London Judgement & Decision Making Group Autumn term 2014 – 2015 Organizers Neil Bramley University College London Contact details: Department of Cognitive, Perceptual & Brain Sciences Room 201, 26 Bedford Way, London, WC1H 0AP UK Telephone: +44 (0) 79 1441 9386 E-mail: neil.bramley.10@ucl.ac.uk Leonardo Weiss-Cohen University College London Contact details: Department of Cognitive, Perceptual & Brain Sciences Room 200, 26 Bedford Way, London, WC1H 0AP UK Telephone: +44 (0) 20 7679 7570 E-mail: l.cohen.12@ucl.ac.uk LJDM website http://www.ljdm.info LJDM members’ (Risk & Decision) list Contact: Dr Marianne Promberger (marianne.promberger@kcl.ac.uk) Seminar Schedule October – December 2014 Wednesdays, 5:00 pm in Room 313, 26 Bedford Way, UCL Psychology 1st October Why are we all here? The origins and history of LJDM Peter Ayton1, Nigel Harvey2 and Larry Phillips3 1 City University, 2University College London and 3London School of Economics 8th October The role of expectancy in human Pavlovian Conditioning Gabrielle Weidemann University of Western Sydney 15th October Subjective and objective decision making in scientific peer review Mike Peacey University of Bristol and University of Bath 22nd October Giving and probability David Reinstein University of Essex 29th October How do risk attitudes affect measured confidence? Chris Starmer University of Nottingham 5th November READING WEEK (NO SEMINAR) 12th November The dynamics of evidence accumulation and choice Takao Noguchi University College London 19th November Cultural norms and identity in coordination games Joanne Laban University of Exeter 26th November Heuristics as special cases of Bayesian Inference Paula Parpart University College London 3rd December Separable processes in the generation of random sequences: Data and a model Rick Cooper Birkbeck University 10th December Developmental differences in causal learning Chris Lucas University of Edinburgh Abstracts 01.10.2014 Why are we all here? The origins and history of LJDM Peter Ayton1, Nigel Harvey2 & Larry Phillips3 1 City University, 2University College London & 3London School of Economics To start the year’s LJDM seminars, we thought that it would be interesting to those attending to learn a little about how the London Judgment and Decision Making Group came into being. We will talk about the origins of the seminar series, the development of research into Judgment and Decision Making in London and the rest of the UK, and the influences on that research of other work within cognition and related areas (e.g., thinking and reasoning, choice models of reaction time, psychophysical judgment). 08.10.2014 The role of expectancy in human Pavlovian Conditioning Gabrielle Weidemann University of Western Sydney Pavlovian conditioning, in which a neutral stimulus (usually referred to as a conditioned stimulus, CS; e.g., a picture on a computer screen) is paired together with a biologically significant stimulus (usually referred to as an unconditioned stimulus, US; e.g., a puff of air to the eye), results in the acquisition of a reflexive response (usually referred to as a conditioned response, CR; e.g., a blink to the picture). The extent to which this learning in humans is the result of a conscious expectancy for the US is the source of much debate. In this talk I will present the results of some experiments which show how expectancy precedes and predicts conditioned eyeblink responses, as well as the results of some studies which show that it is possible to dissociate expectancy from responding. I will explain how it is that these two sets of findings might be reconciled and how this might illuminate the role of expectancy in human Pavlovian Conditioning. 15.10.2014 Modelling the effects of subjective and objective decision making in scientific peer review Mike Peacey University of Bath and University of Bristol The objective of science is to advance knowledge, primarily in two interlinked ways: circulating ideas, and defending or criticizing the ideas of others. Peer review acts as the gatekeeper to these mechanisms. Given the increasing concern surrounding the reproducibility of much published research, it is critical to understand whether peer review is intrinsically susceptible to failure, or whether other extrinsic factors are responsible that distort scientists' decisions. Here we show that even when scientists are motivated to promote the truth, their behaviour may be influenced, and even dominated, by information gleaned from their peers' behaviour, rather than by their personal dispositions. This phenomenon, known as herding, subjects the scientific community to an inherent risk of converging on an incorrect answer and raises the possibility that, under certain conditions, science may not be self-correcting. We further demonstrate that exercising some subjectivity in reviewer decisions, which serves to curb the herding process, can be beneficial for the scientific community in processing available information to estimate truth more accurately. By examining the impact of different models of reviewer decisions on the dynamic process of publication, and thereby on eventual aggregation of knowledge, we provide a new perspective on the ongoing discussion of how the peer-review process may be improved. 22.10.2014 Giving and Probability David Reinstein University of Essex When and how should a fundraiser ask for a donation from someone facing an uncertain “bonus” income?” A standard model of expected utility over outcomes predicts that her Before choice— her ex-ante commitment conditional on her income—will be the same as her choice After the income has been revealed. Deciding “if you win, how much will you donate?” involves a commitment (1) over a donation for a state of the world that may not be realized and (2) over uncertain income. Models involving reference-dependent utility, tangibility, and self-signaling predict more giving Before, while theories of affect predict more giving After. In our online field experiments at UK universities, where commitments to donate were binding giving was larger and more frequent in the Before treatment for male subjects, with a significant gender differential. Our laboratory evidence also found significant effects for men and significant gender differences. Lab treatments isolated distinct mechanisms: for men, donations were higher in all treatments where the donation’s collection was uncertain whether or not the income was known. This supports a self-signaling explanation: commitments realized with a lower probability must involve larger amounts to have the same signalling power. Our results are directly relevant to fundraising and volunteer-recruitment strategies, and offer further evidence that we need to exercise caution in applying expected utility theory in the presence of social preferences. 29.10.2014 How do risk attitudes affect measured confidence? Chris Starmer University of Nottingham We examine confidence in own absolute performance using two elicitation procedures: selfreported (non-incentivised) confidence and an incentivised procedure that elicits the certainty equivalent of a bet based on performance. The former procedure reproduces the “hard-easy effect” (overconfidence in easy tasks and underconfidence in hard tasks) found in a large number of studies using non-incentivised self-reports. The latter procedure produces general underconfidence, which is somewhat reduced when we filter out the effects of risk attitudes. However, even after controlling for risk attitudes our incentivised procedure leads to significant underconfidence, and does not lead to better calibration between confidence and performance than non-incentivised self-reports. Finally, we find that self-reported confidence correlates significantly with features of individual risk attitudes including parameters of individual probability weighting. 12.11.2014 The dynamics of evidence accumulation and choice Takao Noguchi University College London When judging whether a bug is poisonous or whether a person is trustworthy, we often consider multiple pieces of information. Some of the information may help us make better judgement, while others may mislead our judgement. In this talk, I will address how order of information considered impacts on speed and accuracy of judgement, and discuss implications for sequential sampling models. In sequential sampling models, an individual is assumed to accumulate evidence supporting a judgement, and when the accumulated evidence reaches a response criterion, the individual makes a judgement. In these models, accumulation rate is a key to understanding speed and accuracy of judgement, and accumulation rate is typically assumed to be fixed until an accumulation reaches a response criterion. Previous studies, however, report that especially when under time pressure, an individual is likely to evaluate an alternative as attending attribute dimensions (e.g., Lamberts, 1995). These findings indicate that accumulation rate may be based on a subset of dimensions at first, and gradually, more dimensions become incorporated --- accumulation rate is dynamic. Dynamic nature of accumulation rate predicts that when an individual first attends to a dimension that provides misleading information, this individual accumulates evidence for an incorrect judgement at first. As a result, 1) the individual should be slower to make a correct judgement, as the individual has to override initially accumulated evidence, and also 2) the individual should be less likely to make a correct judgement. These predictions were empirically tested and generally supported in various domains. 19.11.2014 Cultural Norms and Identity in Coordination Games Joanne Laban University of Exeter We run experiments with a stag hunt and bargaining coordination game. Using a between-subjects design, we vary the identity of the opponent between someone of the same culture or a different culture. The idea is to see whether cultural norms or identity play a part in coordination decisions. We compare the responses of British and Asian students at the University of Exeter and show the cultural identity of the opponent by physical appearance. The players appear to use cultural stereotypes to predict behaviour, especially in the bargaining game which may require more strategic thought than the stag hunt game. In particular, the British act in way that indicates they believe the Asians will behave more cautiously than other British. According to our results, the stereotype of Asians being cautious is misleading. 26.11.2014 Heuristics as special cases of Bayesian Inference Paula Parpart University College London Bayesian inference models have usually been cast as being rational and at odds with simple heuristic approaches. We show that prominent decision heuristics, take-the-best and tallying, are special cases of Bayesian inference. Why is it possible that simple heuristic are sometimes able to outperform more complex strategies like linear regression? In my talk I will argue that covariance between cues plays an important role and the fact that simple heuristics completely disregard covariance in their cue validity estimates. We developed a Bayesian learning model by extending a popular regularized regression approach (ridge regression) from machine learning. This regularized regression approach contains a penalty term corresponding to a Bayesian prior that reflects the amount of covariance in the environment. By relying on a latent state variable model similar to multivariate regression, our Bayesian model enables us to smoothly move between a model with lots of covariance (linear regression) to one with no covariance (heuristics). Importantly, in the limit, i.e., for a large penalty parameter, the Bayesian model becomes equivalent to the heuristics (cue validities). Thus, our model subsumes both regression and frugal heuristics as extreme cases on a continuum of decision strategies. Interestingly, the optimal performance can be found in the middle most of the time, i.e. between a fully integrative approach and a frugal heuristic approach. This implies that true environmental structure and potentially psychological processing might often lie somewhere between the assumptions of heuristic and standard regression approaches. 03.12.2014 Separable processes in the generation of random sequences: Data and a model Rick Cooper Birkbeck University When participants are required to generate “random” sequences of responses their behaviour typically betrays a number of well-known biases, such as the avoidance of immediate repeats and a tendency to produce stereotyped sub-sequences. These have been accounted for within verbal models in which executive processes modulate schema-based behaviour. In this talk I will first present data from a dual-task study which fractionates the involvement of at least two executive processes in random generation. Following this, I will demonstrate how participant behaviour within the dual-task study can be captured by a general computational model of the interaction of executive sub-processes. 10.12.2014 Developmental differences in causal learning Chris Lucas University of Edinburgh Children learn causal relationships quickly and make far-reaching generalizations from what they observe. I will discuss results showing that in some cases they do so in a manner that is more flexible -- and arguably better -- than adult learners. These results are compatible with at least two kinds of explanations: (1) children have weaker a priori assumptions or expectations than adults, which makes them more sensitive to atypical evidence; and (2) that children and adults respond to evidence and update their beliefs in fundamentally different ways, reflecting differences in their goals and circumstances. I will detail some variations on this latter explanation, drawing on analogies to inference procedures in Bayesian models and optimization, as well as the exploreexploit trade off in active learning. Finally, as time permits I will mention some work in progress that is designed to distinguish between these kinds of explanations and shed light on the processes underlying causal inference.