Superman Sentences Author(s): Ad Neeleman and Kriszta Szendröi Reviewed work(s): Source: Linguistic Inquiry, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Winter, 2004), pp. 149-159 Published by: The MIT Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4179266 . Accessed: 05/03/2012 08:39 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Linguistic Inquiry. http://www.jstor.org SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION 149 Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on governmentand binding. Dordrecht:Foris. Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The MinimalistProgram. Cambridge,Mass.: MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Chomsky,Noam, and HowardLasnik. 1993. The theory of principles and parameters.In Syntax:An internationalhandbookof contemporary research, ed. by Joachim Jacobs, Amim von Stechow, Wolfgang Stemefeld, and Theo Vennemann, 506-569. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Franks,Steven, and NorbertHornstein. 1991. Secondarypredication in Russian and proper govemment of PRO. In Control and grammar, ed. by Richard K. Larson, Sabine Iatridou,Utpal Lahiri, and James Higginbotham,1-50. Dordrecht:Kluwer. Hofmann, Johann B., and Anton Szantyr. 1965. Lateinische Syntax und Stilistik.Munich:Beck. Hormstein,Norbert. 1999. Movement and control. Linguistic Inquiry 30:69-96. Hudson, Richard.2002. Case agreement,PRO and structuresharing. Ms., University College London. Martin,Roger. 1996. A minimalisttheory of PRO and control. Doctoral dissertation,University of Connecticut,Storrs. Martin,Roger. 2001. Null Case andthe distributionof PRO.Linguistic Inquiry32:141-166. Sigur6sson, Halld6r A. 1991. Icelandic Case-markedPRO and the licensing of lexical arguments.NaturalLanguage & Linguistic Theory9:327-363. SUPERMAN SENTENCES Ad Neeleman UniversityCollege London Kriszta Szendro'i UiL OTS, Utrecht University 1 Introduction Suppose Fathercomes home from work and finds Motherin obvious distress. Then the following discourse may take place: (1) Father: What happened? Mother: You know how I think our children should read decent books. Well, when I came home, rather thandoing his homework,[lPJohnnywas [vp reading [DP SUPERMAN] to some kid]]. For many valuable comments, we would like to thank audiences at the 1st Euresco Conference on the Syntax of Normal and ImpairedLanguage; Logic and Language7; InternationalConferenceon the Structureof Hungarian 6; MIT LingLunch;and the 4th Amsterdam-UtrechtWorkshop,"Meaning and Intonation."We would furtherlike to thankJocelyn Ballantyne,Danny Fox, Chris Kennedy, Hans van de Koot, Andrew Nevins, and Craige Roberts for importantcontributionsto this squib. 150 SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION The discourse status of Mother's reply is complex, as it contains a contrastive focus inside a contrastive focus inside an all-focus sentence. First, her answer tells Fatherwhat happenedand thereforethe bracketedIP must be in focus as a whole. Second, the VP reading Supermanto some kid is contrastedwith doing his homework.Finally, the DP Supermanis contrasted with decent books. These three foci share a single phonological marking,namely, the stress on Superman (indicatedby small capitals).' One may have doubts about the reliability of wh-questionslike Whathappened?as a test for identifyingfocus. Thatdoes not invalidate the claim that (1) is an example of a focus embeddedin a largerfocus: the contrastsat the level of the VP and the object are enough to motivate this conclusion. The same point can be made on the basis of the scope of the focus-sensitive operatorsonly and even, as shown by Father's continuationin (2) (adaptedfrom Krifka 1991:131). (2) Father: Despite all our efforts! We even, [only2 read [KAFKA]2 to our children]l! "Superman sentences" like Mother's reply have hardly been discussed in the literatureon focus. Apart from Krifka's paper, one of few relevant works is by Jacobs (1991), whose approachwe briefly turn to below. Supermansentences pose a challenge to any syntactictheory of focus. We will argue, however, that they are more problematicfor theories of focus based on a feature that requires syntactic licensing (Horvath1986, Brody 1995, Rizzi 1997) than for theories based on a mappingbetweenprosodyandmeaning(Chomsky1971, Cinque 1993, Reinhart1995, Neeleman and Reinhart1998, Zubizarreta1998, Horvath 2000, Zubizarretaand Vergnaud2000, Samek-Lodovici2002). We first spell out the two approachesto focus in more detail (section 2). We then discuss to what extent they can accommodateSuperman sentences (sections 3-5). 2 Stress-Based and Feature-Based Approaches to Focus Feature-basedtheories assume (a) that [ + focus] is interpretedat the LF interfaceand (b) thatit affects stressassignmentat the PF interface (Jackendoff 1972). Recent approaches in addition assume (c) that [+ focus] is checked in syntax in the specifier of a designatedfunctional projection (Horvath 1986, Brody 1990, 1995, Laka 1990, E. Kiss 1995, Rizzi 1997). Checking is responsible for focus-related movement in languages like Hungarian,while languages like English have covert focus movement.Thus, in Nick's reply in (3), a memberof 1Any stress on somekidis secondary. (a) It is perceived as less strong than the stress on Supernanby native speakers.(b) It is optionaland sensitive to rhythmiceffects, as is typical of secondarystress: whereas somekidin (1) can remainwithout stress, if a longer DP appearsas the complementof to, the secondary stress is obligatory. SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION 151 the Sex Pistols carries[ + focus]. Accordingly,it moves to the relevant functionalspecifier at LF and is interpretedthere. At the PF interface, [+ focus] is responsible for the stress shift from the normal stress position to the subject. Note that internallyto the subject, stress is as predicted by the Nuclear Stress Rule, as shown by the fact that A MEMBER of the Sex Pistols comes here a lot would be an infelicitous reply in (3). (3) John: So, which celebritiesdid you say frequentthe Jeremy Bentham? Nick: Well, [a member [of the SEX PISTOLS]] comes here a lot. Stress-basedtheories assume thatevery utteranceis associated with a set of potential foci, where members of this set are constituentsthat contain the main stress. (4) Any constituentthatcontainsthe main stressof an utterance can be interpretedas the focus of the utterance. According to this definition, Nick's reply has at least three potential foci, listed in (5). (5b) is the actual focus in the discourse in (3). (5) a. b. [DP the SEX PISTOLS] [DP a member of [DP the SEX PISTOLS]] C. [IP[DPa memberof [DP the SEX PISTOLS]] comes here a lot] In addition, the stress-based theory requires an economy condition minimizingstressshift (or maximizingthe effects of the NuclearStress Rule), which accountsfor the infelicity of A MEMBER of the Sex Pistols comes here a lot as a reply to John's question. This answer has the focus set in (6). (6) a. b. [N MEMBER] [DP a MEMBERof [DP the Sex Pistols]] C [IP[DPa MEMBER of [DP the Sex Pistols]] comes here a lot] The contextrequires(5b)/(6b) as the actualfocus. However,(Sb) maximizes the effect of the Nuclear Stress Rule, while (6b) requires an additionalstressshift withinthe subject.Thus,economyconsiderations favor the reply in (3). As a rule of thumb, "focus projection" from a markedstress position tends to be blocked. (As we will show later, such economy considerationscannot be avoided in theories that take focus to be a syntactic feature and thereforecannot be used to force a choice between the stress-basedand feature-basedapproaches.) The definition of focus set in (4) refers to the main stress of an utterance,ratherthan to stress in general. The reason for this is that secondary stress does not support focus. If stress is shifted to the subject of a transitive sentence, the object usually carries secondary stress. However, if the object is also contrastivelyfocused, this is not enough. Then, it has to bear main stress, like the subject. 152 SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION (7) We have a problembecausepeople don't agree.JOHN wants to rent a VIDEO, but PETER wants to go to the MOVIES. One of the attractionsof the stress-basedtheory is that it does away with the focus featureand relates focus and stress in a direct fashion. This comes at the cost of having to assume communicationbetween LF and PF. Overt focus movement in languages like Hungarianmay at first sight lend supportto the feature-basedaccount,buton closerinspection this turns out not to be so. In Hungarian,as in English, foci contain the main stress. Moreover,the motivationfor the movementcould be the checking of a feature other than [+ focus]: Horvath (2000:202) argues that this featureis [ + exhaustiveidentification].Alternatively, an analysis may be based on the fact that nuclear stress falls on the leftmost constituent in Hungarian.Leftward focus movement can thereforebe seen as movementinto the main stressposition (Szendr6i 2003).2 3 SupermanSentencesin the Stress-BasedApproach Let us now turn to the stress-basedaccount of Mother's reply in (1). Since stress is on Supermanin this example, the focus set associated with it is as follows: (8) a. [DP SUPERMAN] b. [vp reading [DP SUPERMAN] to some kid] c. [lPJohnnywas [vp reading[DP SUPERMAN] to some kid]] It is usually assumedthat in any given context, only one candidateis selected fromthe focus set as the actualfocus, althoughthereis nothing in the stress-basedtheory that forces this. In fact, if we do allow an arbitrarynumberof foci to be selected, the interpretationof Superman sentences follows directly. The targeted pragmaticinterpretationof the example at hand actuallyrequiresselection of all threecandidates. Supermanis contrastedwith decent books, readingSupermanto some kid is contrastedwith doing his homework,and the entire IP carries new information. Recall that, in the stress-basedaccount,economy considerations tend to block "focus projection" from a markedstress position. For example, an all-focus sentence normallyhas main stress on the object (if thereis one). This is because no matterwhere stress falls, the entire sentence is a member of the focus set. But only the candidatewith stress on the object maximizes the effects of the Nuclear Stress Rule. In the example in (1), however, there is "focus projection" even though stress is shifted from the indirect object to Superman.Yet 2 In their appendixB, Koopmanand Szabolcsi (2000) suggest a possible approachto Hungarianexamplescomparableto (1) in termsof checkingtheory. It would take us too far afield to discuss how these can be analyzedin a theory without focus features. SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION 153 economy is not violated, because Supermanis itself contrasted(with decent books). This readingis not availableif the effects of the Nuclear Stress Rule are maximized, as (9) is associated with the focus set in (10), which does not contain [DP Superman] (9) [Ip Johnny was [vp reading Supermanto [DP some KID]]] (10) a. [DP some KID] b. [vp reading Supermanto [DP some KID]] c. [IP Johnnywas [vp readingSupermanto [DP some KID]]] One may thinkthatin Mother'sanswerin (1) the effects of the Nuclear StressRule could be maximizedby puttingmain stresson both Superman and some kid. The shifted stress on Supermanis unavoidable,as just explained,but the focus interpretationof the VP and the IP could be licensed by the stress assigned by the Nuclear Stress Rule. This is not what happens, however: the only constituentbearingmain stress in Mother's answer is Superman.In fact, assigning the same level of stress to some kid as to Supermanis impossible on the intendedreading of the example. We propose an account in terms of the economy condition in (11). Suppose that it is better to have a single stress assigned by the Nuclear Stress Rule than to have a single shifted stress. Suppose, furthermore,that it is better to have a single shifted main stress than to have a shifted main stress as well as main stress in the position favoredby the Nuclear Stress Rule. Then, since a single shifted stress suffices in (1), additionalmain stresses are ruled out. (11) a. Minimize the numberof prosodic peaks (given the targeted interpretation). b. Minimize stress shift (given the number of prosodic peaks). It is of course possible to put focus on both the indirect object and Superman.This cannot be done by using a single stress, since neither constituentis contained in the other. Hence, on this reading, and on this readingonly, the sentence will have to be pronouncedwith main stress on both constituents. (12) You know how I want our children to read decent books and how I think it is importantthat Johnnyplays with kids his own age. Well, when I came home, ratherthan doing his homework, [IP Johnnywas [vp reading [DP SUPERMAN] to [DP some SIXTEEN-YEAR-OLD]]]. More precisely, the focus set associatedwith the bracketedIP in (12) is as follows: (13) a. b. [DP some SIXTEEN-YEAR-OLD] [DP SUPERMAN] c. [vp reading Supermanto [DP some SIXTEEN-YEAR-OLD]] d. [IP Johnny was [vp reading Supermanto [DP some SIXTEEN-YEAR-OLD]]] 154 SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION The only interpretationsallowed by (13) that are not given by the focus sets in (8) and (10) are those in which both the directobject and the indirect object are focused (there may be additionalwide foci). But since (12) is less economical than either (1) or (9), it is only admissibleunderone of these interpretations,as in the context in (12). Notice that if some sixteen-year-oldin (12) does not carrymain stress, but secondary stress (as given by the Nuclear Stress Rule), it is impossible to interpretthis constituentas contrastedwith kids his own age. This is in line with our earlier conclusion that secondary stress is not sufficient to supportfocus. For the same reason, it is not possible to maintain that in the example in (1) it is the (optional) secondary stress on some kid that licenses VP and IP focus. Rather, the shifted main stress on Supermanmust allow focus projection.3 We concludethatfoci embeddedin foci receive a naturalexplanation in the stress-basedapproach.Supermansentences are a subcase of sentences containingmultiple foci, with the crucial difference that each focus is embeddedin the next. It follows from basic assumptions of the stress-basedtheory (the notions of focus set and economy) that all foci are indicatedby a single stress.4 4 Feature-BasedTheorieswithoutChecking As mentionedabove, the feature-basedtheory of focus that we argue against makes three assumptions:(a) that [ + focus] is interpretedat the LF interface,(b) thatit affects stressassignmentat the PF interface, and (c) that it is checked in syntax in the specifier of a designated functional projection. This is not to say that we take issue with all theoriesthatpresupposethe existence of a focus feature.In fact, there are at least two such theories that seem empiricallycorrect.Crucially, these theories do not adopt assumption (c). As we show, they are essentially syntacticencodings of the stress-basedapproach.The two theories are presentedin (14) and (15). (14) a. A syntactic feature [+ focus] can be added to a lexical item when it is selected from the lexicon. This feature is not copied to dominatingnodes. b. At the LF interface,any constituentcontaininga lexical item marked [+ focus] can be interpretedas the focus of the utterance. 3 The claim thata shifted stress allows focus projectionis hardlynew, but the cases in the literatureinvolve stress shift as a resultof anaphoricdestressing (Reinhart1995, Williams 1997, Zubizarreta1998, Schwarzschild1999). Superman sentences are differentfrom these cases: some kid in (1) is not anaphoric. 4 An anonymous reviewer points out a problem with Hungarian, where an example parallel to (1) would requireboth movement of Supermanto the focus position and stress on some kid. It can be argued,however, thatthe stress on some kid is forced if the constituentis not given. See Szendr6i 2003:sec. 11.2, for discussion. SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION 155 c. At the PF interface, a terminalmarked [ + focus] must carry main stress. (15) a. A syntactic feature [+ focus] can be added to a lexical item when it is selected from the lexicon. This feature is obligatorilycopied to dominatingnodes untilit reaches the root. b. At the LF interface, any constituent bearing [+ focus] can be interpretedas the focus of the utterance. c. At the PF interface, a terminalmarked [ + focus] must carrymain stress. Both theories employ a rule that constructs a focus set. In the first theory, this is (14b), the interpretiverule that defines possible foci at the LF interface.In the second, the syntacticmechanismof obligatory percolationand the interpretiverule jointly define the focus set (see (l5a) and (15b)). Moreover,[ + focus] on the terminalis nothingmore than a syntactic encoding of main stress. In order to avoid overgeneration,both theories also need to assume the economy conditionin (11) or somethinglike it. The number of focus features introducedon terminals has to be minimized, as explained above. In addition, where possible, [+ focus] has to be placed on the terminalsingled out by the Nuclear Stress Rule. Thus, in an all-focus sentence, stress is rightmost, while in a sentence in which the subject is focused, stress is rightmostwithin the subject. Although both (14) and (15) are descriptively adequate, these theories face two problems. First, the assumptionof a rule that adds [ + focus] to a lexical item when selected for mergeris incompatible with Inclusiveness(Chomsky1995). This principlestatesthatsyntactic operationscan only refer to lexical features;but [ + focus] cannot be a lexical feature.As lexical items arenot inherentlyfocused, the feature must be inserted after an element has been taken from the lexicon. Second, the behaviorof [ + focus] is decidedly nonsyntactic.We know of no other syntactic featuresthat obligatorilypercolate to the root node or do not percolateat all. According to both (14) and (15), any category that contains the terminalthat introduces[ + focus] is a potential focus, and neither distinguishes the actual focus from any potential foci in syntax. In other words, [+ focus] does not encode actual focus, but potentialfocus. If we want to include [+focus] in the set of regular syntactic featuresthat requirechecking (as stated in assumption(c)), we must allow for percolation,but not make it obligatory. 5 Checking [+ Focus] Whatwe take to be the standardfeature-basedtheory(insofaras there is one) makes the following assumptions: (16) a. A syntactic feature [+focus] can be added to a lexical item when it is selected from the lexicon. This feature may be copied to dominatingnodes. 156 SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION b. There is a designated functional head that attractsthe largest constituent bearing [+focus] (either overtly or covertly).5 c. At the LF interface, the largest constituent bearing [ + focus] is interpretedas the focus of the utterance. d. At the PF interface, a terminal marked [+ focus] must carry main stress. The underlyingmotivationfor this theory is that semanticinterpretation and position at LF are linked in a one-to-one fashion (compare Rizzi's (1996) Wh-Criterion).It is hence not a coincidence that (16b) and (16c) both mention "the largest constituentbearing [+ focus]." As a reminderof how this theory works, consider the answer in (17). Here, hat introduces[ + focus], which percolatesup to the subject DP, but no further.As a consequence,this DP is moved to the specifier of a designatedfunctionalprojection.In English, this presumablyhappens afterSpell-Out(althoughsome analysesassumeovertmovement; see Kayne 1998). At the LF interface, the man in the hat, being the largest [ + focus] constituent,is interpretedas focus. At the PF interface, hat, being the [ + focus] terminal,receives main stress. (17) Susan: Do you think anyone in this bathhouse can play chess? Jo: [THE MAN IN THE HAT] is a serious chess player. Superman sentences pose a serious problem for theories in which [+focus] is checked. The reason is simple. In the example in (1), Supermanmust carry [ +focus], as it carries shifted main stress. As explained, the largest constituentto which this featurepercolateswill be interpretedas the actualfocus. But in (1) thereare threeactualfoci: Superman,reading Supermanto some kid, and the whole sentence. In order to obtain a focus interpretationon the larger constituents, [+ focus] has to percolate up to the VP and IP levels. At the same time, in order to obtain a focal reading of the smaller constituents, [ + focus] must not percolatebeyond the DP and VP levels. This is a contradiction. In the theoriesdiscussedin section4, the syntaxand/orphonology of an utteranceprovidesa set of possible foci from which one or more can be selected as the actualfocus at the LF interface.But in a theory that employs checking to link interpretationand position, the syntax provides the actual focus, not a set of potential foci. This makes it impossible for a single [ + focus] (a single stressedterminal)to encode multiple foci. An anonymousreviewer suggests a variantof the theory of (16) that avoids the problems mentioned so far. The proposal maintains (16a) and (16d) but replaces (16b) with (18) and (16c) with (15b). 5 Weabstract awayfromthepossibilityof pied-piping infocusmovement. It is a problemsharedby the stress-based andfeature-based accounts. SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION 157 (18) Thereis a designatedfunctionalhead thatattractssome constituentbearing [ + focus] (either overtly or covertly). On this view, the interpretationof Supermansentencesrelies on multiple copies of a single [ + focus]. As the reviewerpoints out, this makes the alternativetheory equivalentto the one in (15), except that it assumes an additionaloperationof featurechecking. But this means that the motivationbehind the feature-checkingaccount is lost. Since the constituentmoved to the checking position and the constituentinterpreted as focus need not coincide, there is no longer a one-to-one association between semantic interpretationand position at LF. The traditionalview of checking can be maintainedif Superman in (1) carries three features: [+focus,, +focus2, +focus3]. These would then percolate to different levels: [+focus1] to the DP level, [+ focus2] to the VP level, and [+ focus3] to the sentence level. The crucial question that this approachfaces is how a node can contain multipleidenticalfeatures.Few cases of duplicatefeatures,if any, are attestedelsewhere. For example, there are no wh-wordsthatintroduce two wh-features(forcing a multiple question interpretation).In fact, Neeleman and Van de Koot (2002) arguethat syntactictheory makes it impossible for features in nodes to occur more than once.6 One could argue that the three foci in (1) are differentin nature and hence encoded by differentfeatures.It might be possible to distinguish the IP focus, which is not contrastive,from the DP and VP foci, which are.But thereis no semantic(or pragmatic)reasonto distinguish [+ focus1] and [ + focus2]. The only alternativethat we can see is to distinguish the three focus features on Superman in (1) by claiming that the indices 1, 2, and 3 have syntactic reality. This is what Jacobs (1991) proposes. Indexing of features, however, is an ad hoc device, needed only to deal with multipleembeddedfoci. Second, it is conceptuallyquestionable, since it amounts to assigning features to features. Third, once admitted,it will overgenerate-for instance,it would allow wh-words to carry multiple wh-features.Fourth, indexing of focus features is essentially a means of introducingthe notion of focus set into the feature-basedtheory,because a stressedterminalcan potentiallycarry an arbitrarynumberof focus features that can potentially be copied to any dominatingnode. Even if we allow indexed focus features, there is an additional issue. In Mother'sanswerin (1), why shouldall threefocus featuresbe introducedin the same terminal?In otherwords, how can we exclude a representationin which [+ focus2, + focus3] are generatedon the rightmost terminal, so that the bracketedsentence in (12) could be pragmaticallyequivalent to (1)? As far as we can see, this can only 6 Neeleman and Van de Koot (2002:sec. 5) arguethat duplicatefunctions can be licensed in certaincircumstancesby the constructionof a grid. But the conditions for this are not met here. 158 SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION be achieved if in additionto the assumptionsin (16) and the syntactic indexing of features,an economy conditionlike (11) is adopted.Note that this condition will have to refer to phonological properties of utterances,as (11) does, since there is no reason why a clusteringof identical syntactic features in a single terminal would be preferred over the occurrenceof those featuresin differentterminals. We conclude,then,thatin orderto deal with Supermansentences, the checking theory of focus must make essentially the same assumptions as the stress-basedaccount, and more. References Brody, Michael. 1990. Some remarkson the focus field in Hungarian. In UCL workingpapers in linguistics 2, ed. by John Harris, 201-225. London:UniversityCollege London,Departmentof Phonetics and Linguistics. Brody, Michael. 1995. Focus and checking theory. In Approachesto Hungarian 5, ed. by Istvan Kenesei, 31-43. Szeged: JATE. Chomsky,Noam. 1971. Deep structure,surfacestructureand semantic interpretation.In Semantics:An interdisciplinaryreader, ed. by Danny D. Steinberg and Leon A. Jakobovits, 183-216. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Chomsky,Noam. 1995. TheMinimalistProgram. Cambridge,Mass.: MIT Press. Cinque, Guglielmo. 1993. A null theory of phrasal and compound stress. LinguisticInquiry24:239-267. Horvath,Julia. 1986. Focus in the theoryof grammarand the structure of Hungarian.Dordrecht:Foris. Horvath,Julia. 2000. Interfacesvs. the computationalsystem in the syntax of focus. In Interface strategies, ed. by Hans Bennis andMartinEveraert,183-206. Amsterdam:HollandAcademic Graphics. Jackendoff,Ray. 1972. Semantic interpretationin generative grammar. Cambridge,Mass.: MIT Press. Jacobs, Joachim. 1991. Focus ambiguities. Journal of Semantics 8: 1-36. Kayne,Richard.1998. Overtvs. covert movement.Syntax 1:128-191. E. Kiss, Katalin,ed. 1995. Discourse configurationallanguages. Oxford: Oxford University Press. E. Kiss, Katalin. 1998. Identificationalfocus versus new information focus. Language 74:245-273. Koopman,Hilda, and Anna Szabolcsi. 2000. Verbalcomplexes.Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Krifka,Manfred.1991. A compositionalsemanticsfor multiplefocus constructions.In Proceedingsof Semanticsand LinguisticTheory (SALT)I, ed. by Steven Moore and Adam ZacharyWyner, 127-158. Cornell Working Papers in Linguistics 10. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University, CLC Publications. SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION 159 Laka, Itziar. 1990. Negation in syntax. Doctoral dissertation,MIT, Cambridge,Mass. Neeleman, Ad, and Tanya Reinhart. 1998. Scramblingand the PFinterface.In Theprojection of arguments:Lexical and compositional factors, ed. by Miriam Butt and Wilhelm Geuder, 309-353. Stanford,Calif.: CSLI Publications. Neeleman, Ad, and Hans van de Koot. 2002. The configurationalmatrix. LinguisticInquiry33:529-574. Reinhart,Tanya. 1995. Interfacestrategies.Ms., UtrechtUniversity. Rizzi, Luigi. 1996. Residual verb second and the Wh Criterion.In Parametersandfunctional heads, ed. by AdrianaBelletti and Luigi Rizzi, 63-90. Oxford:Oxford University Press. Rizzi, Luigi. 1997. The fine structureof the left periphery.In Elements of grammar:Handbook of generative syntax, ed. by Liliane Haegeman, 281-337. Dordrecht:Kluwer. Samek-Lodovici, Vieri. 2002. Prosody-syntax interaction in the expression of focus. Ms., University College London. Schwarzschild, Roger. 1999. GIVENness, AvoidF and other constraintson the placementof accent.Natural LanguageSemantics 7:141-177. Szendroi,Kriszta.2003. A stress-basedapproachto the syntaxof Hungarianfocus. The LinguisticReview 20:37-78. Williams,Edwin. 1997. Blocking andanaphora.LinguisticInquiry28: 577-628. Zubizarreta,MariaLuisa. 1998. Prosody,focus, and wordorder.Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Zubizarreta,Maria Luisa, and Jean-RogerVergnaud. 2000. Phrasal stress and syntax. Ms., University of SouthernCalifornia,Los Angeles. FIRST AND SECOND PERSON PRONOUNS AS BOUND VARIABLES Hotze Rullmann Universityof Calgary Dechaine and Wiltschko (2002) argue that, in English, 1st and 2nd personpronounsbelong to a differentsyntacticcategorythan3rd person pronouns.One of their main argumentsis the claim that English 1st and 2nd personpronounscannotbe used as boundvariables,unlike 3rdpersonpronouns.1In this squib,I discuss datashowing thatEnglish 1st and2nd personpronounsactuallydo allow boundvariableinterpre- This researchhas been supportedby SSHRCgrant410-2001-1545.1 would like to thankElizabethRitterand MarthaMcGinnis as well as two anonymous reviewers for their detailed comments on earlier drafts. 1 Dechaine and Wiltschko propose a new and very interestingtypology of pronouns supportedwith observations from a wide variety of languages, arguingthat pronounsfall into three differentcategories:pro-DP, pro-+P, and pro-NP. They claim that in English, 1st and 2nd person pronouns are proDPs, whereas 3rd person pronounsare pro-4Ps (see Ritter 1995 for a similar proposal),and since-according to them-DPs are R-expressions,English 1st and 2nd person pronounscannot function as bound variables.