CHANCE II—JOHN WATLING A person may be more or less strongly convinced that a Channel tunnel will be built. Presumably his degree of conviction will be related to the manner in which he suits his actions to the rewards and penalties the various courses of action open to him will bring if his judgment about the building of a tunnel proves correct, and the rewards and penalties those same actions will bring if his judgement proves incorrect. However, I do not think that his degree of conviction can be identified with this manner since a person will act in face of a higher penalty in a rash mood than in a prudent one. Nor do I think that this manner of suiting his actions to the various rewards and penalties they will, with different eventualities, bring can be measured by discovering the least favourable odds which will induce him to place a bet. The least favourable odds which will induce him to place a bet vary with the size of the bet and with the impression the prospective gains and losses would make upon his financial situation. We test the seriousness of a person’s assertion by asking how much he will bet, not what odds he will take. There seems no reason why one person should not recommend others to take up a certain degree of conviction in a certain matter. Perhaps if one person said to some others “It is certain that a Channel tunnel will be built” he would he recommending them to adopt a very high degree of conviction in the building of the tunnel. Perhaps if he said “It is just possible that a Channel tunnel will not be built” he would be recommending them to moderate their strong conviction that a tunnel will he built by a small degree. Mellor identifies the question whether there is an objective probability of a tunnel being built with the question whether there are sufficient grounds for recommending one coherent betting quotient rather than another. 1 Further, he identifies the objective probability of a tunnel being built with the fact which constitute those grounds. This fact, he assumes, concerns a particular feature of the world. It can hardly be that the objective probability of a tunnel being built is identical with a fact which includes the financial position of the people to whom a recommendation is addressed, nor that a recommendation concerning how prudent to be - as opposed to one concerning how to be prudent - depend upon any fact other than one concerning a non-natural property. Therefore, if objective probability is to be approached in this way at all, the question whether there is an objective probability that a tunnel will be built must be identified with the question whether there are sufficient grounds for recommending one degree of conviction rather than another, and the objective probability itself must be identified with the fact which constitutes the grounds for recommending that degree of conviction. How plausible are these identifications? I do not think that the second is plausible at all and without the second the first does not help very much to explain what objective probabilities are. The fact that nearly everyone in the world wanted a tunnel, that resources were available and engineering skill adequate, would be a sufficient ground for recommending a high degree of conviction that a tunnel would be built, yet it would not he the fact that it was very probable that a tunnel would be built. It would not be that fact since it is also true that the fact, if it were one, that some very powerful financiers would gain if the tunnel were built and no very powerful financiers would gain it the tunnel were not built would be a sufficient ground for recommending a high degree of conviction that a tunnel would be built, so that that fact, if it were one, would be the fact that it was very probable that a tunnel would be built. The same fact could not, even in different circumstances, be identical with each of two different facts, hence Mellor’s second identification is mistaken. Even it were not, what ground would there be for supposing that all facts which provide sufficient grounds for recommending a degree 2 of conviction of a certain strength have it in common that they concern one particular feature of the world? I do not think that the first identification is plausible as it stands; perhaps it could be made more plausible by specifying the relation of being a sufficient ground precisely. If nothing is a sufficient ground for recommending a conviction of a certain strength which does not entail that a conviction of that strength ought to he recommended then—in my opinion—Mellor’s first identification has the consequence that there are no objective probabilities. If, as seems more likely, the question of whether there is a sufficient ground for recommending a conviction of a certain strength rests on considerations of morality, then the first identification makes the existence of objective probabilities entail the existence of moral principles of a certain sort. I find that implausible. I shall not pursue this matter since I do not think that Mellor treats either identification very seriously. If he did he would not assume without argument that all facts which provide sufficient grounds for recommending a degree of conviction of a certain strength have it in common that they concern one particular feature of the world, nor that that particular feature is the subject matter of the statistical sciences, by which he means those sciences which are concerned with hypotheses of statistical, rather than universal, form. He does take two things to be important: first, that the fact that people sometimes have coherent betting quotients does not imply that there are no objective probabilities; second, that problems arise over such propositional forms as this—which he takes to be typical of propositions implied by hypotheses of statistical form—that the chance that this F is a G is 1/n where n is greater than one). I agree with him about both. He uses the term “chance”, rather than the term “probability”, to make clear that the probabilities in which he is interested belong in no sense to logic. His first characterization of the propositions concerning chance he wishes to investigate is that each ascribes the chance of a certain outcome to a trial. A trial is a 3 particular performance of an experiment. Mellor does not make clear whether chances are ascribed to the event of an experiment being performed or to the fact that an experiment was performed, although one of his examples suggests that he intends the latter. The distinction is important, as Peter Downing has pointed out in discussing causation. ‘‘His arrival at two o’clock caused a sensation” invites the question “What was it about his arrival at two o’clock which caused the sensation? Was it the fact that his arrival took place at two o’clock, or merely the fact that it took place at all, or was it some other fact about it?” Events are particulars; strictly, they can no more be causes than physical objects can, but an event or a physical object may be said to be responsible for an effect in order to suggest that some fact about it had that effect, or that there is some fact about it which had that effect. This is the foundation of jokes of the type: “What gave you that black eye?” “My wife hitting me with a pound of tomatoes.” “But your wife hitting you with a pound of tomatoes wouldn’t give you that black eye.” “They were in a tin.” Mellor does not wish to confine his attention to contrived experiments, rather than natural happenings, so that this characterisation does little more than limit the ascription of chances to facts to the effect that something has happened at a time or for a period of time. However, Mellor sometimes seems to be misled by his use of the term “trial”. When he is discussing the probability that a radium atom will disintegrate he speaks of the trial as that of waiting for a year. What chance there is that the fact that I wait for a year will have the outcome that an atom of radium disintegrates depends, of course, upon what chance there is that the fact that I wait for a year has the outcome that a radium atom exists at the beginning of that year. However, the chance that a radium atom will disintegrate does not depend upon that. The trial Mellor has in mind must be the fact that I wait for at most a year with a radium atom. However, if this is the trial, the fact that I wait is redundant to it. The chance Mellor wishes to express is the chance of the fact that a radium atom exists at a certain time having as outcome its disintegration within the year. I suspect 4 that he avoided this formulation because he wishes to regard trials as experiments on, or happenings to, objects. The continuing in existence of an object is neither an experiment on it nor something which happens to it. It is not clear how much of their ordinary meanings the terms “outcome” and “result”—an outcome for Mellor is a disjunction of results—are intended to preserve. It may be that if it is true that since an experiment has been made at least one, and no more than one, of a group of events must occur and not true that since the experiment has been made some particular one of those events must occur, then those events are called results of the trial. However, it may be that a trial is the performance of an experiment and if whenever that experiment is performed an event belonging to one, but to no more than one, of a group of kinds of events occur, and if it is not true that whenever the experiment is performed an event belonging to some one of that group of kinds invariably occurs, then the occurrence of an event belonging to one of those kinds is said to be a result of the experiment. Therefore it may be that the terms “outcome” and “trial” are so used that to call an event the outcome or the result of a trial is not to imply that its occurrence was in anyway due to the trial. To call an event the outcome or result of a trial may not even imply that it follows the trial in time. Disintegrating during a year does not follow waiting for a year, although, of course, it does follow beginning to wait for a year. These questions are not of great importance in the context of Mellor’s paper. What is important is his declaration that: the chance of its happening is not a property that can be ascribed to an event without taking it to be the outcome of a trial. (Section 3) For example, we cannot say “There is a chance of 1/n that a Channel tunnel will be built in this century” but only “There is a chance of 1/n that the existence of the English Channel throughout the remainder of this century will have as outcome that a 5 tunnel will be built under it”, or any number of other things of that sort. We must always speak of the chance that a trial will have an outcome, or of the chance of an outcome with respect to the occurrence of a trial. Evidently this allows that the occurrence of an event of a certain kind may have one chance when it is considered as the outcome of one trial and another chance when considered as the outcome of another. This compatibility accords with the logic of propositions concerning chances. The fact that there is a chance of 1/6 that the landing of a die will have as outcome the turning up of a five is consistent with the fact that there is a chance of 1/3 that the landing of the die with an odd numbered face upwards will have as outcome the turning up of a five. Again, the fact that there is a chance of 1/2 that the existence of a radium atom at a certain time will have as outcome the disintegration of the atom within a period of 1,622 years is consistent with the fact that there is a much greater chance that the existence of a radium atom under bombardment by a stream of alphaparticles at a certain time will have as outcome the disintegration of the atom within that same period. Of course, the compatibility of these different chances is not implied by Mellor’s contention that the chance of an event’s happening is not a property which can be ascribed to it without taking it to be the outcome of a trial; it is merely that unless Mellor’s contention is correct it is difficult to see how these chances could be compatible. In any case Mellor argues at the end of his paper that the fact that the occurrence of an event of a certain kind has a certain chance with respect to one trial is not inconsistent with the fact that such an event is the invariable concomitant of another kind of trial, so it seems that he accepts the compatibility. Neither of these contentions is consistent with his belief that the frequency theory is refuted by the argument Ayer brings against it. Ayer asks for the probability of his living to the age of eighty and complains that the frequency theory tells him the probabilities of his living to that age with respect to his being an organism, a human being, a professional philosopher etc., but never the probability of his living to the age of eighty. Mellor 6 provides a way of regarding this probability as the chance of a trial having a certain outcome when he discusses the chance of a radium atom disintegrating and the concept of an individual’s physiological age. He describes the trial as “waiting for a certain period of years”. I have argued that it is in fact the existence of Ayer at the beginning of a period of years. The frequency theory has certain difficulties in interpreting the chance that this trial will have the outcome that Ayer is alive at the end of the period, hut none of them is the difficulty to which Ayer points. He would be just as dissatisfied with the probability of his survival with respect to this particular trial as he is with probabilities with respect to other trials. The frequency theory has difficulty in interpreting the probability that Ayer’s being alive at the beginning of a period of years will have the outcome that he is alive at the end of it because although it is possible to find a denumerably infinite sequence of such periods of years at the beginning of which Ayer is alive, yet the two outcomes—alive at the end and not alive at the end—are not randomly distributed. The earlier beginnings have the outcome alive at the end, but after a certain point all beginnings have the outcome not alive at the end. If this is Mellor’s objection to the frequency theory then it is quite consistent with his contention that in one respect the frequency theory is correct: it regards chance as a property that cannot be ascribed to an event without it taking to be the outcome of a trial. However, Mellor’s argument in fact follows Ayer’s closely. What is more he agrees with Ayer that the objection to the frequency theory is the analogue of an objection to the theory that probability is a logical relation between evidence and conclusion. The only objection to that theory which could be an analogue of an objection to the frequency theory is the objection that it makes it impossible to speak of the probability of a conclusion, and only allows that a conclusion may be probable with respect to certain evidence. This rejection of the logical relation theory is, therefore, based on an assumption which Mellor explicitly denies. 7 This inconsistency in Mellor’s paper seems to me to be mitigated by another which is more central to the theory which it is the main object of his paper to propose. Once he has characterised the propositions in which he is interested as those which ascribe the chance of a certain outcome to a trial he goes on to investigate the place of the concept of a disposition—that is, of an object having a certain disposition—in the concept of chance. To this end he considers the possibility that there being a chance of 1/n of a trial having a certain outcome might be regarded as the possession of a dispositional property by the object, or device, or arrangement of objects, upon which the trial is conducted. His question is: What is this dispositional property? One answer, the discussion of which Mellor had to delete from his paper from lack of space, is that there being a chance of 1/n of a trial having a certain outcome can be regarded as a property of the object on which the trial is conducted, but not as a dispositional property of that object. The property is closely related to a dispositional property, but it is a tendency, not a disposition. For example, the proposition that there is a chance of 1/6 that the falling of a die will have the outcome of a five turning up will be interpreted as the proposition that the die tends, with a strength of 1/6, to turn up five when it falls. Of such a proposition Mellor said: And it is not at all clear that any analysis of it can be given that does not involve essential reference to chance or, as above, reduce essentially to relative frequency. It is indeed not clear how tendencies can be interpreted except in terms of frequencies or in terms of such relations as that of tending to produce or promoting. I am thinking of example such as “Weight low down promotes stability”. It is the analysis of such propositions as this which seems to me to be the most interesting question concerning probability. Hume’s attack on the idea of causal necessity, that is, on such concepts as 8 producing or bringing about, has convinced very many philosophers that these causal relations hold between two kinds and not between two facts. If causal relations hold between kinds they can be given an extensional interpretation. For example, a typical causal form would be that being F causes being G and this can be identified with the form that there never has been and never will be anything which is F and is not G. This universal proposition has as consequences numerous relations between two facts—for example, that this is either not F or is G—and it is easy to suppose that it has as consequences numerous causal relations between two facts—for example, that the fact that this was F caused it to be G. However, propositions of this form, since they are not of the form “being F causes being G”, have no interpretation. Causation, according to this extensionalist account, is not a relation between two facts. The words “His being F would cause him to be G” might be taken to express the proposition that there never has been and never will be anything which is F and is not G, but to do that is to pretend that causation is a relation between two facts, not to make it one. I am convinced that there are causal relations which stand between two facts and so I reject the extensional interpretation. I find the fact that causal relations are necessary relations to be an independent, and sufficient, ground for rejecting it. Both of these objections tell equally strongly against an extensionalist interpretation of the relation of tending to produce or promoting. A frequency relation between two kinds of event cannot stand between two facts. A frequency relation is an extensional relation which partakes in no way of necessity. I am not sure, when Mellor asks But if frequentists deny that their definition applies to the single case, what does it apply to? What sense can be made of “the chance that an F is a G” that denies sense to “the chance that this F is a G”? 9 whether he has the former of these objections: in mind. It is a telling question but slightly unfair. The frequency theory defines “the chance of being G with respect to being F”. It defines neither “the chance that anything is G with respect to its being F” not “the chance that this is G with respect to its being F”. This is analagous to the extensional interpretation of causation which defines “being F causes being G” but defines neither “this is F causes this to be G” nor “anything’s being F causes that thing to be G”. For some reason the fact that frequencies cannot relate two facts is much more obvious than the fact that regularities cannot relate two facts and the objection that the extensional account of causation cannot allow causation between two facts is much less common than the objection that the frequency theory cannot allow a probability relation between two facts. Perhaps it is because according to the regularity theory of causation causal propositions do have as consequences relations between two facts, although not causal relations, while according to the frequency theory probability propositions have as consequences no relations between two fact Somehow this latter objection gets mixed up with the objection that the frequency theory is a relational theory. This happens, I think, in Ayer’s discussion of the frequency theory. However that may be, Mellor rejects those versions of the dispositional theory of probability which are in reality, not dispositional theories, but tendency theories. Because he rejects any intrusion of frequencies into the concept of chance he equally rejects, but without discussion, theories such as Peirce’s and Popper’s which do regard chances as dispositions of objects, or of arrangements of objects, but as dispositions to behave in a certain way not in a single trial but in a very large number of trials. Peirce says in the paper Mellor cites 10 Now in order that the full effect of the die’s “would be” may find expression, it is necessary that the die should undergo an endless series of throws from the dice box. Again, Popper writes of probabilities, in “The Propensity Interpretation of Probability”: They characterise the disposition, or the propensity, of the experimental arrangement to give rise to certain characteristic frequencies when the experiment is often repeated. It is not clear that these formulations succeed in presenting such facts as that a die turns up five when it fails with a frequency of 1/6 as facts about a disposition of the die. Steel has the dispositional property of becoming hard on repeated blows with a hammer, but there the repeated blows produce a single effect. Mellor’s example of the elasticity of a spring is an example of a dispositional property where a single dispositional property is allowed to be revealed in different responses to different forces. Perhaps, then, if it is a fact that a die responds to 1200 throws with roughly 200 turnings-up of five, and to 2400 throws with roughly 400 fives, and so on, we might regard it as having a dispositional property. What we cannot do is regard the probability as a property of a single experiment as Popper suggests when he says that the main point of a change to the propensity interpretation of probability is: that we now take as fundamental the probability of the result of a single experiment. 11 Perhaps Popper was led into this inconsistency by the solution he had in mind for problems concerning probabilities in the quantum theory. However, he often returns to his former manner of speaking of probabilities as dispositional properties of objects, or arrangements of objects. It is unclear to me what advantage this dispositional manner of speaking has, except perhaps that, as Peirce’s phrasing reveals, it allows subjunctive conditionals—and hence perhaps an element of necessity —to be introduced into a frequency analysis. Having rejected both of these accounts Mellor puts forward his own. It makes use of neither tendencies nor frequencies. He holds that if an object has a disposition to become G in circumstances F, then if ever it gets into circumstances F it will become G. Therefore he argues that if there is a chance of 1/6 of the falling of a die having as outcome the turning up of a five then the die is not disposed to turn up five when it falls: it is disposed to take up a chance of 1/6 that it will turn up, or perhaps has turned up, five. The analogue of the breaking of a glass when dropped is the establishment of a certain chance of turning up five of a die when dropped. That is—although Mellor never puts it like this because he has appropriated the word “result” to mean “noninvariable result”—just as the result of dropping a glass is its breaking, so the result of dropping a die is the establishment of a certain chance of five turning up. I cannot resist the comment that it is rather disingenuous of Mellor to claim that by this account the chance of a trial having a certain result is analysed in terms of a feature of a more familiar kind, namely a dispositional property of a persisting physical entity (Sect, 4). It is disingenuous because the disposition is a disposition to take up a certain chance of that result, and that latter chance remains quite unexplained. However, there is a more serious fault in Mellor’s view than that. Since Mellor analogizes the coming into 12 being of a certain chance of a result with the breaking of a glass he cannot maintain his view that a chance of 1/n of turning up five is “not a property that can be ascribed to an event without taking it to be the outcome of a trial”. Breaking is an event which can be ascribed to a glass without ascribing it as a result of dropping, or knocking, and so a chance of 1/n of turning up five, since it is now regarded as a state which a die comes to be in when it is dropped, can be ascribed to a die without mentioning dropping, or any trial. In short, Mellor analyses “There is a chance of 1/6 that the trial of dropping this die will have the result of turning up five” as “This die is so disposed that when it is dropped it takes up a chance of 1/6 of turning up five”. It is valid to argue from this chance together with the additional premise that this die has been dropped to the conclusion that it has taken up the chance of 1/6 of turning up five. The conclusion of this argument is an ascription of a chance to an event which does not take it to be the outcome of any trial. This inconsistency is a serious matter, for it is the relative concept of chance with which Mellor began that is involved in the chances which are expressed by the statistical hypotheses in which he is primarily interested. It is relative chances with which the probability calculi enable us to reason, and Mellor employs the classical calculus in his arguments in Section 2. It is true that it is non-relative chances which would provide an objective state of affairs on which to base a bet. Mellor argues the opposite but he is mistaken. When a person bets that horse A will win a race he enters into an agreement. It might for example be one according to which if the race is run and A wins he will receive a sum of money, if the race is run and A loses he will pay out a sum of money, and if the race is not run no financial transatlantic will take place. What he has to decide in order to place his bet is the conditional “If the race were run, would A win?“ Now the probability that if the race were run A would win is not the same as the probability of A’s winning on the race being run. If it were, then the fact that the 13 probability of A’s winning on the race being run differed from the probability of A’s winning on the race being run in the rain would imply that the race was not run in the rain. The whole point of the “on” or “with respect to” phrasing is to express probabilities that do not allow detachment. There seem to be other strong objections to Mellor’s dispositional analysis of the chance of a trial’s having a certain result. If chances can be properties of objects which arise from doing certain things to them, it must be possible that they should be causally related to other properties of objects. In particular, since they do not logically imply the possession of the property whose chance they are, they might be causally related to the possession of that property. Yet could it be that the chance of 1/6 which this die has of turning up five could cause the die to turn up five? This must be a logical possibility on Mellor’s view, but it scarcely seems to be one. 14