Isaac de Pinto (1717–1787): An Enlightened Economist and Financier José Luís Cardoso and António de Vasconcelos Nogueira The name Isaac de Pinto does not appear as an entry in The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, which was published in 1987. The equivalent nineteenth-century dictionary dedicates just a few brief lines to Pinto to mention, with a certain air of disdain, that his main work “contains many sound and ingenious ideas, but he is rarely quoted except for the extravagance of his paradoxes” (Coquelin and Guillaumin 1854, 2:405). A search for this author in the index of any manual or general work on the history of economic thought will prove fruitless, unless we include the inevitable footnote that Joseph Schumpeter (1954, 237) could not avoid making. Pinto’s main work, Traité de la circulation et du crédit, was originally published in 1771 in French and had a limited circulation. The subsequent editions were aimed at a very restricted public capable of Correspondence may be addressed to José Luís Cardoso, ISEG, Technical University of Lisbon, Rua do Quelhas 6, 1200–781 Lisbon, Portugal; e-mail: jcardoso@iseg.utl.pt. António de Vasconcelos Nogueira is affiliated with the University of Aveiro, Portugal. Preliminary versions of this article were presented at the Iberian meetings on the history of economic thought in Granada in December 2003; at the annual conference of the European Society for the History of Economic Thought in Treviso in February 2004; and at the conference “French Political Economy: 1650–1850,” at Stanford University in April 2004. We are grateful for the comments provided by the participants at these conferences. We would particularly like to thank Richard van den Berg, Gilbert Faccarello, Arnold Heertje, Antoin Murphy, Ida Nijenhuis, Ian Ross, Margaret Schabas, Donald Winch, and two anonymous referees of this journal for their useful and insightful comments and suggestions. The usual disclaimer applies. All translations from French, German, and Portuguese to English are ours. History of Political Economy 37:2 © 2005 by Duke University Press. 264 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) venturing into the realms of non-English languages (Amzalak 1960; Pinto [1771] 2000). The English translation (Pinto [1774] 1969) also has fairly limited availability. The main biographical account of Isaac de Pinto’s life has been explored only by erudite noneconomists (Wijler 1923; Révah 1966), while the most systematic and complete academic study on his life and work is available only to those who read Dutch (Nijenhuis 1992).1 In view of this somewhat disheartening panorama, the inevitable question must be asked: Is this author yet another victim of neglect, or does such neglect result naturally from the fact of his being a secondary and minor author? Of course, there is a wide range of studies devoted to the specific aspects of Pinto’s work—perhaps a surprisingly large number for those who think that we are talking about an illustrious unknown—to which we shall refer in due course. And there are also testimonies that reveal the impact that Pinto’s writings had on contemporary authors. Yet the inevitable doubt remains: Is it worth devoting any fresh attention to the work of this economist? In this article, we shall seek to show that it is definitely worth making such an effort. It is worth the effort not only for the opportunity of rediscovering the originality and relevance of Pinto’s writings on circulation, luxury, credit, and public debt—the themes that have most interested the commentators on his work—but also because of the series of problems and situations that Pinto experienced as one of the characteristic figures of the Age of Enlightenment. These make it possible for us to better understand the economic and financial matters that he chose to deal with. One of the central issues of Pinto’s biography is how he moved from being someone with a successful career in financial affairs to someone with a literary career who engaged in a permanent and lively discussion with his contemporaries about economic, philosophical, and political matters. Isaac de Pinto enjoyed close relationships and engaged in direct dialogue with writers such as Hume, Voltaire, Diderot, and Mirabeau. His texts are spaces of conversations and debates with such authors as Pierre de Boisguilbert, the Abbé de Saint-Pierre, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Ferdinando Galiani, George Berkeley, Josiah Tucker, and Abbé de Guillaume-Thomas Raynal, to mention just some of the best-known people whose influence Pinto expressly acknowledged in his work, or whom he 1. See also Nijenhuis 2003, which offers an excellent summary in English of Isaac de Pinto’s biography. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 265 specifically opposed. The possibility of improving our knowledge of this ongoing dialogue that Isaac de Pinto maintained with some of the most important figures of the European Enlightenment is more than enough reason to make this fresh attempt to reconstruct his career as both an economist and a financier. This article is designed to provide an integrated approach to the legacy of this somewhat neglected figure in the history of economic, philosophical, and political thought in the second half of the eighteenth century. After a brief biographical note, the article proceeds with an overview of the various topics Isaac de Pinto wrote about, namely Jewish questions, games and speculation, the tax system, luxury goods, freedom of trade, national debt, public credit, and colonies. An attempt is also made to link these bits and pieces together, in order to offer the reader a complete appraisal of Isaac de Pinto’s life and work. We will necessarily come across the interpretations of some specific points already put forward by a few other scholars. It is not our purpose to critically assess those interpretations, nor even to offer any alternative ones. We deliberately follow an overall, general approach trying to make sense of the several particular features that one may find in the writings of Isaac de Pinto. We believe this is the best way to rescue his life and work from oblivion. Given the nature of the problems addressed by Pinto, a better knowledge and awareness of his contributions is particularly welcome among the community of historians of economics. We hope this article will also provide a new background and a useful starting point to allow for a deeper analysis of each of the topics emerging from the reading of his texts. Biographical Sketch and Context Born in 1717, Isaac was one of the three children of David Pinto, one of the richest members of the Amsterdam Sephardic community in the first half of the eighteenth century. Just like many other Jewish families of Portuguese origin who had fled from the Inquisition, the Pinto family passed through the cities of Bordeaux, Antwerp, and Rotterdam before settling in Holland’s most important commercial and financial center.2 The Pintohuis, which even today is an important landmark in Amsterdam’s historic center, is the most obvious and permanent sign of 2. For an overall presentation of Isaac de Pinto’s genealogy, see Pinto [1681] 1975, a manuscript by Isaac de Pinto’s grandfather. 266 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) the dimension and success of the golden period enjoyed by the Pinto family.3 Isaac de Pinto followed in his father’s footsteps and took up his financial business, becoming one of the most widely respected figures in the political and financial life of Amsterdam and being particularly active until the end of the 1750s. Isaac’s marriage to Raquel Nunes Henriques, a descendant of another rich and important family of Portuguese Jews who had settled in Amsterdam, enabled him to consolidate his prestigious position in the hierarchy and network of the Jewish community. He was a director as well as a shareholder of both the Dutch East India Company and the Dutch West India Company. He attained the directorships in 1748 and 1749, respectively, thanks to the prestige that he had achieved as an adviser and supporter in financial matters to the Stadholder William IV of Orange. Pinto also made a colossal loan to England from his own resources for the sum of 6.6 million pounds (representing roughly 22 percent of the total English public debt). Pinto had first-hand knowledge, then, of the practices followed in the creation of public debt through government securities, which was certainly of great use to him in developing his arguments in the 1771 Traité de la circulation et du crédit. The crash that occurred in the Dutch West India Company at the end of the 1750s, and the consequent financial loss to Pinto, led to a significant change in his public career, as he sought to carve out a niche for himself as a philosopher and a man of letters. After 1761, Paris was to become the city where he would seek out his next contacts and triumphs. Thanks to his earlier services and the good relationship that he enjoyed with the House of Orange, he was involved in the peace negotiations between France and England that resulted in the signing of the Treaty of Paris, in 1763, which put an end to the Seven Years’ War. Isaac de Pinto played a decisive role in changing some of the clauses of the treaty, to the benefit of English trading interests—particularly those of the East India Company. This was to prove crucial for the development of his career, for two interconnected reasons. First, this achievement provided him with a lifelong pension of 500 pounds paid by the East India Company on behalf of the English government. Second, in order to obtain such a pension, Pinto established a direct contact with David Hume, who 3. Other places owned by the Pinto family in Amsterdam included the summer house Tulpenberg in Oudekerk and another mansion by the Herrengracht Canal. See Wijler 1923, 12, 15. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 267 at the time held the position of chargé d’affaires at the British embassy in Paris. The details that Hume has left us about his meetings with Pinto clearly reveal the pressure and insistence with which Pinto achieved his aim, recalled by Hume with subtle irony.4 Yet they also reveal that there was some mutual sympathy and understanding between the two men.5 Some years later, Pinto was to say that when these meetings took place in Paris, between 1763 and 1764, he talked at length and showed Hume the preparatory materials for his Traité de la circulation et du crédit. Regardless of any impact and direct influence that may have occurred, there is no doubt that Isaac de Pinto would always fondly remember his personal relationship with David Hume, as we shall see when discussing his proposals about public finance. Returning to Holland in 1765, after passing through England to settle matters relating to his pension, Pinto devoted himself to the preparation and publication of the writings that will be analyzed in the ensuing sections of this article. He died in 1787, at the age of seventy, without leaving any direct descendants. Jewish Questions The close contact and the hierarchical and paternal role that Isaac de Pinto enjoyed with the Jewish community of Amsterdam are clearly demonstrated in the very first text that he published, in Portuguese, in which he pointed out possible solutions for the difficult financial situation affecting the Jews of Iberian origin in particular (Pinto 1748). Poverty was a condition that beset a considerable section of the Sephardic community 4. In discussing this curious episode in the relationship between Hume and Pinto, it is hard to resist reproducing the letter in which Hume ([1764] 1932, 423) declares to the secretary of the ambassador Lord Hertford: “Manifold have been the persecutions, dear Sir, which the unhappy Jews, in several ages, have suffered from the misguided zeal of the Christians, but there has at last arisen a Jew capable of avenging his injured nation, and striking terror into their proud oppressors; this formidable Jew is Monsr. De Pinto, and the unhappy Christian, who is chiefly exposed to all the effects of his cruelty, is your humble servant. He says, that you promised to mention him to me; I do not remember that you did: he says that he has done the most signal services to England, while the Duke of Bedford was Ambassador here; I do not question it, but they are unknown to me: he says that he is poor and must have a pension for his reward; I wish he may obtain it, but I cannot assist him. . . . This, dear Sir, is a very abridged account of the dialogue which passes every day between M. Pinto and me, that is, every day when he can break in upon me, and lay hold of me.” 5. On the relationship between Hume and Pinto and for a detailed analysis of Hume’s letters and Pinto’s search for his pension, see Popkin 1970, 1974. 268 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) that, for political and religious reasons, found that access to economic activities capable of providing means of subsistence was barred to them.6 Pinto basically proposed two measures. First, he suggested encouraging roughly one-third of the poor population to set sail for the Dutch and English colonies in the West Indies, namely Suriname, Curaçao, Jamaica, and Barbados. Sponsors of such a measure, he said, would not need to worry about the cost of this diaspora, since less money would be needed in the future for charitable activities and public assistance in Amsterdam. Furthermore, the cost of the travel expenses could be repaid by the beneficiaries themselves, once they had settled into profitable activity in the promised lands. The second measure that Pinto proposed was that the Jewish community set up an accumulation fund (increase fund, to use the author’s expression) destined to provide assistance to the poor and needy. In this way, Isaac de Pinto revealed his belief that poverty was an inevitable, permanent circumstance in the Jewish community. The fund was to have a diversified composition, consisting of capital and accruing interest from subscriptions, income transfers from the slaughterhouse, legacies and taxes paid to the Jewish community, and the levying of monetary fines. The skillful and rigorous management of this fund would make it possible to overcome situations of vulnerability and urgency, while at the same time guaranteeing the peace of mind of the community as a whole. Isaac de Pinto went on to point out other solutions that would certainly have more consistent effects, such as obtaining permission to install a large factory that could absorb the work of 300 to 400 people. But this type of measure required a reformed attitude from the authorities about both the dignity and the social and political health of the Portuguese nation that had settled in Amsterdam. Of particular note is that Pinto tried to find solutions for his community’s problems, at a time when the success of his career demonstrated that the condition of being a Jew was not a stigma that made it impossible for him to enjoy a dramatic rise in the social hierarchy of the Amsterdam financial market. Moreover, his 1748 Reflexões políticas [Political Reflections] is important for the way in which it reveals and heralds 6. It is not our purpose to address here the economic problems affecting the Portuguese Jewish community (usually referred to as the Portuguese nation) in Amsterdam. This context is, however, crucial for understanding the networking of the Jewish community in economic and financial activities. For a detailed survey, see Bloom [1937] 1969. For a discussion of issues concerning the community’s identity and organization, see Bodian 1997. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 269 interesting facets of the author’s philosophical, political, and financial thought. See, for example, the way in which he presented his conception of social order and public virtue, arising from individual efforts and interests: Whenever noble incentives were lacking to impel men to contribute to the public good, private interest and self-respect would excite them, for prudence has taught them how much their own preservation depends thereon. The various interests are reconciled and combined through the reciprocal convenience between the diverse members of society, which produces the harmony in which good order consists. (Pinto 1748, 1) This idea of the spontaneous harmony of private interests will be seen to be crucial for understanding the economic and financial phenomena later posited by the author. Equally important is the way in which he denounces the inadequate fulfillment of the duties of public positions, stating that “the abuses committed in the administration of public affairs are normally attributed to the ministers, who, in order to satisfy their personal interests, sacrifice those of the public, which is ordinarily the victim of its own passions” (Pinto 1748, 4). But Pinto most clearly expresses his idea of the bold mentality of an audacious businessman prepared to take risks when he philosophizes about the circumstance of risk itself being, after all, the very essence of business: Prudence consists less in avoiding all inconveniences, than in getting to know the nature of these, choosing as a good that which is inferior to others: whoever seeks to wait for all opportunities, prepare all comforts, guard against all accidents, avoid all dangers, will either never undertake any enterprise or will have no success in the enterprise that he undertakes; which caused a famous politician to say that nothing leads more quickly into danger than the excessive care of wishing to forestall it; and, in such a case, prudence degenerates into imprudence. (Pinto 1748, 20) Undoubtedly revealing his own direct involvement in risky activities in the financial market of Amsterdam, this testimony is an integral part of a text in which he also reveals his concern with defending the interests and stability of the Portuguese nation. It is this same concern that can be 270 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) noted in the controversial debate that Pinto engaged in with two of the leading figures in the French Enlightenment, Voltaire and Diderot. The great hostility shown toward Judaism by Voltaire and other important figures of the European Enlightenment has not gone unnoticed by the scholars of the period, especially when seen in the light of the relationship between religion and the intellectual and scientific movement (see Hertzberg 1968 and Sutcliffe 2000). The philosophical cult of tolerance did not involve any concessions on the part of Christianity to the domain of pagan culture, nor did it diminish the intellectual and social isolation of members of the Jewish religious culture (see Gusdorf 1972, 157–68). The Jews who were contemporaries of Voltaire clearly understood that they were stigmatized and reacted against the predominant spirit of the time. Isaac de Pinto played an important role here, for it was under his influence and pressure that a collection of letters addressed to Voltaire by Portuguese, German, and Polish Jews was published in 1769, according to the publisher of the eighth edition of this work (Guénnée [1769] 1817). The collection includes two letters written by Pinto, serving as an advertisement for his Apologie pour la nation Juive, which had been published as a leaflet in 1762 and which was again printed in this volume.7 Pinto defended the honor of the Jewish nation, both Sephardic and Ashkenazi, against Voltaire’s abuse of their character. Voltaire said bad things about them all indiscriminately, making no distinction about their habits, customs, or capacities for adapting to the different social environments in which they were forced to live. But what most upset and disturbed Pinto was the way in which Voltaire depicted the supposed ignorance of the Jews at the scientific level and their lesser importance in literary and artistic spheres (see Nijenhuis 1993). Voltaire replied courteously to Pinto, admitting that he might have been wrong in confusing the whole with the parts. But the ironic tone with which he ended his short missive clearly explains what he was actually thinking: “Remain a Jew, for this is what you are. . . . But be a philosopher, that is the best that I can wish for you in this short life” (Guénnée [1769] 1817, 18). Or, in other words, it was not his condition as a Jew that would prevent Pinto from entering the republic of letters, however arduous the path might be. If any doubts still existed about 7. It is in one of these letters that Pinto provides details of his direct contacts with Voltaire in Holland (Guénnée [1769] 1817, 17). Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 271 Voltaire’s opinion of the Jews, various entries later published in his Dictionnaire philosophique were to corroborate his belief that “it is a singular example of human stupidity that we have for so long regarded Jews as a Nation that taught everything to the others” (Voltaire [1764] 1964, 25). Nor did the contacts that Isaac de Pinto had with Diderot contribute to the rehabilitation of the Jews among the leading figures of the French Enlightenment. In the posthumously published account of his travels through Holland, Diderot ([1782] 1982) relates his meetings with Pinto and his visit to the Portuguese synagogue in Amsterdam. But what Diderot wrote about Pinto is not flattering. Having learned of some love affairs in which Pinto had been involved, both in Holland and Paris, Diderot depicted Pinto as a man of dissolute habits who sometimes had to pay the price of his debauchery both to the courts and to the police: “This Jew Pinto, whom we met in Paris and the Hague, has passed two or three times through the clutches of the magistrates; and despite his old age I do not yet believe him to be safe from this accident. . . . The debauchery of married men is severely punished. It cost Pinto two hundred ducats” (Diderot [1782] 1982, 77, 92).8 What motivated Diderot to give this testimony at a time when the frequenters of salons seemed relatively unconcerned about the infamy or immorality of liaisons dangereuses? Perhaps Diderot bore a certain grudge against Isaac de Pinto for the tone of the open letter written to him by the latter and published in 1767 (Pinto [1767] 1960)—six years before Diderot began his travels around Holland. Games People Play A letter that Isaac de Pinto wrote to Diderot about a game of cards is one of his most intriguing and curious texts. The choice of Diderot as his addressee was perhaps a way of criticizing some traits of the Puritan mentality about games of chance. Quoting Diderot himself, Pinto attacks the idea that passions might destroy the human spirit and that gambling might be included in an ignoble category of human activity. His thesis was a defense of the virtues of the card game as a universal form of entertainment, contributing to a change in European customs. 8. See Nijenhuis 1992, 20–21. 272 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) Some exaggeration and irony are to be noted in Pinto’s writing, so it is therefore not surprising that the letter to Diderot ends with a postscript in which other causes for these changes are explained: namely, the abolition of the feudal regime, the discovery of America, the renewal of commercial life, the invention of the printing press, and advances in science and knowledge, as well as the declining influence of the Machiavellian spirit in political life. Yet the importance of the game of cards was not just in the opportunity it afforded to turn the weapons of irony and parody on Diderot. Indeed, the metaphor of gambling is used by Pinto to show the existence of strategies employed by players who are aware of situations of rivalry, dispute, and competition, but who are nonetheless willing to establish amusing and civilized forms of social interaction: The magic of the game of cards forms a common seat for almost all the passions in miniature . . . : the game seems to establish an illusory equality between the players; it is the vehicle that brings together the most discordant individuals in society; greed and ambition are its motives; the universal taste of pleasure flatters itself into being satisfied by this amusement. (Pinto [1767] 1960, 234) This vision of gambling as an activity that generates different forms of social participation is, after all, the explanation for the insistence with which the word game is used by Isaac de Pinto to describe economic and financial situations. Special attention should be given to the way in which he presents and analyzes the games played by shareholders and speculators, in the light of his own experience and knowledge of the way in which the Amsterdam stock market operated, considering that “the universal taste for gambling, which shareholders have introduced, greatly favors the facility with which loans are made” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 71–72). In other words, Pinto was in no doubt about the instrumental importance of the games played on the stock market as part of the creation of the public debt, which was a central feature of his Traité. Following in the pioneering footsteps of another Jew of Iberian origin, Joseph de la Vega,9 Pinto undertakes in his 1771 Traité de la circulation et du crédit an analysis of the “main elements of a game that seems to me to influence the political system of Europe” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 210). He concentrates his attention upon transactions in the options and 9. Joseph de la Vega’s Confusion de confusiones ([1688] 1939) is a lively description of financial operations at the Amsterdam stock market in the late seventeenth century. See Cardoso 2002. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 273 futures markets, through which players and investors in the stock market agree among themselves on processes for delaying the realization of promises and contracts for the buying and selling of shares. The use and management of time, the prolonging of promissory agreements, the calculation in advance of the interest to be charged, the expectations that shares might rise or fall in value—in other words, the mysteries and magic of the stock market—are the themes that Pinto discusses in a separate section of his Traité, which he titled Tableau ou exposé de ce qu’on appelle le commerce, ou plutôt le jeu d’actions en Hollande [Tableau or Exposition of What in Holland One Calls the Trade or Game of Shares]. It was certainly these reflections that lay at the origin of the epithet that Marx applied to Isaac de Pinto when he called him the “Pindar of the Amsterdam stock market” (Marx [1867] 1970, 165). Just as the ancient lyrical poet of Thebes had celebrated in choral lyrics and odes the feats and glories of the Olympian games, Pinto is seen, in Marx’s bitter irony, singing and celebrating the less noble vicissitudes of the games played on the stock market. Taxes People Pay Among the themes discussed by Isaac de Pinto in the Traité, it is important to stress the attention that he paid to matters of a fiscal nature. The starting point for his incursions into this area was the critique that he made of the taxation system proposed by Mirabeau and, although no express mention is made of them, by other epigones of the physiocratic school. Writing in a period when the physiocrats were intensely active and influential in French circles, Pinto never showed himself to be either influenced or impressed by the economic doctrine and analysis put forward by François Quesnay and his disciples. However, Pinto’s disagreement with the members of that school was only on fiscal matters, and there is no further sign of any opposition to the theoretical basis offered by the physiocrats as regards the notion of the exclusive productivity of agriculture and the need to implement policy measures that would preserve the source of wealth. Despite the fact that he enjoyed fond memories of his brief encounter with Mirabeau (Pinto [1771] 1960, 33), Pinto considered Mirabeau’s reflections and proposals on fiscal policy and his system of rural philosophy to be inadequate. Pinto’s criticism was directed above all at the Theorie de l’impôt (Mirabeau [1760] 1972), in which a defense had been 274 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) made of the well-known and controversial view of the physiocrats about the advantages of a single tax on landed property. Pinto’s condition as a former representative and defender of the Jewish community in Amsterdam—to whom direct access to landed property was denied—may explain his lack of interest in learning more about the means to increase agricultural production. He could not derive his proposals for tax reform from an economic system based on the primacy of land and agriculture, because he did not believe in such a primacy. His keen concern with matters of a fiscal nature naturally arose from his ideas about the importance of the system of public debt. Fulfillment of the state’s obligations to its creditors and the establishment of a climate of trust among most economic agents required tax revenue to be collected on an ongoing basis. Mirabeau’s ideas earned Pinto’s agreement when Mirabeau spoke of impeding the immunity and privilege extended to some landowners. But Pinto did not accept the principle of a single and exclusive tax on this sector: Based on reasoning that is confirmed by experience, I boldly venture to suggest that the project that has seduced so many people, namely that of reducing all taxes to one single tax by way of capitation, abolishing all other taxes and excise duties, is a fanciful dream in countries such as France, England, and Holland; one finds that it was completely impossible to levy on the public sums that the state needed, by any means other than through a taxation on objects of consumption, which is confused with the price of things. This is the least harmful and the only possible means. (Pinto [1771] 1960, 115)10 Pinto draws a distinction between essential consumer goods and luxury consumer goods, considering this distinction to be fundamental for establishing a scale and hierarchy of priorities for the application of fair principles in taxation: “The source of productions, land, the first harvests, must bear the least burden, and the progress of taxes must follow the detail of consumption, being increased on luxury goods” (127). 10. It should, in fact, be noted that this critical distancing of himself from Mirabeau also represented an opportunity to make a more general criticism of the ideas of the physiocrats, whom he accuses of engaging in “agriculture mania” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 131): “This principle of regarding the product of the land as the only source of wealth, has seduced quite a number of people, and it is absolutely false, as is the second principle arising therefrom, that taxes must be established at the source of production: a maxim that is destructive to cultivation of the land and opposed to the aims of its author” (125). Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 275 But Pinto’s most original and controversial idea in matters of fiscal policy is his proposal for the elimination of the capital tax known as belasting, which was levied on the shares of the East India Company. This was a fixed tax per share which, due to the fluctuation in the value of shares, could be highly punitive for those holding capital in the company at times when there was a fall in the stock market. In order to present this proposal of a fiscal shock, Pinto resorted to a justification supported by analogies from nature: All taxation, which destroys and annihilates a mass of these values, or which diminishes the specie money, is contrary to finance: it is akin to attacking the roots of the plants that one is interested in preserving: it is to clip the wings of birds that are meant to fly: in a word, it is to cut down the tree by its trunk in order to pick the fruit therefrom. (239) Pinto’s economic arguments in defense of the abolition of this tax, and its respective replacement by a tax on the consumption of spices originating from the West Indies, clearly show his view of the importance of the financial market of Amsterdam and the agents operating therein. The losses arising from the existence of the belasting tax did not only affect the shareholders of the company. Also involved here was the decrease in the state’s tax revenue due either to the expatriation of capital or the fall in expenditure on luxury goods that were subject to high levels of taxation. From Pinto’s own words, we can understand how he judged that the losses of shareholders represented a loss for the nation as a whole: Now, this active force having been weakened, all the resources of this class diminish in proportion. The misfortunes and losses that the company suffered were more considerable and more catastrophic to the fortune of the shareholders, as a consequence of this oppressive charge, than one had ever felt in more prosperous times. Capital and interest having also been reduced most prodigiously, this led to the ruin of a large number of private individuals, several of whom experienced the sad need to settle abroad, which had a notable influence on the lower classes. It is therefore as clear as day that the state’s revenue must have felt the effects of so many reductions in consumption, or even the total suppression thereof, since this is the source of finance. (239) Exemption of shareholders’ capital from taxation and a tax on luxury consumer goods were therefore the fiscal policy measures most favored 276 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) by Pinto. The former is a clear consequence of the vested interests of a member of the financial community who wanted to avoid such a tax and was trying to pass it on to the merchant community. The latter shows Pinto’s willingness to criticize the physiocrats on the basis that indirect taxes would be easier and would bring more justice than a system based on a direct impôt unique [single tax]. The problem of the taxation of luxury goods deserves further explanation, in view of the importance that Pinto gave it in his work. The Luxury Question Isaac de Pinto’s preference for a tax on luxury consumption necessarily involved weighing up the inherent advantages and disadvantages, as well as considering luxury as a problem that aroused the interest of moral and political philosophers. The eighteenth-century debates on the question of luxury were a response to the large increase in both the production and circulation of new commodities. The products of new industries and the rise in the consumption of luxuries are signs of the development of a new material culture and a new pattern of consumer behavior and desire in enlightened Europe (see Berg and Clifford 1999). Pinto was naturally touched by this matter, to which he dedicated an essay in French (Pinto [1762] 1960) that was later translated into English and published in 1766. Admitting the existence of controversy among different authors about the significance of the phenomenon of luxury—among whom Pinto quoted Melon, Montesquieu, Mirabeau, and Hume—Pinto developed a concept based on the historical relativity of luxury. In his view, the willingness to accept luxury would depend on the level of development, the degree of wealth, enjoyed by the inhabitants of a country and also on the existing patterns and habits of consumption. Thus, the same goods in different countries might or might not be liable to classification under the category of luxury goods. In Pinto’s own words: What is a ruinous luxury in one country might perhaps be useful or indifferent in another. A destructive and indecent luxury in one order of society is honorable, indispensable, and useful in another: and, finally, in the same country, where a certain luxury is necessary, there may be times when sumptuary laws are necessary. (Pinto [1762] 1960, 222) Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 277 Despite this relativism, Pinto leaves us in no doubt about his condemnation of excessive luxury and the processes of imitation that occur in developed societies, in which an attempt is made to pass off as necessary and indispensable that which is, after all, superfluous, accessory, or useless. He condemns luxury as pernicious and harmful, and seems to share the negative judgment of luxury that at the time persisted in France as well as in other European countries. Excessive luxury is therefore prejudicial to society, a factor leading to decadence in states, an element that encourages the corruption of national habits and the eclipse of virtues, a habit that “softens one’s body and weakens one’s courage” (223). The moral tone of these considerations sets them apart from defenses of luxury as the representation and legitimate exercise of private vices, or at least from Mandeville’s claim about the benefits of luxury and his refutation of the usual objections to it. Yet this emphasis does not take precedence over the economic nature of Pinto’s approach to the question (see Popkin 1976), which undoubtedly represented an important step toward subverting the conventional wisdom on the moral dangers of luxury. In fact, Pinto’s concern with condemning excessive luxury basically sought to call for a reorientation of the expenditure made on consumption by classes with higher levels of income, whose demand thus enhanced the value of the sectors of activity producing goods for universal consumption. In this respect, he seems to follow the arguments of the physiocrats as to the need to reduce the expenditure on goods belonging to the category of luxe de décoration [opulent luxury].11 For Pinto, the problem of excess consumption of luxury goods would not be resolved in a lasting manner through prohibitive sumptuary laws, as Adam Smith would also put it fourteen years later. Pinto wanted to demonstrate the advantage of giving greater incentives to an increased production of essential consumer goods, since such increased production would sustain and accelerate the circulation of wealth. The important thing was not that a few people should consume high-priced products that were used for ostentatious purposes, but rather that many people should consume commonly needed goods at a moderate price. Pinto was therefore to state in his Traité: 11. Pinto’s distinction between luxe de décoration and useful luxury is welcomed by Vandermonde ([1795] 1994, 396), thus revealing the widespread and positive appraisal of Pinto’s reflections on the theme. 278 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) It is continual, permanent, sustained, stable, and daily expenditure that maintains this circulation: whereas excessive luxury, by provoking a disturbance in the manifold resources of private individuals, causes their source to dry up; circulation and industry suffer from this. The specie money held by a great number of private individuals is annihilated by enforced luxury; this specie money is not to be found spread among the public, as was erroneously imagined. This is the nub of the question. I do not condemn expenditure, or the relative luxury that is made available to the resources of individuals; but that which confuses states, which makes so many citizens the victims of misunderstood opinion. (Pinto [1771] 1960, 106) This assessment and critique of luxury on economic rather than moral grounds is worth emphasizing. By focusing the analysis on the working of the commercial society, Pinto added original arguments in favor of the “de-moralization” of luxury, without which a modern conception of luxury could never be obtained (see Berry 1994, 101–76). Laissez Circuler Consumption involves the circulation of created wealth. The importance that Pinto attaches to circulation—which in this case refers not only to the stimulus given to mass consumption, but also to the acceleration given to monetary circuits and the easy access afforded to means of payment—is one of his most significant contributions in the field of economic analysis. Fairly important in this regard was the influence that Pinto admits to from his reading of Boisguilbert’s works. His reference to the Détail de la France (Boisguilbert [1695] 1966) leaves no room for doubt: “Of all those works that have come to my attention, this is the one text whose ideas came closest to mine on the subject of circulation. I even find myself forced to say that it is the only work where I have found clear notions expressed about this matter” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 152). What Pinto found most attractive in the writings of Boisguilbert was his analysis of the processes of circulation in the real and monetary spheres of the economy, whose development would depend on the improvement in the processes for the allocation of available resources. For a late-seventeeth- to early-eighteenth-century author such as Boisguilbert, making the monetary circuits and the flows of goods function more Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 279 efficiently meant ridding the nation of the whole set of obstacles and barriers, not only administrative and fiscal, but also social and political, that had been raised against the full development of the internal and external market (see Faccarello 1986). In the mid-eighteenth century, the protests that had accumulated in the economic literature (which obviously included the invaluable contribution made in such matters by François Quesnay and his followers) of the Enlightenment about the deficient functioning of the economic and social structures of the ancien régime found an obvious and natural response in Isaac de Pinto’s work. The problem of the external market and the commercial relationships between nations was a natural theme for discussion. Pinto dedicated a remarkable text to it in the Traité, in which, paraphrasing expressions that were current in the literature of that time, he demonstrated that the international order could not resign itself to the spirit of the jalousie du commerce. This section of the Traité was written in the form of a letter, addressed to an unidentified recipient. Its basic idea was that the fundamental interests of trading nations may converge for the conservation and enhancement of mutual benefits. “A chain in the interests of trade” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 170) and “a connectedness of inseparable interests” (172) are, for example, expressions that clearly convey this idea. Contradicting the logic of mercantilist literature—which was highly favorable to the demonstration of the possibility and need for the hegemony and predominance of one nation over others—Pinto considered that international trade is a game in which those taking part share advantages in a proportionate and balanced manner. Admitting that there may momentarily be some inequality between nations, he did, however, strive to argue that it would be absurd and unfair for each nation to seek to gain exclusive advantages or excessive privileges. When Pinto wrote this text, Hume had already demonstrated, through recourse to the famous price-specie flow mechanism, the impossibility of a nation’s maintaining a permanent trade deficit or surplus, due to the elementary causal relationship occurring between the level of the money supply, the internal level of prices, and the competitiveness of national products in relation to the outside world. He therefore concludes, in his essay Of Money ([1754] 1985, 283), that “there seems to be a happy concurrence of causes in human affairs, which checks the growth of trade and riches, and hinders them from being confined entirely to one people; as might naturally at first be dreaded from the advantages of an established commerce.” 280 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) The conclusion Hume reached through the use of economic reasoning had also been presented in terms that were perhaps more political and philosophical by authors such as the Abbé de Saint-Pierre and JeanJacques Rousseau—whose works are referred to and used by Isaac de Pinto—in order to guarantee the integrity of the European borders.12 The vision of doux commerce and perpetual peace does not, after all, seek to achieve anything more than the creation of a favorable environment for the “harmony of the political picture of a commercial Europe” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 185). In fact, Pinto shows himself to be particularly receptive to this optimistic view of the possibility of building peace between European nations, a peace that would be a fundamental condition for increasing wealth and prosperity. If this were the case, what sense would there be in each nation seeking to gain advantages for itself in its commercial relationship with other parties? Pinto replied to this question by demonstrating a remarkable Europeanist spirit, saying, “As Europe is a family or a body composed of several members, none can be destroyed without the others suffering” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 169). At the economic level, Isaac de Pinto showed himself to be in favor of reducing import duties and encouraging greater openness and freedom in international trade.13 The greater the freedom of internal and external circulation, the greater the order, harmony, and equilibrium that would prevail among the different domains, aims, and protagonists of economic activity. Thus, “in a great kingdom, agriculture, trade, manufactures, circulation, public credit, interior police, finance, the state of war, the colonies, shipping, the navy, moderate luxury, everything must proceed in a reciprocal proportion, in order to preserve the harmony of the state, as well as the good order and prosperity of a nation” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 163). This is one of the concluding passages of the Traité and clearly expresses its author’s concerns about a series of themes relating to order and social equilibrium that had aroused his interest in his opening text in 1748. 12. On the role played by the writings of the Abbé de Saint-Pierre in the formation of the economic culture of the Enlightenment, see Perrot 1992, 38–58. 13. This was certainly one of the subjects that led him to declare his admiration for the work of Galiani (who was equally critical of the unconditional opening up of an economy to the outside), in whose work he admitted to having read “excellent, useful, luminous, profound and instructive” things (Pinto [1771] 1960, 164). Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 281 National Debt and Public Credit Among all the commentaries about and specific approaches to Isaac de Pinto’s work, attention is inevitably focused on his analysis and strong support of the system of national debt that prevailed in England in the mid-eighteenth century. Thanks to the modernity of its financial institutions and instruments after the creation of the Bank of England in 1694, Isaac de Pinto’s model country had managed to achieve a level of prosperity and development that brooked no comparison with those of more populous countries enjoying greater resources. Now, according to Pinto, such success was due to the system of indebtedness adopted by the British Crown toward private individuals and the additional financing that it guaranteed. Although Pinto could not express it in these terms, it should be noted in his arguments that the small and large investors who lent money to the state in return for securities, which could be bought and sold and which earned interest, entered into a kind of implicit contract in which economic and financial dividends were added to the advantages of political stability that was of benefit to both parties. Pinto’s concerns with national debt were therefore motivated by his personal interest in pushing the kind of financial instrument he traded in. In the light of his past business in the trade of government securities, it is only natural that he highly praised national debt and its positive role in economic activity. The analytical perspicacity, but also the fragility, of the theoretical justifications put forward by Pinto have already been carefully analyzed in the text with which Antoin Murphy introduced the most recent edition of Pinto’s Traité (Murphy 2000).14 One need recall only three key ideas that, regardless of their conceptual appropriateness, seem to represent the essence of Pinto’s message. First, the idea that the national debt enriches the nation: “With each loan, the English government, by ceding a part of the charges that are 14. One of the most attractive features of Murphy’s text is the approach that he makes in the light of later developments in economic theory as applied to questions of credit, monetary circulation, and public finances. Although this is not the methodological approach attempted here, we cannot avoid stressing the relevance of Pinto’s text for exercises in retrospective analysis that, for example, involve the concepts of crowding out or Ricardian equivalence. In keeping with the same line of interpretation (albeit moving in a divergent direction), it should be remembered that in the period after the Second World War, Pinto’s work enjoyed a certain revival through the writings of authors with a Keynesian background, who saw in the Traité published in 1771 a powerful exemplification of the success of a deliberate policy of public deficit pursued with the aims of short-term expansion and growth. In regard to this last point, see Harris 1947, 52–59; and Oliveira 1957. 282 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) mortgaged in order to pay the interest thereon, creates a new and artificial capital that did not exist beforehand and becomes permanent, circulating to the advantage of the public, as if it were an effective cash treasure with which the kingdom has enriched itself” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 61). Second, the elementary precaution of not exceeding a maximum limit in the volume of public debt, so the debt is compatible with the economic and financial situation of a nation: “Public funds are an already realized alchemy, but the crucible must not be allowed to overflow” (74). Finally, the promise that the public debt can be alleviated when political conditions so permit, such alleviation being accompanied by a reduction in the tax burden necessary for servicing the debt: “It is absolutely indispensable, in peacetime, to settle as much as one can of the state’s debts; although too great a service would be useless and even dangerous, especially when the credit is supported on solid foundations” (78). While wishing to claim and defend the pioneering nature of his thesis about the importance of the public debt for the formation of the nation’s wealth, Pinto subsequently acknowledged other contributions made by authors whom he read only later and in whose works he found ideas that were similar to his own. He expressly states his debt to the writings of Bishop George Berkeley (1735–37) in the following terms: “I was pleased to see that Dr. Berkeley had already surmised the new truths that I develop here about the subject of the national debt” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 41). In an atmosphere of debate clearly engendered by the belief that public debt did not create wealth, expressed by authors such as David Hume (later seconded by Adam Smith), Pinto’s position had little hope of winning over public opinion. It is interesting to note the testimony made on this subject by the English translator of the Traité, Sir Philip Francis, who, for political reasons apparently related to a governmental appointment, found himself obliged to erase all traces of his personal involvement with Isaac de Pinto and renounce the authorship of the translation, preface, and notes to the English edition, substituting at the last minute the name of his cousin, the Reverend S. Baggs, for his own name.15 Although the English edition was profusely punctuated with explanatory notes in which the translator distanced himself from what he considered the author’s more outrageous theories about the virtues of the public debt, the introduction is sufficiently laudatory to justify Sir Philip’s 15. The details of this curious story are revealed by Popkin 1976, 1712, based on Philip Francis’s own memories and revelations. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 283 prudence about being associated with the Traité. The translator’s preface asserts that the subject of national debt had been treated with excessive lightness by those who upheld its disadvantages, including David Hume himself, who, if he should “be distinguished from the rest, it is not by any marks of that deep intuitive perception, with which he possesses himself of almost every other subject” (Pinto [1774] 1969, iv). It was therefore impossible to ignore opinions that contradicted the predominant way of thinking, as represented by Hume. On the contrary, it was essential to find out more about these contradictory opinions in order to better refute them or use them in a critical and reasonable manner: The doctrine maintained in the following essay on credit and circulation may, in its turn, be liable to the objection of being pushed too far; but it is a doctrine that carries consolation and encouragement along with it. Truth is usually found to mediate between the extremes. The object of the translator is to contribute something to a collection of materials, out of which a wiser and a more methodical head may hereafter form some rational system of finance. (iv) Pinto’s translator clearly shows his opposition to the violent and radical solutions put forward for the reduction of the national debt, in an unmistakable reference to the attitude of Hume with regard to this matter, for whom “either the nation must destroy public credit or the public credit will destroy the nation” (Hume [1754] 1965, 360–61). And the translator feels obliged to recognize that the national debt had brought with it a reduction in the interest rate, an increase in the value of land, an increase in capital and wealth, and an improved access of private citizens to credit. In other words, it was not possible to deny completely that there were undoubted advantages in the system that was in force, which demonstrated England’s superiority in relation to the other European nations. There was a clear awareness at the time of the importance of this debate. Smith devoted careful attention to it in the last chapter of the Wealth of Nations, seeking to demonstrate in great detail the theoretical and political error of those who defended the advantages of the national debt (Smith [1776] 1976, bk. 5, chap. 3, 47). Although he did not mention Pinto by name, Smith was surely thinking of statements made by him.16 Smith argued that the capital obtained through public borrowing was 16. And not just the example of Melon 1734, as is suggested by the editors of the Glasgow edition. It is worth noting that Smith himself seems to have possessed a copy of Pinto’s book, listed as item 1313 in the catalog of his library (see Mizuta 2000). 284 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) removed from and not added to the sum of the national capital stock, and that an increase in the circulation of money did not represent an increase in wealth.17 Notwithstanding the symbolic and authoritative weight associated both with Hume’s position and Smith’s careful justification, Pinto’s work continued to be given attentive reading and earned the moderate support of authors such as Thomas Mortimer (1772), A. Nicolas Isnard (1781), Dugald Stewart ([1809–10] 1968), and Frederic Gentz ([1800] 1803).18 Among the various commentators on and opponents of his theories, the author that presented most problems for Pinto was David Hume, given the personal relationship that the two enjoyed. Pinto expressly admitted such when he said that “Mr. Hume, whom I also refute on occasions, has provided me with more than one token of affection and friendship, for which I shall always be proud to show my gratitude” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 33), or that “I had the honor to meet him in Paris, and it gave me infinite pleasure to recognize that his character was even greater than his mind; it is to the truth that he owes such a eulogy. Some essential services that he later rendered to me in London have earned him the most legitimate rights to my gratitude” (104). Pinto also implied that such admiration was reciprocal, when he referred to the way Hume addressed him on the subject of a preliminary handwritten version of the Traité: “He was very pleased with my essay and modesty does not permit me to repeat what he said to me about it, as well as about the letter that is to be found at the end of this work to prove that the jealousy of trade is misunderstood” (104). He therefore admitted to some discomfort in contradicting an author for whom he felt the most sincere admiration. Further, and above all, Pinto recognized the enormous debt of gratitude that he owed for the role that Hume had played in guaranteeing Pinto the award of a lifelong pension for the services he rendered on the occasion of the signing of the Treaty of Paris. Such discomfort was exacerbated by the fact that Pinto learned of Hume’s essays, Of the Jealousy of Trade and Of Public Credit, only after having written the first part of his Traité. Afterward he sought to clear 17. For a more detailed analysis of those taking part in the discussion about the question of the public debt in England, of the arguments they put forward, and of how those arguments compared with those in other European countries, see Albertone 1992a, 1992b; Pesante 1992; and Winch 1998. 18. On the use of Pinto’s ideas by Mortimer and Stewart, see Popkin 1970. As for Gentz, see Perrot 1992, 455. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 285 up any doubts as to the motivations for his own writing. Pinto’s initial concern had not been to contest Hume’s negative view of the effects of the public debt. Yet, since Pinto’s thesis clearly contradicted an author whom in many other ways he admired and whose arguments he sought to develop further (in the case of the letter about the jealousy of trade), Pinto could not miss the opportunity to press on with the debate: I am persuaded that, when he wrote that essay [Of Public Credit], Mr. Hume had not yet undertaken a precise, commercial analysis of circulation, the nature of funds, and rents; he had seen some disadvantageous truths in paper money, which caused him to think of other means that were liable to correct the inconvenience thereof.19 (105) This was a subject that clearly divided the economists writing during this period, and it was the weighty opinion shared by David Hume and Adam Smith that was to triumph. Berkeley, Melon, and Pinto did not see their theories recognized by others. The time of these debates about the questions of the public debt, about the efficiency of the credit and public finance system, and about the constitutional framework of economic and financial activity would later be considered a formative moment in the modern political discourse about civic virtues and the formation of wealth, especially because of the recognition of the importance of changes in the economic and financial foundations of political life (Pocock 1975, chap. 13). By driving a wedge right into the middle of this debate, Pinto’s work ended up revealing itself as an instrument for the learning of subjects that were to challenge the established order of the prevailing economic and political discourse. Colonial Paths In one of the autonomous texts that introduce the reader to the central themes of the Traité, particularly the factors of British prosperity, Isaac de Pinto defends the idea that the colonies should play a subordinate role 19. From this, it can be seen that it was not just the question of the public debt that gave rise to his disagreement with Hume. For Pinto, it was also impossible to understand that, after recognizing the causal relationship between the increase in the representative signs of wealth (or, in other words, the increase in monetary circulation), the reduction in the interest of money, and the growth in the prosperity of industry, Hume had not deduced the unequivocal advantages of such an increase in monetary circulation (Pinto [1771] 1960, 46). As for the evolution and change in Hume’s thought due to his contact with Pinto and other enlightened French writers, see Ross 2003. 286 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) in a mother country’s economic system, although he recognizes their decisive importance in the supply of raw materials for the manufacturing sector. In his own words: “I have always suspected that an internal trade originating from a population commensurate with the extension of the land, resulting from the industry and ease of its inhabitants, is more natural, more advantageous than that of the distant colonies that take away many people” (Pinto [1771] 1960, 35–36). Some years later, however, as an act of political compromise that has sometimes been interpreted as a repayment to the English government for his lifetime pension, Pinto took a stand against American independence. In a series of published letters, he somewhat belatedly questioned the legitimacy of the rebellion (Pinto 1776b, 1776c, 1776d). Between the first and last letters, some nuances can be noted in the way in which the irreversibility of the independence of the United States is understood. However, in all the letters, there is no doubt about Pinto’s concern with demonstrating the negative consequences of the rebellion, especially at the economic level, caused by the significant loss in tax revenue. The political delicacy of the colonial question almost forced Pinto to renounce his earlier position in favor of doux commerce and perpetual peace, leading to the emergence of an attitude that was much closer to the old mercantilist arguments, whereby the colonies represented a fundamental instrument for building the economic self-sufficiency of the European nations and, consequently, strengthening and consolidating their political supremacy over potential rivals. The excessive zeal with which he defended English interests20 led Pinto to distance himself from the positions of authors who had most clearly demonstrated the inevitability of the independence of the colonies of the European powers, namely Josiah Tucker and the Abbé de Raynal. In England, Josiah Tucker was the one who best advocated the idea of a complete break between colony and colonizer, in writings dating from 1760.21 He openly championed American emancipation, because of the heavy costs of administering and maintaining that most important English colony. He believed that the superiority of English capital could make its presence felt in any part of the globe that Englishmanufactured products were able to reach, so that their hegemony would 20. The relevance of the arguments defended by Isaac de Pinto justified the prompt translation into English of his letters about the American troubles (Pinto 1776a). 21. Josiah Tucker’s most important texts about these matters were gathered together and published in Tucker [1774] 1974. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 287 lead the Americans to reestablish links with the old mother country in a way that Tucker prematurely conceived of as a privileged trading partnership. He also considered that the restrictive processes inherent in the colonial system were prejudicial to the development of trade as a whole, since they impeded the free business of a whole host of agents and interests. The Abbé de Raynal, in the work of which he was the principal mentor and author (Raynal 1770) and which enjoyed an enormous impact and widespread dissemination throughout Europe during the Age of Enlightenment, boldly denounced the inhuman humiliation of slave work and colonial exploitation. By identifying and distancing himself from the arguments of Tucker and Raynal, Isaac de Pinto finally showed himself as a conformist in one of the most decisive matters for the design of economic relations on a world scale. He resigned himself to the American rebellion, although he did not accept it readily. In this regard, his position did not differ much from the one expressed that same year by Adam Smith ([1776] 1976, bk. 4, chap. 7). Concluding Remarks Isaac de Pinto’s work was rich and varied. On matters ranging from the problems faced by the Jewish community of Amsterdam to the American colonial troubles, Pinto’s attention covered a diversified range of themes and sometimes aroused the opposition of the leading figures of the Age of Enlightenment in Europe. Pinto’s work allows us to better understand the essence of the discussion about the problems of luxury, freedom of trade, monetary circulation, and the systems of taxation and national debt. He debated these subjects with authors who merited his greatest respect and who ended up seeing their values recognized in the pantheon of the historiography of the philosophical, political, and economic thought of the Enlightenment. The naive or erroneous points of view that he put forward can only be gauged in the light of the knowledge of those debates that he engaged in with his mentors and opponents. We have tried to show that some of Pinto’s ideas on economic policy issues should be credited as pioneering—namely the critique of the physiocrats’ tax system and the vindication of the advantages of public debt creation—though he was unable to reach a reputation as an economic analyst. 288 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) A first conclusion to be drawn is that Pinto’s ideas emerged sometimes as original, other times as mere reproductions of what had already been said, and most of the time as controversial. His ideas cannot, however, be classified in a simplistic way as right or wrong, nor even as good or bad. It has been our basic concern in this article to present and discuss his ideas in context—that is, in their historical perspective, taking into account the problems and events that motivated and provoked Pinto. These were the problems and events that we have also looked to in our search for both a meaning and a coherent framework within which to place the scattered materials that were the product of Pinto’s intellectual career. Another conclusion to be drawn from the approach adopted in this article is that Pinto’s career helps us to understand the importance of life experience and practical knowledge in the formation of intellectual positions, as well as the rather tenuous frontier between political agreements, civic commitments, and doctrinal guidelines in questions of economic theory and policy. Rather than railing against the injustice of the general neglect of Pinto’s work, it is imperative to underline the importance of studying authors who are supposedly minor and secondary, which would seem to be the status that has been reserved for Pinto. This is a path that will lead to a more profound understanding of the intellectual history of economics, and, in the case of Isaac de Pinto, it will help us to better understand the context of the actions of other better-known economists, financiers, and philosophers in the Age of Enlightenment in Europe. Throughout the article we have implicitly admitted that it also is useful to have knowledge of these minor figures because they show more clearly the brilliance of their great contemporaries. In conclusion, the study of the work of Isaac de Pinto is not only a relevant undertaking to be judged on its own merits, but also a means for learning more about Hume, Voltaire, Mirabeau, or any of the other Enlightenment figures whom he met and conversed with throughout his life. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 289 References Albertone, Manuela. 1992a. Il modello della Gran Bretagna nelle discussioni francesi sul credito. In Passioni, interezzi, convenzioni: Discussioni settecentesche su virtù e civiltà, edited by M. Gena and M. L. Pesante, 469–92. Milan: FrancoAngeli. . 1992b. Moneta e politica in Francia: Dalla cassa di sconto agli assegnati (1776–1792). Bologna: Il Mulino. Amzalak, Moses B. 1960. O economista Isaac de Pinto, o seu “Tratado da circulação e do crédito” e outros escritos económicos. Lisbon: Editorial Império. Berg, Maxine, and Helen Clifford, eds. 1999. Consumers and Luxury: Consumer Culture in Europe, 1650–1850. Manchester: Manchester University Press. Berkeley, George. 1735–37. The Querist. Dublin: G. Faulkner. Berry, Christopher. 1994. The Idea of Luxury: A Conceptual and Historical Investigation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bloom, Herbert I. [1937] 1969. The Economic Activities of the Jews of Amsterdam in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries. Port Washington, N.Y.: Kennikat Press. Bodian, Miriam. 1997. Hebrews of the Portuguese Nation: Conversos and Community in Early Modern Amsterdam. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Boisguilbert, Pierre de. [1695] 1966. Le détail de la France. Paris: Institut National d’Études Démographiques. Cardoso, José Luís. 2002. Confusion de Confusiones: Ethics and Options on Seventeenth-Century Stock Exchange Markets. Financial History Review 9.2:109–23. Coquelin, Ch., and Ch. Guillaumin. 1854. Dictionnaire de l’économie politique: Contenant l’éxposition des principes de la science. Brussels: Meline, Cans et Compagnie. Diderot, Denis. [1782] 1982. Voyage en Hollande et dans les Pays-Bas Autrichiens. Edited by Yves Benot. Paris: F. Maspero. Eatwell, John, Murray Milgate, and Peter Newman. 1987. The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics. London: Macmillan. Faccarello, Gilbert. 1986. Aux origines de l’économie politique libérale: Pierre de Boisguilbert. Paris: Éditions Anthropos. Gentz, Frederic. [1800] 1803. Essai sur l’état actuel de l’administration des finances et de la richesse de la Grande-Bretagne. Lisbon: Impressão Régia. Guénnée, Abbé, ed. [1769] 1817. Lettres de quelques Juifs Portugais, Allemands, et Polonais à M. de Voltaire. 8th ed. Versailles: Imprimerie de J. A. Lebel. Gusdorf, Georges. 1972. Dieu, la nature, et l’homme au siècle des lumières. Paris: Payot. Harris, Seymour E. 1947. National Debt and the New Economics. New York: McGraw-Hill. Hertzberg, Arthur. 1968. The French Enlightenment and the Jews: The Origins of Modern Anti-Semitism. New York: Columbia University Press. 290 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) Hume, David. [1754] 1985. Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary. Edited by Eugene F. Miller. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics. . [1764] 1932. Letter to Richard Aldword Neville. In The Letters of David Hume, edited by J. T. Y. Grieg, 1: letter 229. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Isnard, A. Nicolas. 1781. Traité des richesses contenant l’analyse de l’usage des richesses en général et de leurs valeurs. . . . Lausanne, Switzerland: Chez François Grasset et Comp. Marx, Karl. [1867] 1970. Das Kapital: Kritik der politischen Oekonomie. Berlin: Dietz Verlag. Melon, Jean François. 1734. Essai politique sur le commerce. Paris. Mirabeau, Victor Riquetti, Marquis de. [1760] 1972. Theorie de l’impôt. The Hague: Scientia Verlag. Mizuta, Hiroshi. 2000. Adam Smith’s Library: A Catalogue. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mortimer, Thomas. 1772. The Elements of Commerce, Politics, and Finances, in Three Treaties on Those Important Subjects. London. Murphy, Antoin E. 2000. Introduction to Pinto [1771] 2000. Nijenhuis, Ida J. A. 1992. Een Joodse philosophe: Isaac de Pinto (1717–1787) en de ontwikkeling van de politieke economie in de Europese verlichting. NEHA ser. 3. Groningen: Reijksuniversiteit Groningen. . 1993. The Passions of an Enlightened Jew: Isaac de Pinto (1717–1787) as a “Solliciteur du bien public.” In The Low Countries and Beyond, edited by Robert S. Kirsner, 47–54. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America. . 2003. Pinto, Isaac de (1717–1787). The Dictionary of Seventeenth and Eighteenth-Century Dutch Philosophers, 2:791–94. Bristol: Thoemmes Press. Oliveira, Águedo de. 1957. As avançadas concepções de Isaac de Pinto sobre dívida pública. Boletim da Direcção Geral do Tribunal de Contas 4.12:1–58. Perrot, Jean-Claude. 1992. Une histoire intellectuelle de l’économie politique (17th– 18th siècle). Paris: Éditions de l’EHESS. Pesante, Maria Luisa. 1992. Il debito pubblico e le sue antinomie da Davenant a Smith. In Passioni, interezzi, convenzioni: Discussioni settecentesche su virtù e civiltà, edited by M. Gena and M. L. Pesante, 371–417. Milan: FrancoAngeli. Pinto, Isaac de. 1748. Reflexões políticas tocantes à constituição da Nação Judaica. Amsterdam. . 1776a. Letters on the American Troubles. London: John Boosey & John Forbes. . 1776b. Lettre de Mr. XXX à Mr. S. B., docteur en médicine à Kingston, dans la Jamaïque, au sujet des troubles qui agitent actuellement toute l’Amérique Septentrionale. The Hague: Pierre-Frédéric Gosse. . 1776c. Réponse de Mr. I. de Pinto aux observations d’un homme impartial sur sa lettre à Mr. S. B., docteur en médicine à Kingston, dans la Jamaïque, au sujet des troubles qui agitent actuellement toute l’Amérique Septentrionale. The Hague: Pierre-Frédéric Gosse. Cardoso and Nogueira / Isaac de Pinto 291 . 1776d. Seconde lettre de Mr. de Pinto, à l’occasion des troubles des colonies, contenant des réfléxions politiques sur les suites de ces troubles, et sur l’état actuel de l’Angleterre. The Hague: Pierre-Frédéric Gosse. . [1762] 1817. Apologie pour la nation Juive, ou réflexions critiques sur le premier chapitre du tome VII des oeuvres de M. de Voltaire au sujet des Juifs. In Guénnée [1769] 1817, 4–16. . [1762] 1960. Essai sur le luxe. In Amzalak 1960, 217–30. . [1767] 1960. Lettre de l’auteur à Mr. D. sur le jeu des cartes. In Amzalak 1960, 231–37. . [1771] 1960. Traité de la circulation et du crédit, contenant une analyse raisonnée des fonds de l’Angleterre et de ce qu’on appelle commerce ou jeu d’actions, un examen critique de plusieurs traités sur les impôts, les finances, l’agriculture, la population, le commerce etc. Amsterdam: Marc Michel Rey. In Amzalak 1960, 27–247. . [1774] 1969. An Essay on Circulation and Credit in Four Parts; and a Letter on the Jealousy of Commerce. Translated, with annotations, by the Rev. S. Baggs. Westmead, Farnborough, U.K.: Gregg International Publishers Limited. . [1771] 2000. Traité de la circulation et du crédit. Düsseldorf: Verlag Wirtschaft und Finanzen. Pinto, Ishack de. [1681] 1975. Assendentia de my, Ishack de Pinto, athe onde temos notisia, e genologia de meus antepassados, desde o avoo do señor meu avoo Manoel Aluares de Pinto. Studia Rosenthaliana 9.1:45–62. Pocock, J. G. A. 1975. The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Popkin, Richard H. 1970. Hume and Isaac de Pinto. Texas Studies in Literature and Language: A Journal of the Humanities 12.3:417–30. . 1974. Hume and Isaac de Pinto, 2: Five New Letters. In Hume and the Enlightenment: Essays Presented to Ernest Campbell Mossner, edited by William B. Todd, 99–127. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. . 1976. Isaac de Pinto’s Criticism of Mandeville and Hume on Luxury. Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century 154:1705–14. Raynal, Guillaume-Thomas, Abbé de. 1770. Histoire philosophique et politique des établissements et du commerce des Européens dans les deux Indes. The Hague. Révah, Israel Salvator. 1966. Généalogie de l’économiste Isaac de Pinto (1717– 1787). In Extrait des mélanges à la mémoire de Jean Sarrailh, 265–80. Paris: Centre de Recherches de l’Institut d’Études Hispaniques. Ross, Ian. 2003. Hume’s Correspondence and the Biographical Record as a Quarry for His Economic Thought. Unpublished manuscript. Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1954. A History of Economic Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Smith, Adam. [1776] 1976. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Edited by R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 292 History of Political Economy 37:2 (2005) Stewart, Dugald. [1809–10] 1968. Lectures on Political Economy. Clifton, N.J.: Augustus M. Kelley. Sutcliffe, Adam. 2000. Can a Jew Be a Philosopher? Isaac de Pinto, Voltaire, and Jewish Participation in the European Enlightenment. Jewish Social Studies 6.3:31–51. Tucker, Josiah. [1774] 1974. Four Tracts on Political and Commercial Subjects. Clifton, N.J.: Augustus M. Kelley. Vandermonde, Alexandre. [1795] 1994. Leçons d’économie politique dans l’école normale de l’an III. In Leçons d’histoire, de géographie, d’économie politique, 361–427. Paris: Dunod. Vega, Joseph de la. [1688] 1939. Confusion de confusiones: Dialogos curiosos entre um filósofo agudo, um mercader discreto e un accionista erudito, descriviendo el negocio de las acciones, su origen, su etimologia, su realidade, su juego y su enredo. Edited by M. F. J. Smith. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Voltaire. [1764] 1964. Dictionnaire philosophique. Paris: Flammarion. Wijler, Jacob S. 1923. Isaac de Pinto: Sa vie et ses oeuvres. Apeldoorn, Netherlands: Dixon & Co. Winch, Donald. 1998. The Political Economy of Public Finance in the “Long” Eighteenth Century. In Debt and Deficits: An Historical Perspective, edited by John Maloney, 9–26. Aldershot, U.K.: Edward Elgar.