Group Theory Contents Chapter 1: Review ................................................................................................................................ 2 Chapter 2: Permutation Groups and Group Actions ...................................................................... 3 Orbits and Transitivity .................................................................................................................... 6 Specific Actions – The Right regular and coset actions .............................................................. 8 The Conjugation Action .................................................................................................................. 8 Chapter 3: Sylow’s Theorems ........................................................................................................... 11 Direct Products ............................................................................................................................... 14 Group Presentations (From Algebra II) ...................................................................................... 15 Semi Direct Products ..................................................................................................................... 15 Groups of Small Order .................................................................................................................. 16 Classification of Groups with ...................................................................................... 17 ............................................................................................................................................ 17 .............................................................................................................................. 18 .......................................................................................................................................... 19 .......................................................................................................................................... 19 .......................................................................................................................................... 20 .......................................................................................................................................... 21 .......................................................................................................................................... 21 Chapter 4: Nilpotent and Soluble (Solvable) Groups ................................................................... 22 Commutators and Commutator Subgroup ................................................................................ 24 Characteristic Subgroups .............................................................................................................. 25 Soluble Groups and Derived Series............................................................................................. 26 Composition Series and the Jordan-Holder Theorem .............................................................. 28 Chapter 5: Permutation Groups and Simplicity Proofs ................................................................ 31 Normal Subgroups of Permutation Groups ............................................................................... 33 The Finite Simple Groups (Classified ~1981/2004) .................................................................. 35 Properties of Finite Fields ......................................................................................................... 36 A Closer Study of ( ) for small ................................................................................... 41 Chapter 6: The Transfer Homomorphism ...................................................................................... 43 Chapter 7: Classification of Simple Groups of order 500 ......................................................... 46 Chapter 1: Review Notations or means that is a subset of (not necessarily subgroup), while or means that is a subgroup of . { } is a right coset while { } is a left If and , coset. We know from Algebra II that and if is finite, | | | | and the distinct right cosets partition . Theorem 1.1 (Lagrange’s Theorem) If is finite and then | ||| |. Index of a subgroup | | | The value | is called the index of Normal Subgroup is called a normal subgroup of for all in and is denoted | and is denoted for all | if . Quotient Group If we can define the quotient group operations { } the set of cosets with group and { } and All groups have normal subgroups { } and . A group is called simple if are the only normal subgroups (this is equivalent to having exactly two normal subgroups). and Abelian finite simple groups are exactly those groups which are cyclic of prime order. The classification of finite simple groups was completed in 1981. The aim of this module is to classify all finite non-abelian simple groups of order up to 500 with proofs. It turns out there are only three such examples which have orders 60, 168 and 360. First we recall some more statements proved in Algebra II. Proposition 1.2 If then subgroups of are of the form Homomorphism A map is a homomorphism if ( ) with ( ) ( and ) for all . . In addition: ( ) is a monomorphism if ( ) is an epimorphism if ( ) is an isomorphism if it is both a monomorphism and an epimorphism is an automorphism if is an isomorphism with Kernel If is a homomorphism then the kernel of ( ). Note that Claim is a monomorphism iff Claim For given by ( ) Theorem 1.3 (First Isomorphism Theorem) Let be a homomorphism and denote ( ) iii. The map ( ) { }. ( ) ( ) , the “quotient” map i. ii. denoted is an epimorphism. ( ) (not necessarily normal) ( ) defines an isomorphism ( ). Hence ( ) Order of an element For , the order of denoted | | is the least such that or if there is no } such . For , the set 〈 〉 { is the cyclic subgroup generated by . Remark If | | , finite then 〈 〉 { } while if | | then 〈 〉 } 〉 is the subgroup generated by More generally for { ,〈 and is defined to be the intersection of all subgroups containing which is equivalent to the set of all products of any length of and Cyclic Group A group is called cyclic if it is generated by one element for example | | | | { } | | | | {| | | | | | | | Chapter 2: Permutation Groups and Group Actions Let be a set. Permutation A permutation of is a bijection ( ) where | | and . Define Notation ( ) and If write the image of so means first apply then . under ( ) be the group of all permutations as not ( ), so we get ( ) Example { Take } and denote ( ) as follows: ( )( ) ( )( ) In cyclic notation ( )( ) ( )( ) So and have a cycle of length 2 and a cycle of length 3 hence ( ) cycle type? Why? is a conjugate of : For above, | | ( ) denote | | | | | | o len ths o | | Transposition A permutation of the form ( and have the same is oint y les. Therefore in the example ) is a transposition . Lemma 2.1 If is a finite set, any permutation of generated by transpositions. is a composition of transpositions. I.e. is Proof ( ) and express it as a product of cycles, so it is enough to express cycles as a Take composition of transpositions: ( ) ( )( ) ( ) Even and Odd Permutations ( ) is called even or odd if transpositions respectively. is a product of an even or odd number of Theorem 2.2 No permutation is both even and odd. Proof Not instructive, but in the lecture notes. Clearly, e en e en homomorphism odd. o ( ) o e en and o e en e en o o , so there is a { } where ( ) if is even and ( ) if is ( ) ( ) Observe that the First Isomorphism Theorem. { ( ) Also by the First Isomorphism Theorem if | | , | ( )| ( ) ( )| hence | We will later prove that ( )| is simple for | ( ) by is e en} is a subgroup of ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) so Group Actions We did these in Algebra II, but will use right actions not left actions and use different notation: An Action of a Group on a set ( definition of an action, we have the map and (since ( is a permutation of mapping ( ) and (not ). By for all ) . For , we have as inverse maps so every permutation is a bijection). ( ) is a homomorphism since Then ( ) by Denote ( ) is a map ) ( ) for all (the action of { ( ) . on ). By the First isomorphism, and ( ) } Faithful Action The action on is called faithful if ( ) or equivalently if Dihedral Group Recall that is the dihedral group of order (which is often confusingly denoted by Example : Consider the regular hexagon below Define three actions of On e es on subsets of : actions on ( ) ( )( ) { ia onals Observe that and { } } ( ( On erti es { ) )( )( ( ( ) ) } are faithful but ) is not. It has kernel { } and in fact, ). Equivalent Actions Actions of on sets ( ) ( ) are called equivalent if there is a bijection and . By examining the cycle type of the three actions on are inequivalent. such that , we conclude that all actions of Orbits and Transitivity Let act on . Define for if there exists such that be an equivalence relation. The equivalence classes are called the orbits of of is written as . Example { } and take Let }{ }{ The orbits of 〈 〉 are { }{ 〉 are { The orbits of 〈 so hence . Similarly, orbit but applying to { }. . Similar for Transitive is called transitive if there exists Observe that 〈 . This is clear to on . The orbit ( )( )( ) and ( )( )( ) where . } { } while the orbits of 〈 〉 are { } { } { } { } { }. }. This is deduced because so also because all give results so are all in the same so { is an orbit; that is if so that . } is for all . Equivalently, for all 〉 in the previous example is not transitive. -transitive For , is called -transitive if: 1. | | 2. Given , define pints that for and distinct . Then there exists so . Observe that 1-transitive is the same as transitive and ( )-transitive implies -transitive. Examples 1. 2. } is -transitive on { } )-transitive on { , the alternating group is ( Proof Take distinct and . Then { where and are the other two points. Also Certainly there exists a unique with for are done. Otherwise let be the transposition ( and Stabiliser Let act on and { } }. . If ) then then we and so for . Define the stabiliser of in as ( ) { } and ( ) is a subgroup of : ( ) then Let subgroup. ( so ) Note that the kernel of the action is { action. } so ⋂ Theorem 2.3 (Orbit-Stabiliser Theorem) If acts on with finite and then | | Proof Suppose ? so there exists | with || . ( ) is a so is the kernel of the | or equivalently | | | may not be unique so for which So is in the same right coset of as . So this defines a bijection between | | | as claimed. cosets of in . So | Notation For , denote If denote is and the right the two point stabiliser. Similarly, { ( ) } { Example { Take { } then |. } } and ( ( ) but . In general, it is true that ( ) )( pointwise sta iliser setwise sta iliser ) and { } then ( ) and , but if Corollary 2.4 If acts on , then i. ii. iii. | | is constant for in an orbit. is transitive implies | | | || | If is -transitive and | | then | | ( ) ( )| | for any Proof i. ii. iii. This follows immediately from the Orbit-Stabiliser Theorem This follows immediately from part i. We use induction on . When ,| | | | from part ii. Assume true for ; that is is -transitive implies that transitive straight from the definition since | { }| { } is ( )- . So by induction | ( | )( ) ( )| | also | | | | by part ii. So the result follows. Specific Actions – The Right regular and coset actions Right Regular Action Let be any group. Take . For action. Given , } { } so it is faithful. and we define ( ) so it is transitive. The stabiliser Coset Action A generalisation is a coset action. Let { and take { } gives the right regular action. Note that ( } { ( ) { so . This is clearly an }. Define ( ) } { ) so it is transitive. Then } { As the stabiliser is a subgroup, this particular subgroup is called a conjugate of . In general, this action is not faithful: Example Take i. ii. { 〈 〉 } { }. We have two cosets { }. Then and } kernel of the action so it is not faithful. ( ) ( ) so { 〈 〉 Observe that so kernel so }. We have three cosets { } then 〈 〉 { ( a 3-cycle on . Notice that so ( ) . Then ( ). Therefore | | | | so the action is faithful. ) is Theorem 2.5 Any transitive action of on is equivalent to some coset action. (That is, a bijection between , so that the group action is preserved. Proof Let act transitively on . Let on . Define by ( ) First we check that { . Let . We claim that and for is well defined: i.e. is injective because ( . For equivalence of actions; . Now . is transitive. is clearly surjective because ) ( (( ) ) ) ( ) The Conjugation Action acts on by } we have a coset action is a bijection: . This is clearly an action. ( ) . Remark The default meaning of for is . is a conjugate of in . The orbits are called the conjugacy classes of and denoted { } so the action is not transitive if | | ( ). Note that ( ) { . } { } ( ) otherwise known as the Centraliser of . ( ) ( ) { } Note that As a generalisation we can take { ( ) { Then is the centraliser of } in Remark It can be proved that } the subgroups of ( ) called the normaliser of } is the set { ( ) and define an action by ( ) and in . Also ( ) ( ). Summary of Notation: Take then: ( ) is the conjugacy class of which is { ( ) is the centraliser of which is { ( )|| ( )| finite implies that | | | ( ) is the centre of which is { } } } Conjugacy of permutations ( ) suppose Let is ( )( and . Then so if a cyclic decomposition of )( ). is ( Example ( )( ) and ( )( ) then ( Let note that conjugate permutations have the same cycle type. Theorem 2.7 Two permutations cycle types. ( ) are conjugate in ( )( This is possible because all and . It then follows that )( ). Then simply choose and all )( ). In particular ( ) if and only if they have the same Proof From the above, we conclude that is true. ( ) of the same cycle type: that is Conversely, take and ; that is )( )( ) then ( ( ) so that )( )( ) for all appear exactly once in the cyclic decomposition of . . Example { Let } and ( )( ) and ( ) As ( cycle type take . Note that )( and ) then have the same satisfies is not unique. -groups: For prime, a finite group is called a -group if | | group if all elements have order a power of ). that ( ) Note for { } )( for (for { but for infinite is a - } ( ) Observe that is a -group. We will show soon that -groups have non-trivial centre. Lemma 2.8 If then is a union of conjugacy classes of Proof As and for all . Therefore Theorem 2.9 Let be a finite -group where is prime and with ( ) particular if take to conclude that . ( ) . then ( ) . In Proof ∐ ( ) for some By Lemma 2.8, . This is a disjoint union because ( ) { }. We have conjugacy classes are either equal or disjoint. Choose so | | ∑ | ( )| ∑ | ( )| ∑ | ( )| by the Orbit-Stabiliser | ( )| Theorem. Now observe that for some . Since ,| | mo y La ran e’s Theorem. There ore in or er to a oi a ontra i tion some with since otherwise we get mo . ( )| ( ) and so ( ) That is | for some hence ( ) so . Chapter 3: Sylow’s Theorems Product of subsets: If then { } Lemma 3.1 Let i. ii. If If or and then then Proof i. ii. Suppose ( )( . Take and . Then ) ( )( ) and since is normal, so ) so ( . Similarly ( ) ( ) since by normality. Therefore . ( ) Let and . Then because and by normality of and . Hence is normal. Remark: Note that if then so . Theorem 3.2 (Second Isomorphism Theorem) If and then Proof Let to . Then be the canonical epimorphism ( ) ( ) { } . Then consider the restriction . Moreover, ( ) so applying the First Isomorphism Theorem, we yield the result The on erse to La ran e’s Theorem says: “ i en finite and | | and | , does there | | exist a subgroup so that ”. In eneral this statement is not true: has no subgroup of order 6 but | power. Sylow -subgroup Let | | , prime and subgroup of . Denote for ( ) { | . However the answer is yes if . A subgroup } | | Theorem 3.3 (Sylow’s Theorem) For a finite group let | | , prime and i. ( ) for of order . is a prime is called a Sylow - ii. iii. (containment) Any -subgroup of is contained in some Sylow -subgroup of . ( ) then there exists (conjugacy) If with ( )| (number) | mo iv. We will pro e Sylow’s Theorem in two separate Theorems. The irst one implies Proposition 3.4 Let be a finite group and ( ). Proof Let | | | | { ( ). If || |. Then the number of subgroups of }. Let | | and where then by right multiplication. That is of order . Then using elementary combinatorics, { } so we can define an action of on . This is clearly an action. Let be an orbit of . If and then there exists ( ) then by definition an element with ). If ( ) . Now we consider two cases: Case 1: ( ) . so . (I.e. there exists that is { ( ) is a subgroup since and the orbit | | | | by the orbit-stabiliser is the set of right cosets of . Then | | theorem. In particular, is the only subgroup in the orbit. So if is a subgroup of order then the orbit of has size . . Then } Case 2: ( ) Suppose . Then | | subgroups of . As | | | | | ( )| | | | | , so by Case 1 contains no | | | because | ||| | then | | { } then we have shown that equals the number of orbits of size and the remaining orbits in have || |. Then for some , | | therefore | | ( ) Let As is prime there exists a unique inverse | | that ( ( ) ) ( ( ) ( { } with mod . Therefore ) It then can be proved using elementary number theory ). we can avoid this by using the following argument due to G. Higmann The number ( ) order | |, in particular is a function of | | and mod so it must be the same for all groups of is the same for the cyclic group of order | |. Cyclic Groups have a unique subgroup of order for all groups of order | |. Proposition 3.5 ( ), Let for all a -subgroup of || | so for a cyclic group so that is | | is a power of . Then mod for some . Proof Take | | that is ( with ) {ri ht osets o . Let . This is clearly an action. in }. Consider the restriction of the action to . Orbits of where . This is a power of , possibly . Suppose the orbit of . ( has size 1. That is acts on on have size | | | ( )| ) therefore Proof of Theorem 3.3 Follow immediately from the conclusion of Proposition 3.4 Since is a subgroup of order | | we have ( ) then | | | | so we must have If thus . Corollary 3.6 (Cauchy’s Theorem) If is a finite group and || | for prime then by right multiplication ( ) by Proposition 3.5 and has an element of order . Proof { }. Then | | ( ). Take Choose Then ( | . Then as Corollary 3.7 ( )| Let | | | | | |. ) so ( we must have . Then | | | ) | for some hence for . That is | ( )| where . Then | ( ) and and so . { } In particular Proof ( ) and let act on by conjugation. By definition, ( ) ( ). By Let Theorem 3.3, part iii, this action is transitive. By the orbit stabiliser theorem we have | | | | | ( )| ( ) by definition we have | | | ( )| and so In particular as | | | | | | | | | | | | | Corollary 3.8 | ( )| iff so Proof By Corollary 3.7, | Corollary 3.9 ( ), For ( )| iff | | | ( )| ( ) ( ) iff iff for all iff ( ) Proof Corollary 3.10 (Frattini Lemma) ( ) then If and ( ) Proof Direct Products {( be groups. Then define )( ) ( ). In particular | | | Let ( }. Then ) | | | Proposition 3.11 Let . Let i. ii. If iii. Every {( and } ) with . Then: then can be written uniquely as where Proof Easy Theorem 3.12 Let where and and . Then Proof We first prove that for all , . Consider (called the commutator of ). Observe ( ) and because is normal so . Similarly, is normal so . So and so that is . by ( Define (( )) (( ) . First (( )). Therefore )( )) ( is a homomorphism. . ( ) and because ) is surjective by hypothesis. )) If (( and thus then so ( ) . Therefore therefore is injective and so and so hence is an isomorphism. {( )} as in the definition is an external product of Note and whereas in Theorem 3.12 is called the internal direct product of and . As a consequence of Theorem 3.12, we usually just call them direct products. Corollary 3.13 Suppose except . For each , let ̂ with ̂ ). Assume for all ∏ . Then (the product of all . Proof This is a straightforward induction on , following from Theorem 3.12. Remark It is insufficient to assume for all . Group Presentations (From Algebra II) ⟨ |equations in the ⟩ For example, ⟨ | that is generated by the elements ⟩ for some es ri es the “lar est” roup which satisfy the equations on the right. This is an informal definition. We will only use it when is finite or can be shown to be inite, so “lar est” makes sense. We woul also nee to pro e that any two su h lar est groups are isomorphic. We need group presentations here because they are so useful for defining small finite groups. The example above is the dihedral group where is the rotation, a reflection. | ⟩ for However ⟨ is isomorphic to , the direct product of cyclic groups. In specific examples like the ones above, it is not hard to show that there is a unique largest such group. Semi Direct Products We have seen actions of the action of ( ) on . If on correspond to homomorphisms ( ) and is ( ). That is are groups we can define a group action of on in which ( ) ( ) is a bijective homomorphism from to itself. We still write for the action of ( ) on . Equivalently we define it by the axioms: ( ( ) ) ( ) is a homomorphism Semi-Direct Product Suppose is a group which and 3.12 but not assuming ) We call an (internal) semi-direct product of and . and (as in Theorem Note that conjugation of elements of by elements of defines a group action (easy to check it satisfies the three axioms above) ( )( ) ( . We write or )( ) on . ) so multiplication in is completely determined by the action denotes the semi-direct product with action . Conversely, given groups and an action direct product as follows: {( Given an action on , define by ( of ( ) where of on we can define the external semi} with multiplication defined ) is determined by the action . Claim is a group. Proof Closure is clear, the identity is ( to check. Examples: 〈 〉 Take ( ) and ( ) [In general ( ) and ( 〈 〉. Then ( ) so ) for ( ) ⟨ ) . Associativity is also easy 〈 〉 where ( ) . Then ( ) and prime] ( ) | ( ) ( ), ( ) then ( ), ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ( . ( ) mapping Define ) ⟨ then ⟨ then ⟩ ⟩ | ⟨ ⟩ | then ⟩ | [In general, is the trivial map so for all ] Groups of Small Order We will now classify (up to group isomorphism) all groups Claim If | | prime then with | | (except 16). . Proof Easy. Proposition 3.14 If | | with an odd prime then either Proof Let | | , an odd prime. Choose ⟨ | ⟩ and ⟨ | ⟩. Observe is a subgroup of by Lemma 3.1 and or ( ) and ( ) then | because | . so we must have so . Clearly . So ( for some ; therefore ) ( ) so if we have or The two possibilities give ⟨ ⟨ | Proposition 3.15 If | | for some prime is determined by . ) so |( then mo . So assuming . | ⟩ ⟩ then and . is abelian and or Proof { }. Then | ||| | so | | is abelian by Sheet 2 Q1. Then let or | | . If | | 〈 〉 then . { }. Then choose { }, define 〈 〉 and choose Assume | | for all 〈 〉. Observe | | | |. Then | | | and let or . But | which is a contradiction. Therefore and so (because is abelian so | | so and we use Lemma 3.1) but | | | | so y La ran e’s Theorem | | . By theorem 3.12, we have . Classification of Groups with | | Quickly observe that if | | , for prime or | | for an odd prime then we are done by the previous two Propositions. It remains to classify | | .I start off with another quick Lemma: Lemma If is any group and | | Proof { }. Then ( Take | | Take as | || for all { } then ) . Moreover is abelian. so . we must have | | Case 1: { }. Then by the Lemma, Assume | | for all cyclic groups; that is either or { } the only possibility is that . is abelian, so is a direct sum of or . As | | for every { } for prime then writing with the [In General if is abelian and for all operation addition, can be made into a vector space over a finite field with elements. So if finite, then ⏟ . Groups of this property are called elementary abelian. Case 2: If not, there exists with | | . Let 〈 〉 so | | hence . Choose so . has order so ( ) so . Also implies that . Claim Given and Proof { } { { } }, { is defined uniquely. } { , } then then | | or and so . . . is abelian. ⟨ | If element of order 8. If then ( ) by and get Case 2b In this case ) { } so the Claim is true. The possibilities are that . If We now consider the possibilities that or | | | Observe that | so or Case 2a If ( , ⟩ . Take . and since since was arbitrary in has no we can replace is non-Abelian. ⟨ | ⟩ If we have ⟨ | ⟩ If then we can construct as a group of complex 2x2 matrices. This proves the existence of and is necessary to show the relations above are not inconsistent. Observer that has or order 2 and the other 6 elements are of order 4 so Summarising, | | | | By Sylow’s Theorem | or . Case 1 ( )| If | then ⟨ | ⟩ ( ). | | Let or ( )| ( ) . Also by Corollary 3.7, | { } so Case 1a ⟨ | ⟩. Then Take Either or ( ) 〈 〉 with More formally, both define a homomorphism or ( )||| | so | by Corollary 3.8. Since | | ( )| we may take by Proposition 3.15. ; the group automorphism is determined by . and ( ) . Can have ( ) or ( ) ( ) so we get two possible semi-direct products: ⟨ | ⟩ ⟨ | ⟩ non a elian (No need to prove the existence of these groups; their existence is guaranteed by the SemiDirect Product.) Case 1b Take If ( ) 〈 〉 ( ) ( 〈 〉 again we want ( ) ( ) ) then ( ). There are four possibilities: ( ) ( ) ⟨ | ⟩ The other three cases give isomorphic groups: ( ) The groups obtained by the cases ( ) are clearly the same as the case ( ) ( ) since you can simply interchange and . ( ) 〈 〉 〈 〉 we can simply replace by If ( ) then ( ) . Since so this choice is isomorphic to the two above. So we have a single group ⟨ | ⟩ ( ) ( ) ) (this is in fact isomorphic to as | | Case 2 { ( )| In this case we take | . Let they are all conjugate; that is acts transitively on ( ). homomorphism Let 〈 〉. By Corollary 3.7, | ( )) hence we can assume If ( ) and for ( )| | | | ( )| } ( ). By Sylow’s Theorem by conjugation. That is there is a ( ) so | for any and so ( ; that is ( ) for ) and fixes ( )| ; (as . Then o . 〈 〉 then ( ) or ( ) so if necessary replace by to get ( ) so 〈 〉 ( ) which has order 12. ( ) ( ) so | ( )| | | so must be an automorphism and ( ). Summarising, we get 5 groups in total; 4 in Case 1, 1 in Case 2. | | ( )| ( )|| so then By Sylow’s Theorem, | and by Corollary 3.7 | | ( )| ( )| ( )| Similarly, | and divides 5 so | . Therefore ( ) , ( ) so , implies that . ( (This same argument works with any | | with prime amd and )). | | There are 14 isomorphism types. This was proved by Burnside in approximately 1900. The proof is omitted because it is rather long. | | | ( )| . Take and | mo ( ), ⟨ | ( )| | so | ( )| ⟩. So ( ) . Therefore | | and is a semi-direct product. Case 1 〈 〉 cyclic. As then the usual argument involving the automorphism group shows or each giving the cases or respectively. Case 2 〈 〉 〈 〉 with Claim For a suitable choice of or and . we can assume or and similarly Sketch Proof ( ) In general, if then as we have and so 〈 〉 〈 〉 (since is abelian). Moreover, so we can replace by and can assume or . Now suppose or : ( {so we must ha e ( { ) by . So we ) or In this ase repla e y so an et Therefore the claim is true. There are four possibilities but two are isomorphic by interchanging get three groups: ⟨ ⟨ Now observe that in | | for all | | the element and so and . Therefore we ⟩ has order 6 but no element of . ⟩ has order 6 because Summarising we get five groups of order 18; 2 in case 1 and 3 in case 2, two of which are abelian. | | ( )| By Sylow’s Theorem | ( ) and . Take possibilities for ; either and | ( ), then or ( )|| so | ( )| . Where ⟨ | and so ⟩. There are two . Case 1 Assume ( )| ( ) are the maps . Then | and the elements of ( ) ( ) can be any element of ( ) so we . For the possible get 4 possibilities: If ( ) then ) then If ( ) ( ⟨ | ⟩. As we have ( ) ( ) and so So by replacing by we get the same semi-direct product as the previous case. ). Then The final case is that ( ) ( ⟨ ⟩ | Observe that in order 10. But in . ( , , ) so and ( ) ( ) and centralises ; in fact and has no element of order 10 so Case 2 〈 〉 〈 〉 as usual we get Suppose | | case 1b. This leads to two possible groups and ⟨ and has similar to ⟩ | Therefore we get 5 groups of order 20: three in case 1 and two in case 2. | | | ( )| ⟨ | ⟨ | Let Need action and divides 3 so | ( )| ( ) and hence denote ⟩. ⟩ ( ). Then ( ) and ( . ) so for some with . Then . If so and get two groups corresponding to the cases ⟨ ( ) so | give isomorphic groups (swap and respectively: ). So we ⟩ Observe that the second group is non-abelian so we get two isomorphism classes. Note that in all our cases, all our groups were constructed from cyclic groups as direct or semi-direct products, apart from which we had to construct as a matrix group. Chapter 4: Nilpotent and Soluble (Solvable) Groups Theorem 4.1 (Third Isomorphism Theorem) Let be a group, and with (hence ). Then an [Note that and does not automatically imply that ]. Proof Define by ( ) . Because } { } { , ( ) is well defined and . So . and so by the first isomorphism theorem Theorem 4.2 Let be a finite group. The following are equivalent: 1. | 2. 3. ( )| for all | | | prime. ( ) for all | | | prime. for all ( ) where where are the primes dividing | | Proof 1 2 by Corollary 3.8 3 2 by Proposition 3.11 i. To prove 2 3: Let be the primes dividing | | Let ̃ (excluding . Then ̃ | | ( ) so ). Then | | | | by hypothesis. | || by Lemma 3.1. In particular for and thus ̃ since it is divisible by all . In addition, elements are coprime. Then by Corollary 3.13 | we have ̃ | | | | where | | ̃ | so ̃ since orders of all the . Nilpotent Group A finite group satisfying the three properties of Theorem 4.2 is called nilpotent. The definition for infinite groups is different; see sheet 5. Theorem 4.3 Let be a finite nilpotent group. Then: 1. If 2. If 3. If Proof , then ( ) (nontrivial centre) then is nilpotent then is nilpotent | | 1. Assume Take 2. Let and , so by Theorem 2.9 ( ) . ) ( ). because nilpotent and so . By the . As for ( ) { } then we have ( ( ) for some hence second isomorphism theorem which has order coprime to , so ( )so the Sylow -subgroups of ( ) for some and so 3. Let therefore and so for any is nilpotent. by Lemma 3.1 and so by the third isomorphism theorem order coprime to and so are normal in . Then which has ( ). Hence the Sylow p-subgroups of so are normal in is nilpotent. Examples: Abelian Groups are nilpotent All groups of order for prime are nilpotent. Direct products of nilpotent groups are nilpotent. (Condition 3 of 4.2) . is not nilpotent since it has 3 Sylow 2-subgroups so they cannot be normal subgroups. Maximal Subgroup A subgroup of a group is maximal if but Note that if is finite and with infinite groups have maximal subgroups. then implies or . for some maximal . Not all Theorem 4.4 The following are equivalent for finite groups: 1. is nilpotent ( ) 2. and implies that 3. All maximal subgroups are normal. Proof ( ) ( ) Let so . As is nilpotent by Theorem 4.3, ( ) We proceed by induction on | |. If | | there is nothing to prove. Case 1: ( ) So so ( ) Case 2: ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) implies that but ( ) ( ). ( ) Let . By induction ( ) so ( ) and also be maximal in . ( ) nilpotent so ( ) ( ( ) ( ) ) ( ) for some . ( ). ( ) so ( ) implies ( ) ( ) ( ) and so ( ) so . ( ) ( ) Assume ( ). If is not nilpotent, then for some for some maximal in . By condition iii, ( ) Contradiction. but ( ) so ( ) ( ) so ( ) by Corollary 3.9. Commutators and Commutator Subgroup Commutator Let . Define the commutator to be [ Notice that [ ] and [ ] ] [ ]. Commutator Subgroup ] is by definition The Commutator subgroup of , denoted [ [ ] ⟨[ ]| ⟩ ] } is not a subgroup. The smallest counterexample is of In general, the set {[ order 32. Theorem 4.5 1. [ 2. ] [ ] 3. If is abelian. and abelian, then [ ] that is [ ] is the ‘lar est’ a elian quotient group of . Proof 1. It follows from Theorem 4.7 (i) and (iv). [ ] therefore 2. For all , [ 3. [ ] [ ] so [ ] abelian implies ] . for all Examples: is done in the notes, and [ In fact | | so ] [ [ ] [ ] therefore ] [ so [ is called perfect if ]. It follows on Sheet 5. )( )] ( )( )( )( ) ( then [( ] and ( )( ) [ ]. Therefore )( ) [ { ( )( ) ( )( ) ( )( )} [ because it is a union of conjugacy classes. Moreover is abelian so ] is abelian. Remark ] It should be clear that [ is abelian. that non abelian simple groups are perfect. Take similarly ( [ ] by Theorem 4.5 part 3. )( ] ) [ ] so Characteristic Subgroups Characteristic A subgroup this to . is called characteristic in For any group and any the map ( ). is an automorphism and so Inner Automorphisms The group of inner automorphisms is denoted Observe that this truly is a group because In fact it is a normal subgroup: Let ( ) ( ). and thus if ( ). We abbreviate for all (conjugation by ) mapping ( ) { and ( ) ( ). Then } ( ) so ( ) ( ( ) ) so Outer Automorphisms and the Outer Automorphism Group ( ) ( ) is called an outer automorphism and ( ) ( ) ( ) is the Outer Automorphism Group. Lemma 4.6 All Characteristic Subgroups are normal. Proof Let . Then ( ) so this means for all ( ). In particular, for all and so . for all ( ) Theorem 4.7 Let be a group. Then: 1. 2. 3. ] 4. [ 5. ( ) 6. and and ( ), and finite Proof 1. This is Lemma 4.6. 2. This follows from 3 and 1 ( ). Then 3. Let Claim ( ). The restriction of implies Proof injective and a homomomorphism immediately imply that homomorphism. We only need to check surjectivity. Take then ( ) ( ) so because is injective and a . Then so so is surjective. Therefore since so . ] [ ] so permutes the Commutators ( ) so [ ( ) 4. Let ] ⟨[ ]| ] [ ] that is [ ] char . ⟩ so [ then [ ] ] ( ) and let ( ) then [ 5. Take for all implies [ for ] all so [ for all . As is a bijection from to we have [ ] ( ). Hence ( ) ( ) that is ( ) for all so ( ). If | ( )| ( ). Then 6. Take then there exists a unique | | | | ( ) so that is . Soluble Groups and Derived Series Let be a group and suppose is a series of length . Subnormal series, Normal Series The above is called a subnormal series if for all (in this case subnormal subgroup of ). It is called a normal series if for all . is called a Soluble For a group , we say it is Soluble if it has a subnormal series with each quotient abelian. Examples: Observe that Abelian Groups are Soluble. Let be the set { ( )( ) ( )( ) ( )( )} then has series ] and as [ , and because it is a union of conjugacy classes. Moreover, are abelian and is abelian so this proves Soluble. { } { } implies is soluble. Note that this series is a subnormal series but not a normal series. All groups up to order 23 are soluble. In fact, of order 60 is the smallest group which is not soluble. Moreover is simple for so this implies that are not soluble for . Define ( ) ( ) and ( ) ( ) [ ] and ( ) [ () () ] for all . Then the series ( ) is called the derived series for . Moreover by Theorem 4.7 hence this series is a normal series. ( ) The series may stabilise ( ) for some . (this is always true if infinite groups this may not be the case e.g. free groups. ( ) 1. is soluble if and only if 2. is soluble if and only if ( ) for all is finite) but for Theorem 4.8 Proof is for some . has a normal series with abelian factors 1. [ ] is clear since ( hence is soluble. ) implies that the derived series for [ ] Let be a subnormal series with induction that () for all is a normal series abelian. We prove by . ( ) Take then . Assume true for then by induction and using the fact that ( ) ] [ ( ) ( )] [ Because is abelian, ( ) abelian so 2. [ ] by definition [ ] If is soluble then ( ) for some normal series with abelian quotients. by 1. But then the derived series is a Lemma 4.8.1 . Then [ Let ] [ ] Proof ] 〈[ 〉 〈[ ] 〉 Corollary 4.8.2 ( ) ( ) ( ) for all Proof We apply induction. The Lemma gives us the induction step. Theorem 4.9 1. If is soluble and then is soluble 2. If and is soluble then is soluble 3. If and and are both soluble then is soluble 4. All nilpotent groups are soluble Proof 1. Then 2. 4. ( ) ( ) If for some . ( ) so soluble implies so 3. ( ) is soluble iff ( ) so ( ) so is soluble. ( ) { } then by Corollary 4.8.2, ( ) is soluble. is soluble then ( ) ( ) ( ) for some so ( ) . ) ( If is soluble then ( ) for some and so ( soluble. Let be a nilpotent group. We now apply induction on | |. When | | we get the desired result. ) so is { } For | | soluble so then ( ) by Theorem 4.3 1. So by induction ( ) and ( ) are is soluble by part 3. Now observe we have an ascending chain of sets: elian roups ilpotent roups Solu le roups roups Composition Series and the Jordan-Holder Theorem Maximal Normal Subgroup is a maximal normal subgroup of Simple Group A Group is simple if So if and and implies is a maximal normal subgroup implies or is simple. What are the maximal normal subgroups So | | so | | So | | is of ? is simple, hence cyclic of prime order so | | abelian. if each ⟩ | implies . . A subnormal series is a composition series of ). simple. Not all groups have them for example ( Example: Take ⟨ or ( ), so there is a unique subgroup has three subgroups of order 2; 〈 〉 〈 〈 〉 〈 〉 ( ), or . Since 〈 〉 . Then 〉 so there are three possible 〈 〉 〈 since 〈 〉 〈 〉 so that | | 〉 We consider these in turn: 〈 There is no normal subgroup of order 2 so of . Similarly, with composition series 〈 〉 〈 〉 Since and 〈 〉 so we have two composition series 〈 〉 〉 so the composition series is which has two normal subgroups 〈 〉 〈 〉 Therefore has four composition series altogether. Equivalent Series ( ) and Let series of . Then we say those series are equivalent if { } such that () () for all . ( ) be two composition and there is a permutation of : Theorem 4.11 (Jordan-Holder) Any two composition series of a finite group Proof We apply induction on | |. When | | are equivalent. this is clear. Let ( ) and ( ) be two series as above. Case 1 If then the result follows by applying induction to Case 2 If so Moreover (because simple and and simple implies , so the previous statement proves and both normal in and . and applying Lemma 3.1). are both maximal normal subgroups of . Now by the Second Isomorphism Theorem Let and let construct the following diagram: be a composition series for we then We have four composition series in the diagram: () ( ) ( ) ( ) Now by Case 1, the series ( ) and ( also equivalent so ( ) and ( ) are equivalent using ) are equivalent so ( ) since and the series ( ) and ( ) are and As equivalence of series is an equivalence relation, it follows that ( ) ( ) . Composition Factors The multiset of isomorphism types of factors in the composition series of are } and for it is called the composition factors of . So in the Example above, it is { { } Proposition 4.12 A finite group is soluble if and only if it its composition factors are all that is cyclic of prime order. Proof [ ] If all the composition factors are cyclic then is soluble by definition. [ ] Conversely, if is soluble then it has a subnormal series with abelian factors, so its composition factors are all abelian. So by sheet 1, they are all cyclic of prime order. So soluble and | | then the composition factors are { } Unfortunately a finite group is not determined by its composition factors but knowledge of the composition factors is useful for studying a finite group. Chapter 5: Permutation Groups and Simplicity Proofs In some sense, Nilpotent Soluble groups can be regarded as a generalisation of Abelian Groups. By the previous chapter all their composition factors are . Now we will study non-abelian simple groups. Block Let act on . A block for or . with | | is a subset and but that for all , Primitive Action An action on is primitive if it is transitive and there are no blocks. Imprimitive Action is imprimitive if transitive and there are blocks. (Im)primitivity only applies to transitive actions. Example: { } 〈( on ) on { generally, for ( e.g. taking , then { Lemma 5.1 If is a block then Proof | | )〉 then { } and { } are blocks but { }, if | and then { } { } is a block. is a block for all | | | | | |. Fix } is not. More } is a block. . then let ) then since then take (so is a block so so is a block. Lemma 5.2 Let be transitive and primitive. a block. Then | ||| |. In particular, | | is prime implies Proof } partition By Lemma 5.1, the sets { } form a block system. So { and | | | | for all hence | | Example { Let } take ( ), where [ ] { } we have [ Then in the case ( )( )( ) ]. Then ( )( )( ) and is | |. We have two block systems if . Each row is a block and the set of all rows form a block system. Similarly for the columns. In fact . Theorem 5.3 If is 2-transitive then is primitive. Proof Let be 2-transitive. Then for any and there exists so that and . { }. By 2-transitivity there Suppose is a block and so | | . Let . Let exists so that . Therefore so a block implies that . { } arbitrary, hence But so . As . Contradiction. Therefore there are no blocks and so is primitive. So now we have Remarks )〉 For prime we know 〈( . This is primitive by Lemma 5.2. Hence by Theorem 5.3 it cannot be 2-transitive. (In particular it cannot map the pair ( ) ( )). )〉 is transitive but not primitive. For not prime then 〈( Lemma 5.4 If is transitive and transitive, then . Proof Let as Therefore Theorem 5.5 Let | | and of for any and there exists a subgroup is transitive then there exists so . transitive. Then with with is primitive if and only if and so . is a maximal subgroup . Proof [ ] Take and assume is maximal in . Let be a block and define { }. } partition replace by Since the sets { if necessary and assume . Then so so . By maximality, or . If then let so there exists with (because is transitive) so so so . But as arbitrary then this implies | | so is not a block. Contradiction. If let so by transitivity of , there exists with . Then now by definition of , so . Now as arbitrary, so is not a block. Contradiction. Hence there are no blocks and so is primitive. [ ] Assume is primitive. Let for some . We want to prove or . { } implies { } implies Let . If | | then and so . Similarly, if then this implies that is transitive since was arbitrary. Then by Lemma 5.4, . | | | | we will prove is a block, giving a Now we consider the case when contradiction to primitive. Let and so there exists such that . Since there exist so that and ( . But then so So we have proved that if Contradiction to primitive. . So ) then so so by definition so is a block. Normal Subgroups of Permutation Groups Theorem 5.6 Let be transitive and 1. 2. 3. with . Then one of the following holds: { } and so and so is a block. is transitive. Proof { }. Then Suppose so for all If hence so then . So if and transitive and and for all then implies that . is transitive by definition. In general let . This is a subgroup of by Lemma 3.1 containing and . Assume that both 1. and 2. do not hold. It was proved in Theorem 5.5 that a block, so we have 3. Corollary 5.7 If is primitive and with then is is transitive. Proof We apply Theorem 5.6. As , condition 1. does not hold. As is primitive there are no blocks so condition 3. does not hold. Therefore we must have 2. and so is transitive. Remark By Theorem 5.3, if is 2-transitive then is primitive. Hence every 2-transitive action with a normal subgroup acting non-trivially on implies that is transitive. We now consider the case where . Regular Action An action is called regular if it is transitive and for Regular normal subgroup For a group action , if is a regular normal subgroup of . , and is regular then . Examples { ( )( ) ( )( ) ( )( )}. is a regular normal subgroup of 1. Take and . 2. Affine Groups: ( ) of affine Take for a field, we define a group ( ) transformations. We say that for a map , if there exists and a non-singular linear map such that for all . [If and we restrict to the set of orthogonal maps we get the isometry group of .] We must first prove that is a group. For if with ( ( we have ) and ( ) ( ) ) so . (Closure). Given define by and then so . As the composition of functions is associative and the identity map is in , we have a group. { } be called the translation subgroup. Then for Let and we have ( so hence . is clearly transitive. Now for , if . was arbitrary so by definition ) ( ) with then so is a regular normal subgroup. so Lemma 5.7.1 Let be a finite set. If is 2-transitive and a regular normal subgroup of then is an elementary abelian -group for some dividing | |. Hence for some and in particular | | . Proof Assume . For { }. As , is regular, for all so there exists a unique . As so that is 2-transitive then for all { } there exists { } are with so ( ) . So all elements conjugate in so all have the same order. Therefore every non-identity element has order for some prime so | | for some . By Theorem 2.9 we conclude that ( ) . As ( ) ( ) we must have by Theorem 4.7. As all elements of are conjugate and ( ) this implies that ( ) and so is abelian. Therefore by the Fundamental Theorem of Abelian Groups. Proposition 5.8 has no regular normal subgroup for . Proof Suppose not and let be a regular normal subgroup. As in the previous proof there exist { }. Let ( ) with for all . Since }. As ( ) if and only if . Therefore ( ) { unique we have ( ) | so ( we have and hence | | ) . As we have so . But by Lemma 5.7.1, for some prime and integer we have but this is impossible since is not a prime power. Theorem 5.9 is not simple for . Proof We apply induction on . As is transitive, take a normal subgroup so that . Then by Corollary 5.7 and Theorem 5.3 this implies is transitive. By Proposition 5.8, is not a regular normal subgroup so for some the stabiliser { ( ) ( } ) . Moreover; { } { } and as { }) ( we have so so as . Hence is normal is simple. We must now do . Take . Then by Sheet 2, Q4 part ii, the conjugacy classes of have representations ( )( ) ( )( )( ) using combinatorics, the sizes of these conjugacy classes are respectively. Then | | . But any combination will not yield a factor of 60, so we get simple. The Finite Simple Groups (Classified ~1981/2004) 0. for prime (the abelian ones) 1. for 2. Groups of Lie type over finite fields. 3. 26 sporadic groups Here we deal with the linear classical groups, ( ). ) be the group of invertible Let be any field. Let ( matrices with entries in , or ) equivalently, invertible non-singular linear maps . Now ( the ) is multiplicative subgroup of which is abelian. We usually assume and so ( non-abelian. There are two actions of ( ): 1. Right multiplication of row vectors by matrices. This has two orbits { } and 2. Let be the set of 1-dimensional subspaces of . That is {〈 〉 〈 〉. The Projective Action. Then the action is defined 〈 〉 Theorem 5.10 ( ) is 2-transitive for 1. 2. The kernel of this action is the subgroup { } of scalar matrices. { } { }}. Proof 1. Let 〈 〉 〈 〉 and 〈 〉 〈 〉 .〈 〉 〈 〉 are linearly independent so we can extend to a basis of . Similarly we have a basis of . So there is a linear map mapping for (which is invertible since the domain and the image are linearly independent) hence there exists ( ) with 〈 〉 〈 〉 and 〈 〉 . 〈 〉 { 2. The kernel is the set { }} that is the set { 〈 〉 { }} so in particular applying to basis elements { we obtain that Therefore by the first isomorphism theorem ( ) ( ) ( ( Moreover { ) ) }. ( ) is a homomorphism and } ( ) so by the Second Isomorphism Theorem: ( ( ) ) ( ) ( ) Properties of Finite Fields All finite fields have order for some prime and For each there is a unique field of order (Galois Theory - the splitting field of ). ( ). Take Also, finite implies cyclic. Let be the rows of . Take so | | . is any non-zero vector (there are possibilities). Su[[pse we have chosen . They must be linearly independent. Choose ; to get linearly independent we must not be in the subspace spanned by 〉 {∑ denoted 〈 . Hence the number of } so has size possibilities for | is ( )| The order of , | | ( ) is | ( . Hence | )| ( )( | ( ( )| ) then | ) | ) so the order of )| )| | ( )| }| is ( | | { ( ( | ∏( |{ ( { ) | ( )| 〈 〉. For which ; there are ) ( | ( | )| So is a multiple of So ) and | | | Let ( )| possibilities. ( ) ( )( ) } so | ( )| Example | | ( )| ( ( )| ( The small )( | ( ) ) )| so | ( )| ( ( ( ( ( ( ( )| )| )| )| )| ) )| . ) are: | | | | | | Theorem 5.11 ( For ( ( ) ( | | ( ( ( ) )| )| ) | ( )| ( ) ( ) ( ) is simple for any field , except for ( ) and | | ) or 3. Proof Step 1 ( ) is -transitive. Proof Let 〈 〉 〈 〉 and 〈 〉 〈 〉 .〈 〉 〈 〉 are linearly independent so we can extend to a basis of . Similarly we have a basis of . So there is a linear map mapping for (which is invertible since the domain and the image are linearly independent) hence there exists ( ) with 〈 〉 〈 〉 and 〈 〉 ( ) ( ) by . Let and define 〈 〉 〈 〉 〈 〉. and for so and 〈 〉 Step 2 – Basic Properties of Transvections ( ) is a transvection if its matrix with respect to some basis of ( ) that is the identity matrix but with a 1 in the ( From linear algebra, changing the basis replaces by which shows that all transvections are conjugate. Consider a matrix position ( ( for all ) position. for some ) that is the identity matrix with a ). If this matrix is using the basis so with respect to the basis ( then is ( ), in the and ( )) the matrix becomes ( ) so is a transvection. Observe ( ) ( Recall that matrices of the form zero matrix but with a 1 in position ( column operations of the first type. ) which is also a transvection. are called elementary matrices. Here is a ). These correspond to elementary row and Step 3 ( ) is generated by transvections. Proof ( ) can be From Linear Algebra this is equivalent to the statement “any reduced to the identity using elementary row and column operations of the first type.” This is the operation o a in a multiple o a row or olumn to another row or column. As , we know there is a non-zero entry in the first row. Add a multiple (if necessary) of the relevant column to column 2 to get Now replace column 1 by column ( then so then ) . . Now subtract multiples of the first row and column from other columns to get a matrix of the form ( ) but denote the lower-right hand corner matrix of size ( ( ) by . Then ( ). Now applying a proof by induction on , the result follows. The case (the product of 0 transvections). Step 4 ( ) is perfect if ] only if [ . except for ,| | or . We recall ) is clear perfect if and Proof ] where By Step 3, it is sufficient to prove that all transvections are contained in [ ] char ( ) but [ ( ) so [ ( ) by Theorem 4.7. ] ), the above Furthermore, using the fact that all transvections are conjugate in ( ]. says it is sufficient to find a single transvection in [ For the case , we compute directly that ) ( [( )] ( ) so when | | there exists with so [ transvection. When and | | we use a similar argument: ) ( [( and | | For the case [( That is [ ] contains a )] or | | ) ( we observe that: )] ( ) ] contains a transvection in all cases so in all cases we have [ ] . Step 5 – Iwasawa’s Theorem Let be primitive with perfect. Suppose there exists for any such ⟨ | ⟩. Then that is abelian and is simple. [Note that this is also used in analogous proofs for simplicity of other classical groups.) Proof Let with . primitive implies transitive by Corollary 5.7. Then for , by Theorem 5.5, is maximal so or . In particular, ⟨ | so ⟩ hence is abelian so [ Now this is abelian since by hypothesis so . As . Therefore . Then arbitrary, we have shown ] for all by Theorem 4.5. But so is perfect simple. Step 6 – Completion of the Proof ( ) and We apply Iwasawa’s Theorem with { ( ). By Step 1 we know that is 2-transitive hence 5.3. By Step 4, is perfect except for the cases and or It remains to find the subgroup . Take 〈( )〉. Then . Therefore { ( ) that is ( }. primitive by Theorem . ) ( ) for Let be the set ( expression ( {( ) {( ) ( } ( Let . Observe for the ( And ) ( ( ) ) . Then ( conjugate in ) . is a normal subgroup; 〉. 〈 . 〉 we are done since by Step 3, ) with ( is ). case that: ( )( )( ) ( then take ) ( ) ( ) to an element of ( )( ( . So every transvection is conjugate in For the general case, again let is by the ) . Note that is the kernel of some homomorphism; 〈 It remains to show that Let be a transvection. If we show generated by all transvections. ) ( ( ) ) We know that there exists ( . ) . This is a homomorphism: )( {( Hence }. Denote ( ) by ( ) ( } ) ). It is elementary to check that ) so is an abelian subgroup of Define a map So ( ( ) ) ) to some element of ) so ) ( . that so every transvection is . Therefore all transvections are contained in for some . By Step 3, is generated ⟨ | ⟩. There ore y Iwasawa’s Theorem by transvections so is simple. ( A Closer Study of | ( )| ( ) for small . )( | ) ( )| | | ( ( | ) Let {( | | . Recall | | ( ). Let {( ) }; the subgroup 〈 〉 for )( ( so ( Then ( | | | 〈 ( ( ) {( ). ) ) similarly 〉〈 〉〈 〉〈 〉} 〈 〉 〈( ) and | and 〉 〈 ( { 〉 〈 { ( ( 〈 〉 )( )( )( 〈 〉. We { )} ( ) ). Therefore }. Then as before )〉 )( 〉 〈( } where 〉 〈 〉 and | | ( } ) ) ( Clearly, 〈 )( ) and ( 〉 ) )〉 { . Then } ) 〈 〉 for so ( )( and 〉. Let ) 〉 where ( )( 〈 ( We have 〈 and ) so ( 〈 ( so ) . 〈 〉 and ) is maximal is )( ( . Define and ) and | | is a Sylow -subgroup of ; that is , ) ( ) )〉 {〈 with ) ) in the previous proof. Hence .| | } so ( ) ( : } the order of this is 〉 | | ) by the Orbit-Stabiliser Theorem. for some prime ) ( Now ( }. In this case )( ) ) ( By Theorem 5.5 primitive implies that write down the Generators for small ; So 〈( )( ) ( First we recall some facts about the case {〈 〉} {〈 | ( )| | ( )| 〈( )〉, and 〈( )〉. | | ( Let {( ( )| )( ( ) and | ) ) ( | | ) and | so ( )( ( ). ) . | | 〈 〉 | 〈 { . We have 〈 〉. We have | 〉 ( ( With ( ) ) } with 〈 〉 and 〈 〉, ) ( ( )( )( 〉 〈 〉 〉 where ( ( . 〈 { 〉 ) ). We shall see later that } with 〈 ) ( )| 〉. We have ) ( ( In the same way as before we determine that ( )( )( )( ) and 〈 〈 〉, 〉 〈 〉 〈 〉 and ) ) and ( )( ) and is omitted, although it is no more difficult to compute. In this case } where and . In this case | | and | | { 〉 We choose 〈 〉 〈 〈 〈 ( } where 〈 〉 〈 〉 〈 〉 〈 〉 and ) We can then calculate that ( )( ) ( } where , . 〉 〉, { . We can take and We have 〈 . ( ( { 〉 〈 ) ) and In this case | | and | | 〈 〉 〈 〉 〈 〉 〈 〉 〈 〉 where | 〈 〈 ( ( )( )( 〉 〉 〈 〈 〈 〉 〈 〉 〉. 〉 where ) )( )( 〈 )( ) ( ) ) ( ( )( ) )( ) Chapter 6: The Transfer Homomorphism Let { [ be a finite index subgroup of a group ( itself need not be finite). Let } where | | and . Then we can define a homomorphism , the abelianisation of . ] acts on the coset space by right multiplication. That is, for any some giving a permutation of . depends on and . We can write }. permutation of { ( ) We can write ( ) for some prove this is a homomorphism . Define ( ) . Since [ [ ] ] [ , for giving a ]∏ ( ). We will is a elian, it oesn’t matter a out the ( ) in the product. order of Lemma 6.1 is a homomorphism. Proof Let ( But also, ( ] [ ) ( ) ]∏ is abelian, we get [ Therefore ( Note ) and ( ) ) ( ) ( ( ) ( ) ]∏ for ( ) ) ( ( ) ( ) is a permutation of { The map Since [ ( ) . Then ). Hence ]∏ ([ } and so { ( ) . Then ( ) [ ( )) ([ ( ) ]∏ } ]∏ }. ( ) ( ) [ ]∏ where { } { each Proof Rather than a proof, I will give an example: Example: ( { ( ) ( ). is actually independent of the choice of coset representatinves ). Lemma 6.2 For , ( ) ( )) )( ) then ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) } and (assuming and Therefore: ( ) ( ) ( ) [ So ( ) ]( ( ) )( ( ) )( ). Here and . Normal -complement Let be a finite group, and so ( ). Then is called a normal -complement in if is a semi- ire t pro u t. (They on’t ne essarily exist.) Example For , it has a normal -complement but no normal -complement. Theorem 6.3 (Burnside’s Transfer Theorem) (BTT) ( ). If Let be a finite group, | | | and ( ( )) (that is in the centre of its normaliser) then has a normal -complement. So unless ,| | then is not simple. Note that applied if ( ) ( ) and so ( ( )) is abelian. We need two Lemmas. Lemma 6.4 Let be a finite abelian group with is an automorphism. is abelian. Therefore BTT can only be ( | |) Proof The map is clearly a homomorphism. If this implies that . Hence is injective. As isomorphism and thus an automorphism. Lemma 6.5 Let be finite, conjugate in ( ) and then is finite, abelian. If ( ). This is not true in general if mapping ( ) then ( | |) . As is an are conjugate in then they are is not abelian. Proof We have for some . So and . Since are ( ). Therefore abelian, ( ( )). By Sylow Conjugacy ( ) with ( ) applied to ( ) there exists so ( ). Now ( ) . That is, they are conjugate in ( ). Proof of BTT ( ( )) therefore then ( ) ∏ is abelian so [ where { and so by Lemmas 6.4, 6.5, ] . So the transfer } { } and and hence . By Lemma 6.2, for and are conjugate in ( ) that is and thus for for some ( ). But ( ( )) so , ( ) ∏ ∏ | | so ( | |) ( ) so by Lemma 6.4, | is an We have since automorphism of . So let (and so is normal). As | is an automorphism, ( ) so . Let , since | is surjective, there exists with ( ) and so . Therefore . Corollary 6.6 If is finite, | | for odd and then is not simple. [Also, | | odd then is not simple by Feit-Thompson (VERY HARD!)] Proof Take therefore ( ) then | | ( ) hence { } so for so is not simple by BTT. ( ), so Chapter 7: Classification of Simple Groups of order 500 Proposition 7.1 Let be a finite non abelian simple group. ( ) and 1. If acts on with then is faithful (that is ) and | | | | 2. If with then , and (where means “isomorphi to a subgroup of) ( )| then 3. If || |, for . | Proof 1. Let be the kernel of on . Then (since ) so simple implies that and hence . ( ) then using the second isomorphism theorem Suppose ( ) ( ) | | | | | | ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )| | ( ) ( )| ( ) Hence | . so ( )| | | | Hence If | | and hence simple implies ( ) . Therefore so is abelian which is a contradiction. ( ). ( ) is soluble so it has a subnormal series with abelian then quotients. Therefore is soluble which is a contradiction. Therefore | | . 2. We apply part 1 to the special case of the action of on the set of cosets of . 3. If , has a normal Sylow -subgroup so cannot be simple. ( ) by For , apply part 1 to the special case of the action of on conjugation. Theorem 7.2 1. All finite simple groups of order 60 are isomorphic to 2. All finite simple groups of order 168 are isomorphic to 3. All finite simple groups of order 360 are isomorphic to ( ( ) ) ( ( ( ) ) ) Proof 1. Let be a simple, | | ( )| ( )| By Sylow’s Theorem, | and divides 15 so | ( ) has It cannot be 1, since then by Corollary 3.8 which would give a contradiction. ( )| 3. If | ( )| ( ) then By Proposition 7.1 part 3, | then for | ( )| so ( ) a group of order 4. So ( ) is abelian and hence ( ( )) then by BTT has a normal 2-complement so not simple. ( )| Therefore | . By Proposition 7.1, but | | | | so . 2. Let be simple, | | ( ). | ( )| ( )| Let and divides 24 so | or 8. It cannot be 1 by Corollary 3.8 so | ( )| . Take ( ). We may assume Let { }. 〈 〉. Now, | ( )| | | | | . Recall that 〉. If there are only two groups of order 21; and 〈 | ( ) is abelian then is not simple by BTT. 〉. Therefore ( ) 〈 | Consider the action of on as conjugation so ( ) .| | and so is a 7-cycle. We might as well assume (after reordering the elements of ) that ( ). | | (so is a product of 3-cycles) and so as , must fix some other point in . We may assume that fixes , so . ( ) ( ). Since so , we have Hence ( )( ). Let 〈 〉. | | and implies ). Lemma ( ), let ( ) { Let { } Then Proof ( ). We must prove Let and then ( Now using this notation, ) since ( ) { (as }. If that is ( ). for all . } so ( ) { } that is ( ) fixes | and or interchanges them. Since | . | { }| Now ( ) cannot be abelian since then it contradicts BTT. Therefore ( ) ⟨ | ⟩ so ( ) | As | we have | for any ( is 2-transitive) and so cannot | contain . Therefore is a product of 4 transpositions. The same applies to and since they are all of order 2. ( )( ) and ( )( ). We now Recall so determine : ( ) ( ) ( ) So or . So and so by replacing with or . We can therefore assume wlog that . | | ( )( )( )( ) Now but so 〉 is transitive. |〈 〉| 〉| | | so is generated Now 〈 so |〈 〈 〉. 〈 〉 ( ). by We have proved that 3. Non Examinable, but structured similar to the above with further complications. Theorem 7.3 The only non-abelian simple groups of order Proof If | | prime then have order 60, 168, 360. is not non-abelian simple as ( ) by Theorem 2.9. Also, if | | for odd then is not simple by Corollary 6.6 During this proof we will not use: Theorem (Burnside) Any group of order for prime is soluble. Proof Requires Character Theory. See Groups and Representations. During the rest of the proof, | ( )|. and will denote a Sylow -subgroup of . | | | | We can now omit all possibilities except 6 cases, which we postpone until later: Order Reason Not Simple by Definition Prime Powers 2 times odd Prime powers 2 times odd | | | | contradiction to Theorem 7.1 ii. 2 times odd | | 2 times odd | | | | 2 times odd | | From now on, to speed things up, we omit prime powers and 2 times odd: | | | | and | no possible | | | | No possible : | contradiction. | | No possible | contradiction. [ ] [ ] [ ] No possible and | contradiction. | | Must have so is abelian and ( ( )) contradicting BTT. ( )| [ ] By Theorem 7.2 all non-abelian simple groups of order 60 are isomorphic to . Note that if we have some prime and numbers and with | | then we cannot have || | . To speed things up, from now on we exclude such 2 times odd | 66 67 | | 2 times odd | | no | | | contradicts 7.1. | ( )| | so ( ) abelian contradicting BTT. | no | | contradicts 7.1 | ( )| contradicts BTT | | | ( )| so by Proposition 7.1 but this | | ontra i ts La ran e’s Theorem e ause | by Proposition 7.1 but | | so | and since is simple we apply 7.1 part 2 (to ) so which is a contradiction. so | ( )| contradicting BTT | | , so no | Contradiction to 7.1 | ( )| ( ) abelian Contradiction to BTT No No No | | | ( )| | contradicting contradicting BTT no | | No No No Contradiction to 7.1 part 3. No | No | so but | | simple. No , no | | but Remark Recall that if a group with | | and prime and and then by Sylow, so abelian. | ( )| so ( ) abelian therefore ( )) contradicting BTT. ( | so | ( )| contradicting BTT. No POSTPONED No No | hence | ( )| . By the Remark ( ) above, is abelian contradicting BTT. POSTPONED No | so but | | | | No No | ( )| ( ) abelian. Contradiction to BTT. | | so ontra i tion to La ran e’s Theorem. | | No . POSTPONED No . contradicts BTT no No No contradicts BTT | | No | ( )| so ( ) abelian contradicting BTT. | ( )| ( ) abelian by remark, so contradicts BTT. No so | ( )| abelian so contradicts BTT. Remember that we are omitting prime powers, 2 times odd and | | with for some | . | | | | No No POSTPONED No No POSTONED No No | No | but | | | No No No No No POSTPONED | ( )| so | ( ) abelian, contradicting BTT. All the above orders were covered by Theorems in the course and arithmetic. The postponed orders need more Group Theory. In all cases, we consider the conjugation action of on ( ) for some suitable . During all cases we will use the following notation: ( ) ( ) { } ( ) ( ) Order | | We have . So | ( )| so ( ) by Proposition 3.14. As ( ) abelian, this contradicts BTT, so assume | ( )| 〈 | { }| so 〉 | . Since | | is a single 11-cycle. We may assume WLOG that ( ). | | so must fix some element other than , say . Therefore ( ) ( ) as maps so we must have ( )( )( )( )( ) but then ( ) which is a contradiction. Lemma Let be a finite group. Then || | and ( ) ( ) Proof By the Second Isomorphism Theorem, implies As ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) and ( ) , this implies that ( ) ( ) so ( ) is a -group is a -group. maximal -groups and ( ) ( ) . Moreover, we cannot have ( ) has order 1, so since and | | | |. Order We have . contradiction, so . { }. Since | | ( ), ( ), Take , fixes a unique point , ( ) ( ) since if fixes some other by definition of the conjugation action, { }| ( ) | hence contradicting the Lemma. . { } have | | The orbits of on or ; since there exists an orbit of length 3. Let be in such an orbit. | | . Let ( ) then | ( )| | | | | by Orbit Stabiliser Theorem. By the Lemma, so . ( )| ( )| As | so | | ||| | || | | | | If | | then | Therefore | | . Since | | | ( ) but also . | ( )| ( )| and | and and ( ) as are both abelian. Let . Therefore | | , so If | | then and so contradiction. contradiction to 7.1. ( )| by BTT, has a normal 3-complement with ( ) and ( ) by Theorem 4.4 so | ( ) so . Contradiction. Order 〈 〉 { ( ) . Let ( } and let ). Let or . If Therefore so so | | | ( )| | | . with | | . | ( )| so assume . Then then so action is not faithful. Contradiction to 7.1 ( )( )( ) ( ). Contradiction to 7.1. Order } Take ( ) { . Then ( ) | | ( ) { } consists of two 11-cycles. We may assume that )( ). | ( )| ( ) ( ) conjugation have ( ) with so there exists . . Then 〈 〉| | ( | ( )| Case 1 { } say ( )( then Case 2 { } so permutes the set { } and { of these orbits so . Contradiction. ) ( ) so ( ). ( ) } so fixes at least one point in both Order . } on { | | | | | | { ( ) { }. Let ,| | ( ) so | }. As in the case | | , has a orbit of length 3 say ( ). By the Lemma, and . But and ( ) so then by Theorem 4.4 ii ( ⏟ ( ))| ⏞ so | ( )| ( ) hence | . ⏟ ( )| contradicting 7.1. Order }. | { }| { } have size 2,4,8. ( ) { so the orbits of on So there exists an orbit { } of size 2. Let so | | by the Orbit-Stabiliser ( ) so ( ) and hence | ( )| Theorem and then | ; ( ( ))| contradiction since . This completes the Proof of Theorem 7.3