{Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d Economica (2003) 70, 405–422 The Malleability of Undiscounted Utilitarianism as a Criterion of Intergenerational Justice By GEIR B. ASHEIM{ and WOLFGANG BUCHHOLZ{ { University of Oslo { University of Regensburg Final version received 9 January 2002. Discounting future utilities is often justified by the ethically motivated objective of protecting earlier generations from the excessive saving that seems to be implied by undiscounted utilitarianism in productive economies. We question this justification of discounting by showing that undiscounted utilitarianism has sufficient malleability within important classes of technologies: any efficient and non-decreasing allocation can be the unique optimum according to an undiscounted utilitarian criterion for some choice of utility function. INTRODUCTION In the theory of economic growth it is quite common to determine optimal growth programmes by means of a discounted utilitarian criterion, where the positive discount rate reflects pure time preference. Future utilities of consumption measured on a cardinal scale are transformed, through discounting, into present values, the sum of which one seeks to maximize. Thus, discounted utilitarianism provides a class of objective functions that are often used for evaluating intertemporal choice. Even though discounting has sometimes been considered as ‘irrational’ in the context of individual decision-making, such impatience has still been accepted as a natural part of exogenously given individual preferences. However, when discounting refers to future generations, some fundamental ethical problems seem to arise. In the case of intergenerational discounting, it is natural to question whether it is fair to value the utility of future generations less than that of the present one. This criticism against discounting has a long tradition in economics, dating back at least to Pigou (1932). It was revitalized in the ongoing debate on sustainable development, which — it is sometimes claimed —is in danger when discounting is applied. The proponents of intergenerational discounting, however, also turn to ethical reflections when they try to justify this procedure. Thus, it appears that a deep ethical conflict is present in the debate of the discounting issue. It is the aim of this paper to evaluate the use of discounting in utilitarian social criteria for choice between intergenerational allocations. As a first step, we retrace the ethical arguments of the opponents and the proponents of intergenerational discounting. As a second step, we show that this debate might be considered misplaced, as there is not much room for a serious controversy on the discounting question. In particular, in important classes of technologies the undiscounted utilitarian criterion is sufficiently malleable to avoid excessive saving and thus allow for the choices that proponents of intergenerational discounting seek to implement by discounting future utilities. # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 406 [AUGUST ECONOMICA I. INTERGENERATIONAL DISCOUNTING AS AN ETHICAL PROBLEM The position of the opponents of intergenerational discounting is based primarily on the view that it is not a priori justified to give different generations unequal weight in social evaluations as they do not seem to be fundamentally different, at least if population size is constant and there is no uncertainty. The only obvious distinction between members of different generations is that they do not appear simultaneously on the time axis, which, however, does not provide an ethically compelling reason for unequal treatment. If, under otherwise identical circumstances, welfare comparisons are to be made in a static context with a finite number of agents living within the same generation, one would usually not deny that equal individuals should get equal consideration in social welfare functions. Therefore, it is quite standard in welfare economics to adopt an anonymity principle by which discrimination against particular agents is excluded. However, discounting seems questionable not only from its normative basis but also from its consequences under certain technological assumptions. For example, when the level of production depends not only on man-made capital and labour, but also on the input of an exhaustible natural resource (like oil), applying a discounted utilitarian criterion for any time-invariant and strictly positive discount rate will, in the long run, force the consumption level to approach zero, even though positive and non-decreasing consumption is technically feasible. Thus, in such a Dasgupta – Heal –Solow technology, constant and positive utility discounting leads to an outcome that does not appeal to commonly shared ethical intuitions, and is not compatible with sustainable development —i.e. with no generation enjoying a level of well-being that cannot be shared by future generations. As appealing as these ethically motivated arguments against intergenerational discounting may look, there are also important arguments in favour of the position of the proponents of discounting. The first of these arguments is of a technical nature. If the world does not come to its end at some predetermined date, it is an ethical imperative to take all future generations into consideration, which is well in line with the advocates of sustainability. But it is just the fact that the number of generations are modelled to be infinite that creates specific problems in making welfare comparisons. In the infinite case, the existence of a socially most preferred intergenerational allocation cannot be ensured in the same way as is usually done in the finite case, where the Weierstrass theorem easily applies. This theorem says that on a compact domain a continuous real valued function will have at least one maximum. In the finite case, not very demanding assumptions are needed to ensure that the premisses of this theorem hold so that the existence of maximal elements is ensured. In the infinite case, however, it is not possible— under relevant technological assumptions —to find a topology that leads to compactness of the set of feasible allocations and, at the same time, to a continuity of social preferences that are sensitive to the interest of each generation and treat all generations equally (cf. Koopmans 1960; Diamond 1965; Svensson 1980; and, for a general discussion, Lauwers 1997). Sensitivity here refers to the ‘Strong Pareto’ axiom (which we will also call ‘Efficiency’), meaning that social preferences must deem one allocation superior to another # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM 407 if at least one generation is better off and no generation is worse off; while equal treatment refers to the ‘Weak anonymity’ axiom (which we will also call ‘Equity’), meaning that social preferences must leave the social valuation of an allocation unchanged when the consumption levels of any two generations along the allocation are permuted. That this way of establishing existence cannot be generalized to the infinite case if ‘Equity’ is postulated explains some of the scepticism people have with this normative precept in the infinite number case. From such a perspective, adhering to this axiom may seem rather pointless if it is difficult to make use of it. The second argument, however— for the widespread refusal of the ‘Equity’ axiom in the intergenerational context — flows from ethical reservations. It is claimed that, even if future consumption is perfectly certain to be realized, equal treatment is in conflict with finding an acceptable balance between the interests of different generations. In particular, it is often suggested that the application of undiscounted utilitarianism leads to a distributional imbalance by impairing the earlier generations to an unacceptable degree. For example, Rawls (1971, p. 287) argues that ‘the utilitarian doctrine may direct us to demand heavy sacrifices of the poorer generations for the sake of greater advantages for the later ones that are far better off’; while Dasgupta and Mäler (1995, p. 2395) refer to calculations by Mirrlees (1967) and Chakravarty (1969) showing, in plausible economic models, that the present generation would be asked to save and invest around 50% of GNP under undiscounted utilitarianism. Thus, with a very productive economy, the danger exists that maximizing the sum of undiscounted utilities will lead to a growth pattern that requires high savings rates initially and thereby imposes excessive hardships on earlier generations. Following such arguments, Rawls (1971, p. 297) reluctantly points out that ‘[t]his consequence can be to some degree corrected by discounting the welfare of those living in the future’; and Arrow (1999, p. 16) concludes that ‘the strong ethical requirement that all generations be treated alike, itself reasonable, contradicts a very strong intuition that it is not morally acceptable to demand excessively high savings rates of any one generation, or even of every generation’. To avoid consumption patterns that are too much to the disadvantage of earlier generations, the incorporation of a positive discount rate into the utilitarian criterion is thus considered inevitable even in the case of certainty. Put another way, this justification of utility discounting entails that discounting is required not only in order to be able to make any choices at all, but also to ensure that the chosen distributions are ethically acceptable. The first of these arguments —the problem of existence when the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ are imposed— has been considered in a previous work (Asheim et al. 2001). There we show that the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ are not incompatible with the existence of maximal allocations, given that one considers technologies that are productive in the sense of satisfying the following two conditions: ‘Immediate productivity’, which means that there are negative transfer costs from the present to the future if the future is worse off than the present, and ‘Eventual productivity’, which means that there exist efficient and completely egalitarian allocations. In fact, we show that any efficient and non-decreasing allocation is maximal if the social preferences over infinite intergenerational allocations are generated by the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’. # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 408 ECONOMICA [AUGUST In the present paper we consider the second of these arguments. We show that (i) under a general assumption undiscounted utilitarianism is so flexible that any efficient and non-decreasing allocation can be the unique optimal intergenerational allocation under the utilitarian criterion, provided that the utility function is appropriately chosen, and that (ii) this assumption is satisfied within three important classes of productive technologies. This means that, for any member of these classes of technology, any outcome consistent with ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ can be realized under undiscounted utilitarianism. Hence the problem with undiscounted utilitarianism is neither that it does not allow for optimal allocations, nor that it leads to unequal distributions imposing a too heavy burden on the present generation. Rather, the problem is that, as a class of orderings, it does not limit the set of optimal allocations more than the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ do. Thus, undiscounted utilitarianism has no bite beyond these axioms. Throughout, the well-being of any generation will be measured by a onedimensional indicator, ‘consumption’, which comprises everything that affects a generation’s livelihood. It is appropriate to think of ‘consumption’ as the money metric utility that a generation derives from the goods and services at its disposal, with the money metric utility function being identical for all generations. Even though we prove as our main result that any efficient and non-decreasing allocation is compatible with zero utility discounting, the underlying assumption requires that any such allocation is characterized by a positive consumption interest rate that cannot decrease too rapidly. Our analysis is therefore not an argument against positive discounting in social cost – benefit analysis, even for decisions relating to long-term environmental policy (e.g. controlling the greenhouse effect). However, the consumption interest rate —which will reflect net capital productivity— will be of a magnitude, and have a time structure,1 such that the decisions taken will not undermine the livelihood of future generations. In the analysis of the present paper there is no uncertainty about whether future consumption will be realized. Hence, u is not a von Neumann – Morgenstern utility function, where the corresponding concavity would be an expression of risk aversion. Rather, the concavity of the utility function u represents the aversion in social evaluation towards inequality between generations. The concerns about the unfavourable consequences for the earlier generations of using undiscounted utilitarianism can be seen as an expression of inequality aversion. It seems appropriate therefore to respond to these concerns by making the utility function more concave. If risk and uncertainty were introduced into our analysis, it would still be appropriate in principle to distinguish between inequality aversion and risk aversion (cf. Kreps and Porteus 1979), although this is not often done in practical applications. Furthermore, even if one follows Harsanyi (1953) in arguing that undiscounted utilitarianism derives its justification from hypothetical decisions under uncertainty in the original position, the risk aversion in his setting relates to decision problems that are not faced by actual decision-makers. We therefore claim that the concavity of the utility function u in the undiscounted utilitarian criterion is not observable in a market economy. # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM 409 The paper is organized as follows. Section II contains a simple numerical illustration, while Section III presents the main result. Section IV shows that the assumption underlying this result is satisfied in the three classes of technologies that we explicitly consider. Section V contains a discussion of the results, while analysis of more technical nature is included in the two appendices. II. A NUMERICAL ILLUSTRATION The main argument presented in this paper is that, within certain classes of technology, any efficient and non-decreasing allocation can be realized under undiscounted utilitarianism for some choice of utility function. We now illustrate this possibility within a simple setting where there are only two generations. Let c1 and c2 denote consumption (or well-being) of generations 1 and 2, and let the set of feasible allocations be given by (c1 ; c2 ) 0 is feasible if and only if c1 þ 14 c2 ˘ 2: This linear technology implies that the net capital productivity equals 3 (¼ 4 1). Let u be the time-invariant utility function, and let (2 (0; 1]) be the discount factor. This means that the utility discount rate equals 1= 1. An allocation (c 01 ; c 02 ) is a utilitarian optimum if and only if (c 01 ; c 02 ) solves max c1 0; c2 0 u(c1 ) þ u(c2 ) s:t: c1 þ 14 c2 ˘ 2: This means that, if (c 01 ; c 02 ) 0, then (c 01 ; c 02 ) satisfies u 0 (c 01 ) ¼ 4u 0 (c 02 ). We can now verify that (c 01 ; c 02 ) ¼ (1; 4) is a utilitarian optimum under both of the following constellations of utility function and discount factor: u(c) ¼ c 1=2 and ¼ 1=2 u(c) ¼ ln c and ¼ 1: This illustrates how a more concave utility function can substitute for discounting along an allocation where consumption is strictly increasing. III. MAIN RESULT In a general setting, assume that consumption ct in period t ¼ 0; 1; 2; ::: is onedimensional. Write 0 c ¼ (c0 ; c1 ; :::) and correspondingly for other sequences. Refer to 0 c as an allocation. An allocation 0 c is said to be non-decreasing if ct þ 1 ct for all t 0 and stationary if ct þ 1 ¼ ct for all t 0. Given a set of feasible allocations, a feasible allocation 0 c ¼ (c0 ; c1 ; :::) is said to be efficient if there exists no alternative feasible allocation 0 c 0 ¼ (c 00 ; c 01 ; :::) with c 0t ct for all t 0, with strict inequality for some t. One problem when applying the undiscounted utilitarianism to a situation with an infinite number of generations is that the sum of undiscounted utilities will generally diverge in the infinite-horizon case. To resolve this, we invoke an ‘overtaking’ criterion, under which one allocation is better than another if, as T goes to infinity, the lim inf of the sum up to time T of the difference between # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 410 ECONOMICA [AUGUST the utilities generated by the allocations is positive: (P) 0c 0 Pu0 c 00 u lim inf T21 T X (u(c 0t ) u(c 00t )) > 0: t¼0 We will use this criterion to show how, under a given technological assumption, any efficient and non-decreasing allocation is the unique optimum according to undiscounted utilitarianism for some choice of utility function. The technological assumption —which as shown in Section IV is satisfied for any member of three important classes of technologies — is the following. Assumption 1. If a feasible allocation 0 c ¼ (c0 ; c1 ; :::) is efficient and nondecreasing, then there exists a sequence of consumption discount factors 0 p ¼ (p0 ; p1 ; :::) satisfying 0 < pt þ 1 < pt for all t 0 such that 1> 1 X pt c t t¼0 1 X pt c 0t t¼0 for any feasible allocation 0 c 0 ¼ (c 00 ; c 01 ; :::). We can now state the main result of this paper. Proposition 1. Under Assumption 1, if a feasible allocation 0 c ¼ (c0 ; c1 ; :::) is efficient and non-decreasing, then there exists a continuous, concave and nondecreasing utility function u: Rþ 2 R such that 0 cPu0 c 0 for any feasible allocation 0 c 0 ¼ (c 00 ; c 01 ; :::) that does not coincide with 0 c. Proof. By Assumption 1, there exists a sequence of consumption discount factors p1 ; :::) satisfying 0 < pt þ 1 < pt for all t 0 such that P 0 p ¼ (p0 ; P 1 0 0 1> 1 p c t t t¼0 t ¼ 0 pt c t for any feasible allocation 0 c . Construct a continuous, concave and non-decreasing utility function u as follows. Let u0 2 (p0 ; 1) and ut 2 (pt ; pt 1 ) for t 1: If 0 ˘ c < sup{ct j t 2 N}, write t c :¼ min{t 2 N j ct c}, and let u(c) ¼ tc X ut (ct ct 1 ) ut c (ct c c); t¼0 where c1 :¼ 0. Note that u is a piecewise-linear, continuous and concave function, with u(0) ¼ 0 and with the slope on each linear segment (ct ; ct þ 1 ) lying strictly between pt þ 1 and pt . If sup{ct j t 2 N} ¼ 1, then u has been constructed. Otherwise, write Zc :¼ sup{ct j t 2 N}. Since u is continuous and non-decreasing on [0; c), limc 9 Zc u(c) exists; write Yu :¼ limc 9 c u(c). Complete the construction of u by setting u(c) ¼ u for c sup{ct j t 2 N}. Note that u is constructed so that, for each t 0, u(ct ) pt ct u(c) pt c # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM 411 for any c 0, with the inequality being strict if c 6¼ ct . This implies that lim infT 2 1 T X t¼0 (u(ct ) u(c 0t )) 1 X pt (ct c 0t ) 0 t¼0 for any feasible allocation 0 c 0 , where the first inequality is strict if 0 c 6¼ 0 c 0 and the second inequality follows from Assumption 1. This means that 0 cPu0 c 0 if 0 & 0 c 6¼ 0 c . The construction of the continuous and piecewise-linear utility function u is shown in Figure 1, thereby illustrating the proof of Proposition 1. An extension of the preceding analysis shows that a differentiable utility function can be obtained if and only if 0 c is strictly increasing. As illustrated by the figure, the utility function may have to be chosen such that marginal utility is zero beyond some consumption level. If so, undiscounted utilitarianism will not satisfy the axiom of ‘Efficiency’ (or ‘Strong Pareto’; cf. Section I) unless some amendment is introduced. In Appendix A we show how an extended undiscounted utilitarian criterion can be constructed, having the properties that it 1. yields a (strict) preference for 0 c 0 over 0 c 00 whenever 0 c 0 Pu0 c 00 , 2. is complete in the sense of deeming two allocations indifferent whenever there is not a (strict) preference, and 3. satisfies the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’. Note that the first property means that Proposition 1 holds if such an extended undiscounted utilitarian criterion is substituted for Pu as defined by (P). FIGURE 1. Illustration of the proof of Proposition 1. # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 412 ECONOMICA IV. HOW STRONG IS [AUGUST ASSUMPTION 1? Assumption 1 provides a general condition that, if fulfilled, yields a justification for applying undiscounted utilitarianism. In this section we illustrate the generality of Assumption 1 by considering three standard classes of technology. We show that any technology within these classes satisfies Assumption 1. Hence, by invoking Proposition 1 this in turn implies that an arbitrary efficient and non-decreasing allocation for a given initial endowment in such a technology is the unique optimum according to undiscounted utilitarianism for an appropriate choice of utility function. We consider the classes of linear, Ramsey, and Dasgupta – Heal – Solow technologies. For the technologies of these classes we assume that gross output yt , available at the beginning of period t ¼ 0; 1; 2; :::, is onedimensional. Furthermore, kt denotes invested man-made capital, i.e. the gross output not consumed in period t. Any member of the three classes of technology satisfies the conditions of ‘Immediate productivity’ and ‘Eventual productivity’ (in the terminology of Asheim et al. 2001) under given assumptions. Immediate productivity means that, if 0 c ¼ (c0 ; c1 ; :::; ct ; ct þ 1 ; :::) is feasible and ct > ct þ 1 , then 0 c 0 ¼ (c0 ; c1 ; :::; ct þ 1 ; ct ; :::) is feasible and inefficient. Eventual productivity means that, for any initial endowment, there exists an efficient and stationary allocation 0 c ¼ (c; c; :::). For further comparison, one can associate ‘Immediate productivity’ with positive net capital productivity leading to decreasing consumption discount factors, and ‘Eventual productivity’ with the existence of an efficient and non-decreasing allocation having P ‘finite consumption value’ (i.e. 1 p t ¼ 0 t ct < 1). Only linear technologies explicitly incorporate technological progress. Technological progress corresponds to increasing net capital productivity and makes it easier to satisfy ‘Eventual productivity’. Dasgupta – Heal – Solow technologies illustrate the case where resource depletion plays an important role for future development and leads to decreasing net capital productivity. If production depends on inputs of depletable natural resources, Ramsey technologies can be seen to represent the case where technological progress just ‘makes up’ for diminishing resource availability, thus avoiding the decline in net capital productivity that would otherwise occur. We assume throughout that population is constant. With a non-constant population, and interpreting ct as per capita consumption, ‘Immediate productivity’ entails, in the context of linear and Ramsey technologies, that net capital productivity exceeds the rate of population growth. (a) Linear technologies A technology is linear if, in any period, the ratio of gross output and invested man-made capital is fixed and equal to at . On the other hand, this gross productivity factor can vary between periods. We assume positive net capital productivity, i.e.; (A1) at > 1 for all t > 0: # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM 413 This assumption means that the condition of ‘Immediate productivity’ is satisfied. Let the transformation set T 1t in period t be given by T 1t ¼ {(k; y) j 0 ˘ y ˘ at k}: Let y > 0 be the exogenously given endowment of output available at the beginning of period 0. A programme (0 y; 0 k) is said to be feasible given y if y0 ¼ y and kt ˘ yt (kt ; yt þ 1 ) 2 T 1t and for all t 0: An allocation 0 c is said to be feasible if there is a feasible programme (0 y; 0 k) such that ct ¼ yt kt for all t 0.2 A linear technology determines a unique sequence of consumption discount factors 0 p ¼ (p0 ; p1 ; :::) as follows: p0 ¼ 1 pt þ 1 at ¼ pt and for all t 0: Note that it holds, for all t 0, that 0 < pt þ 1 < pt since at > 1. It follows from Lemma 1 of Appendix B that the set of efficient and non-decreasing feasible allocations is non-empty if the following condition holds: (E1) 1 X pt < 1; t¼0 P since then the stationary allocation 0 c ¼ (c; c; :::) with c ¼ y=( 1 t ¼ 0 pt ) > 0 is feasible given y. If on the other hand (E1) does not hold, then this set is empty. This means that a linear technology satisfies ‘Eventual productivity’ if and only if (E1) is satisfied. An increasing sequence of gross productivity factors — i.e. 0 a ¼ (a0 ; a1 ; :::) satisfies at þ 1 > at for all t 0 —can be interpreted as exogeneous technological progress. Condition (E1) clearly holds if a0 > 1 and 0 a is non-decreasing. (b) Ramsey technologies A Ramsey technology (cf. Ramsey 1928) is determined by a stationary production function g : Rþ 2 Rþ that satisfies (A2) g is concave; continuous for k 0; and twice differentiable for k > 0; g(0) ¼ 0; g0 > 0 0 g (k) 2 1 g 0 (k) Y 0 for k > 0; as k Y 0; and as k 2 1: This assumption implies that the condition of ‘Immediate productivity’ is satisfied. Let the gross output function f be given by f(k) ¼ g(k) þ k for all k 0. The transformation set T 2 is time-invariant and is given by T 2 ¼ {(k; y) j 0 ˘ y ˘ f(k); k 0}: Let y > 0. A programme (0 y; 0 k) is said to be feasible given y if y0 ¼ y and kt ˘ yt and # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 (kt ; yt þ 1 ) 2 T 2 for all t 0: {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 414 ECONOMICA [AUGUST An allocation 0 c is said to be feasible if there is a feasible programme (0 y; 0 k) where 0 k is bounded above, such that ct ¼ yt kt for all t 0. That 0 k is bounded above means that, given 0 k, there exists Mk such that kt ˘ Mk for all t 0. This assumption is made in order to show in Lemma 2 that efficient and nondecreasing allocations have ‘finite consumption value’, and thereby enable Proposition 2 below to be established. All programmes promoted by proponents of discounted utilitarianism in Ramsey technologies are included, as under (A2) 0 k is bounded above in any discounted utilitarian optimum. The set of efficient and non-decreasing feasible allocations is non-empty, since the stationary allocation 0 c ¼ (c; c; :::), where c > 0 solves y ¼ f(y c), is feasible given y. Hence any Ramsey technology satisfies ‘Eventual productivity’. (c) Dasgupta – Heal –Solow technologies A Dasgupta –Heal – Solow technology (cf. Dasgupta and Heal 1974; Solow 1974) is determined by a stationary production function G : R 3þ 2 Rþ that satisfies (A3) G is concave, non-decreasing, homogeneous of degree 1 and continuous for (k; r; ‘) 0; G is twice differentiable and satisfies (Gk ; Gr ; G‘ ) 0 for (k; r; ‘) 0; G(k; 0; ‘) ¼ 0 ¼ G(0; r; ‘); and, given any (k 0 ; r 0 ) 0, there is 0 > 0 such that, for all (k; r) satisfying k k 0 , 0 < r ˘ r 0 , we have [rGr (k; r; 1)]= G‘ (k; r; 1) 0 This assumption implies that the condition of ‘Immediate productivity’ is satisfied. Note that both capital kt and resource extraction rt are essential in production. The available labour force is assumed to be stationary and equal to 1. Still, labour needs to be explicitly considered in order to state the latter part of (A3), namely that the ratio of the share of the resource in net output to the share of labour in net output is assumed to be bounded away from zero. Let the gross output function F be given by F(k; r) ¼ G(k; r; 1) þ k for all (k; r) 0. The transformation set T 3 is time-invariant and is given by T 3 ¼ {[(k; m); (y; m 0 ) j 0 ˘ y ˘ F(k; r); 0 ˘ r ¼ m m 0 ; (k; m 0 ) 0}: Let (y; m) 0, where m is the resource stock available at the beginning of period 0. A programme (0 y; 0 m; 0 k) is said to be feasible given (y; m) if y0 ¼ y and m0 ¼ m; kt ˘ yt and [(kt ; mt ); (yt þ 1 ; mt þ 1 )] 2 T 3 for all t 0: An allocation 0 c is said to be feasible if there is a feasible programme (0 y; 0 m; 0 k) such that ct ¼ yt kt for all t 0. Assumption (A3) does not ensure the existence of a stationary allocation with positive consumption. Therefore assume the following condition. (E3) There exists, given (y; m) 0, a feasible stationary allocation with positive consumption. Dasgupta and Mitra (1983) show, within the setting of Dasgupta– Heal – Solow technologies, that this implies the existence of an efficient and stationary # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM 415 allocation. This means that a Dasgupta –Heal –Solow technology satisfies ‘Eventual productivity’ and has a non-empty set of efficient and nondecreasing feasible allocations if (E3) holds. We state (E3) in its reduced form since it is outside the scope of the present paper to provide primitive technological conditions; instead we refer to Cass and Mitra (1991), who give necessary and sufficient conditions on the production function G for (E3) to hold. The importance of Dasgupta– Heal – Solow technologies in a discussion of intergenerational justice derives from the property that under (A3) net capital productivity Gk (k; r; 1) converges to zero along any efficient and nondecreasing allocation.3 This occurs in a stationary technology setting owing to the dwindling availability of the resource. (d) A characterization result for efficient and non-decreasing allocations Consider a member of the classes of linear, Ramsey or Dasgupta –Heal –Solow technologies. Assume (A1)– (A3). In Appendix B we prove that, if a feasible allocation 0 c ¼ (c0 ; c1 ; :::) is efficient and non-decreasing, there exists a sequence of consumption discount factors 0 p ¼ (p0 ; p1 ; :::) satisfying 0 < pt þ 1 < pt for all t 0 such that 1> 1 X t¼0 pt c t 1 X pt c 0t t¼0 for any feasible allocation 0 c 0 ¼ (c 00 ; c 01 ; :::). Proposition 2. Under (A1) –(A3), any linear, Ramsey or Dasgupta –Heal – Solow technology satisfies Assumption 1. V. DISCUSSION We have earlier (in Asheim et al. 2001) showed that the rather uncontroversial ethical axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ rule out any allocation that is not efficient and non-decreasing in technologies that satisfy the conditions of ‘Immediate productivity’ and ‘Eventual productivity’. All members of the three classes of technologies that we have considered in Section IV satisfy ‘Immediate productivity’ under the assumptions of (A1)–(A3), and they satisfy ‘Eventual productivity’ provided that (E1) and (E3) are satisfied. Hence, ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ alone rule out any allocation that is not efficient and non-decreasing. Here we have showed that, within these classes of technology, any efficient and non-decreasing allocation can be a unique undiscounted utilitarian optimum for a given initial endowment, provided that the utility function is appropriately chosen. Hence the class of undiscounted utilitarian criteria — any member of which satisfies ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ —is sufficiently malleable to allow for any efficient and non-decreasing allocation to be the unique choice for a given initial endowment. This may be taken to mean that no efficient and non-decreasing allocation can be ruled out solely from ethical consideration, at least in the three classes of technologies that we consider. # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 416 [AUGUST ECONOMICA This is a negative conclusion, in the sense that adopting undiscounted utilitarianism as a class of social preferences does not indicate how to provide a sharper prescription for choice among feasible allocations — unless one has a specific ethical intuition concerning the concavity of the utility function, which, however, seems hard to obtain on the basis of ethical axioms alone. In Ramsey technologies discounted utilitarianism with a positive and time-invariant discount rate might be seen as an alternative that, even as an entire class of criteria, yields sharper prescriptions. Suppose that the discount rate is chosen to be smaller than or equal to g 0 (k(y)), where k(y) solves y ¼ f(k(y)) for given y. Then discounted utilitarianism applied to the Ramsey model will, quite independently of the shape of the utility function, lead to an efficient and nondecreasing allocation. In fact, the stock of capital cannot grow to a size that exceeds Mk, where g 0 (k) equals the utility discount rate.4 This means that consumption cannot grow beyond g(k), and thus, the introduction of such a ‘small’ utility discount rate excludes allocations with a large inequality between the present and unfortunate generations and the future and fortunate generations. Hence, even though discounted utilitarianism as a criterion for social decision-making is inconsistent with the axiom of ‘Equity’, in Ramsey technologies it leads to outcomes that are consistent with ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ as long as the discount rate is sufficiently ‘small’. This attractive feature of discounted utilitarianism arises in Ramsey technologies since an efficient and stationary allocation has constant net capital productivity g 0 (k(y)). In a Dasgupta –Heal –Solow (D –H –S) technology, however, the net capital productivity Gk (k; r; 1) converges to zero along any efficient and non-decreasing allocation. This means that discounted utilitarianism will force consumption to approach zero in the long run, independently of how ‘small’ the discount rate is, even if (E3) is satisfied so that the set of efficient and non-decreasing allocations is non-empty. This in turn implies that discounted utilitarianism is what Page (1977, p. 198) calls a ‘fair weather criterion’, which necessarily leads to outcomes inconsistent with the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ in the more severe context of a Dasgupta – Heal – Solow technology. These results are summarized in Table 1. These conclusions mean that, although discounted utilitarianism appeals to our ethical intuitions in the simple context of Ramsey technologies, introducing positive discounting is not in general an appropriate way of achieving ethically desirable outcomes. In contrast, undiscounted utilitarianism is sufficiently malleable that any ethically desirable outcome can be realized as RESULTS ON TABLE 1 UNDISCOUNTED AND DISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM Ramsey technologies D–H–S technologies Undiscounted utilitarianism All allocations consistent with ‘Efficiency’ & ‘Equity’ All allocations consistent with ‘Efficiency’ & ‘Equity’ Discounted utilitarianism More equal alloc. consistent with ‘Efficiency’ & ‘Equity’ No allocation consistent with ‘Efficiency’ & ‘Equity’ # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM 417 long as such an allocation is consistent with ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’. Hence, in the context of utilitarianism, there appears to be no ethical argument in favour of discounting if there is no uncertainty. In the end, such a conclusion may appear uncontroversial, but — as documented in Section I— it contradicts views expressed by many influential scholars. Determining an intergenerational allocation amounts to nothing more than resolving the distributional conflict between the different generations. Following Atkinson (1970), it is quite familiar in economics to have distributional objectives incorporated into symmetric additive social welfare functions where the consumption (or income) of every economic agent is evaluated by some utility function u. Then the degree of inequality aversion contained in the social welfare function is expressed by the degree of concavity of the utility function u. (Cf. Cowell 2000, for a general overview, and Collard 1994, and Fleurbaey and Michel, 2001, for specific applications in the intergenerational context.) In the static case this leads to a completely egalitarian distribution unless there are costs of redistribution. In the present intergenerational context, the condition of ‘Immediate productivity’ means that there are negative transfer costs from the present to the future. Referring to Okun’s well-known ‘leaking bucket’, Schelling (1995, p. 396) vividly describes such a situation by using the term ‘incubation bucket’, in which ‘the good things multiply in transit so that more arrives at the destination than was removed from the origin’. Hence, if such productivity of the technology is assumed, any efficient and non-decreasing allocation may be consistent with the maximization of a symmetric additive welfare function. This means that the familiar welfarist approach might be attractive to apply also for evaluating intergenerational allocations, even in the infinite case.5 That a more concave u can be used for skewing the intergenerational distribution in favour of earlier generations, thus slowing economic growth, has been observed for a long time by interpreting the well-known Ramsey rule for optimal economic growth (see e.g. Dasgupta and Heal 1979, p. 292; Fleurbaey and Michel 1994, pp. 294; 1999, p. 723). Here we have shown, in the context of linear and Ramsey technologies, that whatever decreased inequality is desirable can be obtained under undiscounted utilitarianism by choosing a more concave utility function, since the utility function can always be adjusted so that a given efficient and non-decreasing allocation is obtained as the undiscounted utilitarian optimum. Such adjustment is possible even in Dasgupta – Heal –Solow technologies, where discounted utilitarianism, for any positive and constant discounting, leads to unacceptable treatment of generations in the distant future. Thus, this malleability of undiscounted utilitarianism makes it possible in the intergenerational context to determine optimal allocations that appeal to our ethical intuitions through applying complete and transitive social preferences that satisfy reasonable ethical axioms. However, the conclusion that discounting is not needed for ethically appealing choices to be made in the intergenerational context does not imply that intergenerational discounting is unjustified in any case. Discounting may well provide an instrument for taking uncertainty into account. This aspect makes generations inherently different and therefore has ethical relevance for intergenerational discounting. Referring to Sidgwick (1890, p. 412), Dasgupta # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 418 ECONOMICA [AUGUST and Heal (1979, p. 262) clearly state: ‘The point then is that one might find it ethically reasonable to discount future utilities at positive rates ... because there is a positive chance that future generations will not exist.’ A discussion of such more legitimate reasons for intergenerational discounting has not been the subject here. Rather, our purpose has been to clarify the ethical role of discounting in the case of certainty. APPENDIX A: EXTENDING UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM To construct an extended undiscounted utilitarian criterion that yields a (strict) preference for 0 c 0 over 0 c 00 whenever 0 c 0 Pu0 c 00 (cf. (P) of Section III), is complete, in the sense of deeming two allocations indifferent whenever there is not a (strict) preference, and satisfies the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’, we introduce the following components: 1. a first-order utility function u : Rþ 2 R that is continuous, concave and nondecreasing, and is applied in a ‘catching up’ criterion, under which one allocation is as good as another if the lim inf, as T goes to infinity, of the sum up to time T of the difference between the utilities generated by the allocations is non-negative; 2. a second-order utility function : Rþ 2 R that is continuous and strictly increasing, and is applied lexicographically to resolve ties so that the axiom of ‘Efficiency’ is satisfied; for this purpose we will assume throughout that is given by (c) ¼ c; 3. given u, a complete and transitive binary relation R 00u that is a completion of ‘catching up’ utilitarianism when these utility functions are used lexicographically, and which invokes a result due to Szpilrajn (1930). We first show how an incomplete reflexive and transitive binary relation R 0u can be derived from u when ‘catching up’ utilitarianism is lexicographically extended. We then consider the issue of completing R 0u to R 00u . Let 0 c 0 ¼ (c 00 ; c 01 ; :::) and 0 c 00 ¼ (c 000 ; c 001 ; :::) be two allocations. Let u be given, and determine R 0u as follows: 8 PT 0 00 > lim infT 2 1 t ¼ 0 (u(c t ) u(c t )) 0; > < PT 0 0 00 0 00 (R) and lim infT 2 1 0 c R u0 c u t ¼ 0 ((c t ) (c t )) 0 > > P1 : whenever t ¼ 0 (u(c 0t ) u(c 00t )) ¼ 0: It is clear that R 0u is reflexive and transitive. Let P 0u and I 0u denote the asymmetric and symmetric parts of R 0u , respectively; i.e. P 0u denotes (strict) preference, while I 0u denotes indifference. It follows from (R) and (P) that 0 c 0 P 0u0 c 00 whenever 0 c 0 Pu0 c 00 . To show that R 0u satisfies ‘Efficiency’ (or ‘Strong Pareto’), let 0 c 0 be derived from 0 c 00 by having c 0s ¼ c 00s þ ", " > 0, and c 0t ¼ c 00t for t 6¼ s; then 0 c 0 P 0u0 c 00 , since, even if u(c 0s ) ¼ u(c 00s ), we have that (c 0s ) > (c 00s ). This means that R 0u satisfies the axiom of ‘Efficiency’. To show 00 that R 0u satisfies ‘Equity’ (or ‘Weak anonymity’), let 0 c 0 be derived fromP 0 c by having 1 0 c 0s 0 ¼ c 00s 00 , c 0s 00 ¼ P c 00s 0 and c 0t ¼ c 00t for t 6¼ s 0 , s 00 ; then 0 c 0 I 0u0 c 00 , since t ¼ 0 (u(c t ) 1 0 00 0 u(c 00t )) ¼ 0 and t ¼ 0 ((c t ) (c t )) ¼ 0. This means that R u satisfies the axiom of ‘Equity’. Say that R 0 is a subrelation to R 00 if (i) 0 c 0 R00 c 00 implies 0 c 0 R000 c 00 and (ii) 0 c 0 P00 c 00 implies 0 c 0 P000 c 00 , with P 0 and P 00 denoting the asymmetric parts of R 0 and R 00 , respectively. Svensson’s (1980) Theorem 2 states that any reflexive and transitive binary relation that satisfies the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’ is a subrelation to a complete and transitive binary relation (i.e. an ordering). In proving this result, Svensson refers to a general mathematical lemma by Szpilrajn (1930). By invoking this result, there exists a complete and transitive binary relation R 00u which has R 0u as a subrelation. Note that it follows, from the definition of a subrelation, that R 00u also satisfies the axioms of ‘Efficiency’ and ‘Equity’. For the purpose of Proposition 1 we need not be concerned about how R 0u is completed to R 00u , because Proposition 1 shows that the # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM 419 considered efficient and decreasing allocation Pu-dominates (and thus P 0u -dominates) any alternative feasible allocation for an appropriately chosen u. Then it follows that the considered efficient and decreasing allocation P 00u -dominates any alternative allocation, independently of how R 0u is completed to R 00u . Hence, Proposition 1 obtains also if P 00u is substituted for Pu. APPENDIX B: PROOF OF PROPOSITION 2 The proof of Proposition 2 is based on three lemmas. We start with Lemma 1, which states the following result for linear technologies. Lemma 1. An allocation 0 c in a linear technology is feasible given y if and only if ct 0 P for all t 0 and 1 t ¼ 0 pt ct ˘ y. Proof. Assume that 0 c is feasible. Then there exists a feasible programme (0 y; 0 k) such that yt kt 0 for t 0. In particular, yt þ 1 ˘ at kt for all t 0. This means P Tct ¼ P Tall 1 1 that this implies that t þ 1 at ¼ pt , P T 1 t ¼ 0 pt þ 1 yt þ 1 ˘ t ¼ 0 pt þ 1 at kt . Since pP 1 t ¼ 0 pt (yt kt ) ˘ p0 y0 pT yT . We now obtain t ¼ 0 pt ct ˘ y as pt ct ¼ pt (yt kt ) 0, p0 y0 ¼ y and pT yT 0. P1 Assume that ct 0 for all t 0 and t ¼ 0 pt ct ˘ y. Construct (0 y; 0 k) by y0 ¼ y, and kt ¼ yt ct and yt þ 1 ¼ aP t kt for all t 0. Then pt ct þ pt þ 1 yt þ 1 ¼ pt yt pt kt þ 1 pt þ 1 at kt ¼ pt yt , implying that s ¼ t ps cs ˘ pt yt . As ps cs 0 for all s t, it follows that yt 0 for arbitrary t, and (0 y; 0 k) is feasible. & Turn now to the class of Ramsey technologies. A feasible programme (0 y; 0 k) is competitive if there is a non-null sequence of non-negative prices 0 p such that, for t 0, pt þ 1 yt þ 1 pt kt pt þ 1 y pt k for all (k; y) 2 T 2 In other words, along a competitive programme intertemporal profits are maximized at each point in time. A competitive programme is said to satisfy the transversality condition at the price sequence 0 p if limT 2 1 pT kT ¼ 0: Lemma 2. Under (A2), if a feasible and non-decreasing allocation 0 c in a Ramsey technology is efficient, then there exists a feasible program (0 y; 0 k) with ct ¼ yt kt for all t 0 that is competitive and satisfies the transversality condition at prices 0 p given by pt þ 1 f 0 (kt ) ¼ pt for t 0: Furthermore, it holds that, for all t 0, 0 < pt þ 1 < pt , and P1 t¼0 pt ct < 1. Proof. Assume that the feasible allocation 0 c is efficient and non-decreasing. Construct (0 y; 0 k) by y0 ¼ y, and kt ¼ yt ct and yt þ 1 ¼ f(kt ) for all t 0. Since 0 c is feasible and efficient, it follows that there exists Mk such that 0 < kt < Mk for all t 0. Since, in addition, 0 c is non-decreasing, it follows that kt þ 1 kt 0 for all t 0, because otherwise kt would have been reduced to zero in a finite number of periods. This in turn implies that ct ¼ g(kt 1 ) (kt kt 1 ) ˘ g(k) for all t 1. Determine a sequence of consumption discount factors 0 p ¼ (p0 ; p1 ; :::) as follows: p0 ¼ 1 and pt þ 1 f 0 (kt ) ¼ pt for all t 0: Note that it holds for all t 0 that 0 < pt þ 1 < pt , since f 0 (kt ) ¼ g 0 (kt ) þ 1 > 1. By the concavity of g, it follows that (0 y; 0 k) is competitive. Since kt < Mk for all t 0, it follows that (0 y; 0 k) satisfies the transversality condition: pT kT ˘ T Mk, where P :¼ 1=f 0 (k). 1 Finally, since c0 ˘ c1 and ct ˘ g(k) for all t 1, it follows that t ¼ 0 pt ct ˘ P 1 t g(k) < 1. & t¼0 # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 420 ECONOMICA [AUGUST Finally, consider the class of Dasgupta – Heal – Solow technologies. A feasible programme (0 y; 0 m; 0 k) is competitive if there is a non-null sequence of non-negative prices (0 p; 0 q) such that, for t 0, pt þ 1 yt þ 1 þ qt þ 1 mt þ 1 pt kt qt mt pt þ 1 y þ qt þ 1 m 0 pt k qt m for all [(k; m)(y; m 0 )] 2 T 3 : A competitive programme is said to satisfy the transversality condition at the price sequence (0 p; 0 q) if limT 2 1 (pT kT þ qT mT ) ¼ 0: Lemma 3. Under (A3), if a feasible and non-decreasing allocation 0 c in a Dasgupta – Heal – Solow technology is efficient, then there exists a feasible programme (0 y; 0 m; 0 k), with ct ¼ yt kt for all t 0, that is competitive and satisfies the transversality condition at prices (0 p; 0 q) given by pt þ 1 Fk (kt ; mt mt þ 1 ) ¼ pt qt ¼ q > 0 and for t 0 pt þ 1 Fr (kt ; mt mt þ 1 ) ¼ q for t 0: P1 Furthermore, it holds that, for all t 0, 0 < pt þ 1 < pt , and t ¼ 0 pt ct < 1. Proof. Let s 00 0 be the first period with positive consumption: cs 00 > 0 and ct ¼ 0 for 0 ˘ t < s 00 . Then, by Proposition 2 in Dasgupta and Mitra (1983), kt þ 1 > kt > 0 and 0 < mt þ 1 < mt for t s 00 . Let s 0 , where 0 ˘ s 0 ˘ s 00 , be the first period with positive extraction: rs 0 ¼ ms 0 ms 0 þ 1 > 0 and rt ¼ mt mt þ 1 ¼ 0 for 0 ˘ t < s 0 . If s 0 > 0, then (A3) implies that the resulting allocation is inefficient, since a Pareto-dominating allocation can be constructed by having r 0s 0 1 ¼ " > 0 and r 0s 0 ¼ rs 0 " > 0 (for sufficiently small ") and reinvesting the additional output at time s 0 1. Thus, s 0 ¼ 0. Hence, kt > 0 and rt ¼ mt mt þ 1 > 0 for t 0. The result now follows from Theorem 4.1 and Corollary 4.1 in Mitra (1978). & Proof of Proposition 2 Part 1: Linear technologies. P1 The result follows immediately from 1, since t ¼ 0 pt ct ¼ y (< 1) if 0 c is P 1Lemma 0 0 feasible, given y, and efficient, and t ¼ 0 pt c t ˘ y if 0 c is feasible. Part 2: Ramsey technologies. Lemma 2 establishes the existence of a feasible programme (0 y; 0 k) with ct ¼ yt kt for all t 0 that is competitive and satisfies the P transversality condition at prices 0 p satisfying 0 < pt þ 1 < pt for all t 0 such that 1 t ¼ 0 pt ct < 1. Furthermore, T X t¼0 pt (c 0t ct ) ¼ T X pt [(y 0t k 0t ) (yt kt )] t¼0 ˘ p0 (y 00 y0 ) pT (k 0T kT ) ˘ pT kT ; where 0 c 0 is any feasible allocation with (0 y 0 ; 0 k 0 ) as a corresponding feasible programme, since (0 y; 0 k) is competitive, y 00 ¼ y0 ¼ y, and pT k 0T 0. Finally, P 1 0 0 y; 0 k) satisfies the transversality condition. Note that it t ¼ 0 pt (c t ct ) ˘ 0, since (P 0 follows from Lemma 2 that 1 t ¼ 0 pt (c t ct ) ˘ 0 holds even if the feasible programme (0 y 0 ; 0 k 0 ) corresponding to 0 c 0 does not satisfy that 0 k 0 is bounded above. Part 3: Dasgupta – Heal – Solow technologies. Lemma 3 establishes the existence of a feasible programme (0 y; 0 m; 0 k), with ct ¼ yt kt for all t 0, that is competitive and satisfies the transversality condition at prices # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 2003] 421 MALLEABILITY OF UNDISCOUNTED UTILITARIANISM (0 p; 0 q), where Furthermore, T X t¼0 0p satisfies 0 < pt þ 1 < pt for all t 0, such that pt (c 0t ct ) ¼ T X P1 t¼0 pt ct < 1. pt [(y 0t k 0t ) (yt kt )] t¼0 ˘ p0 (y 00 y0 ) þ q0 (m 00 m0 ) [pT (k 0T kT ) þ qT (m 0T mT )] ˘ pT kT þ qT mT ; where 0 c 0 is any feasible allocation with (0 y 0 ; 0 m 0 ; 0 k 0 ) as a corresponding feasible 0 0 programme, since (0 y; 0 m; P 0 k) is 0 competitive, y 0 ¼ y0 ¼ y, m 0 ¼ m0 ¼ m, and pT k 0T þ qT m 0T 0. Finally, 1 p (c c ) ˘ 0 since ( y; m; k) satisfies the transverst 0 0 0 t¼0 t t ality condition. & ACKNOWLEDGMENTS We have received many helpful comments from two referees, Snorre Kverndokk, Stef Prost, Eric Rasmusen and Martin Weitzman, as well as seminar participants at Harvard, ZEW Mannheim, CESifo Munich, Regensburg and Southampton. Financial support from the Research Council of Norway (Ruhrgas grant) is gratefully acknowledged. NOTES 1. It may to some extent decrease over time. This is called ‘slow’ or ‘hyperbolic’ discounting (cf. e.g. Heal 1998, pp. 62–3; Weitzman 1998, 2001). 2. Writing jt for gross investment, qt for gross product and dt for the rate of depreciation, a linear and technology can be described as follows: ct þ jt ¼ qt , 0 ˘ qt ˘ bt 1 kt 1 0 ˘ kt ˘ jt þ (1 dt 1 )kt 1 , where jt satisfies (1 dt 1 )kt 1 ˘ jt ˘ qt and where net capital productivity is positive at time t 1 if and only if bt 1 > dt 1 . 3. To see that Gk (kt ; rt ; 1) 2 0 as t 2 1, note that kt k0 > 0 and rt > 0 for all t 0 by the proof of Lemma 3, while rt 2 0 as t 2 1, owing to the finite resource stock m. Hence, 0 < Gk (kt ; rt ; 1) ˘ G(kt ; rt ; 1)=kt ˘ G(k0 ; rt ; 1)=k0 since G(0; rt ; 1) ¼ 0 and G is concave, while G(k0 ; rt ; 1)=k0 2 0 as t 2 1 since G(k0 ; 0; 1) ¼ 0 and G is continuous. 4. Since the application of such a ‘small’ discount rate leads to kt being bounded above, the resulting allocation is feasible in the terminology of Section IV(b). Hence, Proposition 2 applies, and the given discounted utilitarian criterion can be substituted by an undiscounted utilitarian criterion. (Cf. Joshi, 1994, for a related but different statement in a special case of the Ramsey model.) Thus, the introduction of pure time preference, which may appear to be without ‘intrinsic ethical appeal’ and therefore ‘purely ad hoc’ (Rawls 1971, p. 298), is not needed to obtain appealing allocations in Ramsey technologies. 5. Following (partly) the same line of argument, Schelling (1995, p. 401) concludes: ‘The discountrate question should disappear. In its place is what utility function to use in valuing future increments in other people’s consumption. This is a real question, not a matter of mathematical convenience.’ REFERENCES ARROW, K. J. (1999). Discounting, morality, and gaming. In P. R. Portney and J. P. Weyant (eds.), Discounting and Intergenerational Equity. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future. ATKINSON, A. (1970). On the measurement of inequality. Journal of Economic Theory, 2, 244 –63. ASHEIM, G. B., BUCHHOLZ, W. and TUNGODDEN, B. (2001). Justifying sustainability. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 41, 252 –68. CASS, D. and MITRA, T. (1991). Indefinitely sustained consumption despite exhaustible natural resources. Economic Theory, 1, 119– 46. CHAKRAVARTY, S. (1969). Capital and Development Planning. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003 {Journals}Ecca/70_3/g212/makeup/g212.3d 422 ECONOMICA [AUGUST COLLARD, D. (1994). Inequality aversion, resource depletion and sustainability. Economics Letters, 45, 513–15. COWELL, D. (2000). Measurement of inequality. In A. B. Atkinson and F. Bourguignon (eds.), Handbook of Income Distribution, Vol. I. Amsterdam: Elsevier. DASGUPTA, P. S. and HEAL, G. M. (1974). The optimal depletion of exhaustible resources. Review of Economic Studies, Symposium, 3–28. —— and —— (1979). Economic Theory and Exhaustible Resources. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. —— and MÄLER, K. G. (1995). Poverty, institutions, and the environmental resource-base. In J. Behrman and T. N. Srinavasan (eds.), Handbook of Development Economics, Vol. III. Amsterdam: Elsevier. DASGUPTA, S. and MITRA, T. (1983). Intergenerational equity and efficient allocation of exhaustible resources. International Economic Review, 24, 133 –53. DIAMOND, P. (1965). The evaluation of infinite utility streams. Econometrica, 33, 170–7. FLEURBAEY, M. and MICHEL, P. (1994). Optimal growth and transfers between generations. Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 60, 281–300. —— and —— (1999). Quelques réflexions sur la croissance optimale. Revue e´conomique, 50, 715–32. —— and —— (2001). Transfer principles and inequality aversion, with an application to optimal growth. Mathematical Social Sciences, 42, 1–11. HARSANYI, J. C. (1953). Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of risk-taking. Journal of Political Economy, 61, 434 –5. HEAL, G. M. (1998). Valuing the Future. New York: Columbia University Press. JOSHI, S. (1994). Duality between discounted and undiscounted models of economic growth. Economics Letters, 44, 403–6. KOOPMANS, T. C. (1960). Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica, 28, 287 –309. KREPS, D. and PORTEUS, E. L. (1979). Temporal von Neumann–Morgenstern and induced preferences. Journal of Economic Theory, 20, 81–109. LAUWERS, L. (1997). Continuity and equity with infinite horizons. Social Choice and Welfare, 14, 345–56. MIRRLEES, J. A. (1967). Optimal growth when technology is changing. Review of Economic Studies, 34, 95–124. MITRA, T. (1978). Efficient growth with exhaustible resources in a neoclassical model. Journal of Economic Theory, 17, 114–29. PAGE, T. (1977). Conservation and Economic Efficiency. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. PIGOU, A. C. (1932). The Economics of Welfare. London: Macmillan. RAMSEY, F. (1928). A mathematical theory of saving. Economic Journal, 38, 543–59. RAWLS, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. SCHELLING, T. (1995). Intergenerational Discounting. Energy Economics, 23, 395 –401. SIDGWICK, H. (1890). The Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan. SOLOW, R. M. (1974). Intergenerational equity and exhaustible resources. Review of Economic Studies, Symposium, 29–45. SVENSSON, L. G. (1980). Equity among generations. Econometrica, 48, 1251–6. SZPILRAJN, E. (1930). Sur l’extension de l’ordre partial. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 16, 386–9. WEITZMAN, M. L. (1998). Why the far-distant future should be discounted at the lowest possible rate. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 36, 201–8. —— (2001). Gamma discounting. American Economic Review, 91, 260–71. # The London School of Economics and Political Science 2003