Introduction Structure in Mind 1 Attention regained It’s all about the choreography of people’s attention. Attention is like water. It flows. It’s liquid. You create channels to divert it, and you hope that it flows the right way.… I use framing the way a movie director or a cinematographer would. If I lean my face close in to someone’s … it’s like a closeup. All their attention is on my face, and their pockets, especially the ones on their lower body, are out of the frame. Or if I want to move their attention off their jacket pocket, I can say, ‘You had a wallet in your back pocket—is it still there?’ Now their focus is on their back pocket … and I’m free to steal from their jacket.1 This is how Apollo Robbins, self-described “gentleman thief” and public speaker, describes his technique. And it is true: moviemakers and magicians do it too. Like pickpockets, they are masterful in how they play with our ever-changing focus of attention. They steal it. Divert it. Distract. Force us to focus. Petty tricksters and light entertainment, of course, are only the beginning. Attention framing and misdirection pervade the very big and very real world. Spin-doctors work hard to ensure that some aspects of reality are shoved into our faces, while others are swept under the rug. Our world is attentionally engineered. Quite literally so. Channels for attention are carved into the fabric of our homes, the news we watch, the social media we consume, and into the urban landscapes around us. By creating channels of attention, agendas are generated and policies are framed. Similar techniques are used in the world of business. In a life full of distractions companies skillfully use the “choreography” of attention to get us to focus on where it suits them. Flickering billboards crowd cities and roadsides. Windows pop up on computer screens. Messages arrive on smartphones. They are designed to capture attention. Other techniques play with our motivation. They use our fluctuating desires and goals to get us to focus on that one buyable item rather than the myriads of others 1 Greene 2013. we could – then and there – have concentrated on instead (why don’t you get some chewing gum when you are waiting at the cashier anyway?). Indeed some argue that in the contemporary economy attention “has become a more valuable currency than the kind you store in bank accounts” and so “understanding and managing attention is now the single most determinate of business success.”2 Attention shapes how our lives are going. Personally and collectively. This is why there are industries dedicated to its manipulation. We should not leave the understanding of attention to those who manipulate it. What is attention? How is related to how our lives are going? How is attention related to other aspects of an agent’s life: her preferences, actions, goals, experience, knowledge, and belief? It is hard to find a place for attention. On the one hand, the idea that attention is a piece of neuronal machinery can seem attractive. The much discussed attention deficits can be fixed, some think, by medicating the child – oiling the brain machine with Ritalin and the like.3 Few would think that knowledge deficits can be fixed in the same way. On the other hand, attention can seem to be one of the most subjective, intimate aspects of our personal experience, and something that can be skillfully engaged. David Foster Wallace, in a widely publicized commencement speech, for example recommends: “if you really learned how … to pay attention, then you will know you have other options. It will actually be within your power to experience a crowded, hot, slow, consumer-hell type situation as not only meaningful, but sacred, on fire with the same force that lit the stars: compassion, love, fellowship, the subsurface unity of all things.”4 Can we provide an account of attention that integrates what we know from its scientific study with its central role in shaping agency and experience? This book provides such an account. Its main goal is to argue that attention is central to the structure of the mind. Attention is not another element of the mind – like perception, cognition, emotion, motivation or intention. Attention is not a separate box or capacity in the organization of mind. Attention is constituted by a structure of the mind that contains elements of the mind as parts. Attentional structure is the organizing of the mind into parts that are central or prioritized and those that are peripheral. Depending on what kind of state is currently the center of our mind, there can be perceptual attention, intellectual attention, emotional attention, desire-like attention and attentive basketball playing. Attention thus crosscuts the usual divisions of the mind: between the cognitive and the conative, the perceptual and the intellectual, the active and the passive, the epistemic and the practical. Attention can be any of these things. The priority structure of the mind is orthogonal to those other partitions of the mental. Because attention is a structure of the mind, attention is both 2 Davenport and Beck 2001, p. 3. See the US National Institute of Mental Health Guidelines (NIMH 2014). A recent meta-analyses of more than 9000 (sic!) studies estimates a worldwide prevalence of ADHD of 5 % in childhood – with strong variations of estimates depending both on world-region and methodology (Polanczyk et al. 2007). Adult prevalence (about which much less is known) is estimated to be around 2.5 % (Simon et al. 2009). Both studies are cited in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-5) (American Psychiatric Association 2013). 4 Wallace 2009, p. 92f. 3 basic and dependent: it is a structure that is basic, but a mental life needs to fill that structure. If one looks at specific elements of the mind, one will never find the attention; attention tends to evaporate on a close look; nothing but one mental state after the other. Attention is about how the parts of the mind are related. This account of the nature of attention, and the corresponding account of how attention structures conscious experience, helps to show why attention matters. The struggle over attention is a struggle over mental territory. What gets into our “universe” 5? What gets a central place in it, and what is a mere side note? To manipulate attention is to manipulate how a mental life is put together. 2 The nature of attention, and how it shapes consciousness The book addresses two main questions. The first question is: What is attention? This is a question about the nature of attention. What is the phenomenon that Apollo Robbins and the advertisement companies try to manipulate, that a child with ADHD has problems in sustaining, and the capacity for which meditation is supposed to enhance? Indeed, is there a single phenomenon or just a complex of syndromes? Is attention a brain mechanism, a mental resource or something else? Are there different forms of attention, and how – if at all – are they unified? My brief answer to the first question is this: attention is a unified phenomenon, but not a unified mechanism or brain property. Attention is a unified subject level phenomenon (Chapter 1). It is a mental activity that we can – but need not – perform intentionally (Chapter 2). Activities in the relevant sense are on-going mental processes (distinguished from mental states) that involve subject level guidance (Chapter 3). Specifically, attention is the activity of prioritizing some parts of our minds over others. It consists in regulating, what I call, priority structures. These are structures of mental states. In terms of priority structures we can provide a unified account of all forms of attention (Chapter 4). I argue that priority structures play a crucial role for organize, integrate, and coordinate the various parts of a subject’s life (Chapter 5). The regulation of priority structures is guided by psychological salience. Guidance by psychological salience, I argue, is subject level guidance (Chapter 6). And can be controlled by the subject’s executive control system: her goals, plans, and intentions. When it is controlled like this, a particular stretch of attention can be a paradigmatic intentional action (Chapter 7). The second question is: What is the relationship between attention and consciousness? 5 We can thus agree with James 1890/1950 (p. 424) who says that “each of us literally chooses, by his ways of attending to things, what sort of a universe he shall appear to himself to inhabit.” What is the subjective side of attention? What is it like to be distracted, and what is it like to keep and control the focus? The difference attention makes to consciousness is often subtle: when the pickpocket shifts your focus to the back pocket, you might not notice that shift. But nevertheless your experience is different afterwards. What is the phenomenological difference made by a difference in the focus of attention? Is there unified type of experience that is characteristic of attention, or is there just a complex of different phenomenological effects of attention? And what, in general, is the connection between attention and consciousness? My brief answer to the second question is: the effects of attention on consciousness cannot be deflated. While attention sometimes simply makes things visible and affects conscious appearances, the phenomenal contribution of attention goes beyond those effects. The phenomenal character of a mental episode is therefore not exhausted by how things appear to the subject (Chapter 8). The structural nature of attention, I argue, is reflected in the structure of consciousness. Attentional structure manifests in consciousness as the differentiation of the phenomenal field into center and periphery. There is phenomenal structure in addition to phenomenal qualities (Chapter 9). The guidance of attention also has a phenomenal manifestation. Psychological salience, I argue, shows why the stream of consciousness is experienced as flowing (Chapter 10). And the active, intentional, guidance of attention provides an answer to how we know about attention “from the inside” (Chapter 11). While the empirical evidence on the relationship between attention and consciousness remains inconclusive (Chapter 12), I argue that the phenomenal structure of consciousness is essential to it. Without structure consciousness would not provide us with a unified, subjective perspective. Consciousness, on the resulting view, is an engaged and active perspective (Chapter 13). On the way to answering those two main questions about the nature of attention and about its relationship to consciousness, we will encountered many other topics that have been at the center of many philosophical discussions – some ancient and traditional, and some of intense current controversy. And they are questions whose answer, I will argue, is fundamentally transformed once we have a proper grasp on what attention is and how it shapes consciousness. 3 Attention and philosophy The book is a work of philosophy. It approaches its goals by looking at the territory through a philosophical lens and by drawing on philosophical tools. The book is intended for philosophers as well as for empirical researchers interested in foundational questions. It is written with the intent that both groups can learn something from it. It aims, on the one hand, to show that the study of attention is of intrinsic philosophical interest and of crucial significance for central topics in the philosophy of mind. On the other hand, it also shows how the current empirical investigation of attention is fruitfully complemented with work at the level of generality that a philosophical analysis provides. In stark contrast to the intensity of public interest in attention and to the richness and detail of its scientific investigation, professional philosophers for a long time have almost completely neglected attention as a topic of study. While philosophers had – for decades – worked on belief and desire, knowledge, memory, intention, plans, action and consciousness, there had been comparably little work on what attention is, its role, its connections to other aspects of mentality, or its normative significance. Where PsycNET, the main database for publications in psychology, contained about as many entries for “attention” as for “consciousness” Philosopher’s Index, the equivalent for publications in philosophy, had only three percent of the number of “consciousness” entries for “attention”.6 This situation is striking. At least in hindsight. Outside Western academia many think of attention as a “philosophical” topic;7 it is a topic that was much discussed in the rich Eastern philosophical traditions; it was an important topic for early modern philosophers such as Malebranche and Thomas Reid; and it never went out of fashion in the phenomenological school of thought tracing its roots to Husserl. So, why did philosophers in so much of Western academia begin to neglect attention? Were they justified in doing so? Here is a first potential reason for the philosophical neglect of attention. It is the thought that there are no specifically philosophical problems about attention. While we might not currently know all the details about attention and lack a fully comprehensive theory, we have a good grip on how to investigate it by using the standard methodologies of psychology and the neurosciences. The image of attention as in itself philosophically boring was no doubt facilitated by the strong influence of information processing tools on empirical attention research. Isn’t attention – after all – just a limitation in processing capacity? Information theoretic tools came to be central in psychology in the 1940s and 1950s. The psychologists who pioneered these new methods, like Donald Broadbent or Anne Treisman, approached the human mind with the attitude of engineers. They asked: how does it work – and how can we improve it? Other pioneers of cognitive science, like Noam Chomsky, engaged with philosophers and with philosophical questions. By contrast, the pioneers of modern attention research, whose approaches shaped the field for almost half a century, were explicitly interested in questions of practical application (how many instruments can a pilot reliably monitor?) and they were explicitly un-interested in “philosophical” questions (is the mind a blank slate? How many mental faculties are there?). And they had a clear picture of attention. Attention, according to them, is a filter in the information-processing machine that is our mind. And once one thinks of attention as such a filter, or relatedly as a set of mechanisms by which pieces of information get channeled, suppressed or exported, a resource, or as a limitation in processing capacity, it is hard to find anything that is philosophically puzzling about it. Broadbent’s or Treisman’s early models might have 6 The situation has started to change, and the philosophical investigation of attention – as the discussions in this book will demonstrate – is becoming a flourishing field. 7 Amazon.com classifies much of the literature on mindfulness as philosophy (Among the 100 top sales in “philosophy” in early 2014 we find six books on mindfulness training; accessed February 7th, 2014). to be refined to integrate them with what we now know about parallel processing, or they might have to be replaced by more specific neuronal models; but these are all challenges and tasks for scientific psychology and neuroscience; they do not pose problems a philosopher would be in an appropriate position to answer. According to the general picture, attention is just an aspect of cognitive processing. One of my goals in this book is to remind us that what we have here really is no more than that: a vague general picture. I show that once we scrutinize that picture, attention does start to pose interesting philosophical questions and it poses challenges to some of the standard methodologies of psychology and the neurosciences. Once we look closer at the science of attention we recognize that the scientific theories of attention do not manage to identify attention with any specific form of information processing or neuronal mechanism (and indeed hardly ever aim at such an identification). The science of attention mostly deals with the effects of attention on information processing and on psycho-physical response, as well as with the neuronal correlates of attention. It leaves open what attention is, i.e. what it is that has these effects and is underpinned by these neuronal correlates. Chapter 1 argues that we should treat attention like many philosophers have treated thought, desire, volition or intention. Attention is a subject level mental activity. It is unlikely that a reductive identification of attention with a specific brain process or property will succeed. There are substantial subject level facts about attention. These need to be integrated with what we know about attentional information processing, but they cannot be identified with such processing. Further, and in this sense different from thought and desire, I will show that attention is in an important sense holistic – it consists of a complex structure, organized both at a time and over time out of other mental states (see Chapter 3 and Chapter 4). For this reason, attention cannot be located as a particular node in a functional analysis of the mind, and thus escapes a standard model of explanation in the cognitive sciences.8 The capacity for attention is not one that we will find by analyzing the capacities of the mind into an organization of simpler and simpler sub-capacities. What I say about my first aim – to investigate the nature of attention – thus will show that the “attention is easy” reason for the philosophical neglect of attention is not a good one. There might be a second reason for the long time neglect of attention in philosophical academia. It derives from the fact that one of the philosophically most interesting aspects of attention – i.e. how it affects the structures of consciousness – for a long time fell outside the view of the most central philosophical discussions. Philosophical discussions of consciousness were focused on understanding the connections between consciousness and the material world (the mind-body problem). They were not focused on getting the details of the structure of consciousness right. But questions about the structure of consciousness have resumed their central position in the philosophical debate. They have re-entered partly from within the debate of the mind-body problem. Consider discussions of the relationship between consciousness and intentionality. Many philosophers have been (and still are) interested in the 8 See Cummins 1983, 2000. interface of consciousness and intentionality because they believe that it holds the key to a successful naturalization of consciousness and hence a solution to the mindproblem. But at the center of this interface lie questions about the structure of consciousness: are all conscious states intentional states, i.e. are they in some special, interesting sense directed at or about something? Is the phenomenal character of conscious experience (what it is like for you) exhausted by its intentional content (or intentional content plus the mode with which that content is presented)? To answer these questions, first and foremost, is to understand something about the structure of consciousness – and hence is independent of ulterior motives concerning naturalization. The second big goal of the book is to show that considerations about attention are highly relevant for answering questions about the structure of consciousness. This second goal – to some degree at least – is independent of what we want to say about the nature of attention. That attention shapes consciousness is something that even a proponent of the view of attention as cognitive mechanism can accept; a cognitive mechanism after all might affect (or underlie) our experience. Further, that there are effects of attention on consciousness is fairly uncontroversial. What it is like to listen to a piece of music is clearly affected by whether you focus attention on the sounds of the piano or on the melody being played by the saxophone. The question is what to make of these effects. I will show that in order to accommodate them we have to go beyond the intentional structure of consciousness. We have to take seriously the idea that certain elements are more central and others more peripheral in the field of consciousness (Chapter 9). Consciousness has centrality structure in addition to intentional structure. Indeed, I will argue, this structure is essential to consciousness (Chapter 13). Without attentional structure consciousness would not be the unified, subjective perspective it is. Considerations about attention also affect other important topics about the structure of consciousness. Consider the unity of consciousness. Are the conscious occurrences in a single subject especially unified? I will argue that the centrality relations between the parts of our field of consciousness serve as a form of glue that connects those parts into a single unified whole (Chapter 13). Attention is at least one important aspect of what unifies conscious experience. Finally, consider the question of whether we can be or become aware of our own conscious experiences. According to some advocates of the so-called transparency of consciousness we are never aware of our own experiences but only aware of the world through our experiences of it.9 According to other views about consciousness, by contrast, every conscious state necessarily is such that its subject is aware of being in it.10 I will show that by appeal to attention we can defend a more subtle position: we are aware of a conscious state when we actively bring it to the attentional center of consciousness. In contrast to some versions of the transparency thesis, we thus can be aware of conscious states (Chapter 11). But we also do not need to claim that every conscious experience brings with it self-awareness. 9 See e.g. Harman 1990 or Byrne 2001. See e.g. Kriegel 2009. 10 4 Methods I said that this is a book of philosophy, that it asks philosophical questions and uses philosophical tools. What do I mean by that? What is my philosophical method? Generally, I agree with those who are skeptical of the existence of a specifically philosophical method. We use many methods. Nevertheless, we can group the tools of this book into roughly the following categories (in praxis the tools interact in often complex ways). First, there are scientific results in the psychology and neuroscience of attention (and consciousness). A study of the nature of attention and the way its shapes consciousness cannot proceed in independence of studies of attentional processing and the psychophysical effects of attention. The science of attention is one of the richest areas in cognitive psychology and neuroscience. Philosophical work on attention is fortunate to find itself in the middle of such riches. While, as I said, I will argue that attention cannot be exhaustively understood on the level of neuronal or sub-subject processing (Chapter 1), the nature of the processes that underpin attention puts constraints on the kind of thing attention could be (see Chapters 2-7). The fact that much of attentional processing consists in synchronized activity of a large variety of functionally distinct brain areas, for example, is at least prima facie evidence against identifying attention with a highly specific computational function that does not require such large-scale neuronal integration (Chapter 1 and Chapter 4). Similarly, the fact that attention often modulates early sensory processing can be used in an argument against the idea that attention just is an agent’s selecting information for higher level processing (Chapter 5). Understanding the various attentional processes, what they have in common, and how they are operating is an essential part of understanding attention. The route from science to philosophy is not a one way street, though. While I sometimes draw on science, at other times I will criticize common assumptions in the science of attention (e.g. Chapter 1 argues – against widespread assumptions – that attention is “real” but not a well-defined set of neuronal mechanisms). And finally, sometimes I will take a stance in on-going scientific debates (e.g. in Chapter 5 I argue against the popular view that the function of attention is to protect the organism from information overflow; in Chapter 6 I take sides with those who hold that all attention capture is contingent on the subject’s tasks, expectations and goals; and in Chapter 12 and 13 I suggest that attention is necessary but not sufficient for conscious experience). My owl of Minerva, to use Hegel’s famous image, thus is going to fly in broad daylight: I am going to work in middle of a lively on-going scientific and philosophical project. Philosophers should neither be ignorant of the relevant science, nor should they show false deference to what “the science says”. Especially in cognitive science most results are (at least somewhat) controversial within the scientific community, and one actually has to get quite deeply into the science to take an informed stance on a topic of philosophical relevance. There are risks to this sort of work (such as being undermined by new scientific findings, but also being disappointing to both philosophers and scientists). But there are also benefits (such as understanding more about a complex domain). How the relevant risks and benefits should be balanced has to be determined on a case-by-case basis. There is a second tool, which will be used in tandem with the first. This tool is our ordinary understanding of attention (and consciousness). Given the central role of attention in our understanding of mentality (see Chapter 1) we can draw on this understanding in order to provide us with a first grip on the phenomenon. I will thus sometimes appeal to ordinary judgments that make use of the concept of attention. Insofar as these judgments are true, they will tell us something about attention. Insofar as they are epistemically warranted, we can rely on them for answering questions about attention. This much I take to be uncontroversial. And sometimes fairly ordinary truths can tell us something important about attention. For example, if some people are able to focus their attention on a painting for more than five minutes, then attention must be something that is sometimes going on for more than an instant (see Chapter 2 and Chapter 3). In addition, attending must be the kind of thing that people are able to do (ibid.). Ordinary judgments about attention, the way I am using them, are not sacrosanct. They might be false. The findings of a psychological study might show that they are false. In this case, our theorizing should not rely on them. My third tool is introspection on conscious experience (this tool, obviously, will be used mostly in the second part of the book – the one that deals with attention and consciousness). In many circumstances subjects reliably report aspects of the phenomenal character of their own experience. We can accept the reliability of such reports without assuming that phenomenal character is constituted by access to it, that we have a special faculty of introspection, or indeed that there is any unified and distinguished introspective method. We also are certainly not infallible at describing our own experience, and at least generalizations about our own experience can be highly contentious.11 Arguably introspection on consciousness is roughly as reliable as perception of our immediate environment. We become unreliable if the circumstances are not right: brief exposures, distraction, delays between observation and report, drugs and sleep deprivation are the usual suspects. Under similar circumstances introspective reports will be unreliable as well. Introspection, like other methods, should be used cautiously and with an eye to when it is likely to be reliable, and when it is likely to fail: it will, for example, be often easier to detect whether there is some phenomenal difference between two scenarios than to say what the difference is, and introspection will be a better guide to finding out about aspects of consciousness than to finding out about mental processing, mental faculties, and the like (see Chapters 8 and Chapter 9 for such uses of introspection). In praxis, scientific results, ordinary understanding and introspection often interact in complex ways and indeed cannot be separated. Many scientific results regarding attention to some degree rely on our ordinary understanding and introspective report. Ordinary understanding is both subtly influenced by popular science and often draws on introspection of the first person case. And introspection often occurs in the context of considering scientific stimuli and within the confines of ordinary understanding. 11 Schwitzgebel 2008. See Watzl and Wu 2012 for discussion, and some of the points of this paragraph. 5 Reading guide The book is divided into thirteen chapters. Together they comprise a comprehensive story about the structuring mind. It is a story that begins with the science of attention and ends with the form of consciousness. The first part of the book is about the nature of attention (Chapters 1-7). The second part is about the relationship between attention and consciousness (Chapters 8-13). As for any book, there are many ways to read the present one. The one intended by the author is: begin at the beginning and end at the end. This to me was the most natural presentation of the ideas. But, of course, there are other options. If you want to get as quickly as possible to some of the main ideas of the book: read Chapter 4, 5 and 9. This should give you a decent overview of both the account of attention and of how it shapes consciousness. Then explore the other chapters to get a sense of the surrounding territory. If you are most interested in the nature of attention, and if your approach to this topic has been the scientific study of attention, you might want to start with Chapter 1 and then jump to Chapters 4-7. You can then return to reading Chapter 2 and Chapter 3 to clarify some issues that may have been puzzling. If you are most interested in the relationship between attention and consciousness, you may start with Chapter 8. Then work towards Chapter 9, Chapter 10 and Chapter 11 (a jump from Chapter 9 to Chapter 13 is also fairly natural), There will probably be some things that will be difficult to understand without the background of the first half of the book. But you will get some idea, and then can work backwards by reading Chapter 4 and then Chapter 3. These alternative routes through the landscape of ideas may intrinsically be as good as the route that goes from beginning to end. Books that followed those traces could have been written. Because they don’t follow the route I have pursued myself they may, though, lead to a more fragmented reading experience.