Nontreatment Decisions for Defective Newborns: Moral, Ethical, and Legal Dilemmas Alice Nystel Bioethics December 9, 198 2 - 00562 It has been said that "[t]he law always lags behind the most advanced thinking in every area. It must wait until the theologians and the moral leaders and events have created some common ground, some consensus." 1 Euthanasia is one such area in which the law has lagged behind the medical profession since new technology and new advances in medical science present the medical profession with moral and ethical dilemmas demanding immediate resolution; the cumbersome machinery of the law does not decide important questions of life and death with such immediacy. The moral and ethical dilemmas of euthanasia have become increasingly problematical as new advances in medicine allow doctors to intervene in situations formerly thought hopeless and to prolong life in many such cases, particularly in the area of pediatrics. In the words of one physician: The care of the newborn infant has become increasingly complex. As knowledge and technology advance, the pediatrician is able to intervene and improve the chances for survival of the highrisk newborn. Formerly, nature took its course uninfluenced by medical treatment. Now, active treatment may lead to survival. The withholding of treatment may lead to death. The physician now must make a moral decision to treat or not to treat in such cases. The decision for nontreatment is not an easy one to make, and reluctance to make the choice of nontreatment has been explained by reasons of the realization of the finality of the decision for death, the fear that any choice for death - 00563 will eventually result in the strong indiscriminately killing the weak (the "slippery slope" argument), the possibility of nontreatment as discrimination against the defective child, and the physician's perception of death 3 as failure. A short discussion of what euthanasia is is a necessary introduction to the arguments and analysis this paper presents. The word itself is derived from two Greek words, "eu" meaning easy or painless, and "thanatos", meaning death. Euthanasia has been described as "death 5 6 with dignity" and "natural death". The different types of euthanasia are active, passive, voluntary and involuntary. Active euthanasia is the commission of a positive death7 . . . producing act , such as administering a lethal dose of a drug. Passive euthanasia is the failure to take certain measures necessary to prolong life: omission. causing death by Voluntary euthanasia is euthanasia committed at the patient's request or with his consent, and involuntary is that committed without the patient's consent. This paper will explore the questions and ethical problems raised by involuntary, passive euthanasia in the context of the defective newborn. Passive euthanasia has been described by one commentator in the following way: "sustaining life is a g good but not an absolute good." The issue is an extremely - 00564 controversial one and raises many questions, including those of criminal liability,^ civil liability, 10 ethics, 11 decisionmaking problems, including that of determining quality of life, and the possibilities for abuse. As stated by Justice 12 Paul J. Lxacos, author of the Saikewicz opinion, "these decisions .[on the meaning of life and death, when life starts and when it ends, on the use of the new technologies to maintain and create life] are not purely medical questions; they are not purely questions of science and technology, but rather they are questions involving ethical considerations, social considerations, moral considerations, as 13 well as medical and legal questions." The law has been slow in catching up with the medical profession in making these important decisions on life and death; no reported cases directly on point could be found for the issue of nontreatment of the defective newborn. However, a discussion of related case law may prove to be helpful in evaluating the law's possible position on this issue. The right to refuse treatment is an important part of the issue of euthanasia in general, and the cases which speak of this right may indicate how the courts will deal with nontreatment decisions. The right to refuse medical treatment can be said14to have arisen out of the doctrine of informed consent. In Schloendorff v Society of New "3" 00565 York Hospital, 15 a landmark case on informed consent, Justice Cardozo stated that the principle of informed consent protected the right of self-determination for individuals of sound mind and that every adult of sound mind had the right to determine what should be done with 16 his body. The right to consent to decisions on treat- ment logically extends to the right to refuse treatment as well, since the right to consent is meaningless without the right to refuse. 17 18 In Ronnie v. Klein, the court held that the patient, who was undergoing psychotropic drug therapy for schizophrenia, had the right to refuse treatment in the absence of a strong countervailing state interest. The court balanced the state's interests, in confining a mentally ill person who presents a danger to himself or society and in exercising the state's parens patrie power to care for those unable to care for themselves, against the patient's interest in exercising individual autonomy, and held that whether the potential benefits of treatment are worth the risks is a purely personal decision of the patient's which should be free from state interference in the absence of a strong state interest. This protection of individual self-determination was also stated m a 1960 decision. 19 Natanson v. Kline, The court in Natanson held that every individual should be considered the master of his own body - - - 0i and therefore able to refuse medical treatment, even that 20 necessary to save his life, if he is of sound mind. The right to refuse life-prolonging medical treatment was recognized for the competent terminallyill patient in Satz v. Perlmutter 21 and for the incompetent terminally-ill or vegetative patient in a line of cases 22 beginning with the much-publicized In re Quxnlan. One court has held that the right to refuse life-prolonging medical treatment, in certain circumstances, must extend to the incompetent patient as well as the competent patient 23 because "the value of human dignity extends to both." These decisions have typically stated that the right to refuse treatment is part of the constitutional right of privacy, recognized by the Supreme Court as being applicable to family and personal matters in such cases as 24 25 Griswold v. Connecticut , Roe v. Made , and Prince v. Massachusetts. absolute, 27 26 However, as this right of privacy is not . . . the courts have used a balancing test, weighing the asserted state's interests against the individual's interest in individual autonomy: A person has a strong interest in being free from nonconsensual invasion of his bodily integrity, and a constitutional right of privacy that may be asserted to prevent unwanted infringements of bodily integrity. Thus a competent person has a general right to refuse treatment in appropriate circumstances, to be determined by balancing the individual interest against countervailing - 5 - 00567 State interests, particularly the State interest in the preservation of life. In striking that balance, account is to be taken of the prognosis and of the magnitude of the proposed invasion. The same right is also extended to an incompetent person to be exercised through a "substituted judgment" on his behalf. The decision should be that which would be made by the incompetent person, if he were competent, taking into account his actual interests and preferencesgand also his present and future incompetency. As one commentator stated, however, the developing case law on the right to refuse treatment and the constitutional right of privacy may not be applicable in all cases, particularly in the context of a nontreatment decision 29 for the defective newborn. This position is based on the language in the Quinlan decision, and in the cases following Quinlan, limiting the right to refuse life-prolonging or 3 0 life-sustaining treatment to "appropriate circumstances" and on the fact that the patients in those cases were adult patients afflicted with either terminal illnesses or permanent vegetative conditions. These decisions were all quality of life decisions in which the courts balanced the patient's right to refuse treatment against the quality of life to be preserved, taking into consideration the patient's prognosis with or without the treatment, the intrusiveness and discomfort 31 of the treatment, and the accompanying risks of treatment. 32 For example, xn the Saikewicz . . decision, the court stressed the patient's inability to understand his present situation 005 or prognosis or the purpose of the chemotherapy that he would undergo if treated, due to his profound mental retardation; the court stressed also the seriousness of the side effects (severe nausea, loss of hair, bladder irritation, anemia) and the limited prognosis even with treatment 33 versus the prognosis without treatment. The situation of the defective newborn is arguably different from that of a patient such as Joseph Saikewicz since the quality of life for defective newborns seems more hopeful with the possibility of future medical advances to correct defects. Even if the life of the defective newborn is grievously afflicted, some believe that it may be preferrable to no life at all to one who has never experienced a life free 3H from such defects. However, quality-of-life may be a consideration in the decision of treatment or nontreatment of defective newborns. There are approximately 30,000 severely defective 35 and deformed babies born each year xn the Unxted States. Ellis, in his article Letting Defective Babies Die: Who 36 Decides? , describes a severely defective newborn as "one who is not likely to survive without surgical and medical intervention and whose prognosis, even assuming this intervention, may be poor in terms of cognitive life and minimal functioning."37 The types of severe defects are varied, but some of the more common are anencephaly, 7 00569 hydocephaly, Down's syndrome (mongolism), spina bifida, and encephalomeningocele. Aneeephaly is one of the most severe birth defects, being partial or total absence of the brain. 38 A baby with this condition has been termed by one medico-legal 39 dictionary "a fetal monster without a brain." A newborn with this condition has little if any chance for cognitive function; Ellis comments that newborns with anencephaly are rarely treated and are sometimes not even fed so that HO death may come more quickly. Hydrocephaly is characterized by increased free fluid in the cranial cavity, resulting in enlargement of the head. HI The symtoms are quite severe and are described as follows: Bulging of the forehead, protrusion of the parietal areas and extension of the occipital region are characteristic changes.... The skin of the scalp is thin and stretched and its veins are dilated.... The head cannot be held up, and walking and talking are delayed. The legs are spastic, the tendon reflexes increased and convulsions may occur. Anorexia, vomiting, and emaciation complicate severe cases. As a rule, hydrocephalic children are dull and lethargic. Blindness can develop, but hearing and the auditory memory may be good. Physical and mental development depend on several factors, such as rapidity of onset, intracranial pressure, compensatory growth of the head, nature of the basic malformations and progress or arrest of the progress. Such variability makes the prognosis and^evaluation of therapeutic measures difficult. Thus, although mental function may be impaired, the degree 01)570 of mental impairment may not be predictable at birth. Down's syndrome is a chromosomal disorder producing mental retardation and is marked by a distinctive 43 physical appearance. The mental retardation can be severe, with an average I.Q. of anywhere from 3 5 (for trisomy 21 mongolism) to 62; it has however, been said that mongoloid children are typically the trainable mentally handicapped and can be taught simple skills. Mongolism is often accompanied by other serious physical defects, such as heart defects and bowel obstructions, which require surgery to prevent death of the newborn; these accompanying 45 defects may provoke a decision not to treat the newborn. Spina bifida is one of the most common birth defects and generally involves a defective closure of the vertebral column, which increases the risk of 46 meningeal infections leading to death or b r a m damage. Symptoms of this condition include a malformed and exposed spinal cord, paralysis of the lower extremities, bowel and bladder 47 • dysfunction, and hydrocephalus. As with the condition of hydrocephalus alone, predictions of mental impairment cannot be accurately made at birth. One child who survived this condition committed suicide at the age of twelve as a result of emotional scars caused by the birth defect; his physical defects had been skillfully treated but the operations had left him with an unsteady gait and a hunchback posture. 48 -9" 00571 Encephalomeningocele, like anencephaly, is an extremely severe birth defect. Newborns with this con- dition have brains that protrude from the skull, and surgery often means removing substantial portions of the brain 49 to close the cranial vault. Therefore, severe mental and motor dysfunction is symptomatic of this condition. All of these conditions are severe enough to make the question of nontreatment arise. Nontreatment in such situations has apparently not been uncommon.^ Many physicians have admitted 51 practicing passive euthanasia or being in favor of it. Results of a 1971 poll of physicians at the University of Washington Medical School showed that 80% had practiced passive euthanasia and 8 7% favored it. 52 A reason for this is suggested by the court in Saikewicz: Prior to the development of such new techniques [i.e. chemotherapy] the physician perceived his duty as that of making every conceivable effort to prolong life. On the other hand, the context in which such an ethos prevailed did not provide the range of options available to the physician today in terms of taking steps to postpone death irrespective of the effect on the patient. With the development of the new techniques, serious questions as to what may constitute acting in,-^he best interests of the patient have arisen. Such an argument, that treatment may not be in the best interests of the patient, may also be used in the context of the defective newborn. Quality of life has been a consideration of what is in the "best interests" ~ 1 0 " 00572 of the patient, not in the sense that a life was not worth saving because of economic or societal reasons but in the sense that a life might be so grievously afflicted that the one afflicted would not want to live in such a fashion. In Saiewicz, the court stated that rather than viewing "quality of life" as demeaning the value of the life of one who is mentally retarded, the term should be viewed as referring to a continuing state of pain and disorientation inflicted by treatment on one incapable of understanding, and the court questioned whether such "quality of life" was m the best interests of the patient. Robertson, in his article Defective Newborns: 54 Involuntary Euthanasia of A Legal Analysis ,55 also presents such a position: Thus the strongest claim for not treating the defective newborn is that treatment seriously harms the infant's own interests whatever may be the effects on others. When maintaining his life involves great physical and psychological suffering for the patient, a reasonable person might conclude that such a life is not worth living. Presumably the patient, if fully Informed and able to communicate, would agree. One then would be morally justified in withholding lifesaving treatment if such action served t^gadvance the best interests of the patient. The quality-of-life argument, as Robertson asserts, is strongest in the case of the profoundly retarded or grossly deformed newborn. In his article, Treatment of Myelomeningocele, 57 Results of Lorber asserts that - 00573 quality of life for a newborn facing a long succession of operations, hospital admissions, and other deprivations, with the end result being a combination of gross physical defects and retarded intellectual development, is such that many people would deem such a life not worth saving (presumably if they themselves were facing such a life). However, judging the quality of life for another raises serious questions. If the person making the judg- ment is a parent, a conflict of interest is obvious. The parent cannot be an objective, disinterested decisionmaker (like the judge in Saikewicz) because the parent will be directly affected by a nontreatment decision. A parent may be considering, in making such a decision, the high cost of treatment (it can be astronomical if the infant is in a special neo-natal intensive care unit), the family financial situation, stability or lack thereof in the marriage, career responsibilities, and the emotional burdens of raising a severely handicapped child. Even if the decision-maker is neutral, problems of actually knowing what is in the best interests of another and what another would want for himself exist, in addition to the difficulty 58 of making an accurate prediction of the extent of disability. The infant's quality-of-life, if the infant is treated, seems minimal compared to a reasonably normal person, but to one who has never known anything else and cannot know - 0574 what he is incapable of experiencing, such a life may be preferrable to no life at all. a position: One court has stated such "[o]ne of the most deeply held beliefs of our society is that life — whether experienced with or without 59 a major physical handicap — is more precious than non-life." Opposing this view, that a severely afflicted life is better than no life at all, is a view that personal function, rather than biological function, is what determines quality of life and humanness and that one who is without cognitive ability "is no longer really 6 0 a human being, no longer a person, no longer really alive." This argu- ment may have some validity in the context of a person like Karen Quinlan who lapses into an irreversible vege- tative coma, because comparisons can be made between former quality of life and present or future quality of life and the person, as she had been, may no longer exist. However, in the context of the defective newborn, to say that such an infant is not a person raises serious questions of the possibility of abuse of such non-person classifications. Some commentators stress the abuse of the concept of "humanity" in historical practices of discrimination and atrocities, such as slavery, witchhunts, and the mass extermination of non-Aryans denied person status by the Nazis. 61 -00S55 POTENTIAL CRIMINAL LIABILITY In addition to the ethical questions raised by a nontreatment decision, a parent who decides that nontreatment is in the best interests of the Infant runs the risk of incurring criminal liability. The courts have not yet ruled directly on the question of criminal liability for q nontreatment decision affecting defective newborns, but a 62 lack of case law on point does not necessarily indicate that criminal liability will not follow a nontreatment decision. Statutory law on criminal homicide, and injury to a child is still applicable, as is case law under these . . . 63 statutes. A person commits criminal homicide in Texas if he intentionally, knowingly, recklessly, or with criminal 67 negligence causes the death of an individual. homicide is broken down into several offenses: Criminal murder, capital murder, voluntary manslaughter, involuntary man65 slaughter, and criminally negligent homicide. The offense of murder is defined as intentionally 66 or knowingly causing the death of an individual. A person may be criminally liable for murder by omission if he has a legal duty to protect another, with knowledge or gross negligence he fails to act, andg nsuch failure proximately gg causes the death of the other. In Martinez v. State , the court held that "[mlurder can be committed by voluntary and - 00576 malicious neglect. The omission or neglect to perform a duty resulting in death, such as of a mother failing to feed her child, may constitute murder where the omission was willful and there was a deliberate intent to cause 69 death [emphasis added]." The much-publicized incident at Johns Hopkins University Hospital, in which a mongoloid newborn was allowed to starve to death as a result of the parents' refusal to consent to surgery to correct an intes70 t m a l obstruction, . . . seems alarmingly similar to the situ- ation in Martinez since the infant was not fed (it could not be because of inability to digest food), and starved to death,and the parents had been informed that nontreatment would result in death. There would be, however, a question 71 of causation : whether death was caused by starvation or the defect itself. 7 2The Martinez decision was followed in Harrington v. State' , in which the parents were jointly convicted of the murder of their two year old daughter by starvation. The court held that each parent has a duty to support his/her minor children, and that both parents may be guilty of an intentional failure to provide sufficient food and care for a child unless it is shown that one parent has sole and exclusive custody. Therefore, both parents risk criminal liability for a nontreatment decision resulting In the infant's death. Failure to provide medical care, hinted at by the court in Harrington, has also been held to be a breach of the parental duty to support minor children. In Dillon 73 v. State, the parents were convicted of involuntary manslaughter for starving their daughter to death; they had been indicted for murder for failing to provide food and medical care in breach of their parental duty, which resulted in the infant's death. The court found that the parents recklessly disregarded a substantial risk that the infant's death would result from lack of feeding, of which they were or should have been aware (this is the standard 74for involuntary manslaughter). In a case more relative to the situation of the defective newborn (the above cases involved normal children), a mother was convicted of murder of her newborn daughter by starvation; the infant was born with a cleft palate and a harelip. impossible. The defects made feeding difficult but not The mother stated that she felt that the child would be "better off" dead than alive because she felt the child would be tormented all her life because of her defects. The mother's decision to starve the child was apparently motivated by emotional and family pressures: she had an insecure marriage, caring for the child was a strain, her husband disavowedthe parentage of the and all her pressures adoptive 7 5 child, mother rejected child also. These are - 16 - 00578 which the parents of severely defective newborns may face. Of course, in this case there was no question of causation of death since the infant was able to eat relatively normally, unlike the Johns-Hopkins mongoloid infant. Criminal liability other than criminal homicide may exist for the nontreatment decision: parents could incur criminal liability for injury to a child. Texas 76 Penal Code Ann. Sec. 22 . 04- provides that a person commits the offense of injury to a child if he intentionally, knowingly, recklessly, or with criminal negligence, by act or omission, engages in conduct that causes serious bodily injury, serious physical or mental deficiency or impairment, disfigurement or deformity, or bodily injury to a child fourteen years of age or younger. This provision is broad enough to cover the situation of nontreatment of a defective newborn, in which the infant dies as a result of nontreatment or is injured by nontreatment (if the infant survives). Here again, causation is a problem; it may be questionable whether the defect 7 7 itself or nontreatment caused the statutory "injury." 78 The court in Ahearn v. State held that "[w]here the parents' omission or neglect to perform a duty results in a serious physical deficiency, such as failing to provide adequate food or medical care to an obviously emaciated child, they must be guilty of injury to a child where the omission was intentional, knowing, reckless or with criminal - 16 - 00579 negligence." 79 • • Thus, failure to provide medical care can result in criminal liability for injury to a child if the failure to provide medical care aggravates the injury (starvation and sores of the skin because of poor hygeine in this case). One commentator suggests that under a statutory scheme for injury to a child or criminal neglect of a child, refusal to operate on, for instance, a Down's Syndrome infant with other serious physical defects like hydrocephalus and an intestinal obstruction is a criminal offense, "a willful and knowing refusal to provide care 80 necessary to avoid serious injury to health." Although there is clearly the potential for criminal liability, there is a lack of reported decisions on the question of criminal liability for nontreatment decisions in the defective newborn context. It has been suggested that the lack of prosecution reflects a moral ambivalence 81 about nontreatment decisions. Several reported decisions on euthanasia of older handicapped children seems to support this view. In a case reported in the New York Times in 19 39 , a man chloroformed his imbecile teenage son to death-, the boy had the mentality of a two year old. The man said he did it because he loved the boy, that "it was the will 82 of God." He was acquitted of first degree manslaughter. In another case, Louis Repouille chloroformed his thirteen year old son, who was blind, bedridden since infancy, - 16 - 19 deformed and profoundly retarded. Repouille was convicted of manslaughter but freed on a suspended sentence of five to ten y e a r s . ^ This conviction surfaced again in a natural- ization proceeding in which Repouille was denied naturalization on grounds of moral character because of this conviction. The court said he was to be allowed to apply for naturalization again after a period of five years, reasoning that: [w]e all know that there are great numbers of people of the most unimpeachable virtue, who think it morally justifiable to put an end to a life so inexorably destined to be a burden to others, and -- so far as any possible interest of its own is concerned — condemned to a brutish existence, lower indeed than all but the lowest forms of sentient life. Nor is it inevitably an answer to say that it must be immoral to do this, until the law provides security against the abuses which would inevitably follow, unless the practice were regulated.... It is reasonably clear that the jury which tried Repouille^ did not feel any moral repulsion at his crime. Another man was found not guilty of murder by reason of insanity when he withdrew his twenty-nine year old daughter, "a spastic incapable of speech," out of a sanitorium and shot her to death because he feared what would happen to 85 her if he should die. Because of the potential criminal liability for nontreatment, even though the possibility of nonenforcement exists, parents may wish to choose alternatives to nontreatment. One alternative is institutionalization of the defective newborn. Parents may decide that they cannot cope with such an infant, emotionally or physically. - 16 - 00581 Raising such a child at home can be extremely demanding because parents must learn to care for the disabled child, meet the needs of siblings, confront feelings of anger, guilt, 86 or shame, and face probable financial hardship. Keeping a severely defective infant at home may put serious strain on even the best marriages, cause behavioral problems in siblings, or cause financial ruin for a family if frequent hospitalization and special medical attention is necessary. Institutionalization may be the best option in such cases. Parents may also exercise the option of terminating parental rights and obligations (or the option may be exercised for them). In Texas, this procedure is found in 87 Chapter 15 of the Family Code. For a voluntary termination under Section 15.01, the petition may be granted if the court finds that it is in the best interest of the child. It may be assumed that a court will find that termination of parental rights is in the best interest of the child, since the alternative may be nontreatment and death. Under Section 15.02, there may be an involuntary termination of parental rights when the parent has knowingly placed or knowingly allowed the child to remain in conditions which 88 endanger the physical or emotional well-being of the child. Parental refusal of medical treatment for the defective newborn arguably fits within the provisions of Section 15.02 since the purpose of the nontreatment decision is the death - «0582 of the child. Under this provision, a hospital or physician who disagreed with the parents' decision not to treat could have the parent-child relationship terminated and the child made a ward of the state, so that treatment could be administered. Two recent court decisions indirectly support this position of involuntary termination of parental rights for this purpose by holding that medical treatment of a child can be ordered over the objection of parents when the parental conduct threatens a child's well being and is against the best interests of the child. In Custody 89 of a Minor, the court held that "where...the child's very life is threatened by a parental decision refusing medical treatment, this State interest [in protecting the welfare of children] clearly supercedes parental prerogatives. The court in so deciding stated that parental rights do not give parents life and death authority over their children and that "the parental right to control a child's nurture is grounded not in any 'absolute property right' which can be enforced to the detriment of the child, but rather is akin to a trust, subject to...[a] correlative duty to care for and protect the child, and...[terminable] 91 by [the parents'] failure to discharge their obligations." The 92 court m In re Storar held that although a parent or guardian has a right to consent to medical treatment on behalf of a child, a parent may not deprive a child of " : 00583 life-saving treatment, even if well mtentioned, 93 and that a court may not permit a parent to deny a child all treatment for a condition which threatens the life of the child. These two recent decisions may indicate how the courts would deal with a decision for nontreatment of the defective newborn, and if these cases are reliable indicators, the parents' right to decide for nontreatment and the extent of parental control in medical treatment situations may be seriously limited. Because of the lack of a general judicial consensus and definitive case law, the issue of nontreatment of the defective newborn may be more appropriately decided by the legislature than the courts. 94 The Florida Supreme Court has stated such a position in Satz v. Perlmutter. 95 saying: [bjecause the issue [whether to withdraw or withhold treatment] with all its ramifications is fraught with complexity and encompasses the interests of the law, both civil and criminal, medical ethics and social morality, it is not one which is well-suited for resolution in any adversary judicial proceeding. It is the type issue which is more suitably addressed in the legislative forum, where fact finding can be less confined and the viewpoints of all interested institutions and disciplines can be presented and synthesized. In this manner only can the subject be dealt with comprehensively and the interests of all institutions and individuals be properly accomodated. 00584 ENDNOTES Burger, The Law and Medical Advances, 67 ANNALS INTERNAL MED. SUPP. 7, 15, 17 (1967), quoted in Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E. 2d 417, 423 (1977). ^Medical Ethics: The Right to Survival, 1974: Hearing on the Examination of the Moral and Ethical Problems Faced with the Agonizing Decision of Life and Death Before the Subcomm. on Health of the Senate Comm. on Labor and Public Welfare, 93d Cong., 2d Sess. 14 (197 4) [hereinafter cited as 1974 Hearing]. 3 1974 Hearing, supra note 2, at 13. Kutner, Euthanasia: Due Process for Death With Dignity; The Living Will, 54INDIANA L.J. 201 (1979). 5 Id. at 20; Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 SO. 2d 160, 164 (Fla. App. 1978 ), aff'd, 379 SO. 2d 359 (1980). 5 TEX. STAT. ANN. art. 4590h (Supp.1982). 7 . . . Sharp and Crofts, Death with Dignity: The Physician's Civil Liability, 27 BAYLOR L. REV. 86 (1975). g 1974 Hearing, supra note 2, at 54. g Foreman, The Physician's Criminal Liability for the Practice of Euthanasia, 27 BAYLOR L. REV. 54 (1975); see also Robertson', Involuntary Euthanasia of Defective Newborns: A Legal Analysis, 27 STAN. L. REV. 213 (1975); Note, Euthanasia: Criminal, Tort, Constitutional and Legislative Considerations, 48 NOTRE DAME LAW. 200 (1973). "^Sharp and Crofts, supra note 7; see also Robertson, supra note 9. "^Fletcher, Ethics and Euthanasia, 2 HASTINGS CENTER STUDIES 47 (1974), reprinted in HORAN S MALL, DEATH, DYING AND EUTHANASIA 2 93 (1977). - 00585 12 . Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E. 2d 417 (1977). 13 Liacos, Dilemmas of Dying, MEDICOLEGAL NEWS, Fall 1979, at 4, 7. 14 Kutner, supra note 4, at 206, 207. 15 211 N.Y. 125 ; 105 N.E. 92 (1914). 16 Id. at 129, 105 N.E. at 93. 17 Kutner, supra note 4 at 207; see also Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 SO. 2d 160, 163 (Fla. App. 1978), aff'd, 379 SO. 2d 359 (1980). 18 462 F. SUPP. 1131 (D.N.J. 1978). 19 186 KAN. 393, 350 P. 2d 670 (1960). 20 . Kutner, supra note 4, at 210. This article contains an extensive discussion on informed consent and the right to refuse treatment, and development of both at pp. 206-17. 21 362 SO. 2d 160 (Fla. App. 1978), aff'd 379 SO. 2d 359 (1980). This patient had Lou Gehrig's disease, which is incurable and has a life expectancy of two years from the time of diagnosis. Mr. Perlmutter was described as being incapable of movement, unable to breathe without a respirator, but fully competent. His family agreed with his wishes to discontinue medical treatment. 7? 70 N.J. 10, 355 A. 2d 647, cert, denied, 429 U.S. 922 (1976 ); In re Severns, 425 A2d 156 (Del. Ch. 1980); In re Spring, 1980 Mass. Adv. Sh. 1209, 405 N.E.2d 115 (1980); Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417 (1977); Eichner v. Dillon, 73 A.D.2d 431 , 426 N.Y.S.2d 517 (1980), modified, 52 N.Y.S.2d 363,420 N.E.2d 64, 438 N.Y.S.2d 266 (1981). 23 . Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417, 427 (1977). - 00586 9U 381 U.S. 479 (1965)(right of privacy extends to matters of contraception and similar family decisions). 25 410 U.S. 113 (1973)(right of privacy broad enough to encompass a woman's decision whether or not to terminate her pregnancy). 26 321 U.S. 158 (1944)(right of privacy applicable to family relationships and parental rights). See In re Quinlan, 70 N.J. 10, 355 A.2d 647, 662-64, cert, denied, 429 U.S. 922 (1976); Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417, 424 (1977); In re Spring, 1980 Mass. Adv. Sh. 1209, 405 N.E.2d 115, 119 (1980); see also Andrews v. Ballard, 498 F. Supp. 1038 (D.Tex. 1980). 27 Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 153,159 (1973). 28 In re Spring, 1980 Mass. Adv. Sh. 1209, 405N.E.2d 115, 119 (1980). Accord, Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 SO. 2d 160, 164 (Fla. App. 1978), aff'd, 379 SO. 2d 359 (1980); Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417, 427 (1977); In re Quinlan, 70 N.J. 10, 355 A.2d 647 , 664 , cert, denied, 429 U.S. 922 (1976 ). 29 • Ellis, Letting Defective Babies Die: 7 AM. J. L.8MED. 393, 405 (1982). Who Decides? , 30 Id. See In re Quinlan, 70 N.J. 10, 40, 355 A.2d 647 , 663 , cert, denied, 429 U.S. 922 (1976 ); Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 SO. 2d 160 379 SO. 2d 359, 360 (Fla. 1980); In re Spring, 1980 Mass. Adv. Sh. 1209 , 1214 , 405 N.E.2d 115, 119 (1980); Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417, 424 (1977). 31 32 Ellis, supra note 29, at 406-07. 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417 (1977). 33 Joseph Saikewicz was 67 years old, with an I.Q. of 10 and a mental age of about 2 years and 8 months; he had resided in state institutions almost all of his life. He was suffering from acute myeloblastic monocytic leukemia, which causes internal bleeding and possibly severe anemia and high susceptibility to infection. It is invariably fatal and remission, for 2-13 months, through chemotherapy is achieved only in 30-50% of the cases. - 00587 34Ellis, supra note 29, at 407-08(citing Berman v. Allen, 80 N.J. 421, 429, 404 A.2d 8,12 (1979); Gleitman v. Cosgrove, 49 N.J. 22, 30, 227 A.2d 689, 693 (1969)). 35 1974 Hearing, supra note 2, at 26. 3 (1971) ^Ellis, supra note 29. 37 Id. at 394. 38 See generally J. WARKANY, CONGENITAL MALFORMATIONS 39 ° B. MALOY, MEDICAL DICTIONARY FOR LAWYERS 4 9 (19 60) (cited in Ellis, supra note 29, at 397). 40 Ellis, supra note 29, at 397. 41 Id. at 395. WARKANY, supra note 38, at 226-27. See also R. BEHRMAN, PERINATAL MEDICINE DISEASES OF THE FETUS AND INFANT 817 (1975) . 43 Robertson, supra note 9, at 213. 42 44 Diamond, The Deformed Child's Right to Life, reprinted in HORAN S MALL, DEATH, DYING, AND EUTHANASIA 127, 129 (1977). 45 Ellis, supra note 29, at 396. 46 . Mueller S Phoenix, A Dilemma for the Legal and Medical Professions: Euthanasia and the Defective Newborn, 22 ST. LOUIS L.J. 501, 502 (1978). 47 Ellis, supra note 29, at 395. 48 Id. at 396. note 46, at 501. 49 See also Mueller & Phoenix, supra Ellis, supra note 29, at 397. 00588 50 See Doctors Ponder Ethics of Letting Mongoloid Die„ Washington Post, Oct. 15, 1971, at A1, Col. 1(about a widely publicized incident at Johns Hopkins University Hospital, in which the parents refused consent for surgery to correct intestinal blockage because the child was a mongoloid; the child was allowed to starve to death); Shaw, Doctor, Do We Have A Choice?, N.Y. Times, Jan. 30, 1972, 6, at 44; Lorber, Selective Treatment of Myelomeningocele: To Treat or Not to Treat, 53 PEDIATRICS 307 (1974); Duff £ Campbell, Moral and Ethical Dilemmas in the Special Care Nursery, 289 NEW ENG. J. MED. 890 (1973)(all of the above cited in Ellis, supra note 29, at 399-401). 51 See Lewis, Machine Medicine and Its Relation to the Fatally 111, 206 J. A. M. A. 387 (1968); see also Rice, Euthanasia: A Time to Live and a Time to Die - How Physicians Feel, PSYCHOLOGY TODAY, Sept. 1974 at 2 9 (cited in Kutner, supra note 4, at 222); 1974 Hearing, supra note 2(a doctor's testimony before the congressional subcommittee indicated that 3/4 of American physicians have practiced euthanasia). 52 Ellis, supra note 29, at 399. 53 Superintendent of Belchertown v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417 423 (1977). 55 Robertson, supra note 9. 55 Id. at 178. 57 13 DEVELOP. MED. £ CHILD. NEUROL. 279 (1971) (summarizing the results of treating 524 cases of myelomeningocele). ^Robertson, supra note 9, at 254-55. 59 Berman v. Allen, 80 N.J. 421, 429, 404 A.2d 8, 12 (1979)(wrongful life case in which the New Jersey Supreme Court refused to recognize a cause of action for wrongful life). 00589 B0 Fletcher, supra note 11, at 295. But see Robertson, supra note 9, at 246-51 (on the difficulties of the person-nonperson distinction). 61 See Bok, Ethical Problems of Abortion, 2 HASTINGS CENTER STUDIES, Jan. 1974, at 33, 41(cited in Robertson, supra note 9, at 247); Wertham, The Geranium in the Window: The "Euthanasia" Murders, reprinted in HORAN S MALL, DEATH, DYING AND EUTHANASIA 602 (1977); Alexander, Medical Science Under Dictatorship, reprinted in HORAN S MALL, DEATH, DYING AND EUTHANASIA 571 (1977). 62 Ellis, supra note 29, at 401-02; Robertson, supra note 9, at 217. 63 For an excellent discussion on criminal liability for nontreatment decisions, see Robertson, supra note 9. 64 TEX. PENAL CODE ANN.^19.01 (Supp. 1982). 66 TEX. PENAL CODE ANN.§19.02 (Supp. 1982). 67 W . LAFAVE S A. SCOTT, HANDBOOK OF CRIMINAL LAW 182-91 (1972). 58 498 S.W.2d 938 (Tex. Crim. App. 1973). 69 Id. at 939. 70 7 1 See Ellis, supra note 29, at 399. Cf. Self v. State, 513 S.W.2d 832 (Tex. Crim. App. 1974)(State must prove that death was brought about by the criminal act or omission of another). 72 73 547 S.W.2d 616 (Tex. Crim. App. 1977). 574 S.W.2d 92 (Tex. Crim. App. 1978). This duty to provide medical care existed at common law as well. See Faunteroy v. United States, 413 A.2d 1294 (D.C. App. 1980); Singleton v. State, 33 Ala. App. 536, 35 S02d 375 (1948) State v. Clark, 5 Corrn. Cir. 699, 261 A2d 294 (1969); State v. Williams, 4 Wash. App. 908, 484 P.2d 1167 (1971). 7U TEX. PENAL CODE ANN.16.03 defines culpable mental states ,% 6 . 03 (c ) defines recklessness ,<sl9 . 05 defines involuntary manslaughter as recklessly causing the death of an individual. 75 People v. Lynch, 208 N.W.2d 656, 657 (Mich. App. 1973). 75 TEX. PENAL CODE ANN.$22.04(Supp. 1982). 77 Cf. Smith v. State, 603 S.W.2d 846 (Tex. Crim. App. 1980)(denial of food and adequate medical attention resulting in injury under % 22.04). 78 588 S.W.2d 327 (Tex. Crim. App. 1979). 79 Id. at 336. 80 Ellis, supra note 29, at 410. 82 N.Y. Times, May 11, 1939, at 10, Col. 2; N. Y. Times, May 12 , 1939 at 1, Col. 5(cited in Sanders, Euthanasia: None Dare Call It Murder, 60 J. CRIM. L.C.&P.S. 351, 355 (1969)). 83 N.Y.Times, Oct. 13, 1939, at 25, Col. 7; N.Y. Times, Dec. 25, 1941, at 44, col. 1(cited in Sanders, supra note 82, at 355). ftU Repouille v. United States, 165 F2d 152, 153 (2d Cir. 1947). 85 N.Y. Times, May 23, 1950, at 25, col. 4(cited in Sanders, supra note 82, at 3 55). 86 Robertson, supra note 9, at 2 57. - 00591 87 TEX. FAM. CODE ANN.% 15.01 (Vernon 1975) deals with voluntary termination,§ 15.02 with involuntary termination. 88 TEX. FAM. CODE ANN.$ 15.02(1)(D) (Supp. 1982). 89 375, Mass. 733, 379 N.E.2d 1053 (1978), aff'd, 1979 Mass. Adv. Sh. 2124, 393 N.E.2d 836 (1979). 90 • 379 N.E.2d at 1066; see discussion of parental rights and limits thereon at 1062-63. 91 Id. at 1063(citing Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.S. 158, 166-67 (1944); Richards v. Forrest, 278 Mass. 547, 553, 180 N.E. 508, 511 (1932); Purinton v. Jamrock, 195 Mass. 187, 201, 80 N.E. 802 (1907); Donnelly v. Donnelly, Mass. App. , 344 N.E. 2d 195 (1976)). 99 ^ 5 2 N.Y.2d 363, 438 N.Y.S.2d 266 (1981). 93 438 N.Y.S.2d at 275. 94 See Ellis, supra note 29, for an excellent discussion of a legislative solution for the nontreatment dilemma. q^ Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 SO.2d 160 (Fla. App. 1978), a f f M , 379 SO.2d 359 (1980). 96 379 SO.2d at 360. - 00592