Departments of Mathematics Montana State University Fall 2015 Prof. Kevin Wildrick An introduction to non-smooth analysis and geometry Lecture 4: The Lebesgue Differentiation Theorem In this lecture, we will see how the covering theorems proven in Lecture 3 give rise to a fundamental differentiability result. 1. Lebesgue’s differentiation theorem for monotone functions The following theorem is at the heart of modern analysis. It is deeper than one might expect. Theorem 1.1. Let f : R → R be a monotone function. Then f is differentiable almost everywhere with respect to Lebesgue measure m. Proof. It suffices to show that given a bounded open interval (a, b) ⊆ R, the function f is differentiable at m-almost every point of (a, b); we may also assume that f is nondecreasing. Let x ∈ (a, b) and consider the functions f (x + t) − f (x) , h→0 0<|t|<h t Df (x) = lim sup f (x + t) − f (x) . h→0 0<|t|<h t Df (x) lim inf For each α > 0 and any interval (a0 , b0 ) ⊆ (a, b) Eα = {x ∈ (a0 , b0 ) : Df (x) ≥ α}. We first claim that for each α > 0, f (b0 ) − f (a0 ) . α To this end, fix any 0 < α0 < α and let F be the collection of all closed intervals [c, d] ⊆ (a0 , b0 ) such that f (d) − f (c) ≥ α0 . d−c By definition, this forms a fine cover of Eα . Hence, we may apply the Vitali Covering Theorem to F and find a countable, disjointed subcollection {[ci , di ]}i∈N such that ! [ m Eα \ [ci , di ] = 0. (1.1) m (Eα ) ≤ i∈N Since f is increasing and the subcollection is disjoint, X X f (di ) − f (ci ) f (b0 ) − f (a0 ) ≤ . m(Eα ) ≤ (di − ci ) ≤ α0 α0 i∈N i∈N Letting α0 tend to α proves claim 1.1. Note that E∞ ⊆ Eα for every α > 0, and so m(E∞ ) = 0. Now, fix numbers 0 < α < β < ∞, and define the set E := Eα,β := {x ∈ (a, b) : Df (x) > α > β > Df (x)}. 1 For > 0, we may find an open set U ⊆ (a, b) such that E ⊆ U and m(U ) < m(E) + . Let F now denote the collection of intervals [c, d] ⊆ U such that f (d) − f (c) < β. d−c Since Df > β on E, the collection F is a fine covering of E. Hence we may find a countable, disjointed subcollection {[ci , di ]}i∈N such that that ! [ m E\ [ci , di ] = 0. i∈N 0 Thus applying the claim (1.1) with (a , b0 ) = (ci , di ) for each i ∈ N, X X f (di ) − f (ci ) m(E) ≤ m(E ∩ (ci , di )) ≤ α i∈N i∈N Xβ ≤ (di − ci ) α i∈N β m(U ) α β ≤ (m(E) + ). α Since β < α, this is a contradiction when is sufficiently small unless m(E) = 0. Now, note that the set of points at which f fails to be differentiable is contained in the union of E∞ and countably many sets of the form Eα,β . ≤ 2. Lebesgue’s differentiation theorem for metric measure spaces A very similar argument gives the following theorem in a very general setting. Theorem 2.1. Let (X, d, µ) be a Vitali space, and let f be a locally integrable function on X. Then for µ-almost every point x ∈ X, it holds that Z lim − f dµ = f (x). r→0 B(x,r) It is worth remarking how this is a differentiation result. Roughly speaking, one should think of the integral as the analogue of the monotone function, and the function f itself as the derivative of the monotone function. Proof. Let E be the set of points in X such that Z lim − f dµ = f (x) r→0 B(x,r) fails to hold. It suffices to consider the case that E is contiained in some ball B on which f is integrable. We first claim that for each α > 0, if A ⊆ B is a set such that for all a ∈ A, Z lim sup − f dµ ≥ α, r→0 B(a,r) then R (2.1) µ(A) ≤ A f dµ α Similarly, if A ⊆ B is a set such that for all a ∈ A Z f dµ ≤ β, lim inf − r→0 B(a,r) then R A µ(A) ≥ (2.2) f dµ . β Suppose that these claims hold. By (2.1), Z lim sup − f dµ < ∞ r→0 B(a,r) at µ-almost every point of B. For 0 < α < β < ∞, set Z Eα,β := x ∈ (a, b) : lim sup − r→0 Then Z f dµ ≥ α > β ≥ lim inf − r→0 B(x,r) Z αµ(Eα,β ) ≤ − f dµ . B(x,r) f dµ ≤ βµ(Eα,β ), Eα,β and so µ(Eα,β ) = 0. This implies that Z g(x) := lim − r→0 B(x,r) f dµ exists and is finite µ-almost everywhere in B. To see that g and f agree µ-almost everywhere, let F ⊆ B, > 0, and n ∈ N be arbitrary, and define An = {x ∈ F : (1 + )n ≤ g(x) < (1 + )n+1 }. Then Z XZ g dµ = F n∈N g dµ ≤ An X n+1 (1 + ) µ(An ) ≤ (1 + ) n∈N XZ n∈N Z f dµ ≤ (1 + ) An f dµ. F Since and F are arbitrary, this implies that f = g almost everywhere. It now suffices to prove the claim (2.1); the claim (2.2) is proven analogously. Since µ is Borel regular, there is an open set U ⊆ A such that µ(U ) ≤ µ(A) + . By the Vitali covering theorem, we may find a countable, disjointed collection of closed balls {Bi }i∈N such that ! [ µ A\ Bi = 0 i∈N and Z − f dµ ≤ α + . Bi Then Z f dµ ≤ A XZ i∈N Bi ≤ X (α + )µ(Bi ) ≤ (1 + )(µ(A) + ). i∈N Letting tend to 0 yields the desired result. We can derive the following interesting corollary: Corollary 2.2. Let (X, d, µ) be a doubling metric measure space, and let E ⊆ X be a measurable set. Then, for almost every x ∈ X, µ(E ∩ B(x, r)) lim = χE (x). r→0 µ(B(x, r) This result says that from the perspective of measure, when zooming in on a point in a set E, we eventually see only E, almost everywhere. Definition 2.3. A point x for which the conclusion of Corollary 2.2 holds is called a Lebesgue point or a density point for E.