ARE CAUSES EVENTS OR FACTS? By John Watling In the collection of lectures edited by Lawrence Foster and J. W. Swanson entitled Experience and Theory there is one in which Donald Davidson proposes a solution to the problem of reconciling determinism with the freedom of the mind. The novelty and, I think, the implausibility of his reconciliation prevented me, for a while, from grasping what it was. I have certainly heard it maintained that antipathy to an opinion stated can prevent someone grasping the statement of the opinion. Such a possibility itself presents a problem concerning causation, although not, I suppose, a really fundamental one. Once I had grasped Davidson’s reconciliation I felt that its implausibility provided a strong argument against the conjunction of its premisses. I suspected one of them, that causes and effects are events, and was led to reflect further upon it. My reflections were undoubtedly influenced by an unpublished paper on the subject which I heard Peter Downing read some years ago. Davidson sets out the contradiction he intends to dispel by stating three principles which seem to form an inconsistent triad but each of which he believes to be true. First, some mental events interact causally with physical events. For example, (p. 8o), “if a man perceives that a ship is approaching, then a ship approaching must have caused him to come to believe that a ship is approaching.” Second, (p. 8o —81), “where there is causality, there must be a law; events related as cause and effect fall under strict deterministic laws.” Third, (p. 81), “there are no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and explained.” These three principles appear to form an inconsistent triad because it seems that mental events cannot fall under strict deterministic laws, as the first two principles require, if, according to the third principle, there are no deterministic laws on the basis of which they can be explained and predicted. Davidson’s reconciliation consists of an argument that they can and do. I will consider his reasons in a moment, but before I do so I want to point out that the existence of this possibility is not sufficient to reconcile the first and third principles. Of course, it is the inconsistency of these which constitutes the paradox; the second principle is no more than Davidson’s explanation of the inconsistency of the other two. It is an inadequate explanation and it enables him to conceal from us that the first principle has a stronger implication, relevant to the third, than that mental events fall under strict deterministic laws. The first principle has the further implication that those deterministic laws imply that the mental events which fall under them are causes of other events and effects of other events. Consider, as an example, an entirely physical event, the acceleration of a car. Let us suppose the acceleration to be jerky and the universal joints in the drive shafts of the car to be worn. Let us further 1 suppose that there is a law according to which wear in the drive shaft universal joints is a sufficient condition of jerkiness in acceleration. We have supposed that the car’s acceleration falls under a strict deterministic law, yet we have supposed nothing which implies that it was itself an effect. The wear in the universal joints did not cause the acceleration of the car. It follows that, even if Davidson can show that it is possible for mental events to fall under strict deterministic laws and yet for there to be no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which they can be predicted and explained, he will not have reconciled principles one and three. To do that he must show that it is possible for mental events to fall under strict deterministic laws which imply that they are causes and effects of other events and yet for there to be no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which they can be explained and predicted. That is obviously a more difficult matter. Davidson’s proposed reconciliation rests upon two premisses: one, that it is events which are causes and effects, the other, that it is the exemplification of kinds of event which is explained and predicted. If these premisses were true, then there would exist the possibility that an event of a certain mental kind could fall under a strict deterministic law although there existed no laws allowing the exemplification of such kinds of event to he explained or predicted. The possibility would exist because the event of a certain mental kind might have non-mental properties which bring it under a strict deterministic law. If, for example, it had physical properties, as Davidson believes every mental event has, then those properties might bring it under the strict deterministic laws of physics. Even if those two premisses were true, the reconciliation would fail unless it could be shown that the laws of physics under which mental events fall do constitute them causes and effects of other events. Can that be shown? First of all, it seems doubtful whether showing that particulars of some kind fall under a law could ever show that they were effects, however much it might show that they were affected. Wax candles fall under the law that as they get hotter they get softer, hut that does not imply that candles are causes or effects. No doubt that points to one reason why those who take particulars to be causes and effects choose events rather than physical objects. However, neither the heating nor the softening of the candle falls under the law that as the candle gets hotter it gets softer. At least, I think not but I am not certain of it, and I will return to a related question later. Laws under which the heating and softening certainly fall, for example that the slower the heating the more uniform the softening, do not imply, as we saw in the similar example of the car’s acceleration, that the heating causes the softening. Second, even if the laws of physics would imply, of some events which fell under them, that they were causes and effects, would that implication hold for a mental event that happened to fall under them? Davidson treats the mental properties of events which have both mental and physical properties 2 as if they were convenient for reference but of no great importance. Certainly, if I believed that the important properties of an event which had happened near me were governed by a law, I would accept that the event had a cause even if I did not believe that any law governed its place of occurrence. Davidson adopts precisely that attitude towards the mental properties of an event with both mental and physical properties. I might say that the event which happened near me just now had a cause, although nothing caused it to happen near me. Davidson would say of an event with mental and physical properties that it had a cause although no strict law allowed its mental properties to be predicted or explained. Evidently he does so without justification. How can it be right to treat the mental properties of events as if they were merely convenient marks for reference? What is more, suppose that two people both believe that a certain event has both physical and mental properties, both believe that the physical properties are governed by law and the mental properties not, but that, while one of them is impressed by the physical properties to the neglect of the mental ones, the other is impressed with the mental properties and finds the physical ones of little account. The materialist, I suggest, would take the event to be caused, to be, in fact, a physical event with accidental mental properties. The mentalist would take it, with equal justification, to be uncaused, to be a mental event with some law-governed physical properties. If effects are events, then it cannot be that they are both right; yet one is as right as the other. Surely a view which gives rise to such an unreal dispute should be abandoned, but, even if it is not, there is no reason to accept that the demonstration that the physical properties of mental events are governed by laws would establish that those events have causes. I should point out that Davidson does not rest his reconciliation upon any materialist denigration of mental properties other than that they are never exemplified except in conjunction with physical properties. It would indeed be interesting to consider whether there is a stronger form of subservience which would enable Davidson to conclude that mental events are caused while still preserving the non-predictability and non-explicability of the mental, but it would take me too far from the subject of causes and effects. I conclude that Davidson’s two premisses do not reconcile the first principle with the third. However, even if they had done so, they would not have reconciled the freedom of the mental with the proposition concerning physical and mental interaction which he wishes to accept and which I quoted at the beginning of this paper. They would not have because that proposition does not concern the causation of a particular. To show that a ship, or a ship’s approaching, might have caused the mental event of his coming to believe that a ship was approaching without there being any possibility of predicting, from the approach of the ship, that he would come to believe this shows nothing more than that the assertion that a ship’s approaching caused him to believe that a ship is approaching does not 3 assert, or does not merely assert, that the ship’s approaching caused a mental event. Davidson’s assumption that his first principle embodies the causal beliefs concerning the mental which he wishes to accept is no better founded than the assumption that ‘Something caused the explosion which happened near me’ implies ‘Something caused the explosion to happen near me’. He should, at least, have admitted the distinction between such propositions and proceeded to attempt to explain both propositions in terms of the causation of particulars. I admit the existence of both forms of speaking but contend that that in which particulars figure as effects cannot be regarded as fundamental, or be quite freed from difficulties of interpretation. That I shall proceed to show. When a tree in leaf casts a deep shadow, it is perhaps true that the tree, a particular, is a cause and has an effect. No-one who supposes so could suppose that the tree would have had the same effect had it not been in leaf. Therefore, if a particular has effects, it does so because of the properties it has, or because of some of them, and because of the relationships in which facts concerning what properties the particular has stand to other facts. Such a relationship might be that, because the tree is in leaf, there is a deep shadow at a certain place. If it is possible for particulars to be causes, then a particular will be a cause if, and only if, because some fact concerning it is a fact, some other fact, not entailed by that one, is a fact. If particulars can be causes, then it must also be possible for particulars to be effects: otherwise, those which were causes would form a class of causes which could not possibly themselves be caused. Evidently, it is not true that if, because one fact is a fact, another fact, not entailed by that one and which concerns a particular, is a fact, that particular is an effect. It might be that, because a glasshouse had been built round it, a deciduous tree was in leaf during the winter. That would not imply that the tree was an effect of the glass-house, although it would imply that the glass-house had an effect upon it. To be an effect, a particular must be caused to exist, that is, produced or created, by some cause. It might be held that particulars are never created, that when we speak of the creation of a particular we should, to be correct, speak of the creation of at least one particular of a certain kind. This seems to have been Aristotle’s opinion in Book VII, Chapter 8 of the Metaphysics: “Obviously then the form also, or whatever we ought to call the shape present in the sensible thing, is not produced, nor is there any production of it, nor is the essence produced; for this is that which is made to be something else either by art or by nature or by some faculty. But that there is a brazen sphere, this we make.” (Ross’s translation, O.U.P.) If Aristotle’s opinion were correct, then the requirement that, to be an effect, a particular must be created, would have the consequence that no particular could be an effect. To speak of a particular brazen sphere as an effect would be to speak of that brazen sphere as created, which, in its turn, would he to speak of the effect that there is a brazen sphere, an effect which is not a particular 4 at all. However, I do not think that Aristotle’s opinion is correct. There is a distinction between the creation of a particular and the creation of at least one particular of a certain kind. If you make someone into a mathematician, then you create a mathematician, but you do not create a particular: you do not create the mathematician you made into a mathematician. What account can be given of the creation of particulars? When we speak of the creation of a particular by a craftsman or an artist, we do not imply that every one of its properties has been determined by him. No doubt certain properties of the particular strike us as important and we regard the craftsman or artist as its creator if he was responsible for those. If, in our eyes, the most notable feature of a brazen sphere is the delicate tracery upon its surface, we shall not regard the man who made the brass round as the maker of the brazen sphere. If, in our eyes, the most notable feature of a pebble we have found on the shore is the shape into which the waves have ground it, the discovery, perhaps from its material constitution, that it was the stopper of a bottle would not lead us to regard it as man made. When we speak of the creation of a particular, someone who wishes to understand us must guess at what properties we find most notable in it, just as in understanding metaphorical language a guess or interpretation is required before the intended meaning can be reached. The situation is no different when we speak of the production of a particular by natural means. The difficulty can be avoided, and a single relation of creation obtained, only by adopting the implausible definition that a particular is a creation, and hence the effect, of a cause if, and only if, because some fact concerning that cause is a fact, every fact concerning that particular is a fact. That implausible definition is required also if the possibility that particulars are causes and effects is to be squared with the transitivity, or at least a form of it, which holds for cause-and effect. If a cause has an effect and that effect, in its turn, a further effect, then the original cause is indirectly responsible for the final effect. If a particular could have another particular as its effect without determining all its properties, then, if the further effects of that effect arose from properties which the original cause had not determined, that original cause would not be responsible, even indirectly, for the final effect. The relationship at which we have arrived might, I think, hold between particulars. Probably people have sometimes supposed that every fact concerning one particular is determined by facts concerning just one other particular. Perhaps those who advanced the theory that the present state of the universe is a consequence of a single explosion suppose that innumerable particulars stand in this relationship to the original explosion. Perhaps particulars which were so related might plausibly be termed cause and effect. However that might be, it is certain that such a relationship is not the only relationship of cause and effect, nor the most fundamental one. 5 For one thing, what account could be given, converse to my account of causation between particulars, in terms of determination between facts, of determination between facts in terms of causation between particulars? For causation between particulars is a much less specific relation than determination between facts. It is useful, for example, to be able to identify the object lens of a telescope as the common cause of two faults in the instrument, unwanted colour and lack of definition of the image, although it would be more natural to speak of the cause of each fault lying in the object lens rather than being the object lens, but it would be a grave disability to be unable to go further and distinguish the cause of one fault from the cause of the other. If a particular can be found which is the cause of one but not of the other, then the view that it is particulars which are causes ascribes both a common cause and different causes to the two effects. If no particular can be found, then the very important fact which we would express by saying that they have different causes is, on that view, no fact at all. Even if the particulars which are causes and effects are events or states rather than physical objects, it may not be possible to make all the causal distinctions we wish. It has been suggested that there cannot be two events occurring at the same time and place. If there cannot, and if it is events which are causes and effects, then it may not be possible to distinguish what is an effect of a cause, for instance the acceleration of a body at one time, from what is not, for instance the velocity of the body at the same time. If we are to accept that a relationship between particulars is the most fundamental relationship of cause and effect, then we cannot regard the relation of causing to exist as involving a more general relation of causation: we must identify ‘causes’ with ‘causes to exist’. If we do so, what sense are we to make of the innumerable other relationships in which, it seems, causation is involved? For we speak not only of particulars being caused to exist, but also of their being caused to turn colour, to harden, to exist no longer. It seems more natural to suppose that causation enters into each of these relations in the same way than to choose one of them and try to see it as a common factor in each of the others. What is more, although it may seem possible to construe each of the others as the creation of a particular—not, of course, the particular which was caused to change colour or exist no longer hut another particular, invented for the purpose—that is not in fact possible. ‘It was caused to turn colour’ cannot be interpreted as ‘Its turn of colour was caused to exist or to occur’ because that implies that, due to some cause, all facts concerning its turn of colour were facts and the facts concerning its turn of colour do not comprise the fact that it turned colour alone. No doubt when we ask what caused the disappearance of the rainbow we are asking what caused the rainbow to disappear, but that shows only that what is phrased to suggest a question concerning the causation of a particular is not such a question at all. It cannot be that to cause and to cause to exist are the very same. Consequently, to establish that it is 6 particulars which arc caused to exist, or caused to occur, is to establish that it is not particulars which are caused. If events are particulars, then it is not events which are, in the fundamental sense, causes and effects. One of the premisses of the foregoing argument—the premiss that, to be an effect, a particular must be produced or created—is, I think, a consequence of a more general truth concerning individuals of all types and which holds for facts no less than for particulars. Of course, no argument parallel to the foregoing could rule out facts as causes and effects. Part of the attraction of facts as candidates for these roles is that they would set no limits to the fineness of our causal distinctions, nor compel us to admit a more fundamental relation which did not have facts as its terms. Nevertheless, from the more general premiss it is a very short step to the conclusion that facts, too, must be dismissed. Just as with the creation of mathematicians, we must distinguish between bringing it about that a certain fact exists and bringing it about that that fact is a fact. A cause can do the latter, but no cause can do the former. Some thing may cause a cup to break but nothing can create the fact that the cup is broken: that fact is a possibility which no cause can bring into existence. Since, to be an effect, a fact must be produced or created, no fact can be an effect. It is absurd to hold that individuals which cannot possibly be effects can be causes, so it is not facts, any more than events, which are causes and effects. Since, I take it, there is a dichotomy amongst individuals between those of logical type, such as facts, and those of non-logical type, particulars, there seems to be no escape from the conclusion that causes and effects are not individuals at all. There is no doubt that that conclusion is, in some ways, a paradoxical one. If it is correct, then causes cannot, strictly speaking, he described in any way. It cannot even be that they hold, obtain, or operate. I can see no way of removing that paradox. Again, if it is correct, causation cannot be a relation between causes and effects. However, that paradox cannot be avoided by supposing causes and effects to be individuals. The relationship which holds when something is produced by a cause— that I contend that, if effects are individuals, it must be that they are produced or created by causes—would have held even if the cause had not existed, or had not had the properties it did have. It might have held, therefore, even if the effect had not existed and it cannot be that the cause and the effect are its terms. Had the effect not existed, the relationship could only have been expressed in such words as ‘If the cause had existed, or if it had had properties it did not have, the effect would have existed’. The difficulty of interpreting such a sentence on the assumption that effects are individuals provides another argument against that assumption. It is, indeed, obvious that a great deal of our knowledge of causal relationships is useful to us just because it enables us to avoid effects we find undesirable, because it enables us not to bring it about that certain possibilities arc realised. Causal relationships can 7 certainly have particulars as terms, although those terms will be neither causes nor effects: presumably the earth and the sun stand in a causal relationship, since when the sun moves the earth is caused to move. However, causal relationships concerning the existence and non-existence of particulars of certain kinds can only be regarded as standing between possibilities. Of course, just as before, those possibilities are not causes or effects. In other ways the conclusion is a natural one. To give the causes of any effect we must discover that certain facts are facts and state that they are. Naming individuals is of no use, whether they be particulars or facts. We must do this merely to present the causes. To state, further, that they are the causes, we must assert a proposition with the general form of ‘The tree came into leaf with the effect that its shadow deepened’. I am inclined, therefore, to accept that causes and effects are not individuals of any type and so, to the question which forms the title of this paper, in the words of John Stuart Mill, I answer ‘No’. 8