1 Rescuing Basic Equality “We hold these Truths to be self-evident, that all Men are created equal” – Thomas Jefferson. “All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. They are endowed with reason and conscience and should act towards one another in a spirit of brotherhood” – Article 1 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. 1. Introduction Some papers on the basis of equality begin with inspirational quotes, such as those above, in order to emphasise the importance of the issue. We begin with these quotes in order to emphasise its vagueness. But despite its vagueness, as the quotes suggest (and notwithstanding the gender exclusive language), the belief that persons are equal is central to our contemporary political and legal culture. Politicians appropriate the rhetoric of equality for strategic purposes, attesting to its cache with electorates in liberal democracies, and the concept underpins some of the most important legal developments in the 20th century, such as the emergence of an international human rights culture. It is also foundational to much normative philosophy, with many theories championing some set of rights or entitlements possessed equally by all citizens or all human beings. Philosophical debate has focused on what moral property or consideration grounds the equality of persons. John Rawls provides one influential view. He claims that equality is grounded in the possession of two moral powers: the capacity for a sense of justice (the first moral power) and the capacity to form, revise, and pursue a conception of the good (the second moral power).1 Whilst individuals presumably have varying capacities with respect to both moral powers, only a minimum is required for an individual to have entitlements grounded in equality. In other words, Rawls relies on a range property. A range property is a binary property that one possesses in virtue of having a scalar property or set of scalar properties that fall within a specified range.2 Only those who possess the John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, Erin Kelly (ed.), (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), 19. 2 See Ian Carter, ‘Respect and the Basis of Equality’, Ethics, 121 (2011), 538-71, 548. 1 2 two moral powers fall within the required range, regardless of variations above or below this threshold. Although the underlying properties on which the range property depends are scalar, the range property itself is binary since individuals possessing the relevant scalar properties either will or will not fall within the specified range. As with all philosophical debates, the literature on equality is riddled with disagreement. But surprisingly there is one conclusion that has achieved near consensus: that Rawls was wrong. Indeed, Richard Arneson concludes that views relying on range properties are not even ‘remotely credible’.3 This consensus crystallises around three objections, each of which is often taken to be fatal. The first objection is that the threshold at which the possession of the relevant scalar properties places an individual within the range that qualifies her for equality is arbitrary. This is the Arbitrariness Objection.4 The second objection is that there is rational pressure to acknowledge that the scalar properties on which the range property depends are also relevant. In other words, it is unclear why variations in individuals’ moral powers both above and below the threshold do not undermine the relation of equality. This is the Variations Objection.5 The third is that Rawls’ view has unpalatable, perhaps even offensive, implications for our treatment of humans who do not possess both moral powers, such as children or adults with severe cognitive disabilities. This is the No Rational Agency Objection.6 These objections are forceful in so far as Rawls neither offers arguments in favour of his view nor anticipates and responds to these objections. His view is laid out briefly and is rightly criticised as under-motivated. Nevertheless, the three objections are not as compelling as they first appear and our aim is to rescue Rawls’ account from the popular view that it is irretrievably misguided in its attempt to justify equality. We hope not only to cast doubt on the objections but also to develop a more substantive positive argument for Rawls’ conclusions than Rawls himself offered. Whilst defending the Rawlsian view, therefore, we also recognise the need for a deeper analysis of the two moral powers and the role they play in his account of equality. Richard Arneson, ‘Basic Equality: Neither Acceptable nor Rejectable’, in Uwe Steinhoff (ed.), Do All Persons Have Equal Moral Worth? On “Basic Equality” and Equal Concern and Respect (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), 30-52, 36. 4 Arneson, ‘Basic Equality’, 36-7. 5 Carter, ‘Respect and the Basis of Equality’, 549-50; George Sher, ‘Why We Are Moral Equals’, in Steinhoff (ed.), Do All Persons Have Equal Moral Worth?, 17-29, 19; and Arneson, ‘Basic Equality’, 36-7. 6 Jeff McMahan, ‘Challenges to Human Equality’, Journal of Ethics, 12 (2008), 81-104. 3 3 One complication with this task is that the precise meaning of the assertion of equality is unclear. We can parse this claim in a number of ways: all persons are equally valuable from an impartial perspective; all persons possess the same set of rights; all persons are due equal treatment of some form, and so on.7 A number of philosophers have distinguished between substantive and formal equality.8 Substantive equality entails a commitment to equal claims to goods or resources of the kind endorsed by egalitarians.9 This form of equality is controversial and is rejected by theorists on both sides of the political spectrum.10 We can contrast this with formal equality, according to which all members of a particular group should equally possess some set of rights. This is a more limited requirement since it is silent about the content of the rights that individuals possess equally. Unlike the former, this belief is shared by views across the political spectrum. For example, both Nozickian libertarians and Rawlsian liberals believe that persons share a set of rights, even though they disagree sharply about the content of those rights.11 It is not obvious that Rawls’ view provides a general basis for either substantive or formal equality. His view claims that the two moral powers give rise to a corresponding set of rights and duties that are possessed equally by all individuals who have such powers. We will call the equal possession of these rights and duties basic equality, though we acknowledge that our use of this phrase may differ from others’. As we have defined it, basic equality differs from both formal and substantive equality. It differs from substantive equality because the rights and duties of basic equality may fall short of the full set of egalitarian entitlements. We Throughout the paper, we put aside a related but separate claim regarding the equal wrongness of killing. For discussion of this topic, see Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 233-48. 8 Similar distinctions are drawn by other commentators. See Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Luck Egalitarianism (London: Bloomsbury, 2015), ch. 2; John Rawls, A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 441-2; and Joseph Raz, ‘Principles of Equality’, Mind, 87 (1978), 321-42. 9 Egalitarians disagree about what goods or resources to which people have an equal claim. Some distributive egalitarians focus on resources whilst social egalitarians emphasise equal respect. See Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000); and Elizabeth Anderson, ‘What’s the Point of Equality?’, Ethics, 109 (1999), 287-337 respectively. 10 Critics on the right include libertarians such as Robert Nozick. See his Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974). Critics on the left include prioritarians and sufficientarians. See Derek Parfit, ‘Equality and Priority’, Ratio, 10 (1997), 202-21; and Harry Frankfurt, ‘Equality as a Moral Ideal’, Ethics, 98 (1987), 21-43. 11 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 49-51; and Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 441-9. 7 4 leave open the possibility, favoured by Rawls, that basic equality is consistent with some degree of socio-economic inequality.12 It also differs from formal equality because there are some rights and duties – such as the right against suffering certain kinds of pain and the duty not to inflict it on others – that are not plausibly grounded in the two moral powers. Whilst the equal possession of such rights and duties would be a version of formal equality, it would not fall within the ambit of basic equality, since this refers to the rights and duties grounded in the two moral powers. To put the point another way, basic equality does not entail substantive equality and is not entailed by formal equality. Our aim in this paper is to defend basic equality, by referring to a distinctive set of interests that possession of the two moral powers generates. We call these basic interests. It is the common and equal possession of these interests that justifies basic equality. We defend this view against the Arbitrariness Objection, the Variations Objection, and the No Rational Agency Objection. 2. Basic Equality, Basic Interests, and the Two Moral Powers It is first necessary to examine in greater detail what is importantly and distinctively valuable about the possession of the two moral powers. Let us begin with the second moral power, since this is the most commonly discussed. What is it to have the capacity to form, revise, and pursue a conception of the good and why do we have an interest in it? Generally speaking, conceptions of the good refer to the beliefs and attitudes people hold about what their aims and ends in life ought to be. These conceptions manifest in our career decisions, how we spend our leisure time, what associations we belong to, and so on. They can encompass metaphysical beliefs, since such beliefs often have implications about how we ought to live. For example, Christians who believe in the divinity of Jesus Christ often take this as grounds to follow his teachings. Perhaps the core beliefs that constitute a person’s conception of the good are about values, such as the belief that it is good to live a life of generosity, bravery, patriotism or spirituality. Taken together and over the course of a lifetime, these beliefs form an overall vision of what it is to live well and to live a good life. For Rawls, basic equality is consistent with socio-economic inequality for at least two reasons. First, possession of the two moral powers is not sufficient to ground principles of distributive justice, since those who possess the two moral powers must also satisfy other criteria, such as be participants within a scheme of social cooperation. Second, even when this is the case, the two moral powers may ground principles of distributive justice, such as the difference principles, that themselves permit socio-economic inequality under certain conditions. 12 5 It is worth making a number of clarifications about this analysis in order to preempt the common criticism that it is unduly individualist or rationalistic. First, I may conceive of my good as relative to me or as something that would be good for anyone to pursue. I need not believe that anyone would flourish if they pursued a spiritual life, or I could believe that others can flourish only if they live such a life – both of these attitudes would qualify as part of my conception of the good. Second, my conception of the good can aim at either personal or impersonal value and may be either self or other-regarding. I may think that I ought to dedicate my life to achieving impersonal value, such as the protection of endangered species, or by furthering the interests of others. My beliefs about the good need not strictly relate to my personal good. Finally, my conception of the good need not be fully precise, systematic, or consistent.13 Of course, no one lives their life as if they are building a house: in a stage by stage execution of a comprehensively pre-conceived plan. Our conceptions of the good are constantly evolving, contain many inconsistencies, and are often unfulfilled due to weakness of will or external impediments. What is it, then, to have a capacity to form, revise and pursue a conception of the good? Here is a rough account: The Second Moral Power: An individual has the capacity for a conception of the good if and only if she can form, revise and pursue beliefs about the good on the basis of critical deliberation. According to this definition, an individual must be able to form beliefs about the good, which encompass both beliefs about what one’s good is and how one can pursue it. They need not, however, track objective reasons. Though we do not here commit to an objective account of human flourishing, if such an account is correct, it is possible for a person to have a wrongheaded conception of the good. Here we can make an important distinction between two versions of the second moral power. According to the first, the second moral power is entirely contentindependent. We have an interest in this capacity regardless of the content of our conception of the good – even if, for example, it involves serious wrongdoing. On this view, even a person whose conception of the good aims at harming others has an interest in the second moral power. On the second, our interest in this moral For further discussion see John Rawls, Political Liberalism (Columbia: Columbia University Press, 1996), 13; and Jonathan Quong, Liberalism Without Perfection (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 13-14. 13 6 power depends upon our conception of the good meeting a minimum threshold of moral acceptability. Although we subscribe to a version of the latter view, it is not necessary for us to commit to it here, and we prefer not to alienate those who favour the former view. It is also important that agents form beliefs about the good at least partly on the basis of critical deliberation. Consider two individuals, Costanza and Hwa. Costanza carefully considers multiple options in determining her own good. She seeks out information about a diverse range of mutually exclusive conceptions and extensively compares them. She also reflects upon the value of these various options and the way they might contribute to her good. She makes her choices for the reasons she identifies through this critical process. Her resulting conception of the good is comprehensive and consistent in the sense that it influences a wide range of her beliefs and choices and does not contain any contradictions. She frequently reflects on her choices and occasionally revises them in the light of this. Finally, she has a high degree of self-awareness about the deliberative process in which she engages. Hwa differs from Costanza in all of these respects. He rarely considers his options or their value and has a deeply fragmented and inconsistent set of beliefs about his good. He is also so impulsive that his beliefs about the good often fail to guide his action. Although Costanza represents the ideal deliberator about her conception of the good, Hwa still possesses the relevant capacity. This comparison clarifies that the threshold of critical deliberation we are suggesting is relatively undemanding. Let us now elaborate upon the first moral power, which is the capacity for a sense of justice. We can summarise this power as follows: The First Moral Power: An individual has the capacity for a sense of justice if and only if she can understand, endorse and apply principles of justice. There are three key elements to this definition. First, an individual must be able to understand principles of justice. She must appreciate the concepts that feature in the principles and have some knowledge of how the principles recommend particular actions or institutional arrangements. This is also intended as a minimal requirement. For example, as long as a person is able to draw some link between the principles and their implications, this suffices for understanding the principles, even if they are incorrect in their beliefs about the specific implications of the principles. Second, it is also important that an agent has the capacity to endorse the principles. She must possess a positive and supportive attitude towards them; an agent who is able only grudgingly to conform lacks this capacity. Third, an 7 agent must be able to apply principles of justice. This may involve acting in accordance with them or administering them in relevant institutional settings. Both of these requirements are content-dependent, in that an agent must exercise them in respect of principles of justice falling within an acceptable range. If an agent is able only to endorse and apply overtly oppressive or discriminatory principles, then she lacks the first moral power. It is important to emphasise again that an agent need only have the capacity for a sense of justice, and therefore the requirement is also minimal. On this view, an agent who in fact holds offensive political views may still possess the capacity for a sense of justice – as long as she is able to understand, endorse and apply appropriate principles – and thus also the first moral power. We should make two general observations about the two moral powers at this point, which are important to the ensuing discussion. First, both powers are complex in the sense that they are composed of a cluster of other psychological capacities. For example, the second moral power requires, among other things, memory, rationality and the use of critical faculties. This means that there may be two kinds of indeterminacy regarding the moral powers. First, there may be multiple sets of capacities that are sufficient for one or both of the moral powers. In addition to this, even if we could identify a specific set of necessary capacities, each of these will be scalar, and thus it is possible that different combinations of quantities of these capacities are also sufficient for one or both of the moral powers. The second observation is that second order judgments play an important role in both moral powers. A second order judgment is a belief or attitude towards one’s beliefs or attitudes about the good. For example, suppose that two Christians take very different second order attitudes towards their commitment to Christianity. The first endorses his Christian beliefs and practices as part of a noble and enlightened life. The second views her Christian beliefs and practices as the product of misguided fear and wishes she could be rid of them. Both take very different second order attitudes, but the point is that only those with second order awareness and judgment can either endorse their conception of the good as distinctively theirs or reject it as an unwelcome compulsion.14 Similar claims apply to the first moral power, as an agent must not possess a second order attitude of disapproval towards her own first order adherence of the principles of justice. For example, acting on principles of justice as a result of habituation or indoctrination, For a discussion of the ethical importance of (the capacity for) endorsement, see Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, ch. 6. 14 8 which are rejected by the agent as unwanted compulsions, does not satisfy this requirement. What makes the possession of the two moral powers valuable? And what are the contours of the interests that the powers make possible? Again, let us begin with the second moral power. Part of what makes this capacity valuable is that it facilitates the achievement of one’s good. But this is not what makes it distinctively valuable, since instinctual or acquired behaviours may perform a similar role. It helps therefore to distinguish between having an interest in one’s good and having a basic interest in the capacity to form, revise and pursue a conception of the good. The former interest can be facilitated by a number of abilities, whilst the latter requires the second moral power. One feature that makes the second moral power distinctively valuable is that it enables its possessor to see the decisions, beliefs, and practices that contribute to her good as rationally justifiable. Given that agents critically deliberate about their reasons in order to make decision about their good, and have second order awareness of this process, they can see the outcome as supported by reasons. This is valuable because agents can thereby recognise the pattern of justificatory relationships between practical reasons and decisions about the good. Intuitively, this recognition has distinctive value beyond the mere facilitation of one’s good. To help illustrate this, consider the following example. Maths Problem: Costanza and Hwa are both set a maths problem and both reach the correct answer. Hwa reaches this answer by applying a heuristic that he has memorised but does not understand. Costanza solves the problem by displaying a higher level of understanding. She determines the calculations she must execute and appreciates how those calculations will reach a mathematically valid answer. Although both reach the correct answer, Hwa does so as a product of habituation: he recognises that the heuristic he has learned is applicable in the present case, without understanding why. He is therefore unable to see his answer as justified by appropriate reasons, even though it is correct. Costanza achieves a deeper level of enlightenment about the justificatory relationship between her mathematical reasoning and the correct answer. Moreover, we maintain that this value would not be lost if Costanza’s reasoning were faulty and resulted in an incorrect answer (though we note that there is independent value in arriving at the correct answer). This is because, even when Costanza reaches the wrong answer through an error in her reasoning, she is still able to see her answer as supported by appropriate reasons, even if in the particular case this perception is inaccurate. Similarly, an 9 agent with the capacity critically to evaluate practical reasons regarding her good is able to perceive the pattern of justificatory relationships between practical reasons and decisions about the good, even if some errors result in misguided conclusions. The second reason why the second moral power is valuable has been well described by others and we have little to add: it is valuable to be the author of one’s own life. Of course, different philosophers take this to entail different things. For some, an individual enjoys self-authorship simply when she is not wrongfully coerced. For others, self-authorship is much more demanding – perhaps it requires that she have an adequate range of options from which to pick, and also that others refrain from shaping either her values or the character of the options that are available to her.15 What unites these views is their sympathy for the idea that every individual has a basic interest in determining the goals that she will pursue, and that others can frustrate this interest by treating her in certain ways. This is a widely-shared conviction and is at the heart of liberal political philosophy. Let us now turn to the first moral power. Unlike the second moral power, we must commit to the idea that the first moral power is content-dependent. Having a sense of justice means that views that are in some sense inconsistent with seeing others as free and equal citizens are excluded from consideration. We have a weighty basic interest in responding aptly to the moral demands that others make on us.16 This also partly explains why committing serious wrongs is not in our interest. To see this, consider the following example: Hospital Bed: Hwa wakes up in a hospital bed and is informed that he was involved in an incident of abuse that descended into violence. However, it is unclear whether he was the perpetrator or the victim of this abuse.17 Does Hwa have reason to hope that he was the perpetrator or the victim? It is uncontroversial that Hwa has an interest in not being the victim of abuse. Therefore if he lacked an interest in not being the perpetrator, it would be straightforward that he should hope he is the perpetrator. But this is not obviously true. Would you prefer to be the victim or the perpetrator? What preference would you have for your children? The mere fact that the answer is not straightforward For a defence of a more demanding account of self-authorship, see Ronald Dworkin, Justice for Hedgehogs (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press, 2011) 209-14. 16 T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press, 1998) Ch.5. 17 This is a variation of a case devised by Victor Tadros. 15 10 suggests that Hwa has some basic interest in not possessing seriously wrongful attitudes towards others. It may be tempting to suppose that the answer is not straightforward for other reasons, such as the possibility of facing criminal sanctions. In response, we doubt that many people would be comfortable discovering that they are the perpetrator even without the possibility of punishment. Here we maintain this claim only in respect of seriously wrongful attitudes, and we leave open the possibility that there is no interest in avoiding views that are less wrongful. With respect to basic equality, it may be thought that, whilst the second power is the source of our rights, the first power is the source of our duties to others to secure those rights. We cannot owe duties of justice to others if we lack the capacity for a sense of justice as this violates at least some versions of the ‘ought implies can’ principle. As the above reflections show, however, this division of justificatory labour is simplistic, since we also plausibly have an interest in the first moral power. In fact, there may be another distinctive basic interest in the combination of the two moral powers. Only individuals who possess both are able to establish and participate in a just society, understood as a co-operative enterprise in which free and equal individuals pursue their conceptions of the good on fair terms. The combination of the moral powers enables the co-operative realisation of individual autonomy. It is this co-operative vision of society that allows us sensibly to speak of a liberal community, whilst maintaining the rights of individual autonomy that liberals traditionally support. In this vein, Rawls writes, For whenever there is a shared final end, an end that requires the cooperation of many to achieve it, the good realized is social: it is realized through citizens’ joint activity in mutual dependence on the appropriate actions being taken by others. Thus, establishing and successfully conducting reasonably just (though of course always imperfect) democratic institutions over a long period of time, perhaps gradually reforming them over generations, though not, to be sure, without lapses, is a great social good and appreciated as such. This is shown by the fact that people refer to it as one of the significant achievements of their history.18 Rawls, Political Liberalism, 204. See also Ronald Dworkin, ‘Liberal Community’, California Law Review, 77 (1989), 479-504, 499. 18 11 Of course, there is a great deal more to say about the basic interests grounded in the possession of the two moral powers. But we hope that the four we have briefly described – the interests in seeing one’s decisions about the good as supported by appropriate practical reasons, living a self-authored life, taking morally appropriate attitudes towards others, and establishing and participating in the co-operative realisation of individual autonomy – help to clarify the kind of interests that we think justify basic equality. 3. The Arbitrariness Objection Let us revisit the first objection to the Rawlsian defence of basic equality. This is the worry that the threshold at which the possession of the relevant scalar properties places an individual within the range that grants her basic equality seems arbitrary. Since the underlying properties that comprise the moral powers are scalar, there is no obvious point to place the threshold. If individuals can possess, say, rational agency in greater or lesser quantities, why is the threshold placed just where Rawls say it is? If there is no justification for the favoured position, this raises the suspicion that the threshold is placed simply to meet pre-established conclusions, such as the almost universal belief that human beings fall above the threshold and that non-human animals fall below it. Not only is such an argument circular, since it assumes a particular placement for the threshold in order to ‘show’ that human beings lie above it, it also smacks of speciesism.19 To help evaluate this objection, consider the following example: Prison Orchestra: A prison has the resources to allow its inmates to participate in only one creative activity: the prison orchestra. Some of the inmates permanently lack the capacity to understand music, how the instruments work, or are unable to implement this knowledge by playing them. Of those who do not fall into this group, some are just about competent whilst others are musically excellent. The prison manager can recognise inmates as members of the orchestra and also has the task of allocating limited playing time amongst members. Before we discuss how this case helps us respond to the Arbitrariness Objection, it will be useful to clarify the importance of this example for basic equality. Here are Very roughly, we can follow Peter Singer in defining speciesism as ‘a prejudice or attitude of bias in favour of the interests of members of one’s own species and against those of members of other species’. See his Animal Liberation (New York: Harper, 2009), 6. 19 12 three respects in which Prison Orchestra helps to illuminate basic interests.20 First, the interests in both cases are non-exhaustive, in the sense that they exist alongside other interests. Just as inmates have interests aside from becoming members of the orchestra, so too individuals have interests aside from possession of the two moral powers. Second, although they are non-exhaustive, the interests in both cases are members of a set of the most valuable interests that an individual has. Notwithstanding the differences between various theories of human flourishing, both creative expression and autonomous living feature heavily in most. Third, the interests are distinctive and are connected with a set of opportunities that are uniquely capable of realising them – in other words, these interests are ones that cannot be realised through any alternative means. Taken together, these features of the interests in question are capable of justifying certain rights and, in particular, the rights that we can justify by appeal to a concern for basic equality. In this respect, we can therefore situate our account of basic equality within an interest theory of rights.21 The first decision the prison manager must make is to decide who to recognise as members of the orchestra. Clearly only those inmates who are at least competent musicians can be appointed as members. Though this may seem like a harsh decision based on differences in ability, it is really because those who permanently lack the capacity to understand music or play an instrument do not have an interest in being members and it would not benefit them to be recognised as participants in an activity in which they have no interest. So it is the capacities that the inmates have that determine the position of the threshold. Here it may be objected that those inmates excluded from the orchestra have an interest in acquiring the capacities that would make them eligible for inclusion. We are happy to accept this, but maintain simply that this is a different interest. Having an interest in acquiring some ability may justify allocating resources that We pick this slightly eccentric example because it fits with, and provides the opportunity for us to defend further, Rawls’s own remarks about the way in which members of a wellordered political society – or, in our case, agents who are owed basic equality – are like members of an orchestra. The example embraces the sense in which individual citizens, like members of an orchestra, are pursuing their own ends, but in a way that contributes to a collective activity. In this example, individual players represent citizens pursuing their own good, whilst the ensemble represents the collective realisation of individual autonomy. See Rawls, Political Liberalism, 204. 21 See Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), ch. 7. 20 13 can be utilised to acquire that ability, but it cannot justify allocating resources that can be utilised only by those who already possess the ability.22 Returning to basic equality, we similarly claim that the possession of the two moral powers determines where the threshold lies. The Arbitrariness Objection is too quick to assume that the range property must be arbitrary simply because it attaches to a set of properties that, taken individually, are scalar. The source of the confusion, we suggest, is a failure to appreciate the difference between the complex capacities represented by the moral powers and the underlying properties that constitute them. Though the underlying properties are scalar, possession of the moral powers is not. The question about whether a being possesses the moral powers must, in most cases, be met with one of two answers. On the account that we defend, therefore, we have principled reasons for placing the threshold at a particular level – just as the prison manager has principled reasons to appoint only some inmates as member of the orchestra – as that is the level at which possession of the two moral powers emerges from the underlying capacities. This is not to deny that the threshold is subject to vagueness. Specifically, there may be two forms of vagueness. First, the threshold may be vague in the sense that it is indeterminate. As we describe above, there may be no precise increment at which possession of some scalar property establishes the moral powers. Additionally, there may be multiple sets of underlying capacities that are sufficient to establish the moral powers. Secondly, the threshold may be subject to epistemic vagueness, such that it is difficult or impossible to ascertain whether borderline cases fall above or below the threshold. Do these admissions of vagueness threaten the previous judgment that possession of the moral powers is binary? No. This is because binariness is not itself a binary property. Instead, binariness exists on a spectrum with fully scalar properties at one end and fully binary properties at the other. The kind of binariness that our argument requires is not absolute: it can tolerate a sizable number of cases that cannot be said either to possess or not possess the property. Such cases are indeterminate but do not threaten the discreteness of the two categories in question. This is distinct from the idea that there are continuous gradations between the two categories. Our view permits indeterminate cases but not cases that can be placed on specific gradations between possessing and not possessing the moral powers. There are difficulties in determining how strong such interests are and who possesses them. For a discussion of the standard for assessing fortune for an outline of similar problems, see McMahan, The Ethics of Killing, 145-59. 22 14 Strictly speaking, only a threshold based on the possession of fully scalar properties would be arbitrary. As long as there are some cases falling above and below the threshold, we can identify some criteria for determining where to place the threshold. Of course, if this were true of the possession of the moral powers, the view would be implausible for others reasons, as it would be overwhelmed with indeterminacy. But this is not the case and, when compared with the full range of the scalar properties that constitute the moral powers, the area of indeterminacy is relatively small. To return to the Arbitrariness Objection, conceding that the threshold is vague in one or more of these senses is not to concede that it is arbitrary. We retain criteria by which to judge where the threshold lies, even if their application is sometimes indeterminate and/or difficult. Of course, vagueness carries its own problems, particularly when we face borderline cases that must be classified. But this is a substantially less significant problem than arbitrariness. Whereas arbitrariness is fatal to the entire view since it suggests circularity and lack of justification, vagueness is problematic only for borderline cases. 4. The Variations Objection The second objection is that there is rational pressure to acknowledge that the scalar properties on which the range property depends are also relevant. It will be helpful to distinguish two versions of this objection. One focuses on variations above the threshold and the other on variations below it. It is unclear why variations in individuals’ moral powers both above and below the threshold do not undermine the relation of basic equality. Although we have clarified that the possession of the moral powers is a binary property, albeit one that is subject to vagueness, our ability to exercise these powers well is scalar and varies significantly. Recall the contrast between Costanza, who is able to exercise the second moral power exceptionally, and Hwa, who barely possesses it at all. Though they equally share the property of possessing the powers, they are not equal in terms of how effectively they can operate them. Similarly, compare Costanza* with Hwa*. Costanza* falls just short of the threshold, whilst Hwa* is well below it. Why shouldn’t these differences affect the moral concern to which they are entitled? The Variations Objection challenges us to explain why these differences do not matter. Let us return to Prison Orchestra. Should the prison manager allocate playing time according to musical talent or apportion it equally amongst inmates? All else being equal, we intuitively hold that the manager should allocate playing time equally 15 amongst members, irrespective of variations in musical talent above the threshold. A barely competent musician is entitled to the same amount of playing time as an excellent musician. This means that resources are allocated to inmates on the basis of a range property: those who fall within the range are entitled to certain goods whilst those outside of it are not, and variations within the range do not affect the size of the entitlement. We can contrast this with how we ought to allocate resources in a professional orchestra. Since the overarching aim in the professional orchestra is to foster excellence, it is perhaps appropriate to allocate resources according to ability. But given the unique creative role that the orchestra plays in the inmates’ lives, it would be objectionable for the manager to aim at fostering musical excellence. In other words, she ought to give considerable priority to the interest in exercising musical capacities over the interest in attaining musical excellence. The same kind of reasoning shows how we can respond to the Variations Objection. We explained before why the interest in exercising the moral powers is both weighty and distinct. In these respects, it is analogous to the inmates’ interest in musical expression. Accordingly, we ought similarly to give considerable priority to this basic interest over the interest of a few individuals in exercising their moral powers to a much higher degree. At this point, one may object that this reasoning justifies only the weighted priority of this basic interest rather than absolute priority. Perhaps there are beings capable of such sublime autonomy that their achievement can deprive others of the chance to take part. This would be analogous to a version of Prison Orchestra in which one inmate enjoys almost super-human musical abilities but needs a greater-than-equal share of playing time in order to realise these. In response, we stress that there is no need for us to exclude this theoretical possibility. Our claim is the more pertinent one that no human deliberators in fact meet this condition. For distinct reasons, variations below the threshold also do not threaten our defence of basic equality. In Prison Orchestra, a person who just about lacks the capacity to play music is in one sense equivalent to a person who is nowhere near it: both lack the capacity to participate in a valuable activity. This is not to deny that the first person may enjoy some interests that the second does not, and that these interests are similar to those possessed by individuals above the threshold. For example, some inmates may be able to produce sounds from their instruments, thus achieving some creative output, without engaging in the practice 16 of playing music.23 These individuals have some interest in this creative outlet that those who are completely unable to engage creatively with the instruments lack. We accept, therefore, that variations between the first and second person may be morally relevant, and thus variations below the threshold matter whilst variations above it do not. In this respect, the view we defend is asymmetrical and follows from the fact that there may be important interests that depend on the same underlying capacities as the moral powers below the threshold but not above it. The more modest point is simply that the interest in the creative production of sound is not as distinctively valuable as fully participating in playing music, and we therefore have principled reasons to maintain a specific and important threshold. The plausibility of this analogy depends upon us being able to distinguish between the great value of the activities that are made possible by an agent’s possession of the two moral powers and the much lesser value of activities whose possibility does not depend upon an agent’s possession of the two moral powers. This, of course, was our aim in section 2. Similarly, some have pressed the Variations Objection to basic equality on the grounds that variations in psychological capacities below the threshold seem to make a moral difference.24 Many people believe that a chimpanzee, for instance, has higher moral status than a mouse, and that it would therefore be wrong to perform the kind of experimentation on a chimpanzee that it might be permissible to perform on a mouse. This difference is explicable in terms of the more developed psychological capacities that the chimpanzee possesses. Why, then, should variations above the threshold not make a moral difference when variations below the threshold do? The answer is that there are other complex capacities and corresponding interests (besides the moral powers) that occur below the threshold of basic equality but not above it. One of these is the ability to experience emotional distress, which is possessed by some living things and not others. Those with this capacity are due moral treatment that those without it are not. This is one capacity that may distinguish the mouse from the chimpanzee and explain why certain kinds of experimentation, which tend to cause emotional distress in some animals, cannot permissibly be performed on chimpanzees. We leave open the possibility that there are other morally relevant complex capacities, with corresponding interests, that occur above the threshold. We are unsure what these For obvious reasons, we put aside the conceptual question ‘what is music?’ Our point is just that there is some activity – which we call music – that has distinctively valuable features and that these individuals are not able to engage in, though they are able to engage in an alternative activity that is structurally similar. 24 For a forceful version of this objection, see McMahan, ‘Challenges to Human Equality’, 83. 23 17 may be, but if they exist they do not negate the point that the rights and duties grounded in the moral powers should be equally distributed. 5. The No Rational Agency Objection The third objection to Rawls’ view is that it has unpalatable, perhaps even offensive, implications for our treatment of those humans who do not possess both moral powers, such as children or adults with severe cognitive disabilities. This is the No Rational Agency Objection. Individuals who do not possess the moral powers are not entitled to basic equality, and this seems to be an offensive abandonment and degradation of these members of the human family. It is true that, on our view, the possession of the moral powers grounds the equal possession of a set of rights, and agents who lack the moral powers do not possess these rights. In this sense, they are not equal to those persons who do enjoy these rights. But this is not an offensive implication. There is nothing offensive about the claim that agents do not have rights when those rights are grounded in interests that they lack. It is obviously acceptable that a young child lacks some of the rights, such as the right to vote, enjoyed by adults who possess the two moral powers: this ‘inequality’ is readily justified. Moreover, young children may enjoy a number of rights based on the interests that they do have. Similarly, adult humans who lack the moral powers may also possess an array of rights grounded in their other interests. Consequently, those who do not possess the two moral powers, such as infants, those with severe dementia or congenital disabilities, may be equal to those who do in a variety of other ways. Part of the problem here is the language in which these debates are traditionally couched. The relation of basic equality in popular rhetoric has great import and any denial of it is perceived to legitimate serious wrongdoing and inhumane treatment to the excluded group. To avoid this, one thing philosophy can do is to demystify basic equality. When basic equality is understood as the equal distribution of rights based on a particular interest, it becomes clear that there are many relations of equality, distinct from what we have called basic equality, each obtaining between different but overlapping groups of individuals, depending on who possesses the relevant interest. It is not problematic to deny opportunities and resources to those who have no interest in them, as the example about the right to vote indicates. More difficult cases occur when there are resources that could be based on multiple interests. For example, medical care may be necessary for living an autonomous life, but may also be needed to avoid pain and suffering, or to be included within the human community, and so on. Although a severely cognitively disabled human would have no claim to medical care on the basis of 18 her interest in exercising the moral powers, she may have a claim based on other interests. Our view is therefore consistent with most other attempts to show why such individuals should have access to the same resources as other humans. We do not presume to solve the problem of distinguishing between the moral claims of severely cognitively disabled humans and non-human animals, but it is important to note that our claims are consistent with any such attempt. 6. Conclusion To be written.25 25 For helpful comments, we thank James Christensen and Zoltan Miklosi.