1 The Paper This paper is concerned with philosophical questions which arise out of theories in psychology, the empirical study of the mind. It differs from the Philosophy of Mind paper in that the topics it covers are more specialised, and require a certain amount of knowledge of the psychological theories involved. The paper divides into three sections: the philosophy of mind, the philosophy of cognitive psychology, and the philosophy of psychoanalysis. You must answer at least three questions, which must be drawn from at least two sections (i.e. it is not possible to answer questions from one section only). If you are doing the Philosophy of Mind paper as well, you cannot answer questions from the first section. 2 Basic Reading A. GENERAL PHILOSOPHY OF MIND Anthologies Rosenthal, David. ed. 1991. The Nature of Mind. New York: Oxford University Press. Perhaps the best anthology around. Extensive selection, less fashionable than others, so less likely to go out of date. Worth buying. Borst, C. V. ed. 1970. The Mind/Brain Identity Theory: a Collection of Papers. London: Macmillan. Dated but quite useful collection of essays on the Type Identity theory. Beakley, Brian, and Stephen Ludlow. eds. 1992. The Philosophy of Mind: Classical Problems/Contemporary Issues. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Interesting collection, with a wide range of historical selections and a good coverage of issues such as imagery, innate ideas and associationism. Books McGinn, Colin. 1997. The Character of Mind: an Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Smith, Peter, and O. R. Jones. 1986. The Philosophy of Mind: an Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Churchland, Paul M. 1988. Matter and Consciousness: a Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Rev. ed. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Kim, Jaegwon. 1996. The Philosophy of Mind. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press. B. PHILOSOPHY OF COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY Anthologies Block, Ned. ed. 1980-1. Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, 2 Vols. London: Methuen. The first volume is about the mind-body problem, the second is about issues in the philosophy of psychology such as imagery and intentionality. Haugeland, John. ed. 1981. Mind Design: Philosophy, Psychology, Artificial Intelligence. Montgomery, Vt.: Bradford Books. (See also Mind design II. Revised and enlarged ed. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1997). Excellent collection of articles on the philosophy of cognitive science. Many of the articles are classics. Lycan, William G. ed. 1990. Mind and Cognition: a Reader. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Useful collection of recent articles on issues in philosophy of psychology. The emphasis tends to be on the issues of folk psychology, the language of thought and eliminative materialism. Boden, Margaret. ed. 1990. The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Excellent collection of articles, though many are printed in other anthologies. Macdonald, C., and G. Macdonald, eds. 1995. Philosophy of Psychology. Debates on Psychological Explanation. Vol.1. Oxford: Blackwell. ——. 1995. Connectionism. Debates on Psychological Explanation. Vol. 2. Oxford: Blackwell. Osherson, Daniel N. et al., eds. 1995. An Invitation to Cognitive Science. 4 Vols. Language; Visual Cognition; Thinking; Methods, Models and Conceptual Issues. 2nd ed. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. All four volumes contain useful introductory essays by psychologists and some philosophers. Books Sterelny, Kim. 1990. The Representational Theory of the Mind: an Introduction. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Clear introduction to the philosophical approach to cognitive science pioneered by Jerry Fodor. Johnson-Laird, Philip. 1993. The Computer and the Mind: an Introduction to Cognitive Science. 2nd ed. London: Fontana. Clear introduction, from a psychologist’s point of view, to the computational theory of the mind (part I) and its applications to the phenomena of vision (part II) learning and memory (part III) and reasoning (part IV). Haugeland, John. 1985. Artificial Intelligence: the Very Idea. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Excellent historical and philosophical survey and defence of traditional artificial intelligence. Cummins, Robert. 1989. Meaning and Mental Representation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Interesting and sophisticated account of the various philosophical theories of mental representation. Clark, Andy. 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. A good up-to-date account of issues in the philosophy of psychology and artificial intelligence. Pinker, Stephen. 1994. The Language Instinct: the New Science of Language and Mind. London: Allen Lane. A lively introduction to the Chomskian revolution and current cognitive psychological approaches to language. Dennett, Daniel. 1993. Consciousness Explained. London: Penguin Books. A provocative book which combines challenging philosophical theses with accounts of suprising results in various areas of cognitive neuroscience. C. PHILOSOPHY OF PSYCHOANALYSIS Freud: the most useful volumes to purchase (in the Penguin edition) are Vols. 1-2, Introductory Lectures and New Introductory Lectures, and Vol. 11, On Metapsychology. Anthologies Wollheim, R. ed. 1974. Freud: A Collection of Critical Essays, (Garden City, N. Y.: Anchor Books) reprinted as Philosophers on Freud: New Evaluations, (New York: Jason Aronson, 1985), out of print. Hopkins, James, and Richard Wollheim. eds. 1982. Philosophical Essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Clark, Peter, and Crispin Wright. eds. 1988. Mind, Psychoanalysis and Science. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Neu, Jerome. ed. 1991. The Cambridge Companion to Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Books Wollheim, R. 1991. Freud. 2nd ed., with Supplementary Preface. London: Fontana. Essential reading. Segal, Hanna. 1979. Klein. London: Fontana. Wollheim, R. 1984. The Thread of Life. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Gardner, S. 1993. Irrationality and the Philosophy of Psychoanalysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 3 Philosophy of Mind See Philosophy of Mind section. Relevant topics here are: physicalism, functionalism and the reduction of the mental; the status of ‘folk psychology’; the causal efficacy of mental content; the explanation of consciousness; psychological laws and psychological explanation; theories of mental content; internalism and externalism about mental content. 4 Philosophy of Cognitive Science A. COMMONSENSE PSYCHOLOGY AND COGNITIVE SCIENCE What is the relation between commonsense psychological explanation and explanations in cognitive science? Fodor (Psychosemantics, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), Introduction and chapter 1) thinks commonsense explanations are backed up by a theory, folk psychology, which posits beliefs and desires as inner causes of behaviour, and that the success of cognitive science shows that this theory is on the right track. He calls this position ‘intentional realism’: i.e. realism about intentional states and their contents. Paul Churchland agrees that folk psychology is a theory, but he thinks it is on the wrong track (see ‘Folk Psychology and the Explanation of Human Behaviour’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 (1988): 209-221; ‘Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes’, Journal of Philosophy 78 (1981): 67-90). Daniel Dennett tries to steer an instrumentalist middle course between Fodor’s and Churchland’s eliminativism (see The Intentional Stance, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), especially the essays ‘True Believers’, and ‘Three Kinds of Intentional Psychology’; see also Dennett’s ‘Real Patterns’, Journal of Philosophy 88 (1991): 27-51, for his latest view). For a good collection of readings, see John Greenwood, ed., The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). B. THE COMPUTATIONAL THEORY OF MIND/ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE Is the mind, or any part of it, a computer? The claim that the mind is a computer should be distinguished from the claim that mental processes can be modelled on computers (this is often taken to be the main claim of artificial intelligence or ‘AI’). An excellent account of the computational theory of mind is John Haugeland, ‘Introduction’, and ‘The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism’, in Mind Design, (Montgomery, Vt.: Bradford Books, 1981). See also Ned Block ‘The Computer Model of the Mind’, in Edward E. Smith and Daniel N. Osherson, eds., An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Vol. 3, Thinking, (2nd ed. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995). For more detail, see Haugeland’s Artificial Intelligence: the Very Idea, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985); and Cummins, Meaning and Mental Representation, (Mass.: MIT Press, 1989), chapter 8. See also Clark Glymour, Thinking things through: an Introduction to Philosophical Issues and Achievements, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992), chapters 12-13; and Johnson-Laird, The Computer and the Mind: an Introduction to Cognitive Science, (London: Fontana, 1993), part I. For a critical assessment of the fundamental elements of the computational theory, see D. H. Mellor, ‘How Much of the Mind is a Computer?’, in his Matters of Metaphysics, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). The computational theory has been famously attacked by John Searle, ‘Minds, Brains and Programs’ (in D. Dennett, and D. Hofstadter, eds., The Minds I: Fantasies and Reflections on Self and Soul, (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1981) and in Boden, Haugeland and Rosenthal, see the replies by Dennett, and Fodor in these anthologies); an interesting critique of AI from a phenomenological standpoint is Hubert Dreyfus, What Computers Can’t Do: a Critique of Artificial Reason, (New York: Harper & Row, 1972). (New edition: What Computers Still Can’t Do, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992)), which also contains an interesting critical history of the early days of AI research. C. THE LANGUAGE OF THOUGHT One of the most influential theories in philosophy of cognitive psychology is Jerry Fodor’s thesis that we think in a ‘Language of Thought’. The idea is that mental processes have a structure that is best explained by postulating sentence-like structures realised in the brain. This was first proposed in his book The Language of Thought, (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1975); the best exposition is the appendix to Psychosemantics: the Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), reprinted in Lycan’s anthology; and ‘Fodor’s Guide to Mental Representation’, Mind 94 (1985): 55-97, reprinted in his Theory of Content & Other Essays (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990). See also Hartry Field, ‘Mental Representation’, Erkenntnis 13 (1978): 9-61, reprinted in Block, Vol. II; and (for an introduction) Sterelny, The Representational Theory of the Mind: an Introduction, (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990). For criticism, see Dennett, ‘A Cure for the Common Code?’, in his Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology, (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1981); Paul and Patricia Churchland, ‘Stalking the Wild Epistemic Engine’, in Lycan; R. Stalnaker, Inquiry, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1984), chapters 1-2; and C. Peacocke, Sense & Content: Experience, Thought and their Relations, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), chapter 8. Fodor has always maintained that the Language of Thought is an empirical theory; Martin Davies has argued that it can be defended through a priori philosophical argument, see ‘Concepts, Connectionism and the Language of Thought’, in William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich, and David E. Rumelhart, eds., Philosophy & Connectionist Theory, (Hillsdale, N. J.: L. Erlbaum Associates, 1991). D. CONNECTIONISM Connectionism understands mental processing in terms of the activation and inhibition of many simple units, connected in various ways. Representation resides in the strengths of the connections between the units, and the subsequent pattern of activation across the whole network. For a short non-technical introduction, see Paul Churchland, ‘Cognitive Activity in Artificial Neural Networks’, in Edward E. Smith and Daniel N. Osherson, eds., An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Volume 3, Thinking. (2nd ed. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995). William Bechtel and Adele Abrahamsen, Connectionism and the Mind: an Introduction to Parallel Processing in Networks, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), is a more technical introduction. Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, edited by Ramsey, Stich and Rumelhart (Hillsdale, N. J.: L. Erlbaum Associates, 1991) is a good anthology. Connectionists claim that their theory provides a substantial alternative to ‘classical’ artificial intelligence and cognitive science research. Are they right? See Paul Smolensky ‘On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism’, Brain & Behavioral Sciences, 1983, for the affirmative answer; and Cummins, ‘The Role of Representations in Connectionist Explanations of Cognitive Capacities’, in Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Fodor and Pylyshyn, ‘Connectionism & Cognitive Architecture’, Cognition, 1988, defend the Language of Thought against Smolensky. See also Fodor and McLaughlin, ‘Connectionism & the Problem of Systematicity: why Smolensky’s Solution doesn’t work’, in Cognition, 1990, which is a reply to Smolensky’s ‘Connectionism, Constituency & the Language of Thought’, in Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, edited by Barry Loewer, and Georges Rey (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991). Some argue that the success of connectionism would support eliminativism about beliefs and desires posited by folk psychology (see (a) above). See Patricia Churchland and Terence Sejnowski, ‘Neural Representation and Neural Computation’, in Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition; and the papers by Ramsey, Stich and Garon, and by Martin Davies in Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Andy Clark, ‘Beyond Eliminativism’, in Mind and Language 4 (1989): 251-279, argues that connectionists need not be eliminativists. E. MODULARITY AND THE FUNCTIONAL STRUCTURE OF THE MIND AND BRAIN One of the distinctive features of cognitive psychology is an approach to psychological structures and capacities through functional analysis—on this mode of explanation see Robert Cummins, The Nature of Psychological Explanation, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1983). Both Chomsky and Fodor have argued for the modularity of various psychological capacities, but the notion of a module has been open to different interpretations. For Chomsky on these matters see, Knowledge of Language: its Nature, Origins, and Use, (New York: Praeger, 1985), Chs. 1 & 2; for Fodor, The Modularity of Mind: an Essay on Faculty Psychology, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1983), and ‘The Modularity of Mind: A Precis’, in his A Theory of Content & Other Essays, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990). Within psychological work itself the notion of modularity has become of central concern partly through single-case studies of patients with impairments that reflect dissociations of various psychological capacities from each other: the broadest overview of the approach, and the methodology behind it can be found in Tim Shallice’s From Neuropsychology to Mental Strucure, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988). For evidence of modularity in language abilities see Neil Smith and I. Tsimpli, The Mind of a Savant: Language Learning and Modularity, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995). For further application of the notion of modules involved in psychological capacities see also Simon Baron-Cohen’s Mindblindness for an account of this in our abilities to ascribe mental properties to ourselves and others; contrast this with the approach of Harold Wellman in The Child’s Theory of Mind, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990) and Alison Gopnik and Andrew N. Meltzoff in Words, Thoughts and Theories, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1998). One of the other startling areas in which modularity theses seem strikingly to be confirmed is work on certain specialised areas of visual recognition, for example face recognition. On this see, Farah in S. M. Kosslyn and D. N. Osherson, eds., An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Vol. 2, Visual Cognition, (2nd ed., Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), and the chapter on face recognition in Vicki Bruce, Patrick R. Green, and Mark A. Georgeson, Visual Cognition: Physiology, Psychology, and Ecology, (Hove: Psychology Press, 1996). See also A. Karmiloff-Smith, Beyond Modularity: a Developmental Perspective on Cognitive Science, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992); and Jay L. Garfield, ed., Modularity in Knowledge Representation and Natural-language Understanding, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987). F. THE THEORY OF VISION The main example of a psychological theory used by contemporary philosophers is the theory of vision. David Marr’s theory has been one of the most influential, see his Vision: A Computational Investigation into Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information, (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman and Co., 1982), chapter 1, for an account of the project. John Fisby, Seeing: Illusion, Brain, and Mind, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979); Philip Johnson-Laird, The Computer and the Mind, (2nd ed., London: Fontana, 1993), provide non-technical introductions, and philosophical accounts of Marr’s theory can be found in Sterelny, The Representational Theory of the Mind, (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990) and in Michael Tye’s The Imagery Debate (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991). A number of papers discuss internalist versus externalist interpretations of Marr’s theory: Gabriel Segal, ‘Seeing What is Not There’, Philosophical Review 98 (1989): 189-214; Tyler Burge, ‘Individualism and Psychology’, Philosophical Review 95 (1986): 3-45; Martin Davies, ‘Individualism and Perceptual Content’, Mind 100 (1991): 461484; and Gabriel Segal, ‘In Defence of a Reasonable Individualism’, Mind 100 (1991): 485-494; Frances Egan, ‘Must Psychology be Individualistic?’, Philosophical Review (1991): 179-203, and ‘Individualism, Computation & Perceptual Content’, Mind 101 (1992): 443-459. For accounts of recent developments in vision research see S. M. Kosslyn and D. N. Osherson, eds., An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Vol. 2, Visual Cognition, (2nd ed., Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), in particular the essays by Nakayama, et al.; Goodale; Kosslyn; and Spelke, et. al. You might also look at Irvin Rock’s The Logic of Perception, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1983), and his posthumous collection, Indirect Perception, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1997); Stephen M. Kosslyn’s Image & Brain: the Resolution of the Imagery Debate, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994); and possibly Shimon Ullman’s High Level Vision: Object Recognition and Visual Cognition, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996). For a very different approach to perception and psychology as a whole see J. J. Gibson, An Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, (Boston, Mass.: Houghton Mifflin, 1979), and his earlier The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems, (London: Allen & Unwin, 1966). Gibson’s approach is emphatically anti-representational, yet his views have influenced some of the best recent work in visual cognition. Further issues about visual cognition are raised in an interdisciplinary volume, Perception, edited by Kathleen Akins, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), the introduction of which is a good starting point—some of this work discusses ideas raised in Dennett’s Consciousness Explained, particularly those of chapter 5; also have a look at Naomi Eilan, Rosaleen McCarthy, and Bill Brewer, eds., Spatial Representation: Problems in Philosophy and Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), see in particular essays by O’Keefe, Cooper, Spelke, et al., Meltzoff, Atkinson, Braddick, and McCarthy, for psychologists on various aspects of visual perception and spatial perception in general, and contributions by Campbell, Peacocke, and Eilan, among philosophers for relevant material. G. THE EXPLANATORY AND CAUSAL ROLE OF CONTENT What explanatory or causal role does the content of representational states play in psychological theories? It has been suggested that content plays no causal role in producing behaviour if a computational theory of cognition is true, since in a computational system the form, but not the content, of representations determines how they are processed. See Cummins, Meaning and Mental Representation, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1989), chapter 10; and G. Segal, ‘The Causal Efficacy of Content’, Philosophical Studies 67 (1991): 1-30. Does psychology use or need to use an internalist notion of content, according to which the content of psychological states supervenes on intrinsic properties of their bearers, or an externalist notion, according to which content is partly determined by environment? Chapter 2 of Fodor’s Psychosemantics, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), argues for internalism, while Burge’s ‘Individuation and Causation in Psychology’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989): 303-322, defends externalism. See also the papers on internalist and externalist interpretations of Marr’s theory of vision (f), especially the paper by Burge. H. LINGUISTICS Linguistics is the empirical study of language. The theories of Noam Chomsky, arguably the leading practitioner in the field, have been of particular interest to philosophers. Chomsky rejects any conception of language as an abstract object or a social practice. Instead, he sees language as a faculty of the mind, and linguistics as a branch of cognitive psychology which studies the properties of the language faculty. On this view there are no linguistic facts over and above the psychological facts about individual language users: so the theory of grammar offers both a description of the structure of a language and a model of a speaker’s competence (i.e. his or her knowledge of the language). Here we have the much disputed claim for the psychological reality of grammar. This is of interest to philosophers both because it raises questions of how to tell which is the correct grammar of a speaker’s language, given his or her linguistic behaviour, and because competence, as understood by Chomsky, is a species of tacit knowledge. Furthermore, Chomsky argues that a speaker’s ability to acquire native competence depends upon an innate knowledge of the principles of universal grammar: a common species-specific inheritance due to the initial state of the language faculty. Philosophers have contested this innateness hypothesis and questioned the grounds for postulating tacit knowledge of grammar. For a guide to Chomsky’s views on the above issues, the nature of rule-following, and non-existence of shared public languages, see his Knowledge of Language: its Nature, Origins, and Use, (New York: Praeger, 1985), and his ‘Language and Nature’, Mind 104 (1995): 1-61, reprinted in New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000). For platonist and behaviourist alternatives to Chomsky’s mentalism, see J. J. Katz’s useful anthology,The Philosophy of Linguistics, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985). For a detailed philosophical discussion of Chomsky’s views, there is Fred D’Agostino’s Chomsky’s System of Ideas, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), and a collection of philosophical essays edited by A. George, Reflections on Chomsky, (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989). For an accessible introduction to the empirical issues surrounding the study of language see Lila R. Gleitman, and Mark Liberman, eds., An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Vol. 1, Language, (2nd ed. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press , 1995). 5 Philosophy of Psychoanalysis This part of the paper examines the central psychoanalytic concepts and issues in the philosophy of psychoanalysis, with reference to general issues in the philosophy of mind and special attention to the grounds of legitimation of psychoanalytic claims. Central topics are: the view that psychoanalysis is continuous with commonsense psychology, the critique of psychoanalysis as a science, the concept of the divided mind, the concepts of Kleinian theory, the relation of psychoanalytic theory to connectionism (see above), the psychoanalytic theory of sexuality, and the concept of unconscious mental states. A. SELECTED WORKS OF FREUD Editions Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, translated under the general editorship of James Strachey, in collaboration with Anna Freud, 24 Volumes, (London: Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psychoanalysis, c1964). In all libraries. Pelican Freud Library, translation originally published as ‘The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud’, 15 Volumes, (Harmondsworth: Penguin, c1984). (Volume numbers are to each in turn.) Texts You should aim to read as many of as possible; essential reading is starred. Studies on Hysteria, (1895d [1893-95]) (with Josef Breuer) SE 2/PFL 3, Ch.1, ‘Preliminary communication’. * The Interpretation of Dreams, (1900a) SE 4-5/PFL 4, Chs.2-3. * On Dreams, (1901a) SE 5. Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality, (1905d) SE 7/PFL 7. ‘Fragments of an analysis of a case of hysteria’, (‘Dora’) (1905e [1901]) SE 7/PFL 8. ‘Notes upon a case of obsessional neurosis’, (‘The Ratman’) (1909d) SE 10/PFL 9. * Five Lectures on Psycho-Analysis, (1910a [1909]) SE 11 (and in Penguin, Two Short Accounts of Psychoanalysis, 1962). ‘Repression’, (1915d) SE 14/PFL 11. ‘The unconscious’, (1915e) SE 14/PFL 11. * Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, (1916-17 [1915-17]) SE 15-16/PFL 1. ‘From the History of an Infantile Neurosis’, (‘The Wolfman’) (1918b [1914]) SE 24 /PFL 9. The Ego and the Id, (1923b) SE 19/PFL 11. * New Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, (1933a [1932]) SE 22/PFL 2. An Outline of Psychoanalysis, (1940a [1938]) SE 23/PFL 15. B. REASON EXPLANATION AND PSYCHOANALYTIC EXPLANATION Dreams and symptoms; the nature and scope of commonsense explanation by reasons. Smith, P., and O. R. Jones. 1986. The Philosophy of Mind: an Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. See esp. chs. 9 and 17. Davidson, D. 1980. ‘Actions, Reasons, Causes’. In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Lepore, E., and B. McLaughlin. 1985. ‘Actions, Reasons, Causes, Intentions’. In E. Lepore, and B. McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford: Blackwell. Sayre-McCord, G. 1989. ‘Functional Explanation and Reasons as Causes’. In James E. Tomberlin, ed., Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory, Philosophical Perspectives 3, Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Pub. Co. C. PSYCHOANALYSIS AND EXPLANATION BY REASONS i. The applicability of the belief/desire model to psychoanalysis Wollheim, R. 1991. Freud. 2nd ed. London: Fontana. Supplementary Preface, pp. xxvi-xxxviii. Hopkins, J. 1982. ‘Introduction: Philosophy and Psychoanalysis’. In R. Wollheim, and J. Hopkins, eds. Philosophical essays on Freud. Cambridge University Press. See esp. pp. xix-xxvi. Cavell, M. 1986. ‘Metaphor, Dreamwork, and Irrationality’. In E. LePore ed.,Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford: Blackwell. Freud, The Interpretation of Dreams, ch.2, ‘Analysis of a Specimen Dream’. Freud, On Dreams, (1901a) SE 5. ii. Psychoanalysis as an extension of commonsense psychology The nature of the extension, and its consequences for methodology. Sketches of the mode of extension Hopkins, J. 1982. ‘Introduction: Philosophy and Psychoanalysis’. In R. Wollheim, and J. Hopkins, eds. Philosophical essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hopkins, J. 1988. ‘Epistemology and Depth Psychology: critical notes on The Foundations of Psychoanalysis’. In Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Hopkins, J. 1991. ‘The Interpretation of Dreams’. In Jerome Neu, ed., The Cambridge companion to Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Methodological critiques of psychoanalysis Popper, K. 1969. ‘Conjectures and Refutations’. In Conjectures and Refutations: the Growth of Scientific Knowledge. 3rd ed. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. See esp. pp.33-9. Grünbaum, A. 1986. ‘Précis of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique’. In Clark and Wright, eds.; also (with Commentary and Response) in Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1986, or, at length, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984. Pts. I-II. Methodological defense of psychoanalysis Hopkins, J. 1992. ‘Psychoanalysis, Interpretation, and Science’. In J. Hopkins, and A. Savile, eds., Psychoanalysis, Mind, and Art: Perspectives on Richard Wollheim. Oxford: Blackwell. D. CASE HISTORIES AND THEIR INTERPRETATION Dora Freud, ‘Fragments of an analysis of a case of hysteria’, (‘Dora’) (1905e [1901]) SE 7/PFL 8. Cummins, R. 1983. The Nature of Psychological Explanation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Ch.4, sec.3, pp.142-61. The Ratman Freud, ‘Notes upon a case of obsessional neurosis’, (‘The Ratman’) (1909d) SE 10/PFL 9. Hopkins, J. 1982. ‘Introduction: Philosophy and Psychoanalysis’. In Wollheim and Hopkins, eds., pp.xxx-xxxvi. Gay, P. 1988. Freud: A Life for Our Time. London: Dent. See index. Glymour, C. 1982. ‘Freud, Kepler and the Clinical Evidence’. In Wollheim and Hopkins, eds. E. FREUD AND CONNECTIONISM The text of Freud’s which this topic is concerned with is his ‘Project for a scientific psychology’, Standard Edition 1 (not in Pelican Freud Library). Wollheim, R. 1991. Freud. 2nd ed. London: Fontana. Ch.1. Glymour, C. 1991. ‘Freud’s Androids’. In Jerome Neu, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. F. PSYCHOANALYSIS, AKRASIA AND SELF-DECEPTION Davidson, D. 1980. ‘How is weakness of the Will Possible?’. In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Pears, D. 1984. Motivated Irrationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Chs. 1-3, and, optionally, Chs. 6-10. ——. 1975. ‘The Paradoxes of Self-deception’. In Questions in the Philosophy of Mind. London: Duckworth. G. DIVISION OF THE MIND Freud, ‘The unconscious’, SE 14/PFL 11. Freud, ‘The dissection of the psychical personality’, New Introductory Lectures, Lecture 31. Sartre, J.-P. 1958. Being and Nothingness: an Essay on Phenomenological Ontology. Translated by Hazel E. Barnes. London: Routledge. pp.50-4. Davidson, D. 1982. ‘Paradoxes of Irrationality’. In Hopkins and Wollheim, eds.; or ‘Deception and Division’, in Jon Elster ed., The Multiple Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986. Pears, D. 1984. Motivated Irrationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Ch.5; or ‘Goals and Strategies of Self-deception’, in Elster, ed., The Multiple Self.. Cummins, R. 1983. The Nature of Psychological Explanation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Ch.4, sec.3, pp.142-61. H. FREUD’S THEORY OF SEXUALITY Freud, Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality, (1905d) SE 7/PFL 7. Freud, Introductory Lectures, SE 16/PFL 1, Lectures 20 and 21. Wollheim, R. 1991. Freud. 2nd ed. London: Fontana. Ch.4. Neu, J. 1991. ‘Freud and Perversion’. In Jerome Neu, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Klein, M. ‘The Development of a Child’, and ‘Personification in the play of Children’, in her Love, Guilt and Reparation, and other works, 1921-1945. London: Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-analysis, 1975. (see below, topic 8). I. INTERNAL OBJECTS Freud, ‘Mourning and melancholia’, (1917e [1915]) SE 14/PFL 11. Hinshelwood, R. 1991. A Dictionary of Kleinian Thought. 2nd ed. London: Free Association. See the entries on Internal Objects. J. KLEIN Mitchell, J., ed., The Selected Melanie Klein, (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986) contains a good selection. Melanie Klein’s complete works (Hogarth Press, 1975) are available in libraries. Klein’s most important papers can also be found in the Virago paperback editions, Love, Guilt and Reparation and Other Works 1921-1945 (LGR), and Envy and Gratitude and Other Works 1946-1963 (EG) (London: Virago, 1988). Essential reading ‘The development of a child’, in LGR. ‘Early development’, in LGR. ‘Personification in the play of children’, in LGR. ‘A contribution to the psychogenesis of manic-depressive states’, in LGR. ‘The importance of symbol-formation in the development of the ego’, in LGR. ‘Notes on some schizoid mechanisms’, in EG. On Klein Segal, H. 1973. Introduction to the Work of Melanie Klein. London: Hogarth. New enl. ed. London: Karnac and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, 1988; or Segal, H. 1979. Klein. London: Fontana. Hopkins, J. 1987. ‘Synthesis in the Imagination: Psychoanalysis, Infantile Experience and the Concept of an Object’. In J. Russell, ed., Philosophical Perspectives on Developmental Psychology. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Hinshelwood, R. 1991. A Dictionary of Kleinian Thought. 2nd ed. London: Free Association. To be consulted for its entries on individual Kleinian concepts. Segal, H. 1981. The Work of Hanna Segal: A Kleinian Approach to Clinical Practice. New York: Aronson. See esp. ‘The importance of symbol-formation’. ——. 1991. Dream, Phantasy and Art. London: Routledge. See esp. ch.3, on symbolism. Projective identification Klein, ‘Notes on some schizoid mechanisms’, in EG. Hinshelwood, R. 1991. A Dictionary of Kleinian Thought. 2nd ed. London: Free Association. ‘Projective Identification’, ‘Projection’, ‘Splitting’. Spillius, Elizabeth. ed. 1988. Melanie Klein Today: Developments in Theory and Practice. London: Routledge. Part Two, especially Introduction, Betty Joseph, and Herbert Rosenfeld. Wollheim, R. 1984. The Thread of Life. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, pp.270-5. ——. 1982. ‘The Bodily Ego’. In Wollheim and Hopkins, eds. K. UNCONSCIOUS MENTAL STATES Freud, ‘The unconscious’, (1915) SE 14 /PFL 11, Pt. I, ‘Justification for the concept of the unconscious’. Searle, J. 1989. ‘Consciousness, Unconsciousness, and Intentionality’. Philosophical Topics 17: 193-209. See also Philosophy of Mind on Consciousness and Experience.