Contents 1 Introduction 4 I 8 Theories of justice 2 About distributional justice 2.1 Economic goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.2 Global and local justice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.3 Principles of justice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.4 About theories of justice . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.5 Egalitarianisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.6 The social contract . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.7 Libertarianism and Marxism: Two special cases . . . . . . . 9 11 12 13 15 19 21 23 3 Deserts and the fruits of our labour 3.1 Deserts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3.2 Rewards according to contribution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3.3 The fruits of our labour . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 24 26 28 4 Welfarism: utilitarianism and 4.1 Utilitarianism . . . . . . . . 4.2 Welfarism and equality . . 4.3 Social evaluation functions 4.4 Welfarism and ethics . . . . . . . . 33 36 41 43 49 . . . . . 58 60 64 64 67 69 welfare . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . economics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5 John Rawls’s theory of justice: the social contract 5.1 The original position . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5.2 The difference principle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5.3 Illustrations of the difference principle . . . . . . . . 5.4 The difference principle and the theory of uncertainty 5.5 Primary goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 Equality of what? Resources and capabilities 6.1 Approaches to economic equality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.2 Dworkin and equality of resources . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.3 Capabilities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 75 75 77 79 7 Libertarianism and Marxism 85 7.1 Libertarianism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85 7.2 Marxism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91 8 Children and their mothers 8.1 What is special about children? 8.2 Welfarism and children . . . . 8.3 Libertarianism and children . . 8.4 The Rawlsian social contract . 8.5 The good of children . . . . . . II . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Measuring inequality 9 Income and wealth 9.1 Economic goods . . . . . 9.2 Income . . . . . . . . . . 9.3 Components of income . . 9.4 Extended income . . . . . 9.5 Full income . . . . . . . . 9.6 Lifetime income . . . . . . 9.7 Wealth . . . . . . . . . . . 9.8 Access to economic goods . . . . . 94 96 98 101 102 106 108 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 Household income 10.1 Equivalent adult scales . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.2 The cost of living function and economies of scale 10.3 The cost of children . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.4 Estimating equivalent adult scales . . . . . . . . . 10.5 The unit of analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109 109 111 116 118 123 125 127 129 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 131 . 131 . 134 . 137 . 141 . 144 11 What should we measure? 145 11.1 Household or individual income? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147 11.2 Standard income, extended income, full income? . . . . . . . . 151 11.3 Lifetime income or annual income? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 153 2 12 Lorenz curves and inequality measures 12.1 The distribution function . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.2 The Lorenz curve . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.3 Inequality measures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.4 The theory of inequality measures . . . . . . . . 12.5 Ordinality of inequality measures . . . . . . . . 12.6 Some properties of different inequality measures. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 156 156 161 164 165 170 172 13 Social evaluation of inequality 176 13.1 Lorenz dominance and inequality aversion . . . . . . . . . . . 176 13.2 Ethical inequality measures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 178 13.3 Atkinson’s inequality measure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180 14 Some inequality measures 14.1 The Generalised Entropy class of inequality measures 14.2 The M-curve and the A-measure. . . . . . . . . . . . 14.3 Kolm’s inequality measure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14.4 Choosing an inequality measure . . . . . . . . . . . . 14.5 Inequality in some OECD countries . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 183 . 183 . 185 . 187 . 188 . 190 15 Poverty 193 15.1 Relative poverty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 194 15.2 Measuring poverty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 197 15.3 The importance of equivalence scales . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 198 16 Decomposition of 16.1 Decomposition 16.2 Decomposition 16.3 Decomposition 16.4 Decomposition inequality measures by group . . . . . . . . . . by group: an example . . by income component . . . by component: An example . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 200 . 200 . 204 . 205 . 212 A Uncertainty and expected utility 215 B Sampling errors 218 Further reading 221 References 224 3 Chapter 1 Introduction Women work longer hours than men in nearly every country, but men receive the lion’s share of income an recognition.1 In November 2002, British firefighters threatened to strike for higher wages. One firefighter interviewed by the Guardian earned around 30,000 pounds a year after 22 years of service.2 An English premiership football player might well earn as much in a week, while a care assistant had yearly earnings of 10 000 pounds.3 These are some examples of differences in economic circumstances, and I know in my heart they are unjust. For many years, I did not know that I could use my reason to explain why. When I studied economics in Oslo in the beginning of the 1960s, a truth universally acknowledged in the profession was that justice in distribution is not, and cannot be, the subject of academic research. There is, to be sure, the social welfare function. But the social welfare function is for the politicians to determine, and for the economics profession to put unquestioned into practice. Accordingly, when I first began doing research on income distribution, I started off by learning what I could about empirical methods, inequality measures and the intricacies of concepts and definitions in income statistics. But increasingly I found myself more interested in the why than the how of the analysis. Why is the distribution of household income more interesting than the distribution of individual income? Why should we be interested in measuring the degree of inequality in either of them? So I tentatively started to read Rawls and Sen, and made two discoveries, one of them delightful and the other rather disheartening. The delightful discovery was that academic research into questions of 1 Human Development Report 1995: 88 The Guardian 12 November 2002 3 The Guardian 15 January 2003. (Polly Toynbee: Who cares?) 2 4 justice in distribution is not only possible and legitimate, but a flourishing academic discipline with an increasing number of practitioners. The disheartening discovery was that I did not understand the literature. I found it dense, abstruse, impenetrable. As I slowly began to understand something of the content, I made a third discovery, namely of the gap between what the philosophers write about and what is studied in empirical analyses of income distribution. Researchers working with empirical methods seem to take for granted that the ultimate aim of public policy is to increase welfare, and the task of the empirical analyst is to find the level and distribution of individual welfare. On the other hand, such outstanding moral philosophers as Ronald Dworkin, Martha Nussbaum, John Rawls and Amartya Sen are not at all concerned with welfare, but with opportunities, resources, rights and capabilities. According to them, achieving individual welfare and happiness is the person’s own responsibility. The state has the moral duty to further the means to, and remove constraints on, the pursuit of happiness, but not to secure that happiness itself. But then again, these same philosophers seem quite unconcerned with how their concepts can be made operational for empirical analysis. So I decided to write this book to bridge the gap between moral philosophy and empirical research. I have not succeeded; the bridge is still unbuilt. But here at least is a book where moral philosophy and empirical methods co-exist between the same two covers, and with some attempts at interaction between the two parts. The book is addressed to those students of the social sciences who are interested in both the why and the how of studying income distribution. Perhaps it may be of some interest also to researchers on either side of the gap who want to learn something about how the other half thinks. Moral philosophy cannot, of course, prove that one way of organising society and arranging the distribution of economic goods is ‘objectively’ better than another. But it can make our ideas of justice more precise, help us to reason logically about justice and to find areas of agreement and disagreement. I also think that knowledge of moral philosophy could make empirical research more relevant to people’s concerns about justice in distribution. I happen to know Norwegian income statistics fairly well, which is the reason why they supply most of the numerical examples in this book. Here is one: by the end of the nineteen nineties, the average woman in Norway received about 60 per cent of the income of the average man. (The percentage varies slightly with the definition of income used.) Is this difference in income unjust? To answer the question, we have to know the reasons for the difference. These are reasonably well known. About half the difference is due to different wage rates. Some part of these 20 per cent may be due to women 5 receiving lower wages than men for the same work, but this part is probably fairly small. It is also very difficult to identify, because women on the whole do not do the same work as men. And the kinds of paid employment women tend to do, are also the kinds of paid employment that are not very well paid. The remaining 20 per cent difference is due to women either working part-time or not being in paid work at all. Most people now agree that it is wrong and unjust to discriminate against women by giving them lower pay than men for the same work. (But trade unions in Norway negotiated separate wage rates for women and men until about 1960.) The greater part of the difference in incomes, however, does not stem from discrimination, but from men and women making different choices in the labour market. In my country, it is a long time since any profession or education was formally closed to women. Women’s choices of education and profession are made of their own free will. So it seems is their choice of part-time work. At this point in my lectures, I usually ask the students to suggest why so many women work part-time. Invariably, the answer is given by one of the female students: women spend time taking care of the children. Disagreement about the justice of women’s low incomes then stems from disagreements on two points. The first concerns the question of just wages in the typical women’s professions, like nursing. The second concerns the justice of women’s doing most of the domestic unpaid work, particularly child care. There are also those who feel that the difference in men’s and women’s own incomes is of no importance because of income sharing between married couples. (I have never yet met a woman who agreed with this last statement.) All the empirical research drawn on in the above example has been carried out in the last twenty to thirty years. (Before 1970, Statistics Norway did not even publish separate tables on women’s and men’s income.) The research was grounded in moral concerns about women’s economic and social position. The use I have made of it stems from what I have learned in moral philosophy about the importance of free choice and contingent circumstances. It has led me to question the widespread practice of basing empirical analysis on household income only. In spite of this example, the present book is not a feminist treatise. It contains no specific feminist methods or analyses. But it is written by a woman concerned about justice to women. The book is in two parts: Theories of Justice, and Measuring Inequality. Part I is an introduction to some important theories of justice. It starts with an overview of the theories considered in the following chapters. Chapter 3 discusses the idea of rewards according to deserts. I have tried to present welfarism (chapter 4), Rawls’s social contract (chapter 5), Dworkin’s equal6 ity of resources and the Nussbaum/Sen capability approach (chapter 6) both critically and, I hope, fairly. But I found it impossible to hide my lack of enthusiasm for libertarianism and Marxism (chapter 7). The final chapter 8 contains my own ideas on children and motherhood in relation to distributional justice. I had to develop my own ideas because I found very little about children and women in the theories presented in the first seven chapters. It should be emphasised that Part I is an introduction to the subject, aimed at social science students, not students of political philosophy. And it is my hope that the text can be read by social scientists in general, not only economists, even though there are some (very simple) formulas in chapter 4. Students of economics may find parts of this same chapter wordy and lacking in rigour precisely because the mathematics are missing. The first two chapters of part II contain a detailed discussion of various ways of defining and measuring access to economic goods. I have tried to make clear that such access is more than cash income, and that therefore justice in distribution of economic goods concerns not only distribution of income. In chapter 11, I have tried to make a connection between theories of justice and empirical measurement by regarding income as a constraint rather than as a measure of welfare. Chapters 12 to 14 and chapter 16 contain the theory of inequality measures, and a discussion of their properties. I have tried to avoid unnecessary formalisation. But it is impossible to compute measures of any kind without taking the trouble to understand at least a few formulas. Measuring inequality is not altogether a straightforward business, and it is important to understand why. I have given no proofs, only assertions. Those interested will find references to more rigorous expositions, containing references to the original articles with proofs, in Suggestions for further reading at the end of the book. Chapter 15 is a minimalist treatment of the definition and measurement of poverty. There are a number of examples from Norwegian income statistics in part II, because these are statistics I know well and have access to. They are there to illustrate the methods, not because I imagine conditions in Norway to be of absorbing interest. As for the vexing problem of he, she or they, I have addressed this issue by sometimes writing he and sometimes she more or less at random. 7