11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 329 AFTERWORD Transcendental Perspectivism: Anonymous Viewpoints from Inner Asia MARTIN HOLBRAAD and RANE WILLERSLEV1 m.holbraad@ucl.ac.uk University College London rane@mail.dk Aarhus University INTRODUCTION After Spinoza, and apropos Buddhist cosmology in Tibet, Da Col asks: What can a body do? In perspectivism this is always the question. Viveiros de Castro proposes it by analogy to the more familiar concern, intuitive to us Western intellectuals: ‘What can a mind do?’ We are accustomed to worrying about our minds because we assume that even if our mental powers are ultimately generated by our brains (bodily parts we have in common with others), it is what we can do with our minds – the ideas we come up with, our way of thinking about things – that makes us different from others (other people, other cultures, or even other species or spirits). Perspectivism inverts this assumption, as Viveiros de Castro writes for Amerindians: The ability to adopt a point of view is undoubtedly a power of the soul, and nonhumans are subjects in so far as they have (or are) spirit; but the differences between viewpoints (and a viewpoint is nothing if not a difference) lie not in the soul. Since the soul is formally identical in all species, it can only see the same things everywhere – the difference is given in the specificities of bodies. (Viveiros de Castro 1998: 478) Of course comparisons between Amerindian perspectivism and Western intellectualism are not at all alien to Viveiros de Castro’s theoretical aspirations (e.g. see Viveiros de Castro 2003). While establishing an ethnographic argument about the ontological premises of Amerindian cosmology, the theory of perspectivism is also meant to suggest that such premises can substitute ordinary assumptions about what theory itself might be, what it might do, and how. A theory of Amerindian perspectivism, then, is meant also to suggest a perspectivist theory. But if Viveiros de Castro’s theory is itself perspectivist, we argue, it must be so just because it is ‘Amerindian’. For one ordinary assumption regarding anthropological ‘theory’ (from Greek theoria, the perspective of ‘contemplation’ – Inner Asia 9 (2007): 329–345 © 2007 Global Oriental Ltd 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 330 4/12/07 15:32 Page 330 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV Taylor 1982: 89) is that it is an essentially intellectual artefact: theory is born of the anthropologists’ mental effort, albeit one that is constrained by the ethnographic material with reference to which the theory is conceived. In this view, the possibility that a theory might transcend the ethnographic particulars to which it may have originally referred testifies to its robustness as an intellectual artefact. So ‘cross-cultural comparison’ becomes a matter of testing the possible applications of a theory on different ethnographic materials – ‘What can a theory do?’ On a perspectivist premise, however, the possibility of theory transcending ethnographies to which it might refer, and therefore compare, is not open. Just as in Amazonia, a single cross-species perspective is rendered impossible by the differences between species’ bodies – ‘bundle[s] of affects and capacities …which [are] the origin of perspectives’ (Viveiros de Castro 1998: 478) – so in anthropology comparisons oriented towards establishing a transcendent crosscultural theoretical perspective are barred by the unique specificities of ethnographic cases. In other words, in perspectivist anthropology, ethnography is to theory what in Amerindian perspectivism bodies are to perspectives. This is a ‘hyper-empiricist’ anthropology, if you like, in that ethnographic materials do not provide just ‘evidence’ that may constrain its theorems, but rather constitute the very ground from which such theorems originate as intellectual extrapolations (Holbraad forthcoming, cf. Jackson 1989). In such a view, the virtue of crosscultural comparison lies not in testing the robustness of a theory, but rather in showing how it can be, precisely, ‘stretched’ – rendering a theory vulnerable to ethnographic differences with a view to transforming it. What, then, can ethnography do? More specifically, in the case of this volume, what can Inner Asian ethnographies do to Amerindian perspectivism? Drawing on the preceding articles, our aim in this Afterword is to show that Inner Asian materials suggest a theoretical elaboration of perspectivism that remained unanticipated in Viveiros de Castro’s Amerindian theorisation. In particular, we argue that if one may talk of ‘Inner Asian perspectivism’ – and we consider that the present collection amply demonstrates that one can – then one must talk of a perspectivism that incorporates a notion of ‘transcendence’. We suggest, in other words, that Inner Asian ethnographies of perspectivist phenomena must qualify the ‘immanentist’ premise of Viveiros de Castro’s model. For him, exchanges of perspectives between different kinds of beings are conceived in thoroughly ‘horizontal’, or symmetrical, terms. Each being has the potential to transform into every other because all beings (or at least all the cosmologically significant species that enter into this perspectivist game) contain each other’s perspectives immanently. Beings can ‘become-other’, in Viveiros de Castro’s Deleuzian terminology, because in a crucial sense they already ‘are other’: they are constituted as beings by their very potential to become something else. By contrast, as the articles in this collection suggest, in Inner Asia changes of perspective frequently take place in ways that are best described as ‘vertical’ (sensu Hugh-Jones 1996; cf. Holbraad 2007). Here, beings’ capacity to transform themselves is conceived in irreducibly restrictive terms inasmuch as their relation- 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 331 AFTERWORD 331 ships to others are deemed to be inherently asymmetrical. For example, as Pedersen showed in his pioneering attempt to transposeAmerindian perspectivism to the North Asian region (2001), in Mongolia, perspectivist transformations are typically restricted to shamans (e.g. hunters’ perspectival exchange with prey is deemed to be a ‘contamination’and is to be avoided at all cost). Furthermore, such transformations are often conceived in terms of the shaman’s ability to embody the perspective of an ancestral spirit and, given the patrilinial kinship ideology prevalent in the region, this implies a vertical ‘ascent’ that approximates the hierarchically superior position of an ‘elder’ (cf. Humphrey 1996). In such cases, we argue, changes of perspective cannot only be a matter of actualising a potential that already exists immanently within all beings, since beings are asymmetrically circumscribed in terms of their relative lack of precisely such a potential. Rather, beings’ perspectivist transformations must also involve the capacity to occupy perspectives that are transcendent to them. So, subverting Viveiros de Castro’s Amerindian formula, we might say that in Inner Asia beings can ‘become-other’ not because they are themselves already ‘other’, but rather because the perspectives that they can occupy in a crucial sense remain other to them, i.e. they are constituted as what we call ‘transcendent perspectives’. Now, we are aware that such an inversion of Amerindian perspectivism may appear untenable or even contradictory. If, as we want to argue, hierarchical or otherwise asymmetrical relationships between beings render their respective perspectives ‘transcendent’ to one another, then is this not a way of saying by fiat that perspectival transformations – shifts from one ‘transcendent’ perspective to another – are in fact impossible? How can any being occupy a transcendent perspective if what is meant by ‘transcendent’ is precisely a perspective that cannot be occupied by that being? How, in other words, can perspectivism and transcendence be rendered compatible if, as it would seem, one is defined in terms of the absence of the other? In such a view, the attempt to ‘stretch’ perspectivism with reference to Inner Asian emphases on verticality (hierarchy, asymmetry and so on) seems a stretch too far. Indeed, we would argue that precisely this assumption, that the dilemma between perspectivist transformation and transcendence is insoluble, is present in a number of the contributions to this volume. For example, both Kristensen and Swancutt, in ethnographic analyses that are otherwise highly suggestive as we shall see, articulate Mongolian incarnations of perspectivist transformation in opposition to ‘the somewhat more rigid hierarchical order and social values of … everyday life’ (Kristensen this volume), so that perspectival changes become a matter of ‘levelling out of “differences” between subjects’ (Swancutt this volume). In doing so, they both follow Pedersen’s tendency in the aforementioned article to predicate perspectivism and transcendence upon two contrasting ‘social ontologies’, namely what he calls ‘animism’, articulated as a continuous universe in which different beings relate to one another on a principle of ‘analogous identification’, and ‘totemism’, presented as a discontinuous ‘grid’ that places beings in relationships of ‘homologous differentiation’ (Pedersen 2001). 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 332 4/12/07 15:32 Page 332 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV In fact, while Pedersen’s contribution to the present volume can be seen as a consummate attempt to overcome the dualism of his earlier account, his analysis tends to uphold the idea that perspectivist transformations and transcendence are ultimately irreconcilable. Expressing reservations about the ‘virtualist’ premise of Viveiros de Castro’s perspectivist model (see also below), Pedersen seeks to formulate a Mongolian version of perspectivism that springs from a cosmology in which different beings exist in splendid isolation from one another, separated by intervals of unmarked ‘void’ – an image that recalls the grid-metaphor of his earlier article. In such a universe perspectivism ought not to be construed as a matter of‘becoming’ at all, he argues, but rather as one of ‘abrupt’ or ‘intervalic’ perspectival exchanges involving ‘leaps from one discrete form of being to another, equally discrete form of being’ (this volume). Compelling as it may be as a highly original position in the anthropological debate about perspectivism, this suggestion arguably amounts to an assertion of a particularly strong version of what we are calling ‘transcendence’, and does so unapologetically at the expense of the very idea of transformation. On Pedersen’s view, different beings’ perspectives are not just ‘beyond’ each other, but rather exist in ‘parallel universes’ – a stance that seems confluent with Højer’s analysis in this volume of how in their economic transactions contemporary Mongols often seek to avoid exchanging perspectives with others altogether. While it is beyond our ethnographic expertise to determine the extent of such ‘isolationist’ tendencies in Inner Asian cosmologies (islands of being existing ‘indifferently’to each other, to use Højer’s expression), we would point out that other contributions to this volume, including Mongolist ones, suggest that perspectivist transformations in the Inner Asian region often do take place within a framework of perspectives that, while transcendent to each other, are nevertheless deemed to be related in determinate ways – e.g. in terms of social and cosmological hierarchies (Kristensen, Swancutt), kinship positions (Empson & Delaplace), concepts of ownership (Broz), degrees of pollution (Da Col) and so forth. In fact we would suggest that by excluding such relationships, Pedersen’s model falls short of presenting a complete theorisation not only of perspectivist transformation as such, which it denies, but also, paradoxically, of the ‘isolationist’ image of transcendence (or ‘parallelism’) it affirms. The central idea that on the isolationist equivalent of transformation beings’ perspectival ‘jumps’ involve ‘piecing together (as opposed to merging into one hybrid mixture) two radically different points of view’ (Pedersen this volume) is ambiguous. If different viewpoints can be ‘pieced together’ then how exactly are they ‘different’? In other words, if the radical transcendence of each perspective can be overcome in a ‘jump’, then in what sense are perspectives transcendent at all? We are left, it seems, with the antinomy of perspectivism versus transcendence. The aim of this Afterword is to offer a solution to this general problem. If perspectivism and transcendence appear contradictory, then what is required, we suggest, is an analytical frame that modifies the premises of both in such a way as to remove the contradiction. The key idea here is that there is a coherent analyt- 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 333 AFTERWORD 333 ical story to be told – one which accommodates perspectivism and transcendence within a single analytical frame – if one bites the bullet of the apparent contradiction between perspectivism and transcendence, by redefining each in terms of the other or, in other words, by rendering them mutually constitutive. In this view, perspectivism turns not on the ability of each being to contain all others’ perspectives within it as immanent possibilities (as in Viveiros de Castro’s model), but rather on its ability to contain them all as what we call a ‘transcendental’ impossibility. Each perspective, in other words, is indeed constituted by its relations to all other perspectives, and in this sense ‘contains’ them, as the Amerindian model has it. However, as we propose to show, what makes these relations transcendent rather than immanent is precisely the fact that they are contained by each perspective as a totality. If each perspective is constituted in relation to ‘all possible perspectives’, as perspectivism requires, then, we argue, it is constituted in relation to an impossibility, since the view from all possible perspectives – the transcendental ‘view from everywhere’, as we call it – is not one that can possibly be occupied. So we define perspectivism in essentially ‘negative’ terms: each perspective is constituted in relation to (and thus contains) an impossible ‘view from everywhere’. Conversely, we define transcendence ‘positively’. The irreducibly ‘impossible’ element that renders each perspective transcendent is not to be understood in terms of some ‘lack’, as habitual ways of thinking about transcendence might have it, but rather in terms of an ‘excessive presence’, if you like. What makes perspectives transcendent is that they contain within themselves too many, rather than too few, viewpoints – the ‘view from everywhere’ rather than the perhaps more familiar ‘view from nowhere’. In what follows, we begin by exploring the implications of this ‘having-thecake-and-eating-it’ logic (negative immanence, positive transcendence) with reference to Merleau-Ponty’s late writings on perception – thoughts published posthumously (1968), and reconstructed by the philosophical commentator Sean Dorrance Kelly (2005). As we hope to show, the analytical frame we elaborate is able to illuminate three related ethnographic conundrums posed by the contributions to this volume. First, the fact that spirits are never deemed to be seen as such, but rather invariably appear as distorted or otherwise anomalous bodies. Second, that in Inner Asia perspectivist transformations typically take on an asymmetrical character, as already mentioned. Finally, that perspectival transformations in this region often occur in an explicitly ‘temporal’ dimension. Spirits and the view from everywhere Merleau-Ponty’s theory of perception proposes a radical break with our intuitive, commonsense understanding of vision as located where our eyes are. In a literal sense, our commonsense assumption is egocentric: the world is centred upon the perceiver. However, according to Merleau-Ponty, such subject-centred notion of vision is actually misleading: 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 334 4/12/07 15:32 Page 334 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV When I look at the lamp on my table, I attribute to it not only the qualities visible from where I am, but also those which the chimney, the walls, the table can ‘see’; the back of my lamp is nothing other than the face which it ‘shows’ to the chimney. I can therefore see an object insofar as objects form a system or a world and insofar as each of them treats the objects around it like spectators of its hidden aspects and a guarantee of its permanence (Merleau-Ponty 2002 [1945]: 79) Let us explain this somewhat cryptic passage, which pushes vision into the odd realm where every object grows eyes and stares back. Given that our perception of an object always takes place from one perspectival point of view or another, we can never see the object in its totality but only partly. There will always be a ‘hidden side’, which remains absent from our direct view. Nevertheless, we immediately presume that there is more to the object than what is exhibited to our ‘naked eye’. If this were not so, we would experience the object as a two-dimensional façade and not as a fully-fledged three-dimensional reality. So there is a sense in which we see the object as having sides that are hidden from view. Merleau-Ponty explains this by arguing that it is because our own perspective is entangled in a vast sprawling web of viewpoints, which surrounds the focal thing and provides the supporting context for that side of the object which is in view at any one time, that we experience it to be deep or solid rather than just flat. Without this matrix of other viewpoints, weaving the object through to its core, the directly given aspect of the thing would simply lose its sense of depth and volume – that is, it would lose its three-dimensionality. Accordingly, it is, so to speak, ‘because vision is everywhere that we as perspectival beings are able to see things from somewhere – that is, from one particular perspectival viewpoint or another’ (Willerslev & Ulturgasheva 2007: 92, our emphasis). Merleau-Ponty calls the ‘view from everywhere’ the ‘normative ideal’ (Kelly 2005: 91). It might be imagined as a kind of cubist presentation in which every side of the object is presented simultaneously to us in a single – though ‘general’ – perspective. Crucially, however, such a perspective is impossible to adopt. While we can understand the ‘view from everywhere’ intellectually, we can never actually see things in their totality, simply because seeing in its nature is embodied and therefore perspectival. Even so, ‘the view from everywhere’ is a viewpoint that we cannot do without. It underlies every perspective as the ‘invisible’ background that allows things to stand out in their visibility. As Merleau-Ponty expresses it: ‘the proper essence of the visible [the view from somewhere] is to have a lining of invisibility [the “view from everywhere”]… which it makes present as a certain absence’ (1964: 187, our emphasis). In other words, while the ‘view from everywhere’ implies the world seen in totally clear and unambiguous visibility – that is, the world as laid bare in absolute transparency – it is a view that must ‘hide itself’ in order for the visible world to appear before our eyes. As such, the ‘view from everywhere’ is a view that cannot be an object of our perspectival seeing except ‘negatively’, that is by its absence. 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 335 AFTERWORD 335 It seems to us that Merleau-Ponty’s theory of perception, in which vision transcends immediate perspectival seeing, offers an appropriate framework for exploring what ‘soul’ or ‘spirit’ might mean in perspectivism. Let us begin by drawing attention to the important similarity between Merleau-Ponty’s notion of the ‘normative ideal’ and what Viveiros de Castro describes as the grounding or origin of perspectivism in mythical past (this volume) – later we also point to their differences. In the ‘absolute past’of myth, Viveiros de Castro tells us, bodily differences along with their distinctions of perspectives were not yet actualised. Instead, what prevailed was a ‘condition endowed with perfect transparency – a “chaosmos” where the bodily and spiritual dimensions of being did not yet reciprocally eclipse each other’ (original emphasis). Moreover, this mythical condition, rather than being an actual point in time was never present, and therefore never passes and thus underlies the present-day somatic matrix of bodies as invisible spirits or souls, with their infinite capacity for transformation (see also below). Were we to express it in terms of Merleau-Ponty’s theory of perception, the condition that Viveiros de Castro describes is none other than the ‘normative ideal’ – the ‘view from everywhere’ – in which the world is laid bare in absolute transparency. It is this pre-perspectival world – this prototype of being – marked, as it were, by an ‘anonymous’ or ‘general seeing’, that underlies every bodily perspective as its vital or animating principle (Willerslev 2006: 34). In the terminology of perspectivist theory, this can only be the ‘soul’ or ‘spirit’, which, as Viveiros de Castro points out, provides all beings with ‘the ability to adopt a point of view’, but which is ‘formally identical in all species’ and, therefore, marks no divisions or differences (1998: 478). This, we argue, explains why no one (not even beings that hunt for souls2) ever sees souls or spirits as such, since no achievable perspective allows for seeing this ‘anonymous’ or ‘general seeing’ that is nothing but a transcendental abstraction, defined as the totality of all viewpoints. All that is ever seen are bodies, which is how beings are assigned their particular perspective within this vast, tangled network of an otherwise ‘invisible’ anonymously given vision. So ‘soul’ or ‘spirit’, on this interpretation, is the body seen in its totality or absolute visibility, leaving nothing hidden – that is, the body seen from all sides, in all relationships all at once. However, no one (including shamans, about whom more below) can take up such a viewpoint. Indeed, this is why ‘soul’ or ‘spirit’ is a ‘normative ideal’ and not an actual thing to be seen. SEEING LIKE A SPIRIT AND SEEING INTO THE WORLD OF SPIRITS With these observations in mind, let us turn to Humphrey’s (this volume) illuminating description of the shamanic séance among the Horchin Mongols. The Horchin woman shaman has encircled her body with mirrors, which hang all around her hips facing outwards. The participants sit in a circle around the shaman, 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 336 4/12/07 15:32 Page 336 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV looking into the mirrors. The mirrors, Humphrey proposes, produce two different kinds of perspectives, from ‘outside the mirrors’ (looking into them) and from ‘inside the mirrors’(looking outwards). The first type of perspective is taken up by the participants, who rather than seeing their own reflections in the mirrors’cloudy, often mottled surface, see what is on the mirror’s ‘other side’ – the world of the spirits. The second type of perspective, from within the mirrors facing outwards, is that of the spirits themselves – a perspective the shaman embodies. What is to be understood by spirit here? The ethnographic image that Humphrey presents suggests an answer. The woman shaman, we are told, is a spirit during the séance because one or more of them possesses her. Yet, we might add that what constitutes the shaman as a spirit is also her placement within the circle of viewpoints. The shaman is in a very literal sense looked at from all possible viewpoints by the surrounding participants, and a spirit is, as we have just argued, nothing but the body seen from everywhere all at once. Thus, the shaman is constituted as a spirit by the viewpoints of the participants whose collective view approximates the ‘view from everywhere’. However, the shaman herself could also be said to embody this ‘spirit’ viewpoint that sees everything. By encircling her body with mirrors facing outwards, the shaman provides herself with what in principle is an indefinite number of additional eyes. In this way, she extends or even replaces her own embodied perspectival vision with an ‘anonymous’ or ‘general seeing’ that reveals the world transparently. Indeed, were it not for the fact that we are told that the Mongols do not have an idea of a primordial mythical time (see Humphrey and Pedersen this volume) as described by Viveiros de Castro for Amazonia, we could say that the shaman sees right into the world of mythical existence, seen as the totality of all possible perspectives. The fact that the Mongols do not have a conception of such mythical pasts of endless becoming is suggestive of how they conceive the shaman during the séance. This becomes apparent when we turn to the perspective of the audience. Humphrey tells us that what the audience see when looking into the cloudy surface of the mirrors is not a perfect reflection, but a slightly distorted image, which ‘opens up their vision to what is on the mirror’s other side’ – the world of the spirits. In this sense, people rather than looking into the mirrors ‘see through [them]’ (original emphasis). Indeed, we would argue that the fact that the figures seen in the mirrors are distorted is just as significant. It reminds us that the present volume is abundant with ethnographic examples of how the peoples of Inner Asia conceive spiritual beings in an essentially non-realist and sometimes monstrous fashion. Empson & Delaplace (this volume), for example, describe the so-called ‘little humans’, who are said to be a kind of miniaturised version of humans, and Pedersen gives a vivid and rather terrifying account of the ‘half people’, who, as the name suggests, appear to the human eye as half bodies, the other half being absent. Why this crude, monstrous and essentially non-realist depiction of spiritual beings? We would argue that if the ‘invisible’ world of spirits is defined as the 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 337 AFTERWORD 337 ‘view from everywhere’, then it follows that such a viewpoint cannot be embodied in any conventional realist form. As Merleau-Ponty puts it, ‘Since the total invisible [the “view from everywhere”] is always behind, or after, or between the aspects we see of it, there is access to it only through an experience which like it, is wholly outside of itself’ (1968: 136, our emphasis). What he is pointing to here is that it is only through a disruption or defamiliarisation of realist perspectival seeing that the invisible ground of vision can be revealed. So the spirit way of seeing the world from everywhere all at once, can never be perceptually grasped as it really is, but only sensed through ‘absence’. This is exactly what Empson & Delaplace point to when they state that encounters with spiritual beings in Mongolia tend always to be: described as sensations at the same time incomplete and intermitted … e.g. frying smells with no one seen frying or bell rings with no bell in sight… These particular sensations are rendered with verbs which convey a doubtful experience, something the narrator is unable to identify clearly… (original emphases). Similarly, in Humphrey’s ethnography, what the audience see when looking into the distorted images in the mirrors is not the spirit world per se. Rather, they get a glimpse of it at work, in much the same as we, when looking at a Cubist painting, do not see the nature of the object as it really is – that is, the ‘normative ideal’ – which cannot be represented. Instead, we perceive its workings through the sensed presence of that which is always absent, ‘the view from everywhere’. But what about the shaman, who by surrounding her body with mirrors facing outward, extends her ‘normal’ perspectival vision with additional eyes? Does she see the world from everywhere as it really is? Certainly, by adopting a multiplicity of viewpoints all at once, the shaman must see much more and much better than ordinary perspectival seeing. The fact that the Mongols often see the shaman’s mirrors as ‘miniature copies of the universe … that reflect everything, inside and outside’ (Loubo-Lesnitchenko and Heissig in Humphrey this volume) would support this general idea. Still, we venture to claim that the shaman does not fully occupy the ‘view from everywhere’, since no embodied subject can fully occupy this view. As Humphrey also points out: The ontological difference at issue here is that between a ‘being of the physicallylimited living human kind’ [that is, an embodied being] as against that of a ‘being of the former-human, dispersed, and universalised spirit kind’ [that is, a disembodied spirit]. So while shamans may artificially extend their number of eyes and thereby assume the spirit perspective, they cannot take up the ‘view from everywhere’ in an absolute sense (we return to this point below). Perhaps this is the reason why not even shamans are clear about what spirits actually see. As Humphrey points out, ‘evidence of what the world of the Living looks like from the perspective of Beyond Death is more scanty and uncertain’. This leads us to a further point. Humphrey argues that the shaman’s mirrors 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 338 4/12/07 15:32 Page 338 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV are both armour and weapon, they are ‘both container for incoming helper spirits of the shaman and provide protection against curses and attacks from external evil-intentioned people and spirits’. Building on this, we would argue that there is also a sense in which the mirrors protect the audience, who by looking into them not only get a glimpse of the spirit world at work, but are also reminded of the limitation of their own perspectival seeing. Why is this important? Well, had they been Amerindians and had they been able to see the spirit world as it really is – that is, from a ‘view from everywhere’ – it would imply transforming into mythical existence, from which people have estranged themselves with such great effort. In the Mongolian context in which no such origin myth of becoming exists and where the world, with all its divisions and dichotomies, along with its emphasis on hierarchical ordered differences (see Kristensen and Swancutt this volume), is taken to be the natural order of things (see Humphrey and Pedersen this volume), any such condition of absolute indistinction of perspectives would simply mean the ‘end of the world’ – a condition that recalls Empson’s Mongolian informants’ description of the ‘Time of Great Calamities’ (Empson 2006). A HIERARCHY OF PERSPECTIVES Having provided the above analysis of spirits, understood as ‘views from everywhere’, we may now turn to the key question of the role of transcendence in Inner Asian perspectivism. That such a move is viable is suggested by the fact that, as so many of the contributions to this volume reiterate, the perspectives of the spirits that shamans are able to embody (albeit always incompletely as we have argued) are so often conceived in irreducibly asymmetrical and often ‘vertical’ terms. For example, Broz argues that in the Altai, the relationship between people and eeler (the animal master spirit) is asymmetrical in terms of power. It is ‘eeler who have the power to punish people for improper behaviour, not the other way around’ (this volume). Likewise, in her contribution, Kristensen describes how among Duha herders, the distinction between beings relies on a difference in rank. In fact, as many of the contributors also suggest, the hierarchical character of Inner Asian spirits marks a key difference from the Amerindian cosmologies that Viveiros de Castro’s perspectivist model articulates (see Swancutt, Humphrey and Pedersen this volume). As Viveiros de Castro describes in this volume, in Amazonia all cosmologically significant beings are spirits. To Amerindians under ordinary conditions (i.e. when they are not shamanising, hallucinating, dreaming, hunting and so on), beings appear in the form of their ‘speciated’ bodies (humans, jaguars, Whites, thunder, etc.) but this takes nothing away from their irreducibly spiritual character. As ‘laminated’ or ‘crystallised’ forms of spirits, all beings are indexes of the pre-cosmological ‘chaosmos’ of origin myths which, as we have already touched upon, constitutes the condition of the ‘bifurcat [ion] … of a relative invisibility (human souls and animal spirits) and a relative 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 339 AFTERWORD 339 opacity (the human body and the somatic animal ‘clothing’) which determines the make-up of all present-day beings’ (original emphases). Viveiros de Castro continues: The heterogenic continuum of the pre-cosmological world gives way, therefore, to a homogenic ‘discretum’, where each being is only what it is, and is only what it is by not being what it is not. But spirits are testimony to the fact that not all virtualities were actualised, and that the mythical river run of fluent metamorphosis continues its turbulent course not too far below the surface discontinuities separating the types and species. The key consequence of the immanence, albeit ordinarily invisible, of spirits as the virtual residue of all actualised beings is, of course, perspectivism. If all beings are spirits, and spirits are defined by their capacity to undergo mythic transformations, then all beings are constituted by their potential for transformation, i.e. the adoption of another being’s point of view. Indeed, it follows, as Viveiros de Castro describes, that since all humans are spirits too (they have ‘souls’), they also have the capacity to transform themselves, a capacity shamans, dreamers, hunters and so on display. Hence, for example, for the Yanomami ‘“to become a shaman” is a synonym of “to become a spirit” (xapiripru [from xapiripë, the Yanomami word for “spirit”])’, and is conceived as a capacity that all humans possess, albeit to different degrees of expertise (see also Swancutt this volume). The ethnographic premise, then, of perspectivism is spirit. Now, our argument about the transmutation of perspectivism to the ‘vertical’ setting of Inner Asia turns precisely on this premise. As we have just seen, Viveiros de Castro’s ‘horizontal’ model lays supreme emphasis on the immanence of spirits as the virtual counterparts of all beings. It is, if you like, by virtue of always being more (virtually) than they are (actually) that all beings have the potential to become something else. From an Inner Asian point of view, however, the problem with this image is that it tends to preclude the kinds of distinctions between perspectives that are necessary to articulate perspectivist transformations in vertical terms. As Viveiros de Castro himself points out, the virtual domain in which beings qua spirits transform themselves is one of ‘indistinction’ and ‘transductivity’ – an anarchic ‘chaosmos’. So it follows that an Inner Asian model of perspectivism requires an analysis of spirits that does not entail a ‘chaosmotic’ potential for indiscriminate transformation. It is here, we argue, that the ‘transcendental’ analysis of spirits that we have provided above – spirits as the unattainable ‘view from everywhere’ – becomes pivotal. Indeed, such an analysis performs the same work for our model as Viveiros de Castro’s ‘virtual’ analysis does for his. In Inner Asia all beings are spirits (or have souls), much like in Amazonia. Furthermore, as in Amazonia again, Inner Asian spirits are defined in terms of the ‘excess’ of perspectives that they can occupy – indeed, the totality of all possible perspectives. The crucial difference of a ‘transcendental’ analysis, however, is that precisely this excess 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 340 4/12/07 15:32 Page 340 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV renders the perspective of spirits unattainable as such. So, on this view, the fact that all beings have spirits suggest that each being entails (viz. is constituted by) a relationship to the unattainable ‘limit’ of all possible perspectives. Inverting Viveiros de Castro’s ‘virtualist’formula, we might say that each being is what it is (actually) by virtue of being ‘less’ than it is (transcendentally) or, in other words, beings are always present by being partly absent. And, as we now propose to show, it is precisely in terms of their relationship to their own inherent absence that beings’ perspectives can be differentiated hierarchically, as Inner Asian ethnography would require. We explained how the ‘view from everywhere’ is not a view that can be held. Nevertheless it is implicit in each particular perspective as the background to what is seen. As such, the view from everywhere is constituted as an ideal from which all perspectives are felt to be deviating to some degree. As Merleau-Ponty remarks, the ‘normative ideal’ tends to be experienced as a motivational invitation to change one’s position, so as to get a better, fuller, or more optimal view of the perceived object. Thus, not all perspectives are of equal value. While they all deviate from the same ‘normative ideal’ some are closer to it than others. The philosophical commentator Holenstein is particularly clear in his discussion of the ‘optimal’ viewpoint: We soon realise that, in the case of viewing a building, we have to go to a specific side in order to bring out more clearly the function of the building, and yet to a third in order to realise in an optimal way how the architecture takes up and continues the main lines of the landscape … These series [of perspectives] characterise themselves as ascending, culminating in an optimal perspective … The optimal perspective … tends to establish itself as absolute, making the rest of the perspectives appear to be orientated towards it. (1999: 82) In other words, the idea of a ‘normative ideal’ allows particular perspectives to be differentiated in terms of the degree to which they approximate the ‘optimal perspective’. Such an analysis, we argue, allows us to makes sense of the ‘vertical’ character of Inner Asian perspectivism. Swancutt’s penetrating analysis of Mongolian games in this volume illustrates this particularly clearly. As social activities, Swancutt shows, games mirror the abidingly hierarchical character of wider social and cosmological orders in Mongolia. The experience of learning to play games typically revolves around the asymmetrical relationship between a novice and a master. Indeed, as Swancutt argues, the ‘virtuosity’ that masters exemplify can be conceived as a ‘bodily affect’ that players hold to varying degrees. Novices become virtuosos by learning to emulate their masters in the context of pedagogical contests with them or, occasionally, by being favoured with ‘fortune’ by the spirits – a state of being that also has strong corporeal connotations (see Swancutt this volume). Crucially, however, the attainment of virtuosity consists in the ability to gain an increasingly complete purview on possible ‘moves’ within the game at any particular juncture. Thus virtuosity, for Swancutt, is a thoroughly ‘perspectival’ phenomenon and involves transforma- 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 341 AFTERWORD 341 tions on the part of players that are strictly comparable with more familiar perspectivist scenarios, such as human–animal transformations and so on. With regard to our argument, what is most interesting about Swancutt’s analysis is how she theorises novices’ attainment of virtuosity in terms of an essentially hierarchical order of perspectives. In particular, she shows how such a hierarchy is organised with reference to a notional limit – what she calls the ‘ideal game’. This, as she explains, is the game seen from every player’s viewpoint all at once, in which ‘Devoid of competition, the ideal game ceaselessly gives rise to victories and lasts indefinitely’. In direct parallel to Merleau-Ponty’s notion of the ‘normative ideal’, then, the ‘ideal game’is not one that can actually be played. It is ‘ideal’ just in the sense that each player’s viewpoint during an actual game is experienced as deviating from it. Indeed, as Swancutt shows, these deviations vary according to the skill and fortune of each player. The closer to the ideal game – the transcendental ‘view from everywhere’ – one’s perspective is, the more ‘optimal’ it is, so that the process of learning the game involves players’ shifts along a spiral of increasingly optimal positions. Swancutt’s detailed discussion of how ‘fortune’, understood in terms of ‘fluctuating degrees’of ‘spiritual potency’, facilitates such shifts places her discussion of games in the context of a wide ambit of perspectivist phenomena in Mongolia and other Inner Asian regions. For example, if fortune in games consists of players’ ability to expand the range of perspectives that they are able to adopt, then game playing can be compared directly to the experience of the shaman of Humphrey’s example, who gets a clearer and more transparent view of the world by artificially extending her ordinary human vision with a number of extra eyes. In this sense, the notion of a hierarchy of perspectives, articulated on an axis of relative proximity to the transcendental limit of all possible perspectives, can arguably be transposed beyond the confines of Mongolian games to include a wide variety of forms of ‘spiritual potency’ which, so often in Inner Asia as we have seen, is conceived in irreducibly hierarchical terms. Inner Asian perspectivism then forces us to deal with degrees of perceptive power. Indeed, the possibility of differentiating perspectives by pointing to the degree to which they deviate from the ‘ideal’ allows us to supplement our earlier comments about the nature of spirits. For while in our earlier discussion we identified spirits with the ideal ‘view from everywhere’, we also noted that, as a matter of ethnographic fact, spirits are never seen as such, but are rather depicted in a variety of quasi-corporeal forms. Particularly relevant here is the fact that, as many of the articles in this volume suggest, the embodied spectres of spirits in Inner Asian cosmologies are not seen as equal, but are often classified into taxonomic pyramids with respect to their varying degrees of authority and power (e.g. see Swancutt, Kristensen and Broz). Following the logic of our argument on the hierarchy of perspectives, such cosmological orderings of variously embodied spirits come as no surprise. Just as the shaman becomes perceptually more powerful and also more spirit-like by transcending her ordinary human vision with an extra number of eyes, so a spirit become less powerful and perceptually 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 342 4/12/07 15:32 Page 342 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV more limited, the more embodied it becomes. In other words, insofar as spirits are embodied in a variety of ways, they are subject to the same deviations from the pure ideal of the ‘view from everywhere’ as non-spiritual beings, only in an inverse sense. Indeed such an inversion, we would suggest, accords with the fact that in Inner and North Asia in general the world of the spirits is so often depicted as a mirror reversal of the world of the living, where everything is inside-out or back-to-front: Light becomes dark, old becomes young, left becomes right, and so on (e.g. see Humphrey and Broz this volume; Willerslev 2007: 11) TEMPORAL PERSPECTIVISM One way to summarise our contrast between Amerindian ‘immanentism’ and Inner Asian ‘transcendentalism’ would be in terms of the semiotic distinction between ‘paradigmatic’ and ‘syntagmatic’ structures (cf. Holbraad 2007: 217). In Viveiros de Castro’s model, different perspectives are immanent to each other in the sense that each perspective can in principle substitute every other, much like the members of a semiotic ‘paradigm’ can in principle act as each other’s equivalents (e.g. each letter of the alphabet can in principle substitute every other since their order (a, b, c, …, z) is merely a conventional aide-mémoire). By contrast, on the model we have presented for Inner Asia, different perspectives are transcendent to one another in the sense that switches from one to the other typically take place asymmetrically, inasmuch as perspectives are related to each other in ordinal sequences that are ranked ‘syntagmatically’. After all, ranking perspectives with respect to the degree to which each approximates the transcendental norm of ‘the view from everywhere’, as we have suggested, yields precisely such an ordinal distribution. So if the semiotic metaphor for the perspectives that beings can occupy in the Amerindian case is something like the letters of the alphabet, in the Inner Asian case it would be the words that letters can make up or, by extension, the sentences and narratives that words themselves can build in syntax. The Inner Asian shaman, for example, becomes a spirit less like an ‘x’ could become a ‘y’ or ‘z’, and more like Cinderella could become a princess. An advantage of thinking of the contrast between Amazonia and Inner Asia in these terms is that it allows us to address the final ethnographic conundrum presented by a number of the articles in this volume, which is that in Inner Asia perspectivist transformations are frequently deemed to occur on an irreducibly temporal axis. We have already seen, for example, that on Swancutt’s account the perspectival shifts involved in Mongolian games are to be understood in sequential terms. Over time, novices can become experts by learning to adopt their teacher’s perspective on the game, which is articulated at the moments in which a multitude of possible ‘moves’ becomes transparent to the player – the moments Swancutt, following Deleuze, calls ‘aleatory points’ (this volume). Particularly suggestive in this context is that, as Swancutt explains, players’ ability to occupy 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 343 AFTERWORD 343 such increasingly ‘better’ perspectives is not only a matter of emulating a teacher, but depends also, as we have seen, on ‘boosts’ of fortune that shamanic spirits or Buddhist deities may confer on players temporarily during a game. As a fluid ‘bodily affect’ (Swancutt this volume) that may at times be contained and at other times lost (see also Empson 2007), fortune itself is an inherently temporal state of being. It would follow, therefore, that if players’ ability to adopt others’ perspectives is deemed an event of fortune then those perspectives themselves must also be seen as distributed on a temporal axis. While the implications of a temporal view of perspectivism are explored by a number of the contributors to this volume (e.g. see Broz), they are treated most explicitly by Da Col in his remarkable discussion of the ways in which a variety of Tibetan Buddhist concepts explicitly relate beings’ capacity to transform themselves to their position on various temporal scales. For example, drawing a direct analogy with Tibetan concepts of fortune and the body – they are both an assemblage of forces, efficacious configurations of affectual dispositions – Da Col (this volume) shows how various types of fortune serve to trigger beings’ ability to temporarily transcend ontological and social hierarchies. Moreover, as Da Col shows, in Tibet concepts of fortune exist alongside a host of further notions that associate both the cosmological positions that particular beings occupy and their ability to transcend those positions at particular junctures with a variety of temporal conceptions, including cycles of karmic reincarnation. Da Col writes: Everything is either ultimate or conventional truth, essence or appearance, depending on one’s karma and body of fortune. Revelations will happen at the appropriate moment. It will be a view from somewhen since a Being has to be conceived in time, being not a singularity but a multiplicity, not one life but a multiplicity of lives and perspectives: the sum of all the perspectives it will traverse during the course of the virtually infinite extension of its possible lives. Among Tibetans, karma and fortune generate an evenemental perspective, a view from somewhen. A Being has to be conceived in time, being not a singularity but a multiplicity, not one life but a multiplicity of lives and perspectives: the sum of all the perspectives it will traverse during the course of the virtually infinite extension of its possible lives … In the Tibetan world, events not things create points of view. (Da Col, this volume, original emphases) Such a temporalised notion of perspectivism, which as we have seen finds echoes in other Inner Asian regions, is certainly confluent with our attempt to encompass transcendence within a perspectivist scheme. To say, as we have done, that on a ‘transcendentalist’analysis perspectives are ordered syntagmatically is just to say that they are ordered according to asymmetrical relations of ‘before’ and ‘after’. Clearly such an image implies a temporal distribution just as it implies a hierarchical one. Indeed in such a view, time is a straight corollary of hierarchy, at least in the sense that any ‘ascent’ or ‘descent’ from one hierarchical position to another is a movement of some sort, and movement requires a time within which to unfold, as Cinderella with her 12 o’clock deadline knew only too well. In this 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 344 4/12/07 15:32 Page 344 MARTIN HOLBRAAD AND RANE WILLERSLEV sense it is perhaps not so surprising that, in Inner Asia, perspectival shifts should so often be thought of in hierarchical and temporal terms at once. However, Da Col’s analysis also suggests an intriguing, if somewhat speculative, extension of the transcendentalist position. Throughout this Afterword, our argument about transcendence has been elaborated in the language of space. Following Viveiros de Castro, we have been thinking about perspectives as ‘points of view’, adding that the relative partiality of such viewpoints can be differentiated normatively with reference to the total ‘view from everywhere’ which is contained within each perspective as a transcendental limit. However, it would appear that the frequently temporal premise of Inner Asian perspectivism allows us to add time as a further dimension of this analysis. To the extent that particular perspectives can be construed as views from ‘somewhen’, to use Da Col’s suggestive neologism, should the transcendental totality from which they deviate not also be conceived as a ‘view from everywhen’? As unattainable, logically, as the Merleau-Pontyan ‘view from everywhere’ (cf. Merleau-Ponty 2002: 69–71), such a view could amount to nothing less than the view from eternity – eternity, that is, not merely as a line of infinite time, but rather as the full plenitude of all possible events. Perhaps it is just the unattainable ‘excess’ of such a view that Da Col’s Buddhist friend had in mind when he explained that to conceive of the co-existence (rather than the dualist separation, as we would add) of a noumenal world alongside the sensible world of tulpa (illusion), you have to think in terms of ‘emptiness’. ‘Everything is endless, infinite and circular. If you really want to conceive an originating point, you need the concept of time but in emptiness itself there is not even that, there is only eternity’ (Da Col, this volume). In this sense, the Buddhist doctrine of ‘two worlds’ (illusion and eternity) can be viewed as a particularly explicit cosmological rendition of our logical argument about co-existence of perspectivism and transcendence in Inner Asia more generally – a permutation of ‘transcendental perspectivism’ that makes its own logical premises cosmologically transparent. NOTES 1The authors have contributed equally to this article. The order of names was the result of a coin toss. 2The Siberian Yukaghirs’ conception of the much-feared evil spirits, abasylar, illustrates this point. These spirits are said to hunt for human souls, the ayibii. However, they never in fact see souls as souls. Instead, they see the ayibii as bodies – that is, as elks of different sizes and ages (Willerslev 2007: 82). REFERENCES Empson, R. 2006. Time, Causality and Prophecy in the Mongolian Cultural Region: Visions of the Future. Kent: Global Oriental. 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 345 AFTERWORD 345 2007. Separating and containing people and things in Mongolia, in A. Henare, M. Holbraad & S. Wastell (ed.), Thinking Through Things: Theorising Artefacts Ethnographically: 113–40. London: Routledge. Holbraad, M. 2007. The power of powder: multiplicity and motion in the divinatory cosmology of Cuban Ifá (or mana, again), in A. Henare, M. Holbraad & S. Wastell (ed.), Thinking Through Things: Theorising Artefacts Ethnographically: 189–225. London: Routledge. forthcoming. Definitive evidence, from Cuban gods, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute. Holenstein, E. 1999. The zero-point orientation: the placement of the I in perceived space, in D. Welton (ed.), The Body: 57–94. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Blackwell Readings in Continental Philosophy. Hugh-Jones, S. 1996. Shamans, prophets, priests and pastors, in N. Thomas & C. Humphrey (ed.), Shamanism, History and the State: 32–75. Ann Arbor (MI): The University of Michigan Press. Humphrey, C. with Onon, 1996. Shamans and Elders: Experience, Knowledge and Power among the Daur Mongols. Oxford: Oxford University Press Jackson, M. 1989. Path towards a Clearing: Radical Empiricism and Ethnographic Inquiry. Bloomington (IN): Indiana University Press. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1964. Eye and mind, in J. M. Edie (ed.), The Primacy of Perception and Other Essays on Phenomenological Psychology, the Philosophy of Art, History and Politics. Evanston (IL): Northwestern University Press. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1968. The Visible and the Invisible. A. Lingis, trans. Evanston (IL): Northwestern University Press. Merleau-Ponty, M. 2002 [1945]. Phenomenology of Perception. C. Smith, trans. London and New York (NY): Routledge. Pedersen, M. 2001. Totemism, animism and North Asian indigenous ontologies, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 7 (3): 411–27. Taylor, C. 1982. Rationality, in M Hollis & S. Lukes (ed.), Rationality and Relativismi: 87–105. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press. Viveiros de Castro, E. 1998. Cosmological deixis and Amerindian perspectivism, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 4 (3): 469–88. Viveiros de Castro, E. 2003. And. Manchester: Manchester Papers in Social Anthropology. Willerslev, R. 2006. ‘To have the world at a distance’: reconsidering the significance of vision for social anthropology, in C. Grasseni (ed.), Skilled Visions: Between Apprenticeship and Standards: 23–46. New York (NY) and Oxford: Berghahn Books. EASA Series, Vol. 6. Willerslev, R. 2007. Soul Hunters: Hunting, Animism, and Personhood among the Siberian Yukaghirs. Berkeley (CA): University of California Press. Willerslev, R. & Ulturgasheva, O. 2007. The sable frontier: the Siberian fur trade as montage, Cambridge Anthropology, 26 (2): 79–100. 11 Afterword IA0902:Layout 1 4/12/07 15:32 Page 346