Green, supra note 40. To the extent that compensating canvassers is more costly on a dollars-per-voter-reached basis than paying for a direct mail or telemarketing campaign (an assumption that ignores volunteer participation in campaign activities), greater campaign resources might have the indirect effect of increasing voter turnout. See id. at 661. 96. See supra note 30 and accompanying text. 88 170 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 contribute to political campaigns as they see fit and in some cases would limit the financing of political campaigns to these funds.97 Such proposals share their justificatory reasoning with a recently overruled98 line of Supreme Court campaign finance decisions: FEC v. Massachusetts Citizens for Life,99 Austin v. Michigan Chamber of Commerce,100 and McConnell v. FEC.101 In Massachusetts Citizens, the Court suggested in dicta that regulation of the political activities of business corporations could reflect a legislative judgment that the corporate form permits the accumulation of great wealth through economic pursuits that do not necessarily correlate with popular support for the corporation’s political positions;102 in Austin the Court upheld a Michigan law embodying such regulation as a constitutional exercise of legislative judgment.103 Finally, in McConnell, the Court relied on similar reasoning (and invoked Austin as precedent) to uphold against a facial challenge a recently enacted federal statute limiting the rights of corporations and labor unions to use general treasury funds to engage in “electioneering communications.”104 This reasoning – based on the premise that, in the absence of the wealthaccumulating advantages of the corporate form, private financial contributions in the aggregate might provide a “rough barometer of public support”105 – holds that correlation of levels of campaign financing and levels of public 97. For examples of such proposals, see generally BRUCE ACKERMAN & IAN AYRES, VOTING WITH DOLLARS: A NEW PARADIGM FOR CAMPAIGN FINANCE (2002); Foley, supra note 12; Hasen, supra note 12. 98. Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, No. 08-205, slip op. at 4950 (U.S. Jan. 21, 2010) (overruling Austin v. Michigan Chamber of Commerce and so much of McConnell v. FEC as relied on Austin as precedent). 99. 479 U.S. 238 (1986). 100. 494 U.S. 652 (1990). 101. 540 U.S. 93 (2003). 102. Mass. Citizens, 479 U.S. at 258 (“Relative availability of funds is after all a rough barometer of public support. The resources in the treasury of a business corporation, however, are not an indication of popular support for the corporation’s political ideas. They reflect instead the economically motivated decisions of investors and customers. The availability of these resources may make a corporation a formidable political presence, even though the power of the corporation may be no reflection of the power of its ideas.”). 103. Austin, 494 U.S. at 658-60 (upholding a state statute that “aims at a different type of corruption in the political arena: the corrosive and distorting effects of immense aggregations of wealth that are accumulated with the help of the corporate form and that have little or no correlation to the public’s support for the corporation’s political ideas”). For the view that small-dollar, grass-roots contributions do not reflect even a “rough barometer of public support,” see SMITH, supra note 15, at 45-48 (arguing based on recent historical examples that “the ability to raise large sums in small contributions is a sign of fervent backing from an ideologically committed minority, rather than a sign of broad political support”). 104. 540 U.S. at 204-07. 105. Mass. Citizens, 479 U.S. at 258; see also Hasen, supra note 8, at 41-42. 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 171 support is normatively preferable to the absence of such correlation insofar as disparate funding can “unfairly influence elections.”106 From the moment these cases were decided, their reasoning invited criticism. Dissenting in Austin, Justice Scalia pointed out the inconsistency of that case’s holding with the principle, established in Buckley, that limiting independent campaign expenditures is constitutionally impermissible.107 This view has now won the backing of a bare majority of the young Roberts Court, which recently overruled Austin and related precedents on the ground that their underlying “antidistortion rationale” did not justify departure from Buckley in the specific case of corporate campaign expenditures.108 Despite Austin’s demise, its normative judgment concerning the appropriate relationship between wealth and political participation is and will remain axiomatic to equal-dollars-per-voter arguments.109 Adherents to this normative position have never depended on Buckley for support – and indeed have often denounced Buckley’s anti-corruption rationale as cramped and inadequate. To the contrary, such reformers view equalization of campaign resources at the level of the individual citizen as an implementation of the democratic ideal of political equality110 and further raise the instrumentalist argument that such equalization will lead to legislative outcomes that better reflect the “true dis- 106. Austin, 494 U.S. at 660. 107. Id. at 682-85 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (criticizing the Austin majority’s reason- ing and pointing out that, by its logic, there would be no constitutional barrier to restricting the political speech of wealthy individuals simply by virtue of their wealth). 108. Citizens United, slip op. at 32-50. 109. Indeed, Professor Hasen – a leading proponent of equal-dollars-per-voter reform measures – concedes that Justice Scalia’s dissent in Austin is sound but argues that this merely demonstrates the inadequacy of Buckley’s anticorruption rationale to deal with the problem of the influence of wealth on politics. Hasen, supra note 12, at 41-42 (“Justice Scalia is correct. . . . But whereas [he] concludes that the Michigan law [at issue in Austin] cannot pass muster under Buckley, I believe the better approach is to acknowledge the logical implications of the Court’s reasoning and accept political equality as an interest adequate to justify regulating campaign expenditures.”). See also Heather K. Gerken, The Real Problem with Citizens United, THE AMERICAN PROSPECT Jan. 22, 2010, available at http://www.prospect.org/cs/articles ?article=the_real_problem_with_citizens_united (“It’s not surprising that reformers are outraged. Austin has long been the darling of reformers; it’s as close as the Court has ever come to saying Congress can regulate campaign finance to promote ‘equality.’”). The analysis in this Article suggests a somewhat different critique: that the rule of Buckley, like most First Amendment jurisprudence, rests on an assumption that is empirically dubious, i.e., that “[f]actions . . . [can] be checked by permitting them all to speak, and by entrusting the people to judge what is true and what is false.” Citizens United, slip op. at 39 (internal citation omitted), citing THE FEDERALIST NO. 10 (James Madison). 110. Hasen, supra note 12, at 42-44 (discussing arguments in favor of egalitarianism as a compelling government interest). 89 172 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 tribution and weight of societal interests.”111 Whether this instrumentalist claim is supportable depends on the influence of the distribution of campaign resources on the outcomes of elections, particularly of legislative elections. As discussed throughout this Article, the reformist assumption that equalization of campaign finances will align actual voter decisions with optimal, rational decisions is flawed. The equal-funding-per-voter reform model lays bare the source of that flaw. What is the “unfair[] influence [on] elections” that resource equalization – either actual or approximate – would remedy? The instrumentalist First Amendment theory set out at the beginning of this Article suggests that the danger is divergence of voter decisions from a rational, deliberative ideal.112 The equal-dollars-per-voter proposal, however, suggests that the unfair influence to be remedied by reform is simply deviation from the preferences voters would express in the absence of the effects of campaigning. In bridging this gap, we move from the realm of First Amendment theory into the realm of democratic theory. We must, therefore, briefly consider the differences between two models of democracy: deliberative and aggregational.113 111. Id. at 31. 112. See supra notes 2-6 and accompanying text. 113. A full explanation of these two modes of thinking about democratic processes is well beyond the scope of this Article. A good collection on the deliberative model and its problems is DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY: ESSAYS ON REASON AND POLITICS (James Bohman & William Rehg eds., 1997), in which the first four selections constitute the leading expressions of the basic principles of the model. In the modern era, the aggregational model is a central subject of social choice theory, based largely on the work of Kenneth Arrow and those building on his insights. See generally KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES (2d ed. 1963); Amartya Sen, The Possibility of Social Choice, 89 AM. ECON. REV. 349 (1999) (reprinting the author’s Nobel Prize lecture outlining the history and scope of social choice theory). Each model has deep roots in Western thought. See, e.g., ARISTOTLE, POLITICS bk. 3, ch. XI (defending democratic governance on grounds that the whole body of the people can arrive at better political results than any of them individually); JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT ch. VIII, §§ 95-99 (1690) (describing the origins of civil society as the entry of individuals into a community to protect collectively their individual interests and to be governed by the will of the majority of the community even where express unanimous consent is not possible). In contemporary discourse, there is considerable debate as to whether the insights of social choice theory can be reconciled with democratic ideals, particularly deliberative democratic ideals. Compare generally, e.g., WILLIAM H. RIKER, LIBERALISM AGAINST POPULISM: A CONFRONTATION BETWEEN THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY AND THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE (Judith Wilson ed., 1982) (arguing that the axiomatic impossibility of aggregating individual preferences consistently with a meaningful conception of democratic choice makes the notion of popular will an empty concept), with John S. Dryzek & Christian List, Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation, 33 BRIT. J. POL. SCI. 1 (2003) (attempting to reconcile social choice critiques of democracy with deliberative democracy principles). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 173 The deliberative model sees democratic processes as a mechanism to engage the political community in building consensus and resolving disagreements as to the scope and content of community policy, all in pursuit of objectively (i.e., rationally) superior outcomes.114 The aggregational model, in contrast, sees such processes as a mechanism for aggregating and mediating independent and subjective individual preferences to yield a set of acceptable policies to govern the whole community.115 Much modern work in the aggregational tradition suggests that democratic processes are fundamentally inadequate to the task of producing satisfactory community policies from the individual preferences of community members.116 Regulation to ensure a correlation between the units of campaign finance and the units of voting would appear to be consistent with an aggregational agenda, protecting voter preferences against undue contamination from the persuasive activities of others with diverging preferences.117 How114. See Sunstein, supra note 13, at 1392 (“Politics should not simply register existing preferences and their intensities, especially as these are measured by private willingness to pay. In the American constitutional tradition, politics has an important deliberative function. The constitutional system aspires to a form of ‘government by discussion.’”). 115. See Hasen, supra note 12, at 8-14 (describing two key models in the aggregational tradition: interest group theory and social choice theory). 116. See generally ARROW, supra note 113 (demonstrating the logical impossibility of simultaneously satisfying basic reasonable conditions with any non-dictatorial system of aggregating preferences); Allan Gibbard, Manipulability of Voting Schemes: A General Result, 41 ECONOMETRICA 587 (1973) (same, but adding the additional dimension of the potential to game the preference-aggregation system); Mark Allen Satterthwaite, Strategy-Proofness and Arrow’s Conditions: Existence and Correspondence Theorems for Voting Procedures and Social Welfare Functions, 10 J. ECON. THEORY 187 (1975) (same). 117. See, e.g., Hasen, supra note 12, at 6-7 (touting the equal-dollars-per-voter model as providing “proper incentives and safeguards that channel self-regarding political behavior to produce fair and efficient political outcomes” and ensuring that each voter has roughly equal ability to have his or her preferences enacted into legislation). It is notable that Professor Hasen’s reliance on interest group theory and public choice theory largely ignores questions concerning changes in voters’ political preferences as a result of campaigns – treating such changes essentially as a form of market exchange. See id. at 10 & n.32 (“Politicians will attempt to maximize the votes they get by selling access, influence, or positions on legislation to the different interest groups. The interest groups pay for these goods with their political capital: either they deliver votes directly, or indirectly by manipulating public opinion; or they make campaign contributions which the politician spends on advertising to get votes herself.”) (emphasis added; footnotes omitted). Of course, votes are an expression of the voter’s political preferences, and the very notion that the influence of campaign activities on a voter’s subjective preferences has normative implications suggests the existence of an external standard by which political preferences and behaviors should be judged. If subjective voter preferences are the lodestar of political equality and the function of political processes is simply to aggregate them fairly, how those prefer- 90 174 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 ever, assuming (as reformers appear to do) that such contamination is a function of the magnitude of campaign spending, and further assuming that political preferences are not equally distributed across the electorate, equal-dollarsper-voter regimes would not truly eliminate such contamination. To the contrary, they would merely cause the net effect of such contamination to be consistent with the preexisting distribution of political preferences: they might widen the electoral margin that would have existed absent campaign activities but would not alter the electoral result. As an example, consider a pre-campaign electorate of one hundred citizens, fifty-five of whom harbor a preexisting preference for candidate Smith and forty-five of whom prefer candidate Jones. Now presume that each of the one hundred citizens has $100 to spend on campaign activities and that each citizen dedicates the full amount of her $100 to her preferred candidate’s campaign fund. This would leave Jones with $4,500 to spend and Smith with $5,500. If, as reformers appear to believe (with some support from the social science literature), higher campaign expenditures correlate to higher vote shares than would be achieved in the absence of such expenditures, the net effect of this equal-dollars-per-voter system could only be to reinforce voter preferences that existed prior to the campaign, as Smith’s ability to outspend Jones would increase Smith’s vote share to a greater extent than Jones could increase hers. Thus, all else being equal, Jones would be incapable of winning the election under an equal-dollars-per-voter system. Indeed, even if all else were not equal and there were some new information revealed over the course of the campaign that altered pre-existing preferences in Jones’s favor, the financing gap would allow Smith to mitigate that shift in preferences and potentially still win the election, even if in the absence of campaign spending the new information would have tipped the election to Jones. While this simple illustration can obviously be complicated in many ways – for example, to account for non-linear campaign effects, for varying degrees of competence across campaigns, or for intermediary campaign groups that use aggregated funds in ways that were not anticipated or intended by their donors – it suffices to demonstrate the essentially aggregational character of equal-dollar-pervoter regimes. More importantly, this example demonstrates the extent to which equal-dollars-per-voter reform proposals are likely to entrench preexisting majorities and pluralities. ences are formed should be of little concern to reformers. To the extent that the formation of subjective preferences is a concern, it would seem that the concern would have to be grounded either in some objective standard – such as the rational standard of the deliberative model – or else in a desire – perhaps even an unconscious one – to elevate the subjective preferences of the reformer over those of the voter. See supra notes 17-19 and accompanying text; cf. SMITH, supra note 15, at 139-52 (arguing, somewhat polemically, that those who argue for resource equalization “believe that some views, which they do not like, are heard too much, and others, which they prefer, are heard too little.”). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 175 This scenario is a far cry from the deliberative ideal underlying First Amendment instrumentalism, which views political processes as a means to identify and pursue the public interest. But it is equally inconsistent with an aggregational model that views political processes as a means of reconciling competing private interests. Unless we assume that pre-campaign preferences are inherently superior to post-campaign preferences (an assumption in serious tension with the propositions that campaigns provide information and that deliberation improves decisionmaking), equal-dollars-per-voter regulation would not (except perhaps coincidentally) be consistent with fully informed, rational decisionmaking. Nor would such regulation eliminate the influence of persuasive activity on subjective preferences. Rather, given the low-information and low-attention nature of the American electorate and the resulting incentives with respect to campaign tactics, equal-dollars-per-voter systems would at best amplify the distortions of pre-existing bias and political ignorance with the distortions of potentially misleading affect- and repetitionbased campaigning. V. CONCLUSION: EQUALITY VS. RATIONALITY Here we come to the crux of the problem with equality-based campaign finance reforms. As noted at the beginning of this Article, Professor Ortiz has argued that the deliberative ideal of rational decisionmaking is in tension with a commitment to absolute political equality.118 This Article suggests that these normative values are not merely in tension; they actually work at cross-purposes. Given the decisionmaking patterns of the majority of the electorate, the road of equality does not lead to the destination of rational political outcomes. Accordingly, applying egalitarian principles as the guiding framework for regulation whose end is optimal, rational, fully informed, and deliberative political decisionmaking is not merely unhelpful where most citizens are not rational or deliberative political actors; it is counterproductive. Each of the equality-based reform measures discussed above, when analyzed through the lens of social science research into campaign effects and their analogues in psychology and marketing, appears more likely to exacerbate the non-rational tendencies in our democratic processes than to ameliorate them, creating tremendous incentives for political interests to manipulate and mislead. In short, there is a tradeoff between equality and rationality in our democracy. This is not to say that equality-based campaign finance regulation can serve no purpose, nor even that it is normatively undesirable. If politics is seen as essentially a distributive exercise – the competition of subjective interests over resources – then equalization may well be desirable in decreasing the correlation between prospective distribution patterns and pre-existing 118. See supra notes 17-19 and accompanying text. 91 176 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 wealth patterns.119 Such regulation may also constitute an expressive validation by the community of the egalitarian or participatory normative commitments of our democracy, it may work to curb the appearance or even the reality of political corruption or coercion, and it may reduce rent-seeking behavior.120 But it would appear that these potential benefits of equalizing reform measures come at a cost in terms of the rationality of political outcomes. As such, it is incumbent on reformers – many of whom surely harbor normative commitments to both equality in the body politic and rationality in public policy – to decide which is the more compelling value. This dilemma is not inevitable. To the contrary, it results not from economic inequality being leveraged into political debate but from the fact that many voters do not make political decisions by means of rational or deliberative processes. Where the problem with our political outcomes lies in the nature of voters’ decisionmaking process, the proper target of reform is that process itself, not its inputs (i.e., campaign activities). To escape the normative dilemma, reformers should focus less on legislating ever more formal equality – which would only deepen the dilemma – and more on bringing voter decisionmaking processes closer in line with the rational, deliberative ideal. There are serious obstacles to such progress. One is the fact that failure to engage in rational, deliberative political decisionmaking is, in economic terms, a rational strategy. Given the low probability of any one vote affecting the outcome of an election, the subjective benefit to any one voter of gathering the information necessary to assure a rational, fully informed decision is far outweighed by the costs of gathering such information – a classic collective-action problem.121 In order to change this calculus, the individual voter’s subjective valuation of being politically active and informed must change – in welfare economics terms, the citizen must derive sufficient subjective utility from the process of gathering information and deliberating on issues of public concern to offset the subjective costs of such information gathering and deliberation. It is highly unlikely that this recalibration of subjective utility could be accomplished by legal regulation. Such preferences are more likely a product of culture. Another obstacle to increased rationality in democratic decisionmaking is the fact that even where political knowledge increases throughout the electorate – a key benefit of campaign activities according to the discussion above122 – voters’ use of that knowledge seldom accords with the dictates of reason. Voters have a tendency to discount information that conflicts with their worldview and to accept uncritically information that confirms that 119. See supra note 94 and accompanying text. 120. On this latter target for regulation of the political process, see Hasen, supra note 12, at 8-18. 121. See, e.g., DOWNS, supra note 33, at 238-59. 122. See supra note 30 and accompanying text. 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 177 worldview.123 Indeed, this tendency is so strong that efforts to correct factually inaccurate beliefs held as a matter of ideology often induce the same kind of backlash as efforts to correct factually inaccurate beliefs held as a result of repetition – they can actually increase the strength of the mistaken belief.124 Thus, simply increasing voters’ interest in politics will not do if that interest is driven by ideology; voters must develop a commitment to the deliberative process itself if that process is to yield the benefits promised by deliberative theory. Fostering such a commitment, like fostering political engagement generally, is a problem that moves beyond the design of legal rules and into deeper issues of social norms, education, and cultural change. Those who believe that our political processes and their outcomes fall short of some rational ideal would therefore seem to have limited options for remedying the situation. With regard to the problem of deterring misleading and false claims that evade correction due to the structural disincentive to engage them, one could conceive of a legal rule punishing the dissemination of such claims in political debate, though it would be difficult to square such a rule with current First Amendment jurisprudence.125 With regard to the problem of unscrupulous manipulation of the campaign effects described in this Article, reformers dissatisfied with the policy outcomes generated by 123. See generally Kari Edwards & Edward E. Smith, A Disconfirmation Bias in the Evaluation of Arguments, 71 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 5 (1996) (finding that people tend to evaluate new information inconsistent with their prior beliefs by trying to disconfirm the new information); Charles S. Taber & Milton Lodge, Motivated Skepticism in the Evaluation of Political Beliefs, 50 AM. J. POL. SCI. 755 (2006) (same, but also finding a tendency to seek out information that confirms prior-held beliefs); see also Ilya Somin, Knowledge About Ignorance: New Directions in the Study of Political Information, 18 CRITICAL REV. 255, 260-62 (2006) (noting that the biased interpretation of political information makes sense if the interest of the political “fan” is not necessarily to become a better voter but to increase his or her enjoyment of politics); CAPLAN, supra note 90, at 114-65 (arguing that biased interpretation of information is a rational response to the structure of democratic processes and discussing the implications of this “rational irrationality” for political outcomes in democratic societies). 124. Compare Nyhan & Reifler, supra note 55 (finding such a backlash effect in response to efforts to correct mistaken beliefs that are tied to political ideology, particularly among conservatives), with discussion supra notes 67-73 and accompanying text. 125. See, e.g., N.Y. Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 271 (1964) (“Authoritative interpretations of the First Amendment guarantees have consistently refused to recognize an exception for any test of truth – whether administered by judges, juries, or administrative officials – and especially one that puts the burden of proving truth on the speaker.”). But see Brown v. Hartlage, 456 U.S. 45, 60-61 (1982) (reversing a judgment voiding a local election under a state law forbidding certain false claims by political candidates, but apparently reaching its result by weighing the First Amendment policy of free and robust political debate against the state’s interest in protecting the political process against factual inaccuracy, with particular emphasis on the speaker’s state of mind). 92 178 MISSOURI LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75 such manipulation could certainly dedicate themselves to manipulating campaign effects in furtherance of their preferred policies. Of course, this would imply a considerable level of cynicism in reformers to the extent they harbor normative commitments to either rational policymaking or deliberative democracy. As an alternative to such unworkable or unpalatable options, this Article suggests that reformers should set their sights not on the campaign finance system but on the American citizen – and on raising the baseline level of political interest, engagement, and perspicacity – in the hopes of diminishing the effectiveness of tactics that encourage and leverage non-rational political decisionmaking. In this regard, this Article closes with two final observations from the social science literature. First, of the most common forms of voter mobilization techniques, the technique with the strongest effect on political engagement as measured by voter turnout is face-to-face contact between a door-todoor canvasser and a voter: we respond more strongly to in-person appeals than impersonal, mass appeals by telephone or direct mail.126 Second, over the course of the late twentieth century, as political participation steadily declined, there was a similar decline in Americans’ participation in voluntary civic organizations: people grew less and less likely to congregate over issues of public or community concern as democratic politics consolidated and became professionalized.127 Reading these results together suggests that the solution to the normative dilemma presented by this Article may very well lie not in a magic bullet of campaign finance regulation, but in the organic process of engaging with our neighbors and building civic communities. In the end, faults in the outcomes of our political processes are likely to lie not in our laws, but in ourselves. The process of sifting through various arguments and preferences to arrive at a policy to govern the community inevitably has its winners and its losers. While the idea of a skewed playing 126. See Gerber & Green, supra note 40, at 661 (“[F]alling rates of voter turnout [likely] reflect a decline in face-to-face political activity.”). Indeed, awareness of the comparative advantage of more personal forms of political interaction may be a driving factor behind more recent non-equality-oriented reform measures, such as the BCRA’s regulation of broadcast electioneering communications during the period of weeks preceding an election but not electioneering communications through nonbroadcast media. Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 § 201, Pub. L. No. 107155, 116 Stat. 81, 88 (2002) (codified at 2 U.S.C. § 434(f) (2006)). 127. See generally ROBERT D. PUTNAM, BOWLING ALONE: THE COLLAPSE AND REVIVAL OF AMERICAN COMMUNITY (2000); Theda Skocpol, Voice and Inequality: The Transformation of American Civic Democracy (APSA Presidential Address), 2 PERSP. ON POL. 3 (2004). This view of declining American civic participation has been critiqued by some who argue that Americans’ civic engagement has actually increased, albeit through support of professionalized activist lobbying groups representing citizens’ political interests rather than through direct citizen participation in civic activities and institutions. See generally, e.g., JEFFREY M. BERRY, THE NEW LIBERALISM: THE RISING POWER OF CITIZEN GROUPS (1999); see also id. at 164-67 (specifically addressing the argument in PUTNAM, supra). 2010] THE MYTH OF THE LEVEL PLAYING FIELD 179 field may give comfort to those who believe in the rightness of their cause but find themselves on the losing end of political processes, the social science literature suggests that such discontents have inverted the causal link between the influence of campaign activities and the nature of the political process. It may simply be that such disgruntled political players, faced with the descriptive failures of the normatively attractive deliberative ideal, have a basic distaste for the nature of the political game itself. Nevertheless, to the extent that we both value electoral democracy as an instrument of policy development128 and want our social policies to be rational and based on accurate information, attempting to control the flow of information through law appears less likely to fulfill our goals than cultivating a culture where the use of that information by voters is more likely to conform to the dictates of the deliberative model. Of course, this process of civic and cultural reform may seem utopian. But the difficulty – even the impossibility – of mitigating the effects of ignorance, irrationality, and falsehood on our political processes is no argument in favor of legal regimes that will exacerbate those effects. Sadly, in this process of cultural change the lawyer, the legislator, the academic, and the lobbyist enjoy no comparative advantage over any other citizen and thus have less of an incentive to engage in the serious and inefficient work of forming the personal and civic relationships that can increase political engagement and enforce deliberative norms than they might have to construct a legal regime to regulate money in politics. But this lack of professional advantage is perhaps a truer expression of political equality than the formal notions of equality motivating many resource-equalizing campaign finance reform proposals. 128. At least one scholar of voter irrationality has apparently decided that the best policy response to it is a significant curtailment of democratic processes – and of the franchise. CAPLAN, supra note 90, at 197-99. 93