JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 1 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 Educational Philosophy and Theory, 2011 doi: 10.1111/j.1469-5812.2010.00748.x 1 2 Dialogue in the Shadow of Ideologies 3 T K 4 Professor Emeritus of Education, Simon Fraser University 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 A large part of my work in Philosophy of Education has been influenced by important events and significant experiences in my life.There was a time when I thought this a fault, but now I think that it is the right way to approach philosophical problems in education. Personal experiences are important and genuine rather than remote and abstract. ‘What is the use of studying philosophy’, said Wittgenstein to his friend and disciple Norman Malcolm, ‘if all that it does for you is to enable you to talk with some plausibility about some abstruse questions of logic, etc., and if it does not improve your thinking about the important questions of everyday life?’. It still puzzles me as to why philosophers have spent so much time trying to make Descartes’ irrational doubts legitimate and consequential. If you doubt that you and the world exist, says Wittgenstein, we don’t think you are making a mistake but consider you ready for an insane asylum! In what way has humanity been illuminated and enriched by focusing on such absurd ideas? While working on my book Education as Dialogue: Its prerequisites and its enemies I was reminded once again of R. M. Hare’s claim that the important issues in Ethics arise from the question, ‘how shall we bring up our children?’ That, I think, is also the fundamental question in all education; it requires, of course, that we examine not only the appropriate content and methods for bringing up children but also the necessary social, political and economic conditions that must prevail in our world, as well as a proper vision of a life worth living. Because of my bitter experiences during WW II (the Germans killed my father and the communists my brother) and of my early life within the Greek Orthodox church, I became convinced quite soon that one of the most important enemies of education and of a civilized society is the continuing systematic indoctrination of the young into arbitrary doctrines and dangerous ideologies. The last time I went to ‘confession’ I asked the always-smiling priest to explain to me why there was so much natural and man-made evil in the world if our Creator was all-powerful and good. All of a sudden that phoney smile disappeared from his face, he frowned, raised his voice and said: ‘That my son is the question the devil put in your mind and you have to get rid of it’. I was stunned! Instead of an explanation and rational dialogue I got an insulting retort: How could I be such a stupid sinner as to let the devil put such inappropriate questions in my mind! I walked out of the room realizing what I always suspected—that the priesthood was interested above all in controlling our lives; later I concluded that they were actually working towards establishing an illiberal theocratic state. © 2011 The Author Educational Philosophy and Theory © 2011 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia Published by Blackwell Publishing, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 2 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 2 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 Tasos Kazepides While I was in Greece in my twenties I used to write a weekly column in the local newspaper criticizing the clergy and the public authorities for their behaviour. I had not realized that by so doing I was actually helping them; what I was providing was internal criticism which, however, did not examine the underlying foundations of their beliefs and actions. I did not have the necessary philosophical equipment to address the larger and deeper issues of indoctrination, propaganda and other forms of control. After my arrival in the United States I became fascinated by philosophy and abandoned psychology, for which I had received my scholarship, and studied philosophy of education instead; I felt that philosophy was an enlightening, enriching and enabling discipline. Among my many essays against indoctrination there was an early one (1979) written in Greek and published in Greece criticizing the Greek constitution for sanctioning indoctrination of the young within the public schools. The result was an uproar from within church circles and extreme right wing groups; the public prosecutor in Athens charged me for ‘insulting the Greek Orthodox religion’ and I was ordered to appear in court in May 1980.The Greek church and all its fanatical adherents wrote more than one hundred articles or letters in their papers accusing me of being an atheist trying ‘to undermine the Greek-Christian foundations of the nation’— only two letters were published in the papers in my defence. My ten-year-old son asked me one day what was happening and I tried to explain to him what the problem was. He became nervous and upset when he heard about the trial and asked what would happen if they found me guilty. I told him that there was a remote chance that I might go to prison for two years, (or be fined?) but I tried to pacify him by saying everything was going to be all right, given the irrationality of the charges and the reaction of my colleagues throughout the English speaking world. When I asked him what he thought I should do he said with determined seriousness: ‘Dad, I think you should go, if it’s for the good’. I hugged him and told him how proud I was of him. I still cannot forget that phrase ‘if it’s for the good’. Michael confirmed my own belief that Lawrence Kohlberg was wrong when he claimed that people of that age are not capable of acting on the basis of fundamental moral principles. My son had the prerequisite virtues and did not need the high-sounding but abstract and anaemic moral principles of Kohlberg and other rationalists. The decision as to what we ought to do, says Aristotle, must always be based on perception of a particular situation where we are guided by our virtues and are required to use our judgement; general abstract rules will not help us. Well, I decided to go to my trial in Athens and defend myself and, above all, ‘the good’. It was one of the most important experiences of my life: the Ministry of foreign affairs received over 500 letters and petitions from colleagues from the English speaking world, including Australia and New Zealand. The SFU senate sent a unanimous motion to the Greek government through the Canadian Ministry of Foreign Affairs protesting the charges against me. Noam Chomsky and other well-known intellectuals wrote a joint letter to the New York Review of Books drawing the attention of its readers to the impending trial. Our colleagues at the University of London convinced one of their representatives in the European Parliament to raise a question on whether a country like Greece that persecutes free speech should be allowed into the European Union! © 2011 The Author Educational Philosophy and Theory © 2011 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 3 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 Dialogue in the Shadow of Ideologies 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 3 That kind of overwhelming response, from colleagues most of whom I had never met, gave me the great feeling that I belonged to an alert, genuine and committed intellectual and moral community ready to defend our civilization from backwardness and barbarism. Eight distinguished lawyers from Athens volunteered their services and the leading newspapers of Athens (even other countries in Europe) all sent their journalists to cover the trial.The trial lasted four days as I managed to persuade the lawyers to prolong it and we turned it into a public seminar on Greek educational policy. Some of the most important intellectuals of the country came as witnesses for me, a few drawing comparisons to Socrates and Galileo, quite heady stuff!! During the trial one of the three judges made a serious blunder by asking me if I considered myself to be a Christian! The presiding judge felt embarrassed and said to me: ‘You don’t have to answer that question’. I thought, however, that this was a great opportunity to put things straight and I proceeded to answer the question. Your honour, I said, if by Christian your colleague means whether I believe in the literal truth of religious doctrines about an after life and about miracles which are present in all fundamentalist religions—the answer is a resounding No. If, however, by that question he means whether I believe in the quiet virtues of justice, benevolence and equality, cooperation, tolerance and respect and caring for my fellow human beings, then all I can say is that I am trying to be a good Christian. And although I am not a theologian, I think I have the support of St. Paul. Then I proceeded to recite the whole of chapter thirteen of his first epistle to the Corinthians about love, which I still remembered by heart. Let me just remind the reader of what he says about miracles: ‘... and though I have all faith, so that I could remove mountains, and have no love, I am nothing’! Some of the people in the audience broke into applause and the judge had to caution them not to. The prosecution witnesses, all theologians, were totally confused and couldn’t believe that this ‘atheist’ could recite a whole chapter from St. Paul’s letter in the original and thus fight them from within their own world. An older priest who was in the crowded chamber approached me during the break with a smile and said: ‘Professor, let me kiss you on the forehead because you are the true Christian and all these theologian prosecution witnesses are primitive and ugly people’. Also, a well-known journalist of the leading liberal newspaper in Athens came and whispered in my ear: ‘Thank you for giving me the headline for tomorrow’s paper’. The headline on the first page of the paper was: ‘Christians of love and theologians of doctrines’. I knew then that we had managed to move a mountain! As I had expected, I was found Not Guilty and then was invited to speak to thousands of people in various Greek cities. My ‘lectures’ turned into true dialogues with the audiences participating in a genuine way.What astonished me was that the overwhelming majority of the people accepted my arguments and the appointed representatives of the Church who came to disturb the meetings were completely silenced by the end of the end of each meeting. As a result of the trial and subsequent events the Ministry of Education revised all the textbooks on religion; the changes were not radical but improved the textbooks considerably. Today religion in public schools is no longer a compulsory subject. Sorry for talking about these personal experiences at length, but they convinced me that we philosophers of education have a highly important mission in our world. The © 2011 The Author Educational Philosophy and Theory © 2011 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 4 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 4 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 Tasos Kazepides fundamental problems in education and in our public world are not abstruse, abstract or hidden: they are ordinary and open to view. All they require is clarity of thought, appropriate knowledge and methods for resolving them and above all, all the human virtues and excellences that characterize genuine dialogue and a civilized way of life. After writing my most recent essay on ‘Indoctrination, Doctrines and the Foundations of Rationality’ I saw more clearly what was the antidote to indoctrination, control and propaganda, namely genuine dialogue. I wrote a short book in Greek on the importance of dialogue because it is almost totally absent from the educational institutions and their public life; they have what one could call public duologues rather than dialogue. While I was working on that book it became clear to me that the most appropriate way to approach education is to see it as genuine dialogue. ‘Education as Dialogue’ is both an introduction to Philosophy of Education and a contribution to the field from a particular perspective; the reader will see the significant influence of Wittgenstein’s later work on my thinking. Unlike other introductions the book constitutes one extended argument that invites the reader to see education as dialogue and to appreciate dialogue’s intrinsic value. What surprised me when I examined the literature on dialogue was that there was no serious in-depth study of dialogue in the philosophical literature. I think the most profound relevant idea is still Plato’s view on the dialogical view of all our thinking as expressed in the Sophist and the Theaetetus. And since we are not born with that capacity we must develop it as we grow up within a human community; the quality of our dialogical thinking then must depend to a large extent on the quality of dialogue that prevails in our society. There are occasional references to dialogue in more recent works by Gadamer, Habermas, Freire, Taylor and others, but they are usually casual, too general and vague and of little use for educators. Above all, none of these authors examines the prerequisites of dialogue which, as I argue extensively in my book, are the necessary foundations of genuine dialogue and education; and they require different methods for teaching them than propositional learning. Any discussion of dialogue and education that does not examine their prerequisites is seriously lacking and of little importance for educators. I also realized that all of us in Philosophy of Education are better equipped than other intellectuals to examine these prerequisites, appreciate their importance and suggest the most appropriate ways of establishing them in the young. In order to identify the proper prerequisites, however, we must first reach an agreement on the meaning and dimensions of our concept of education; we cannot talk about the prerequisites of education if we have no clear idea what education is about. It is truly frustrating that after half a century of intense discussions on that concept we still hear people talking about ‘the aims of education’, ‘the process of education’ or ‘the process of thinking and understanding’. Equally primitive and obfuscating is the pseudoscientific definition of education as ‘the systematic socialization of the young’, which ignores or obliterates the criteria of education and as a result cannot distinguish it from indoctrination and other forms of miseducation. It was also astonishing to me that the standard discussions of the concept of teaching focused almost exclusively on the intellectual acts of teaching, thus ignoring their © 2011 The Author Educational Philosophy and Theory © 2011 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 5 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 Dialogue in the Shadow of Ideologies 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 5 indispensable prerequisites, which, as I argue in the book, can be established mainly by authentic living exemplars. As a result of this exclusive emphasis the predominant method of teaching in public schools has been embarrassingly monological, didactic and usually authoritarian. If however, as I tried to show in my book, dialogue is one of the most central concepts, if not the most important one, in educational and political theory, then we have to reconsider our whole way of thinking about the way we teach, organize our schools and above all the way we select and prepare future teachers. If the prospective teachers cannot be good examples of human excellence they should not be allowed to enter the profession, no matter what their grade point average is. Thus, the first part of the book could be described as therapeutic and preparatory for the important discussion that follows on the prerequisites of education and dialogue, and their enemies in the second part. In the second part I examine past attempts that consider the important habits, beliefs, attitudes, etc., which must be established before the young develop the ability to think rationally; unfortunately, this work was not very helpful. It was a pivotal sentence in Wittgenstein’s Zettel that started me thinking seriously about the prerequisites of education and dialogue. The riverbed beliefs that form our system of verification, says Wittgenstein, ‘is something that a human being acquires by means of observation and instruction. I intentionally do not say “earns” ’ (#279). When I examined those ‘riverbed beliefs’ (which we ‘acquire’) in a more systematic way I discovered that they involved a surprisingly large number of human certainties including common certainties, such as that I have two parents or that the world exists, but also all the language games, the principles of logic that are inherent in language, the intellectual excellences and even the moral virtues (which, as I argue, are akin to ordinary certainties). The study of these prerequisites that lie at the foundation of all education and dialogue I discuss in chapter five in considerable detail; I consider that to be the most original and important part of the book. Two important points struck me as I was trying to sort out the character of the various prerequisites of dialogue.The first was that those prerequisites of dialogue were identical with the prerequisites of education. And the second point was that the intrinsic value of both education and dialogue becomes even more obvious and convincing as one examines the character of genuine dialogue; the reason is that the prerequisite intellectual and moral virtues that underlie all our intellectual acts must be part of the character of the educated person who engages in genuine dialogue; they are not negotiable or conditional like skills. I finally understood the depth of Heraclitus’ saying that a person’s character is his or her demon! In the next two chapters I discuss the enemies of dialogue, beginning with indoctrination. I examine the various criteria that have been proposed in the literature and conclude that the correct criterion of indoctrination is the doctrinal content—the criteria of intention and method being logically parasitic on content. This enables us to see precisely the nature of doctrines, because they are neither knowledge claims nor some kind of prerequisites of reason; unlike the prerequisites they do not enable us to think but disable us or limit rational thought. They are arbitrary stoppers that aim at controlling people’s thought and behaviour. Without literal doctrines there cannot be infallible © 2011 The Author Educational Philosophy and Theory © 2011 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 6 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 6 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 Tasos Kazepides popes, arbitrary and authoritarian hierarchies, sinners and salvation and all the rest that Wittgenstein refers to as ‘froth’. Fundamentalist religions have us all born with original sin; the more sinful they make us feel the greater their power in controlling us, since they are the privileged representatives of their respective deities. The only hope is that people will gradually begin to interpret all religious doctrines metaphorically and thus render them harmless and allow people to live in freedom, pluralism and responsibility and with the wonderful sense of wonder that keeps us open-minded. Although, in general, religious people try to live virtuous lives none of their human virtues (or vices) has its origin in any of the present religions.This should not surprise us because virtues have not been created by prophets or saviours but have their origin in our nature and the fact that we are social animals. The claim that Christianity is superior to other religions because it preaches love is false for two reasons; most religions talk about love and all of them are wrong because love in not a virtue but an emotion—unless they are offering a stimulative definition of ‘love’ and use it as an umbrella term that embraces all the quiet virtues, such as charity, benevolence, caring and the rest. The enemies of dialogue are countless. There are first all the defects in our mind and character: ignorance, lack of discipline and respect for others, selfishness and greed, racism and dogmatism and all the other human vices. As I have suggested earlier virtues are not like special skills or abilities that we can use if and when we need them. They are unconditional and categorical commitments that constitute our real self; we cannot abandon or neglect them at will without betraying our humanity. It is widely accepted that we call depraved, inhuman or even monsters only those who perform morally appalling and repugnant acts, not those who don’t know their way in the world of mathematics or nuclear science. The social and economic conditions prevalent in our world today are also serious impediments to genuine dialogue. Ruthless competition and exploitation, inequality, poverty, fear, violence, uncertainty and incessant wars make genuine dialogue extremely difficult in our world today. It is unrealistic to expect educational institutions alone to create the dialogical world. We need gradual changes in all aspects of our lives; what I want to emphasize is that if we want to achieve our goal we must put greater emphasis on dialogue in our homes, our educational institutions and our social life so that the foundations of dialogue are relatively secure. The task is enormous. Finally, we must humanize our religious institutions and free ourselves of all parochial religious codes of conduct that distort our moral code and divide the world. The preaching of religious doctrines very often violates our moral code or distorts it. Consider, for example, the Sermon on the Mount that deprives moral acts of their intrinsic value by linking them to non-moral objectives, i.e. if we want to see or please God, or because this is the only way we can inherit paradise. At best, then, fundamentalist religions distort the autonomous intrinsic character of our moral code by reducing it to a mere instrument, and at worst they violate it. In the last chapter of the book I return to Plato’s seminal idea that our thinking is dialogical. Since we are not born with that capacity but acquire it, it follows that our human nature is not a natural given but a human achievement that can be developed within a genuinely dialogical society; we are born, as it were, at the threshold of our humanity but not at our destination.We have all the empirical evidence that supports that © 2011 The Author Educational Philosophy and Theory © 2011 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 7 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 Dialogue in the Shadow of Ideologies 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 7 claim. Children who have been found surviving in the wild with or without other animals had no human characteristics and, beyond a certain age, were totally uneducable; they did not have a chance to acquire the prerequisites for further human development. I classify all statements about human nature into four categories and examine closely the category of programmatic statements which are religious, political or educational, in order to show the hidden purposes behind such definitions. These purposes vary as we go from Plato to St. Paul and Augustine who were interested in controlling people’s behaviour, to Rousseau who tried to liberate us from such negative preconceptions of human nature. I show how Sartre’s and Oakeshott’s claims, that there is no human nature, prove exactly the opposite, namely, that there are many universal truths about human beings. I conclude this chapter enumerating the numerous universal truths about human nature and development. I close by reiterating and supporting Democritus’ view that ‘nature and teaching are similar, for teaching transforms men, and as it transforms them, it creates nature’. The conclusion of the book is that the concept of human nature is, like our concept of education, vague and open-ended; neither of them can be a specific objective that can be reached but an ideal that can only be approximated. © 2011 The Author Educational Philosophy and Theory © 2011 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 8 SESS: 17 OUTPUT: Thu Dec 30 18:31:04 2010 /v2503/blackwell/journals/epat_v0_i0/epat_748 Journal Code: EPAT Article No: 748 Page Extent: 7 Toppan Best-set Premedia Limited Proofreader: Elsie Delivery date: 30 December 2010