ESSAY LEGAL EDUCATION AND THE VISION THING Timothy W. Floyd* The 1990s have presented American law schools with their most serious challenges in decades. After years of steady increase, the number of law school applicants is declining. Because tuition and other student costs continue to rise, and placement rates are not what they once were, default rates on student loans are increasing. In response to these trends, law schools everywhere are attempting to "downsize"; they are reducing enrollment, cutting budgets, and reducing the number of faculty members. The pressures are not just budgetary: the ABA's Macerate Report1 has strongly criticized law schools for doing an inadequate job of instructing students in professional skills and values. In addition, the ABA accreditation process, for many years the law schools' best friend, has been sharply attacked from both outside and inside the legal academy. This is not bad news. Challenges can serve to strengthen institutions. How well an institution responds to challenges, however, depends largely upon the clarity of its vision concerning the purpose and identity of the institution. In the case of legal education, unfortunately, there is not much reason for optimism. To quote our forty-first president, law schools flunk the "vision thing." We are in trouble because we legal educators are confused about the purpose of our institution. That is odd, because our purpose * Professor of Law, Texas Tech University School of Law. 1 SECTION OF LEGAL EDUC. AND Am-nssIONS TO THE BAR, AMERICAN BAR AstN, REPoRT OF THE TASK FORCE ON LAw SCHOOLS AND THE PRoFESSION: NARROWING THE GAP, LEGAL EDUCATION AND PROFESSIONAL DEVELOPMENT-AN EDUCATIONAL CONTINUUM (1992) [hereinafter MACeRATE REPoRT]. 853 HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 853 1996-1997 854 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 ought to be obvious. Our primary mission, indeed our v,ery reason for existence, is to prepare our students to become competent, ethical practitioners. Yet we do not do nearly enough to prepare our students to be good lawyers. The problem is that we legal educators lack a vision ofwhat good lawyering is. If law schools are to better prepare students for law practice, legal educators, as teachers and scholars, must take the practice of law more seriously. Far too many law teachers are simply not interested in what lawyers do. I am not suggesting bad faith or conspiratorial intent among law faculties. Most law professors are conscientious about their teaching and their scholarship, and most law teachers care about their students. What we do not care enough about is the practice of law. This disregard oflaw practice by law professors takes two related forms, and many professors exhibit both. Some professors would tell you that law practice is not intellectually challenging and is not a worthy subject for academic endeavor. Others appear to believe that law practice is morally corrupt. Most law professors did not practice for very long, and they did not like it when they did. For most, their practice experience was as an associate in a large firm, work which is hardly typical of what most lawyers do. To be sure, the practice of law is a complex and challenging endeavor, and I am not suggesting that it is an easy task to prepare persons to be competent, ethical professionals. The problem is that American law schools do not really try. Law schools do not see their mission as preparing their students to be lawyers, and we have traditionally disclaimed any responsibility to prepare students for the full range of professional 'Work as lawyers. For that reason, this problem is not easily resolvable. It cannot be fixed by tinkering, such as adding a few so-called "skills" electives to the existing third year curriculum. The problem lies at the heart of legal education, with the "core" curriculum and the prevailing pedagogy, starting with the first year. The "core" oflegal education consists ofcourses based on traditional doctrinal categories, taught to large classrooms of students facing a professor, who either lectures or leads a discussion ofappellate opinions from a casebook, followed by one comprehensive bluebook exam at the end of the semester. In spite of many changes at the margins, that core is still what legal education largely is, at virtually every law school, HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 854 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 855 as it has been for over a century. But this curriculum and pedagogy do not adequately achieve law schools' basic purpose and reason for existence-the preparation ofcompetent, ethical lawyers. Indeed, the prevailing law school curriculum and pedagogy cannot possibly achieve that purpose. What purpose does underlie and animate this curriculum and pedagogy? At most law schools the curriculum and pedagogy appear to embody a belief in one of two purposes: either to teach students a body of knowledge, that is, the "law"; or to teach students a certain type of analysis called "thinking like lawyers." The first purpose is woefully misguided, not only because it is impossible to teach even a fraction of the law that a student vlill need to know as a lawyer, but also because students need much more than knowledge of the "law" to be good lawyers. The curriculum assumes that there is a certain body of "law" that students must learn in the three years of law school. The problem is that very little of American law can be covered even in three years of courses. In addition, much of the law that students learn while in law school will change several times during a student's legal career. Some of it, of course, will change before the student even acquires a license. Besides, even if law never changed, who could rely on memory? The second purpose, and one that is often articulated, is to teach our students to "think like lawyers." On the surface, this reason makes more sense. It fails, however, because we do not have an adequate conception of what the practice of law is, and therefore how one "thinks" as a lawyer. 2 As a result, we are fooling ourselves (although we are less and less fooling anyone else) when we continue to assert that our curriculum and pedagogy somehow teach our students to think like lawyers. We law professors must return to basics. There is too much at stake for us to continue blindly down the paths we have trod. We must begin exploring, articulating, and debating what constitutes good lawyering. Our answers to that question should then dictate all curriculum and pedagogical choices. See Robert Coles, The LSAT-Refkdions on an Erperience, 34 J. LEoAL Eouc. 412, 422 (1984) (questioning whether LSATs and law schools have anything to do with good lawyering). For a proposed definition of good lawyering emphasizing the professional obligation to promote equality, see Phoebe Haddon, Education for a Publk Calling in the 21st Century, 69 WASH. L. REv. 573, 574 (1994). 2 HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 855 1996-1997 856 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 I. TEACHING GoOD LAWYERING Having said that, I must admit that I'm not sure I can articulate to my own or anyone else's satisfaction exactly what "good lawyering" is. I do, however, have a sufficient sense of good lawyering to recognize that law schools do not take seriously their obligation to prepare students to be good lawyers. To support my case, I offer ten ways law schools would be different if they were serious about preparing students to be good lawyers. 1. Legal Education Would Focus on What Lawyers Do. Presently, law school curricula focus on the law rather than on the many roles of lawyers in our society. The vast majority of courses are designed to "cover" the law on a particular subject. Very little attention is paid to what lawyers actually do or to how they do it. Because most courses are taught through the study of appellate cases, students are simply not exposed to the work of lawyers, except for arguments made on appeal. Even the study of appellate cases focuses more on the judge's role than that of the lawyer. Jerome Frank. suggested long ago that law school should instead be "lawyer school."3 The basic law school curriculum, however, still largely ignores the practice of law. The current curriculum does not give students much of a picture of the world of law practice. The current curriculum's doctrinal focus is a legacy of Christopher Columbus Langdell's antiquated notion that law is a science. Langdell's assumption that law is a science is no longer accepted by many, but we're still stuck with Langdell's curriculum and pedagogy.4 Instead of organizing the curriculum around doctrinal subject matters, the curriculum could be organized around the various functions oflawyers in society. Students should understand the various roles that lawyers play in the community. Lawyers serve as counselors, planners, mediators, and organizers, as well as advocates. The curriculum should explore the ways lawyers help to achieve justice and peace, and also how they fail to do so. Jerome Frank, Why Not a Clinical Lawyer-School?, 81 U. PA. L. REv. 907, 915 (1933). There are many accounts of Langdell's enormous influence on legal education. See generally RoBERT STEVENS, LAw SCHOOL: LEGAL EDUCATION IN AMERICA FROM THE 1830S TO THE 1980s (1983) (analyzing legal education through general history of American law school as significant force in American legal establishment). 3 4 HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 856 1996-1997 LEGAL EDUCATION 1997] 857 Nevertheless, by focusing on practice we need not sacrifice the traditional skills of doctrinal analysis; that would be a false tradeoff. An emphasis on practice can help students better understand doctrine and its uses. Doctrine is one way our legal system resolves disputes, and students need to understand that doctrinal arguments are an essential persuasive technique in court. In emphasizingjustice and fairness, we must be careful not to give our students the impression that doctrinal arguments don't matter. I have colleagues who express frustration that students do not want to engage in legal analysis, but instead substitute gut reactions for careful analysis and argument. My colleagues upbraid these students for substituting emotion for reason-but the students then see reason as devoid ofjustice. The real trick in teaching doctrinal analysis is emphasizing detachment and the ability to see arguments on both sides of an issue, without making students think their beliefs about justice and fairness do not matter. Understanding doctrine is essential, but not as an end in itself. Casebooks, the almost exclusive teaching materials for first year classes, contribute greatly to students' problems with doctrinal analysis. The way students read casebooks is nothing like the way lawyers read appellate opinions. Casebooks would be much better teaching tools if they were organized around problems of the sort lawyers actually encounter in practice and if the doctrinal material were included to help the students solve that problem.6 Students better understand the role of legal doctrine and precedent in context, that is, as they help to solve a -client's problem. Students often struggle in reading the typical casebook to know whether cases are included as examples of what the law is, as examples of the "minority view," or as examples of bad reasoning for the professor to criticize. In my experience, students come away from the first year very confused about the way lawyers and judges use precedent. 2. Legal Education Would Focus at Least as Much on People as on Rules. In addition to ignoring the role of lawyers, law schools actively hide the clients and other people in the middle of legal One casebook for first year classes that does preciEely this is MYRON MOSKOVITZ. CASES LAw (2d ed. 1991). It is an excellent model for the kind of lawyering-focused casebook that I describe. 5 AND PRoBLEMS IN CRIMINAL HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 857 1996-1997 858 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 disputes. Law students are not exposed nearly enough to how law and the legal system impact people. We study rules and cases, not relationships between people. The facts are given in a.ppellate cases. That means the clients and other people involved get lost. Even organizations are made up of people, and in representing organizations, lawyers must still deal with the people who make up the organizations. Despite the fact that lawyers are professional communicators (in the sense that they make their living by communicating with other people), communication and other "people" skills are taught very little in law schools. Interviewing, counseling, and negotiation are not required subjects in most curricula; they are not considered part of the core. The important skills of fact investigation and proof of facts are also largely ignored. It is easy in law school to forget that the law is about people and how they get along (or do not get along) with each other. Law schools should confront students more directly with queeltions of justice. But justice gets lost when the people involved aro hidden from view. The problem is not just that the emotive and affective dimensions oflaw practice are not fully explored; it is also that the law students' feelings for the people about whom they are reading are actively suppressed in the classroom. 3. Legal Education Would Teach More of the Types ofAnalysis that Lawyers Use. Law study involves too much rote learning and coverage of material at the expense of creativity and problemsolving. Law schools purport to "teach people to think like lawyers"; but they do not teach many of the kinds of analysis lawyers really use. Again, the problem is an inadequate conception of lawyering. Anthony Amsterdam delineated many of the modes of lmalysis used by practicing lawyers which are not taught in law schools. 6 Three examples Amsterdam describes are ends-means thinking, hypothesis formulation and testing, and contingency planning. 7 In order to prepare students to "think like lawyers," legal educators 6 Anthony Amsterdam, Clinical Legal Education-A 21st Century Perspective, 34 J. LEGAL Enuc. 612, 614-15 (1984). I will not go into Amsterdam's prescriptions here, but the article is perhaps the best starting point for anyone who cares about real change in legal education. 7 [d. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 858 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 859 must explore more how lawyers actually think, and design the curriculum and pedagogy to give students the opportunity to practice those kinds of analyses.8 Even the analytical skills that law schools do purport to teach get slighted. The focus is far too often on imparting a body of information rather than on learning analytical skills. The curriculum focuses on coverage of the material, and courses are subject matter based.9 No matter how much we emphasize to our students that we care more about analysis than rule memorization, to the extent we grade by how many issues students can "spot,n our standard bluebook exams send the opposite message. And legal research and writing courses, the one first year course at almost every law school that focuses explicitly on analytical and communication skills, is treated as a stepchild, not worthy of the time, attention, or (heaven forbid) teaching of the tenured faculty. Some may complain that a focus on the practice of law will neglect "theory." That word, however, is overused in discussions of legal education. Although I hear students complain that they do not get enough practical instruction because law schools teach too much "theory," the fact is that precious little theory is taught in law schools. Law schools teach debating skills rather than theory; they teach analytical skills rather than ideas and the critique of ideas. The practice of law is well served by a good theoretical grounding in several disciplines. Legal education needs both more practice and more theory. to 4. Law Study Would Not Be So Individualistic; It Would Prepare Students for the Cooperative and Relational Dimensions of Law Practice. Lawyers seldom work in isolation from other people. In any legal matter they always have a client. In addition, the vast majority of law school graduates will work together with others in 8 For a wonderful account of "practical wisdom" as the essential lawyerly mode of analysis, see ANTHONY T. KRoNMAN, THE Losr LAWYER: FAILING IDEALS OF THE LEGAL PROFESSION 53-109 (1993). Unfortunately, Kronman assumes that traditionnl appellate case instruction is sufficient to inculcate practical wisdom in our students. Apart from his assertions, however, there is no evidence that traditional doctrinnl-based instn1ction will create better lawyers. 9 Unfortunately, the bar exams greatly exacerbate this problem. Bar examinations are another institution greatly in need ofrefonn, but that topic is beyond the scope ofthis Essay. 10 This point has been made by many others. E.g., Roger C. Cramton, The Current State of the Law School Curriculum, 32 J. LEGAL EDUC. 321, 330-32 (1982). HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 859 1996-1997 860 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 a law firm. or other organization. In representing clients, lawyers often work together with lawyers representing other parties. Legal education, however, tends to be very individualistic. Students rarely are required to work in groups toward common goals. Moreover, students tend to be highly competitive with each other over grades, class rank, and other rewards such as law review. Law schools need to encourage more cooperation, collegiality, and interpersonal work. Projects in which students collaborate toward a common goal are essential to foster the ability to work together. Students also need to be reminded that grades lmd class rank do not necessarily have much to do with how successful they will be as lawyers. In the professor-student relationship, a mentor-mentee attitude would be a useful model for which to strive. As law professors, we need to recognize that we are initiating students into a profession and that we likely are the first role models of professional behavior for our students. New lawyers will be learning from more experienced lawyers in practice. While the professor-student relationship cannot truly approximate that type of relationship because the student-faculty ratio is far too high, the faculty's attitudes of accessibility and cooperation toward a common goal can be improved nonetheless. 5. Legal Education Would Give Students an Opportunity to Learn from Experience. Learning to practice law is a lifelong educational process. One of the most important insights of the Macerate Reportll is that the educational process for lawyers is a continuum that stretches both long before and long after law school. For that process to be effective, lawyers must acquire the ability to learn from experience. 12 Yet the current law school curriculum and pedagogy are not designed to help students learn from experience. In most courses, students get little feedback during the course; the fmal grade is typically based on one comprehensive fmal. This is probably because the student-faculty ratio is too high to permit lmything else. This is lousy pedagogy for any course, but especially so for See supra pages 854-855 (discussing gap between legal education and legal profession). For an excellent statement of the importance of fostering the ability to learn from experience, see Amsterdam, supra note 6, at 615-16. 11 12 HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 860 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 861 learning skills. To master any skill (including the prototypical skill called "thinking like a lawyer") students need to plan for the skill, perform the skill, receive critique on their performance, and then reflect on the experience. That simply does not happen in most courses. Some law professors might counter that they are not "skills teachers"; clearly, however, learning to read statutes and cases and applying that law to fact situations is a skill. Most teachers do try to teach analysis rather than simply a body of knowledge, but the lack ofopportunity to practice that skill is a problem. The modified Socratic dialogue employed by most first year teachers is certainly .superior to lectures, but even so, there is limited feedback. More written assignments in which students work through basic legal analysis, receive feedback from the teacher, and then try again would be a big improvement. Law students do not write nearly enough. Another way in which law schools do not foster the ability to learn from experience is that law school curricula are generally not structured in terms ofprogression. The second and third years are typically composed almost entirely of electives that can be taken in any order. In terms of analysis and skills development, the curriculum does not build from simple to more complex. Advanced courses teach more of the same analysis and skills under a different doctrinal rubric. For all ofthese reasons, new lawyers are ill-equipped to learn from experience once they begin to practice. 6. Legal Education Would Focus More on the Law that Matters in the Real World. Although flawed pedagogy is the biggest problem with legal education, the selection of substantive law taught is also flawed. The first year curriculum is virtually uniform throughout legal education; nearly all first year students take torts, contracts, property, civil procedure, and criminal law. The compartmentalization of the curriculum into these doctrinal cubbyholes leaves students ill-prepared to deal with problems that cross doctrinal categories. Moreover, it is not self-evident why these should be the core subjects. It is structured the way it is because it has always been that way; those are the subjects that virtually all American lawyers took in their first year. We must also remember that the curriculum at most law schools is based on the individual faculty members' preferences. It is easier to teach HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 861 1996-1997 862 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 what we have always taught and courses for which there are already casebooks. This "core" curriculum, however, is not sufficiently tied to the legal world of the late twentieth century. For example, torts has been changed enormously by no-fault insurance and workers' compensation; property by land use laws and enviI'onmental regulation; and criminal law and procedure by overcrowdl3d dockets and plea bargaining. No doubt many teachers try to bring these realities into the classroom, but they are not dealt with much in casebooks. There are more subject matter anomalies: In the advanced curriculum, there is a pronounced bias in favor of business courses over family, personal injury, and criminal law-the areal; oflaw in which ordinary people and lawyers are involved. The curriculum is designed more for the benefit of those students who will become associates at large firms representing businesses than for those students who will represent individuals. 13 7. Legal Education Would Reward the Contributions o)"Teachers Who Focus on Practice. Teaching for practice competency is undervalued at every law school. The second class l;tatus (or worse) of clinicians and legal research and writing teachers is the best example of my point. Those teachers whose teaching is the most demanding have the least status. It is no coincidence that those are the teachers who focus more on law practicl3 than on specific doctrinal areas. Creative scholarship is more valued than innovative teaching. The reputation of law school faculties is a function of their scholarship rather than their teaching. Yet, for at least ninety-five percent oflaw professors, the most important impact they can have is through their teaching rather than their writing for law reviews. 14 13 Sandy D'Alemberte has pointed out how the current structure of le1:al education benefits the large firms. Talbot D'Alemberte, Keynote Address, in THE MAcCRATE REPORTBUILDING THE EDUCATIONAL CONTINUUM 4-17 (1994). He goes so far as to label this arrangement between law schools and large firms a conspiracy. Maybe it is, but I suspect the problem is more the result of inertia and unthinking commitment to the lItatus quo. 14 John Elson has stated the case against legal scholarship more eloquently and in more detail than I can here, in The Case Against Legal Scholarship or, If the Professor Must Publish, Must the Profession Perish?, 39 J. LEGAL Enuc. 343 (1989). Elson's main point, with HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 862 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 863 This does not mean that legal scholarship is unimportant. However, the scholarship that is produced reflects the fact that law professors do not take practice seriously. Scholarship by law professors does not contribute much to our understanding of the legal profession and the legal system.16 One reason for that is that most law professors are not trained in the social sciences and empirical research methodology; we generally do not have advanced degrees in other disciplines. We are most comfortable writing about the opinions of appellate judges. Some law teachers feel that if we are to maintain "law" as an autonomous discipline, we should stick to writing about legal doctrine. Law can never be a truly autonomous discipline, however; such autonomy is another of Langdell's conceits. Practicing lawyers know that the practice oflaw is always interdisciplinary; that is, in representing clients, lawyers must be familiar with many different fields of knowledge. Legal problems are always more than just "legal" problems. In focusing more on practice, law professors must become more familiar with other fields. 16 Writing is important, even essential, for law teachers. People who write are better thinkers. All law professors are given the time and resources to write, and as a group they should be writing more. The main purpose of writing, however, ought to be to improve our ability to prepare competent, ethical practitioners. which I completely agree, is that the focus on scholarship too oRen detracts from the central purpose of law schools-the preparation of good lawyers. Id. at 354-56. 15 This criticism is akin to that of Judge Harry Edwards, which initiated a remarkable debate about the purpose of legal scholarship. See Harry T. Edwards, The Growing Disjunction Between Legal Education and the Legal Profession, 91 MIca L. REv. 34, 75 (1992) ("(T]he growing disarray we now see in the profession is direet1y related to the growing incoherence in law teaching and scholarship."); Harry T. Edwards, The Growing Disjunction Between Legal Education and the Legal Profession: A Postscript, 91 MIca L. REv. 2191, 2219 (1993) (expressing fear that "without a great effort by the legal community as a whole ••• concrete, effective, and lasting reforms" will not be brought about). Although I agree with Judge Edwards's basic premise, I do not agree with the implication that a newer generation oflaw professors is to blame for the disfunction. AB I hope I have made clear, I don't believe that legal educators of any generation have done 11 good job of preparing students for practice. 18 On this point I part company, at least to a small extent, with Judge Edwards. While I agree that law teachers must pay more attention to law practica, I am not convinced that the best way to do that is for law professors to write more about legal doctrine. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 863 1996-1997 864 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 More writing about how to prepare students for law practice would be helpful, as would be more writing directed toward practicing lawyers. Research into the practice of law could greatly improve practice education. 8. Law Schools Would Make Admissions Decisions on More Than LSAT Scores and Grades. The vast majority of students are admitted to law school based solely on the index of their LSAT score and undergraduate GPA Conversely, the vast majority of applicants who are not accepted to law school are rejected on the basis of this index. Most admissions decisions are made without regard to the applicant's other qualities. Very few law schools conduct interviews. Today, very few law students flunk out of school and most law school graduates pass the bar exam. Thus, the real gatekeepers to the profession are law school admissions offices and committees. Although LSATs and GPAs may be somewhat reliable pr,edictors of law school performance, we have no idea as to their reliability in predicting who will be good lawyers. So long as law schools are judged in relation to their peers on the LSATs and GPAs of their entering classes, however, they will continue to base admissions primarily on those numbers. 9. Law Schools Would Focus on the Delivery of Legal Services. Law schools do very little to educate our students about how clients obtain access to the services of lawyers. Delivery of legal services to the poor and the middle class raises significant moral and professional issues, but those issues are largely ignored. Pro bono obligations and opportunities should be emphasized more. Mandatory pro bono for law students as a condition of graduation is an encouraging trend; just as important would be mandatory pro bono for law professors. In addition, placement offices in most law schools aElsume the large corporate firm as the norm. Law schools assume-and students are not in a position to question that assumpf;ion-that students who can work for the larger law firms that represent corporate America will want to do so. Law schools do not do enough to help students explore the kind of legal job that would best suit them. This leads to my last and most important point. 10. Law Schools Would Require Students to Explore Issues of Professional Identity, Meaning, and Purpose. At no point in the HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 864 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 865 curriculum of most law schools are students expected to explore issues of professional identity and purpose.17 Students should be pushed to grapple with those questions made famous (if only briefly) by Admiral Stockdale: "Who am I and what am I doing here?" We need more reflective practitioners, but the habit of reflecting on our work as lawyers must begin at the outset of our career, that is, in law school. Habits ofreflection and introspection need to begin in law school because the strains and pressures of law practice make them much more difficult to develop later. Almost all students take a course in Professional Responsibility, but that course is too often reduced to learning the Model Rules and passing the MPRE. The subject of professional regulation and minimal standards is an important subject; however, we need far more instruction in the ethics, history, sociology, and philosophy of lawyering. Students must be confronted with the meaning of their own calling to this profession.18 The practice of law is a ca]]jng,19 and we should inculcate that understanding in our students.20 Practicing lawyers make a world 17 In the past decade several law professors have written excellent books on meaning and morality in the practice oflaw• E.g., MARY ANN GLENDON, A NATION UNDER L.\WYERS: How THE CRISIS IN THE LEGAL PRoFESSION IS TRANsFolWINGAMERICAN 8ocIETY(1994); MICHAEL J. KELLy, LIvEs OF LAWYERS: JOURNEYS IN THE ORGANIZATION OF PRAcTICE (1994); ANTHONY T. KRoNMAN, THE LoST LAWYER: FAILING IDEALS OF THE LEGAL PRoFESSION (1994): DAVID LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE: AN ErmCAL STuDy (1988); and THOMAS L. SHAFFER, AMERICAN LAWYERS AND THEIR COMMUNlTIES: Ermcs IN THE LEGAL PRoFESSION (1991). The problem is that these subjects have not found their way into the heart ofthe law school curriculum. One book written specifically for law students on these themes is JACK L. SAMMONS, LAWYER PRoFESSIONALISM (1988). I have assigned this book in several c:lasses; it works wonderfully in getting students to grapple with questions about professional meaning and identity. 18 Some seminaries require their students to write a credo, a formulation of their own beliefs and their understanding of their calling. Perhaps law schools should do something similar. Most law students write personal essays on this theme as part of the law school admission process. It would be beneficial for students to refine those essays throughout law schooL Sandy D'Alemberte has unabashedly called for law schools to retum to their "seminary mission." D'Alemberte, supra note 13, at 12. 19 See JOSEPH G. ALLEGRETl'I, THE LAWYERS' CAU.lNG: CHRIS'1'W'l FAlTH AND LEGAL PRACTICE 24-36 (1996) (containing fruitful discussion of concept of "calling"). 2Il To those who are uncomfortable with the notion of"incu1cation" in law school, I would point out the inevitability of communicating certain values in law schooL We ought to be self-conscious ofour own views ofprofessional identity and meaning, and honest in conveying our own ideas to our students. For the best discussions of this topic. soo Roger C. Cramton, Beyond the Ordiruuy Religion, 37 J. LEGAL EDUc. 509 (1987): Roger C. Cramton, The Ordiruuy Religion of the Law School Classroom, 29 J. LEGAL EOUc. 247 (1978). HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 865 1996-1997 866 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 of difference in how just our society is. If law schools do not adequately prepare students, justice suffers. Although lawyers are called to serve justice, we can legitimately disagree about: how just our current society and legal system are. Lawyers and law students need not necessarily be devoted to existing "law" and current legal institutions, but there is nothing wrong with requiring devotion to justice. I realize that talk of "devotion" and "calling" makes some people nervous. Paul Carrington, in a noted article in 1984, stirred up a firestorm of protest when he suggested that law professors who do not have faith in "law"-persons whom Carrington termed "legal nihilists"-should leave the law schools.21 He reasoned that law schools are more like seminaries than graduate depar1;ments of religion, and as such have an obligation to the students not to hire the legal equivalent of "atheists."22 Carrington was off the mark in his criticism of critical legal scholars or "crits" (the legal "nihilists" to which he referred). I have represented many poor people, and I know how unjust our existing legal system often is. For that reason, the crits' insistencE~ that law serves to safeguard the powerful and that doctrine alone cannot constrain power is entirely accurate and necessary. Thus, Carrington's criticism of critical legal scholars seems misguided. Nonetheless, Carrington was on to something. Because law schools have an obligation to prepare students for a profession, they are more analogous to seminaries than to graduate school. The "faith" that I believe is necessary, however, is not faith in "law" or legal institutions-that has always struck me as idolatry. Sometimes law serves justice; sometimes it serves injustice. InBtead, the faith that is essential is faith in justice itself. At the deepest level, the just and the holy are one. Our calling as lawyers is to work for justice. We do not have to agree about what justice is in our society, nor about how much or how little justice exists in our society, but we should all agree that lawyers have responsibilities beyond their narrow self-interest. 21 Paul D. Carrington, Of Law and the River, 34 J. LEGAL EDUC. 222, 227 (1984). Correspondence generated by Carrington's essay appears in Peter W. Martin el; aI., "OfLaw and the River," and ofNihilism and Academic Freedom, 35 J. LEGAL EDUC. 1 (1985). 22 Carrington, supra note 21, at 227. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 866 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 867 I worry that the individualistic and narrow law school curriculum and pedagogy do nothing to encourage students to see themselves as having any obligations beyond themselves or their clients. Law schools should focus more on their institutional purpose of preparing competent, reflective practitioners, and students must explore their individual purposes in becoming lawyers as well. Most students come to law school expecting to become lawyers so they can make a difference in the world. During their three years in law school they become more cynical, suspicious, dogmatic, and authoritarian-and also more lonely and depressed.23 Why? In part, this is because law school is too impersonal, abstract, and competitive. Most importantly, however, it is because students lose sight of why they came to law school in the first place.zc Law schools must encourage students to explore their own calling to the legal profession. II. OBSTACLES TO CHANGE Criticism of law schools on the grcund that they inadequately prepare students for practice is nothing new. For decades, people have been pointing out that this particular emperor has no clothes. My criticisms and prescriptions for legal education are not original. 25 Over the years, there have been many essays like this one. In spite of these criticisms, however, the core curriculum and 23 For a good discussion of the deleterious effects oflegnl education on law students. see John Mixon & Robert Schwerk, The Personal Dimenswn ofProfesswMl Responsibility. 58 LAw & CONTEMP. PRoBS. 87 (1995). 24 Is the current professional malaise related to this? I suspect lawyers are dissatisfied for the same reasons that law students are. They have lost sight of their purpose. They do not perceive that their work adds meaning to their lives; their work is no better than a necessary evil. Since so many enter the profession because they do seek meaning in their work, and since. in any event, work is such a big part of our lives. it is no wonder that 80 many lawyers are dissatisfied. There are many lawyers who are grappling with questions ofmeaning and identity in their practice. The Texas Tech Law Review recently published a special symposium issue on "Faith and Law." containing personal essays by 44 lawyers. Symposium. FaiJh and Law. 27 TEx. TEcH L. REv. 911 (1996). 25 It would take several pages to provide citations to every article in the Journal ofLegal Education alone that has been critical of legal education. Instead. here is my personal "top three" list ofworks about the problems with legal education: THOMAS 1.. SHAFFER & RoBERT S. REDMOUNT. LAWYERS. LAw STuDENTS. AND PEoPLE (1977) (now unfortunately out of print); Amsterdam. supra note 6; and Elson. supra note 14. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 867 1996-1997 868 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 prevailing pedagogy of legal education have changed very little in at least a century, since that curriculum and pedagogy were "discovered" by Christopher Columbus Langdell at Harvard and then spread throughout American law schools.26 What is striking (and a little discouraging) is how little real change has resulted in response to these criticisms. The discerning reader may wonder, therefore, why one would bother to write, or read, another one. The answer lies in the challenges I roferred to at the outset of this Essay.27 It is an appropriate time to review what we know of our failings. I even see some glimmer of hope that, in response to those challenges, we just might re-examine some of our fundamental and cherished assumptions about legal education. Nonetheless, as I said at the outset, there is not much reason for optimism. It would be very difficult for law schools to change in the directions I have suggested. Many obstacles stand in the way of law schools attempting to redirect their focus toward preparing competent, ethical lawYers. What are those obstacles? ]~ollowing is a list of ten reasons we might hear in opposition to such a change in focus. After each, I suggest why that reason is really an excuse that will not hold up under scrutiny. 1. "It's Not Our Job." Some law professors do not believe that the principal purpose of law schools is to prepare students to become lawYers. Schools are university departments; as such, their primary mission is to seek knowledge. These professors argue that law study has intrinsic value, as does liberal education generally, and that it is therefore a mistake for law schools to perform any gate-keeping role for the profession. According to that view, legal education should ignore any suggestions that law schools could better prepare persons to be lawYers, because that is simply not their purpose.28 26 See supra note 4 and accompanying text (describing Landell's influence on legal education). 27 See supra page 853 (discussing declining student application, law school "downsizing," and Macerate Report's criticisms oflaw schools). 28 Owen Fiss has stated this view quite baldly: "Law professors are not paid to train lawyers, but to study the law and to teach their students what they happen to discover." Letter from Owen M. Fiss to Paul D. Carrington, in "OfLaw and the River," ana! ofNihilism and Academic Freedom, supra note 21, at 26. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 868 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 869 That argument is hard to take seriously. Why do the vast majority of students come to law school? In order to enter the profession. An overwhelming percentage become licensed attorneys. Even for those students who go to law school solely out of an academic interest in the legal system with no intention of practicing, the curriculum and pedagogy must be especially disappointing. The near exclusive doctrinal focus ofmost of the curriculum hardly serves to educate about the role of law and lawyers in our society. I concede that a good legal education may serve to hone students' analytical skills-skills that serve students well even if they do not intend to practice-but while there may be students who attend law school solely in order to hone their analytical skills, I have yet to meet one in thirteen years of teaching law. Moreover, legal education is far too expensive to attract many students who have only an "academic" interest in the law. To be sure, many law professors are wary of practice-focused education. They fear that it would dilute the academic character of legal education, turning a university discipline into a trade school. This attitude rests upon a fundamental misconception of the nature of law practice. If professors would only pay attention, they would find that the practice oflaw is an enormously challenging intellectual endeavor. Indeed, the most fascinating intellectual questions concerning the law relate to practice rather than doctrine. The philosophical, political, moral, sociological, and psychological issues associated with law practice are much more intellectually sophisticated and challenging than the usual doctrinal riddles we pose to our students. In its focus on legal doctrine, legal education is curiously behind the intellectual times. Langdell's world view was decidedly "modern." Current intellectual life across the campus reflects much more of a "post-modern" world view. Post-modernism emphasizes context rather than universal rules, narrative accounts rather than generalizations, and the particular over the abstract. A postmodern account oflaw will inevitably focus on practice rather than doctrine. The claim that law is an academic discipline is no excuse for ignoring practice. As members ofthe university community, faculty members have a scholarly commitment to researching and teaching the truth about reality. In focusing primarily on the written HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 869 1996-1997 870 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 opinions of appellate courts, however, law schools ignore large chunks of reality. Langdell believed that the law consisted of principles that could be found in appellate decisions. 'The law in action is much more than that. Legal doctrine is simply not a selfcontained body ofknowledge in the "modern" sense. A post-modern sensibility would look to the context of the rules and principles discerned in opinions. Decisions made by lawyers and clients in the law office can be just as momentous as decisions in the courts of appeals. We legal academics do not commonly ask fundamental questions about the nature oflaw practice. Two examples ofpossible avenues ofexploration oflaw practice follow. First, Alasdair MacIntyre, one ofthe leading moral philosophers ofour time, has written about the nature of a "practice." According to MacIntyre, it is through engaging in a practice that one acquires virtues.29 Whether law practice constitutes a practice in the Maclntyrean sense, and can therefore lead to the development of virtues, is a fascinating, but largely unexplored, question. Second, Donald Schon has written extensively about professionals' "knowledge in action"; that is, a professional's art of applying technical knowledge and expertise to practice. 3o Again, the law school curriculum and pedagogy largely ignore such insights about professional knowledge. 2. "Let the Practicing Bar Do It." A second response would acknowledge the gate-keeping function of law schools, but would argue that law schools currently teach the only skills that can be taught in the traditional classroom setting. The other practice skills are best left to post-law school experience.31 It is misguided, according to this point of view, to try to teach anything other than legal doctrine and policy and the analytical skills that lawyers use to make legal arguments. One problem with this argument is the assumption that practice skills cannot be taught effectively in law school. The experience of ALAsDAIR MAcINTYRE, AFTER VmTUE 175-89 (1981). DONALD A. SCHON, EDUCATING THE REFLECTIVE PRACTITIONER: TOWARDS A NEW DESIGN FOR TEACHING AND LEARNING IN THE PROFESSIONS (1987); DONALD A. SCHON, THE REFLECTIVE PRACTITIONER: How PROFESSIONALS THINK IN ACTION (1983). 31 See Jonathon Rose, The MacCrate Report's Restatement ofLegal Education: The Need for Reflection and Horse Sense, 44 J. LEGAL EDUC. 548, 560·61 (1994) (assesuing validity of statements in MacCrate Report). ' 29 30 HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 870 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 871 the clinical movement and of courses on professional skills has disproved that assumption,. Of course, the practice skills learned in law school will only be a start; those skills will be continually refined for years. That is just as true, however, of the analytical skills. The other problem with this argument is the assumption that students will practice under careful supervision until they are competent to represent clients on their own. Many law graduates will not work for lawyers who take the time to mentor new lawyers in good lawyering. Our students are licensed to practice without any experience requirement. All persons with a J.D. who pass the bar exam are licensed to do anything that any licensed lawyer may do. Many will not work for anyone-they will go out on their own from day one. We have to teach our students as ifwe are their last teachers, not their first. Graduates should know how to play music, not just read music. Perhaps the most valuable aspect of the MacCrate Report is its concern about the obligation of law schools to our students' future clients.32 We must do more to ensure that those clients are not the victims of the law schools' failure to prepare lawyers for practice. 3. "We Are Already Doing It.» Many law teachers contend that legal education has already undergone significant change in the direction that I urge. The last twenty-five years have seen the development of clinics and simulation skills courses. As the MacCrate Report acknowledges, the biggest changes in legal education have been in the skills curriculum.33 Many law teachers, and even some schools, do focus on teaching for practice competency. Real change, however, has not occurred. All of the changes have come at the margins; the "core" has changed very little. For most students graduating from law school today, the vast majority of their credit hours were spent in courses that "cover" a body oflegal doctrine, are taught through casebooks, and conclude with comprehensive final exams. Courses that focus on law practice rather 32 MACCRATE REPoRT, supra note I, at 124-25. For an excellent discussion of the obligations law schools owe to the future clients ofour students, Bee THOMAS SHAFFER, FAInJ AND THE PROFESSIONS 260 (1987). 331fAcCRATE REPoRT, supra note I, at 237. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 871 1996-1997 872 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 than legal doctrine made up less than 20% of the courseload. It is not unduly pessimistic to see that the glass is not 20% full; it is 80% empty. 4. "If It Ain't Broke, Don't Fix It." There are tho~le in legal education who feel that we should not tamper with success. We should not assume so readily, however, that legal education has been "successful." When we assert that legal education is successful, we should be careful to specify for whom and how. For law professors? Certainly so. We law professors make more money and teach fewer hours than our colleagues in other departments of the university. For universities? Yes. They gain a lot of money and prestige from their law schools. But successful for whom else? Do we have a just society? For a great many Americans, their caste makes. statistically certain their disproportionate subjection to crime, joblessness, homelessness, prejudice, miseducation, ill health, and early death. 34 Lawyers can and should do much more to make ours a more jusf; society. The legal profession? Many have documented the malaise within· the ranks of lawyers today.35 The professionalism movement, while subject to some valid criticism, is a legitimate expression of concern about the lack of a sense of service for the common good.36 For our students? Over the course of three years, our graduates become more cynical, suspicious, dogmatic, and authoritarian. They also become more lonely, depressed, and prone to addiction and substance abuse. They also graduate greatly in debt, and without the necessary competence to be successful lawyers. Sure, I am being somewhat hyperbolic here, but my point is that it is not obvious in what sense legal education is a success. And there is ample evidence that law schools are failing in their obligations to our students, the profession, and society. 5. "We Aren't Competent to Teach Lawyering." Many law teachers do not have much experience in law practice. The common Elson, supra note 14, at 358 nA1. See, e.g., BENJAMIN SELLS, THE SOUL OF THE LAw 19 (1994) (discuBsin~: psychological problems facing law and individual lawyers). 36 For a sympathetic description of the professionalism movement, including a responso to its academic critics, see Jack L. Sammons, The Professionalism Movement: The Problems Defined, 7 NOTRE DAME J.L. ETHICS & PuB. POL'y 269 (1993). 34 35 HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 872 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 873 attitude among law professors is that too much experience somehow taints a candidate for a faculty position. We need to place more value on practice experience in hiring decisions. I am not asserting that extensive practice experience must be a prerequisite to law teaching. Some of the best law teachers I know have little or no practice experience. What is crucial, however, is an attitude that law practice is important. Extensive practice experience is of little value if the professor then turns his or her back on the world of practicing lawyers. The MacCrate Report noted "the apparent lack of participation by law professors in the organized bar.,,37 When they do participate, it is usually on the national level, not the county or state level. Law professors have much to contribute to the bar and the judiciary; this participation can in turn greatly improve their teaching. 6. "Fd Like to Do More, But It Will Ruin My Reputation. n Fundamental changes such as I suggest, even for those who agree that they are necessary, carry large risks for individual faculty members and individual law schools. To enhance their reputation and move up in the rigid hierarchy of legal education, individual law schools must emulate those above them in the hierarchy. The same is true for individual faculty members. The safe course is to do things the way they have always been done, especially at the elite institutions. For that reason, newer law teachers are sometimes warned not to teach so-called "skills" or clinical courses. 7. '7 Have Tenure, and You Can't Make Me Do It. n As a practical matter, we must recognize that the people in charge of legal education-the law professors-do not have much incentive to change. Legal education is the way it is in part because it is a good deal for professors. As I said, law professors are paid more and teach fewer hours than most of their colleagues in other schools and colleges in the university. A realist would expect law professors to resist change. That is why pressure from outside the academy is a good thing for legal education. That, however, leads to the next obstacle. 8. "We Shouldn't Respond to COutside' Pressures. n Some have raised the banner of academic freedom against any suggestions of 37 MACeRATE REPORT, supra note I, at 5. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 873 1996-1997 874 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 change from outside the academy.3s They believe that only fulltime law teachers know what is best for legal education. Those who complain grossly misunderstand th.e fiduciary obligations of law schools to society and to their students. Law schools are obliged to prepare students for practice--obliged to society because law schools are the gatekeepers of a public profession, and to students because they come to us expecting professional preparation. Law schools have a covenant with these constituencies, a fiduciary obligation and a position off;rust. When we fail to prepare students adequately for practice, we hreach those fiduciary duties. In failing to prepare students for the practice of law, law schools have abused their position of trust; they have broken the covenant.39 Because society has entrusted law schools with the gate-keeping function, law professors are public personages who have special responsibilities to the public. This is especially true Bince we are virtually immune from removal from office.40 These changes are possible, but orily if those outside legal academia continue to push legal education toward preparation for practice. Some academics have cautioned against treating the MacCrate Report as an accreditation standard and worry about threats to academic freedom. 41 They also warn that implementing the MacCrate Report's recommendations will stifle innovation.42 Obviously, innovation is crucial; experimentation as to different 38 See Wallace Loh, Introduction: The MacCrate Report-Heuristic or PrescriptilJe?, 69 WASH. L. REv. 505, 513 (1994) (arguing that law school should serve all "laboratory for curricular experimentation"). 39 The notion offiduciary obligations arising from a covenantal relationllhip is a familiar one to the law. Because of the fiduciary nature of the covenantal obligat.ion, it is a much better concept than the analogous notion of contract. ALLEGRETl'I, supra note 19, at 37-50. For a description of the concept of covenant in the context of physicians' ethics, sea WILLIAM MAy, THE PHYsICIAN'S COVENANT (1983). May discusses tho advantages in exploring physicians' ethics under the metaphor ofcovenant as opposed to notions ofcontract or philanthropy. [d. at 116-27. Another work of ethics that takes covenant as a central theme is JOSEPH ALLEN, LoVE AND CONFLICT (1984). I mention these booku in part becauso I believe legal ethics could benefit greatly from further exploration oftha concept ofcovenant. 40 See Leslie E. Gerber, Can Lawyers Be SalJed?: The Theological Legal Ethics o/Thomas Shaffer, 10 J.L. & RELIG. 347, 359 (1994) (discussing professional disEJngagement and avoidance of accountability). 41 E.g., Rose, supra note 31, at 561-64. 42 E.g., Loh, supra note 38, at 513-14. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 874 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 875 means of professional preparation is much needed. However, it is ironic for the leaders of legal education to argue for innovation. The accreditation guidelines as to curriculum are extremely general, yet law school curricula at most schools could not be much more cookie-cutter than they are now. Mandates from outside the academy are not necessarily a bad thing, if that is what it takes to cause the necessary changes. It would certainly be preferable for law schools to change their curriculum and pedagogy on their own, but I do not see it happening without "external" pressure. The challenges to the ABA accreditation process were brought about by the arrogance of legal educators. The entire process has embodied an assumption that only full-time law professors know what is best for legal education. Site inspection teams from the ABA have been overwhelmingly made up of law professors and deans. Thus, we should not be surprised that accreditation has reinforced the status quo. Of course an accreditation process is necessary for the protection of students and the public, but the ABA should involve more evaluators from outside the academy. 9. "We Can't Afford It." Some who otherwise might agree that law schools should do a better job of professional preparation say that we cannot afford it.43 That is correct; it is true that law schools cannot continue to do everything the way they do now and just add on a "skills component." The student-faculty ratio is not going to improve so as to allow for many more small classes. There will not be new money to hire a new group of professors.« We must therefore change much of what we do now. We do need more clinics and skills courses. Small courses in which students perform lawyering activities in role, receive extensive feedback and critique from the teacher, repeat the performance, and reflect upon the experience are the best way to 43 See. e.g., John J. Costonis, The Macerate Report: OfLoaves, Fishes, and the Future of American Legal Education, 43 J. LEGAL EDUC. 157, 189-97 (1993) (arguing that we have problem, not crisis, and that we cannot achieve vision oC competence at nlllevels oflegal proCession unless society, legal proCessionals, and university centrnI administratioOll are willing to pay price). 44 David Barnhizer has recently suggested several ways to mise additional money to pay for implementing the Macerate Reports goals. David Barnhiz.er, Of Rat Time and Terminators, 45 J. LEGAL EDUC. 49, 56-59 (1995). I am all for his recommendatioOll, but I also insist we must change the core curriculum and pedagogy whether or not those additional resources are obtained. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 875 1996-1997 876 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 teach good lawyering. I wish most courses in law school could be like that. In my own experience as a law teacher for over thirteen years, I have been a full-time clinical teacher, have taught small simulation skills courses, and have taught large required doctrineoriented classes. I have no doubt that clinical and other small class role-based teaching is the best pedagogy for legal edu(:ation. I also know, however, that we will continue to havl~ very large classes in law school. The relatively high student-faculty ratio in law schools is a big problem. Close supervision of individual student work is very difficult when the size of the average class is between fifty and sixty. Law schools have been successful in the university because of the high ratio and low overhead.. The ratio is not likely to get any better in the near future; if anything, declining resources for legal education will force the ratio even higher. It is also clear that the curriculum will continue to consist of largely the same courses. That is why it is so important to change the teaching of the "substantive" courses.46 In the large courses at the "core"· of the curriculum, especially the required fIrst year courses, we can focus on the role of lawyers who pra(:tice in that area of law. We can employ student role-playing on simulated problems. We can focus on clients and on the human relationships involved. We can employ more group exercises. We can teach our students the kinds of analyses lawyers actually use in helping clients with their problems. We can structure our COW7ses and the curriculum as a whole to allow students to learn from their experience. Most importantly, we can focus on justice, on the role of lawyers in achieving justice, on public service, and on the meaning of our professional calling. All of this can and must be accommodated within our existing resources and in tho traditional "substantive" courses. 10. "We Don't Know What Good Lawyering Is." As I hope I have made clear by now, this is our basic problem. We should not expect law schools to be effective at preparing good lawyers until we 45 I have a pet peeve about calling certain courses "substantive," as a wa:( to differentiato doctrine-oriented courses from practice-oriented courses. Substantive as opposed to a course ~th no substance? Or substantive as opposed to trivial? I realize that I am too sensitive about this; it probably stems from years of teaching courses that are considered peripheral to the enterprise. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 876 1996-1997 1997] LEGAL EDUCATION 877 develop a VISIon of what good lawyering is. Our curriculum decisions should be driven by that vision. We law teachers, however, rarely articulate or debate our vision of good lawyering. One reason may be that it is a difficult task. The MacCrate Report made an effort at describing good lawyering. The centerpiece of the Report is the Statement of Skills and Values (SSV),46 which purports to be those skills and values possessed by minimally competent and ethicallawyers.47 Unfortunately, as a statement of "good lawyering," the SSV is not entirely satisfying. On one level, the SSV is hard to quarrel with-of course lawyers should be competent at counseling, communication, negotiation, etc., but the list implies that good lawyering is primarily a matter of technique. To that extent, it gives ammunition to the critics of a more professional orientation for legal education by implying that professional preparation involves teaching technique without any broader framework. Good lawyering, however, is much more than technique. Good lawyering is more a matter of practical wisdom, goodjudgment, empathetic understanding, and a passion for justice than it is a mastery of a certain number of "skills and values." The MacCrate Report was asking the right questions, however. What we need in legal education is more consideration and debate of questions such as "What do lawyers actually do?" and "What are the characteristics of a good lawyer?" Those questions may seem basic, but that is where we need to start. Thinking about and discussing those questions is much more important than the answers we ultimately give. CONCLUSION Our task as law professors must be to redirect our focus, as teachers and as scholars, toward the practice oflaw. This will take a fundamental change in law professors' ideas about the meaning of their jobs. I am suggesting that law teachers must be prepared to re-examine their deepest assumptions about the current curriculum and pedagogy of law school. MACCRATE REPoRT, supra note I, at 121 passim. On this point, I agree with and follow Carrie Menkel·Mendow, Narrowing the Gap by Narrowing the Field: What~ Missing from the MacCraIe Report-OfSkills, Legal Science and Being a Human Being, 69 WASH. L. REv. 593, 607-15 (1994) (indicating thllt -difficulty'" with Macerate Report is its scientific and deductive description of law and lawyering). 4S ,47 HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 877 1996-1997 878 GEORGIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 31:853 Of course that kind of change will be very difficult, but there is too much at stake in legal education to leave it as it is. r;rhe quality ofjus~ce is dependent on our lawyers. Lawyers and law professors must together rediscover our public calling and public rE~sponsibili· ties. We legal educators must do our part by doing all we can to educate students to be good lawyers.48 48 I am grateful to Daisy Hurst Floyd, Jack Sammons, Tom Shaffer, and Roy Simon for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this Essay. They should not, however, be hold responsible for everything I say here. In other words, if this Essay has made you mad, please do not blame them. HeinOnline -- 31 Ga. L. Rev. 878 1996-1997