S^CKUs^^ >' Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium IVIember Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/whydidwestextendOOacem .01'^ 7^ working paper department of economics WHY DID THE WEST EXTEND THE FRANCHISE? GROWTH IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE INEQUALITY AND massachusetts institute of technology 50 memorial drive Cambridge, mass. 02139 WHY DID THE WEST EXTEND THE FRANCHISE? INEQUALITY AND GROWTH IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE Daron Acemoglu 96-32 October, 1996 FEB 5^ Why Did the West Extend the Franchise? Democracy, InequaUty and Growth in Historical Perspective* Daron Acemoglu^ James A. Robinson^ October 1996 Abstract During the nineteenth century, most Western societies extended the franchise, and then undertook previously unprecedented redistributive programs. We argue that these poUtical reforms can be viewed as strategic decisions by elites to prevent widespread social unrest and revolution. This accoimt suggests a new view of the origins of redistributive politics, a different explanation for the Kuznets curve, terize between democracy and growth. We characthe conditions under which an economy would go through the and new links equilibrium path experienced by Western societies, as opposed to an 'autocratic disaster' with stagnation at a low level of per capita in- come and high inequality, or an 'East Asian' type of development path with high output, low inequality, but no democracy. Keywords: Democracy, Enfranchisement, Growth, InequaUty, Re- distribution, Revolution. JEL Classification: D72, 015. We would like to thank Herschel Grossman, Claudia Goldin, Peter Lindert, Peter Temin, Jaume Ventura, Michael WaUerstein and seminar participants at Boston University for helpful comments and suggestions. Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Department of Economics, E52-371, Cambridge, 02319; e-mail: daronQmit.edu f University of Southern California, Department of Economics, LA, CA 90089; e-mail: j2Lrobins@alnitaLk.usc .edu. * "^ MA Introduction 1 The nineteenth, century was a period of high growth by historical standards; per capita income in Britain, the leading country, grew by approximately 2% per annum between 1830 and 1870 as opposed to less than 0.3% during th^ previous century (see Mokyr, 1993). The same period was also an era of fundamental political reform redistribution; British society and unprecedented changes and in taxation was transformed from an 'autocracy' run by an ehte to a democracy; the franchise was extended in 1832 then again in 1867 and 1884 to transfer voting rights to portions of society which did not previously have any political representation (see Lee, 1994, DarvaU 1934, Briggs, 1959). The decades after the pohtical reforms witnessed radical social reforms, increased taxation and the extension of education to the masses. Finally, as noted by Kuznets, the large increase in inequality which preceded enfranchisement was followed by rapid progress towards more equality: the Gini coefficient for income inequality in England and Wales had risen from 0.400 in 1823 to 0.627 in 1871, and feU to 0.443 in 1901 (see WiUiamson, 1985, Table 4.2). Two key factors in the reduction in inequality were the increase in the proportion of skilled workers (see Williamson, 1985) and redistribution towards the poorer segments of the society; for instance taxes rose from 8.12% of National Product in 1867 to 18.8% by 1927, and the progressivity of the tax system was increased substantially (see Lindert, 1989). Similar trends were visible in other countries. While the unique historical origins of the United States have typically exception to many been regarded as making generalizations, the struggle towards full it an democracy was a protracted one, even after the Civil War (see Crotty, 1977). Moreover, exactly as in Britain, there was the same close relationship between the and rise fall see Lindert of inequality (which in the and Williamson, 1980) and the in the early 1930's. of the society in reached rise of its peak around 1930, the redistributive state Voting rights were also extended to larger segments Germany, France, Norway, Netherlands, Austria, Finland, Sweden, Belgium and France during the (see US Rueschemeyer et al. latter part of the nineteenth century 1992 and Carstairs, 1980). In all of these countries there was also unprecedented redistributive activity, though the exact form and the emphasis on education versus welfare or other forms of transfers varied from country to country (see Flora and Heidenheimer, 1981). The economics redistribution literature has offered a large and growth and recently a nimiber interact, number many explanations of models in which for the of attempts to understand the links Kuznets curve, between democ- racy and development. However, the events of the nineteenth century do not conform to any of these models. First of aU, existing theories do not model political reform, making it impossible to understand the extension of the franchise which has changed the political Furthermore, even why it if there is and economic landscape a choice to extend the franchise, it is radically. not clear should have been extended, given that this extension led to massive redistribution at the expense of the ruling elites in every society. Therefore, there exists no convincing explanation to date for perhaps the most massive redistribution in history. In this paper, we offer a theory which provides an explanation for the extension of the franchise, and for the major political and economic trends of the nineteenth century. we Our approach is based on two assumptions which will substantiate using historical evidence in the next section: (i) before power industrialization, political is concentrated in the hands of a rich elite; the masses can attempt a revolution, or at least major social disturbance, (ii) and these by economic considerations. decisions are at least partly motivated These two assumptions lead to the following configuration of events: industrialization often starts with the poor unable to accumulate physical or capital while the rich do, thus inequality worsens. This more makes revolution a attractive option for the masses. In order to prevent social disturbances and revolution the itself to their human elite is forced to extend the franchise Once the future redistribution. newly acquired and inequality is franchise is and thereby commit extended, the masses use power to enact redistribution political in their favor, reduced. This story immediately implies the existence of some alternative develop- ment paths: first, growth could occur without increased inequality in which case a revolution never becomes a possibility, and there tion. The precondition for this equilibrium path, which is is no democratiza- reminiscent of the economic experiences of South Korea, Taiwan and Singapore, equal a relatively income so that even the poor segments of initial distribution of ciety can accumulate is (human) capital. Second, the economy may so- actually converge to a low level steady state before a revolution becomes a serious threat, in which we which case there call is an 'autocratic tial inequality is high, and neither democratization nor growth. This case, disaster', more is interestingly, when likely to happen when ini- the working classes are not well-organized and thus do not pose an effective threat of revolution. Overall, our analysis not only explains it also sheds light 1 . some central political trends but on a number of existing debates: We show that the link between democracy and growth is multi-dimensional. First, and is is fiill democratization is the response of elites to political pressure therefore often associated with growth this and rising inequality. It which causes our model to generate the positive relationship between development and democracy found in many cross-country empirical studies (see Przeworski and Limongi, 1993, HeUiwell, 1994, and Barro, 1996). Second, the impact of democratization on economic per- formance is ambiguous. To the extent that tion to the masses, taneously however it it encourages may distort the agents (such as the previous correlation between 2. We human elite). it leads to more capital accumulation, simul- accumulation by capital of other Thus, perhaps the lack of robust democracy and growth should not be explain the Kuznets curve, but do not predict that feature of all development processes Anand and Kanbur, Instead we redistribu- (this accords 1993, Fields, 1995 and Fields it surprising. should be a with the findings of and Jakubsen, 1993). predict that a Kuznets curve should be observed economy democratizes due when an to social pressure. This appears to general pattern in the data. fit the Further, although previous research has offered potential rationalizations for the Kuznets curve (e.g. Aghion and Bolton, 1993, Banerjee and Newman, 1996, Galor and Tsiddon, 1996), redistribution from above does not play a role in these theories, and yet in practice, the downturn of the Kuznets curve often takes place after a large increase in redistributive activity (see Lindert, 1989).^ 3. Our analysis also offers a tive correlation between new interpretation of the cross-country nega- groiArth ^The finding that democratization and inequality. Previous research has leads to reduced inequality cross-country studies, for example, Muller, 1988. is also found in recent taken either one of two routes: Persson and Tabellini (1994) and Alesina and Rodrik (1994) suggest that more inequality leads to more redis- tribution thus to lower growth, but this does not appear to accord with cross-country facts as documented by Perotti (1996). In contrast, Saint-Paul (1995) and Benabou (1996b) suggest that less inequality leads to ital more redistribution, but redistribution encourages human cap- accumulation and this stimulates growth. This approach however does not conform to the historical experience where the most radical redistributive policies were introduced at times of high inequality. theory predicts that the degree of redistribution is likely to jump up at times of social unrest is Our non-monotonic and which coincide with peri- ods of high inequality^, and also that redistribution may lead to higher growth. However, our model does not yield a positive correlation be- tween inequality and growth (or output) because economies that reach a high level of inequality redistribute enough to reduce inequality significantly in order to prevent social unrest, and thus in the post-war data they appear to have limited inequality (and high output). 4. We also suggest a non-linear relation between political unrest nomic performance whereby the threat of revolution and may be an effective way of avoiding a poor economic income per capita and high inequality. and eco- social unrest outcome with low Previous research has empha- sized the costs of 'rent-seeking' type activities, or of 'insurrections' (see Benabou, 1996a for a survey), but the support for these conclusions comes from recent cross-country regressions using only the post-war data. A historical ^The empirical ity is view again suggests that there is relationship between increased income inequality more and to the story political instabil- indeed strongly positive, see for example Muller and Seligson, 1987. than a simple negative link between fact, political ixnrest the political unrest which led to redistribution and growth. In may have been the key to the success of a number of Western countries. Our paper belongs to the growing literature on political economy and growth. As weU as the papers already mentioned, there are a number of im- portant contributions more closely related to our work. First, the possibility of revolution is modelled in an important contribution by Roemer (1985), but he does not relate it to the level of inequality, nor does he discuss poHtical reform can prevent the unprivileged against the it. Grossman (1991,1993) models predation by rich, and Ades (1995) and Ades and Verdier (1993) investigate a model where there the hands of an elite. how is concentration of political power in However, none of these papers note that democratiza- tion can occur strategically in order to prevent political unrest, nor do they and growth consequences discuss the redistributive of democratization, al- though Grossman (1993) analyzes the case of land-reform as the outcome of political pressure. Our paper is also closely related to Galor and Zeira (1993) and Banerjee and Newman (1993) who model investment opportunities indivisible and thus show that distribution of income matters development. Finally, our contribution shares a and Weingast (1989) who commitment, but growth and common theme with North also argue that political reform can in the context of the for as be a method of ascendancy of the English Parliament in the seventeenth century. The plan of the paper is as foUows. The next section gives a brief of overview of some historical evidence that has motivated us and supports our key assumptions and conclusions. Section 3 describes the economic environment. Section 4 characterizes equilibrium dynamics in the absence of the threat of revolution. Section 5 introduces the possibihty of revolution. Section 6 discusses three possible paths of economic and political development. Section 7 briefly discusses some extensions. Section 8 concludes. Historical Perspective 2 Our theory is partly motivated by historical evidence. Here we will provide a brief overview, emphasizing the evidence in support of the following three features: 1. Inequality was increasing before the extension of the franchise. 2. The franchise was extended as a strategic move to avoid a revolution or at least very costly pohtical imrest.^ Democratization led to a surge in redistribution, and the increased 3. supply of educated workers caused by this redistribution, and the direct impact of these redistributive efforts were key factors in the reduction in inequality. Most of our evidence comes from Britain but we wiU also refer to the his- torical experiences of other countries. In Britain, the franchise in 1832, and then again women were 2.1 Inequality and 1884 (and later in 1919 and 1928 when finally allowed to vote). Data on income liable. in 1867 was extended inequality for the nineteenth century are not extremely re- However, a number of studies using different data sources on Britain ^The discussion pertaining to this point will also establish that before the enfranchisement power was concentrated in the hands of an elite and there was a threat of revolution. reach the same conclusion. Inequahty increased substantially during the first half of the nineteenth century, then started falling in the second half. The turning point appears to be sometime after 1870. This picture also con- with the findings of Crafts (1989), and of Lindert (1986) on wealth sistent inequality, but 1 is is not completely uncontroversial (see Feinstein, 1988). Table taken from Williamson's (1985) Table 4.2 gives a representative picture: - British Income Inequality Share of the Top 10% Gini Coefficient Table 1 A 1823 47.51 0.400 1830 49.95 0.451 1871 62.29 0.627 1891 57.50 0.550 1901 47.41 0.443 1911 36.43 0.328 1915 36.46 0.333 similar pattern also emerges from earnings inequality data reported Williamson (1985) Table 3.2 where the Gini and in 1827 to 0.358 in 1851 Another country is the US for for falls coefficient increases in from 0.293 to 0.331 in 1901. which there has been research into inequality trends which Williamson and Lindert (1980) find a Kuznets curve type relation. Though Goldin and Katz (1995) disagree about the timing, there is no disagreement that contracted. came some point inequality The most common view in the early 1930's policies in the '''This is at US is increased, and then that the peak of the Kuznets curve which are the years when the most redistributive history were introduced.'^ however a long-time after universal suffrage. It is important to note that in the Franchise Extension and the Threat of Revolution 2.2 When introducing the electoral reform to the British parliament in 1831, the prime minister Earl Grey said "There is no-one more decided against annual parliaments, universal suffrage and the of my reform is to ballot, than am I... prevent the necessity of revolution...! am The Principal reforming to preserve, not to overthrow." (quoted in Evans, 1983). This view of political reform is shared by modern historians such as Briggs, 1959 and Lee, 1994. For instance, Darvall (1934) writes: 'the major change of the first three decades of the nineteenth century was the reform of Parliament by the 1832 Reform off Act, and this was introduced by the Whigs.. as a measure to stave any further threat of revolution by extending the franchise classes. " In fact, the years by unprecedented to the middle preceding the electoral reform were characterized political unrest including the Luddite Riots from 1811- 1816, the Spa Fields Riots of 1816, the Peterloo Massacre in 1819, and the Swing Riots of 1830 The reforms (see Stevenson, 1979, for an overview). that extended political power from a narrow elite to larger sections of the society were immediately viewed as a success not because of some ideal of enlightenment or democracy, but because the threat of rev- olution and further unrest were avoided Reform Act, the (see Lee, 1994). Before the 1832 total electorate stood at 478,000 out of a population of 24 and even poor and illiterate and Crotty, 1977). Perhaps more importantly, lower middle-class non-immigrant voters saw themselves as highly upwardly mobile (see Kaelble, 1986, Lindert, 1989,1996), and thus their desire for redistribution was different than the lower class British voters. In this respect, 1930's are a turning point: the end of maiss immigration and the Great Depression appear to have altered people's perceptions of social mobility, and the level of inequality widened enough so that the costs and benefits of redistribution for the lower middle-class voters are likely to have changed. While we do not incorporate this story into our formal analysis below we feel that it shows the relevance of our results to the US case. US, the poorest segments of the society, immigrants, blacks whites, were excluded from the political process (see Williamson, 1960 Although the Act increased the electorate to 813,000 by reducing million. the property and wealth restrictions on voting, the majority of British people could not vote. Moreover, the elites still age since 123 constituencies contained 'rotten-boroughs'), and there had considerable scope less for patron- than 1,000 voters (the so-called evidence of serious corruption and intimida- is tion of voters which was not halted in Britain until the Ballot Act of 1872 and the Corrupt and lUegal Practices Act of 1883 which introduced effective secret ballots at elections. The process of increased representation gained movement during the 1830's representation as the only momentiim with the Chartist and 1840's and leading way to guarantee a chartists more equitable saw increased distribution of the gains of growth (see Briggs, 1959). In the meantime, the response of the elite to the Chartist movement was again one of preventing further unrest. For instance, during the 1850's Lord John Russell made several attempts to introduce franchise reform arguing that chise to the upper revival of political levels of the it was necessary to extend the fran- working classes as a means of preventing the radicahsm (Lee, 1994). In discussing the lead up to the 1867 Reform Act, Lee argues that "as with the first Reform Act, the threat of violence has been seen as a significant factor in forcing the pace; history repeating for itself. " This interpretation is supported by example Trevelyan (1937) and Cowling (1967). many was other historians, The Act was preceded by the founding of the National Reform Union in 1864 and the Reform League in 1865 and the Hyde Park riots of catalyst (see Harrison, 1965). torate was expanded from 1.4 As a result of these reforms, the total elec- miUion to 2.52 million and then doubled again by the Reform Act of 1884 (though and the Redistribution Act July 1866 provided the most immediate of 1885 this represented only 65% of adiolt males) removed many remaining 10 inequalities in the distribution of seats (see Wright, 1970). Britain was not alone in responding to poHtical pressure with reform, much the same forces were at work in instance, the predecessor of the many modern other Western societies. welfare state and For social security system were introduced in German by Bismarck as a way of preventing the democrats gaining further power and enacting more radical reform. social Bismarck was from an industrial groups. He industrialist background and had very close never denied that it was their interests he had in mind, and frequently emphasized that these reforms would stop the He opposed measures aimed democracy and sociahsm. links to rise of social at opening higher education to the poor very rigorously because he thought they would lead further 1990, and more radical demands from the working Tampke, 1981, and Heidenheimer, 1981, especially p. 281). Redistribution 2.3 Starting from the end of the nineteenth century, enced increased redistributive of policies and it is came from. For much classes (see Baldwin, all Western societies experi- Each country followed a activity. different mix not currently understood where exactly these differences instance, the US and to a lesser extent Canada, achieved higher primary school enrollment rates than European countries^ but did not introduce social security provisions nor other direct redistribution measures its until well into the twentieth century. Germany, perhaps thanks to bureaucratic tradition, was able to develop the most far-reaching welfare state at the turn of the century but among made no effort to increase schooling the masses (see Heidenheimer, 1981). Again the salient case for our ^This seems to have stemmed primarily from idiosyncratic factors such as from the many immigrants, see Easterlin (1981). non-conformist rehgious backgrounds of 11 analysis appears to be Britain which adopted a mixture of direct redistribu- tion and mass education. The Reform Acts the British state. of the 1867-1884 were a turning point in the history of In 1871 Gladstone reformed the civil service, opening to public examination and making it meritocratic. Liberal it and conservative governments introduced a considerable amount of labor market legislation fundamentally changing the nature of industrial relations in favor of workers. During 1906-1914, the Liberal Party under the leadership of Lloyd George introduced the modern redistributive state into Britain, including health and unemployment insurance, government financed pensions, and a commitment to redistributive taxation. As a result of these fiscal changes, taxes as a proportion of National Product more than doubled in the 30 years following 1870 and then doubled again. In the meantime, taxation also became highly progressive (see Lindert, 1989). Consistent with these trends, Lindert (1994) has recently shown that variables measuring democracy, in particular voter turnout, had a significant positive effect on the expansion of government expenditures on social programs (welfare and unemployment compensation, pensions, health care and housing subsidies) in the period from 1880-1930, again supporting the interpretation that democratization has been a key driving force of the radical shift towards redistributive fiscal and social policy. Meanwhile the education system which was only open to the eUtes during most of the nineteenth century also became more and more open to the masses (see Schofield, 1973 and Mitch, 1992 and 1993, on the poor educational standards of the British workforce during the early 1800s). First, school leaving age was set at 11 in 1893, then increased to 12 in 1899 and special provisions for the children of needy families were introduced. Finally, the reform act of 1902 introduced pubhc schooling as a duty of the government 12 towards people. its As a result of these changes, the proportion of 10-year olds enrolled in school which stood at a disappointing to 100% in 1900 (see Ringer, 1979, p. Many 207). 40% in 1870 increased educational historians argue that the democratization of British society was the key driving force behind these changes (e.g. Simon, 1960). Williamson (1985) sees the increase reason for the in inequality. fall Thus skills as to the extent that contributed to this increase in the supply of were a key factor in reducing inequality. and Williamson (1985) who write that supply of in the skills, This the key mass schooling the education policies summed-up by Lindert is "the rate of skill deepening reached impressive levels in the era following the educational reforms of the 1870's, coinciding with the drop down Britain's Kuznets Curve." They continue; "The American correlation looks similar, though the turning points come well into the 20th century." later, Moreover, the data already reported in the previous subsection suggests that the reduction in income inequality was faster than the compression in earnings inequality which is consistent with the view that increased and more progressive taxation, and more transfers to the poor played a key role in reducing inequality. In the US too, increased schooling seems to have been a crucial factor reducing earnings inequality. The proportion of high school graduates which stood at 4% in 1890 reached 12% in 1930 (Goldin Williamson and Lindert, 1980). Further, in heimer (1981, p. line also with our approach, Heiden- 273) notes that the seven-fold increase in the electorate between 1824 and 1840 was the driving force mon and Katz, 1996, see for the emergence of the com- school movement, but notes that "entitlement remained closely linked to enfranchisement. When the blacks were excluded from voting following the Reconstruction period. Southern countries spent about ten times as 13 much " per child for teachers' salaries in the white as in the black schools" (see also Goldin, 1994, on the increase in schooling and the role of the government in this process). Overall, 'i;o we can summarize our discussion by quoting Easterlin (1981): judge from the historical experience of the world's 25 largest nations, the establishment and expansion of formal schooling has depended in large part on to political conditions mass education is and and ideological influences" frequently symptomatic of a and associated ideology in a "a major major commitment shift in political direction conducive to greater power upward mobility for a wider segment of the population. The Model 3 Fundamentals 3.1 Consider a non-overlapping generations model with bequests. Time crete and runs from zero for only to infinity. one period and each beget a growth. This continuum and a proportion level their 1 — A I dis- continuum of agents of mass one live single offspring. is initially split There into a proportion A A who form a rich "elite", so that if there is member is no population who are "poor" only distinguished by the endowments. Throughout the paper superscript p agent and r will denote rich agent (or A > is will denote poor of the elite) .We assimie that fuU democracy and majority voting, the median voter will be a poor agent. There is a unique consumption good y with price normalized to unity, and a unique accumulable as a combination of asset, human and human capital h (which should be thought physical capital). the economy at time zero and assume that for 14 i We < 0, begin our analysis of the economy is in a steady state with the poor having capital h^ and the starting level of capital in the At time t = 0, a new technology able and will be used for all capital. where The H^ Hq = is > 0. is The Xjh^. becomes avail- This technology offers two methods linear in htmian human + H^ = Ht market production. capital devoted to , or "home-production" technology: home ^ J h\di. We assume that production. Natu- A> B, thus market always more productive. The advantage of home production is not taxable whereas taxes can be imposed on the market produc- tion sector. The only role of home production in our analysis that the equilibrium tax rate wiU be less than 100%. human (before tax) is to guarantee Finally, we assume capital always trades in a perfectly competitive market, thus the wage rate per unit of human Wt 3.1.2 + (1 — 1. a market technology: a non-market, "informal" we have H^ it is i industrial production) the amount of himian capital used in is production that XIiq Both production techniques are the amount of is The second where H^ first is (e.g. periods of producing the final good. that therefore is hQ> hQ> Technology of Production 3.1.1 rally, economy elite = capital is given as: A. Preferences All agents have identical preferences defined over their own consumption and the 'educational bequests' they leave to their offspring (the "joy of giving" 15 ' model of bequests). These are represented by a logarithmic = = fJ'"{4,4+i) «^(4) 4+1) for i = group i r,p and alive in period (1 - 7)logCt + 7logej+i - 7) log 4 Here (0,1). and t, ej^j if 4+i if 4+1 >1 < 1 the consumption of a cj is at the end of the individual's implies that there is member the investment in the offspring's is Both the consumption and the investment (bequest) capital. made 7 G (1 utility function: The form life. a minimimi amount of bequest, of human decisions are of the utility function el_^i = 1, and when the agent cannot afford this amount, he wiU leave nothing to his offspring. This non-convexity will capture the feature that be able to accumulate assets paper we will also The will treat all be identical, and aU members himian capital 1, and also jd < given by: is = max {l;Z{4^,y} 1 which will The presence (1) guarantee that accumulation does max{l; .} that even in the absence of any investment, there is not continue indefinitely. of human capital that each agent 3.1.3 Individual Maximization Problem With in equation (1) implies a minimum amount of would have. these assumptions in place, individual max ^An of the elite identical. offspring's Z > agents wiU not Galor and Zeira, 1993).^ Throughout the poor agents as hl_^_i where (see when very poor i's problem can be written u(cl, ej+i) alternative formulation would be to eissume that there of consumption below which people save nothing. 16 as: (2) was some subsistence level subject to: 4 + ei^, <yl = where yl is the post tax tax) price of one unit of and > Tf - {1 income of household human capital + Ti n)wthi (3) Wt is the equihbrium (before at time t,Tt is the tax rate on income, i, the transfer that the agent receives from the state. is The budget constraint faced by the agent implies that a unit of consumption be either consimied or invested in the offspring's 3.1.4 Political Institutions At time t = the government who of the agents are rich), therefore, the transfer Tt. specific, thus T/ = Tt, is human good can capital. controlled by the elite (the proportion 1 and they are able to set-the tax rate, Tt, —A and Further, government transfers cannot be person and the government budget constraint has to hold every period, therefore: Tt where we used the H^, can be jority, TtAHr, human (4) capital used in (A poor agents), though initially excluded from the political endowed with a revolution technology. Since they form the ma- they can overthrow the existing government and take over the means of production, i.e. the capital stock in any period t that in the course of the revolution a proportion the economy is 1 destroyed, but in return, the poor control can retain an market production, taxed. The masses process, are fact that only = all the output of the economy. ineffective revolution technology (e.g. 17 > — 1. However, we assume /i > of the capital of who have now taken A low value of fi over implies a society in which the poor are unorganized). Since output following a revolution AjiHt, each poor agent receives, is ^. It should be clear that below (5), all if (5) the return to a worker from the existing system falls workers will be willing to undertake a revolution/ Franchise Extension and Timing of Events 3.1.5 Finally, the elites have another political choice. They can also decide to extend the franchise. In the event of franchise extension, there wiU be an effective transition to full since A > democracy where the median voter 1/2) will choose The timing poor agent (a Tt. of events within a period can be summarized as foUows. 1. education bequests are received. 2. the elite decides whether or not to extend the franchise to workers. 3. the workers decide whether or not to initiate a revolution. If revolution they share the remaining output of the economy. there If is there a is no revolution, then: 4. the political system decides on what tax rate to choose median voter if there is democracy, and a rich agent if (i.e. a poor not). ^Here, there could be a 'free-rider' problem as poor agents could try not to take part in the revolutionary activity but still share the gains of the revolution. We avoid this problem by assuming that if an agent does not participate in the revolution, he receives no returns. We are also assuming that part of the elite cannot enter into a political coalition with the poor. 18 the 5. human capital stock allocated between market is and home pro- duction. 6. human capital is 7. consumption and bequest decisions are made. traded in a competitive market and receives its This timing of events emphasizes the commitment problem. The return. elite can- not commit to a tax rate before workers decide on whether or not to initiate a revolution. Therefore, promises of high taxes will not prevent a revolution, but extending the franchise may. This assumption of no commitment captures the fact that if a section of the society them process, promises of future transfers to this assumption can be relaxed sume that once the franchise is is excluded from the pohtical is will often discussed in section be non-credible. 7. How Moreover, we as- extended, the rich have no special political power, and since the median voter will always be a poor agent, there will be no return to autocracy (again 3.2 see section 7). Consumption and investment Problem (2) has a very simple solution; = = 4+1 el+i Thus if an agent can afford it, ivi if ivi > 1 if ^yi < 1. he wiU invest a fixed proportion of his post tax income in the education of his offspring, but when his income minimum, he At will this stage Assumption 1: consume all we make the jA < 1 and of it. following assumption: {"jB) Z> 19 1. is below a The Tt = part implies that in the case where there first 0), an agent who has the minimum level of not leave any education to his offspring, thus possible for some households not is human = /ij_,_j capital {hi 1 also. human is B< capital takes place, and even A, a steady state level of second part it human h > 1 1) will it is The second when accumulation the rate of return on capital = human capital can be reached. This not only enable accumulation by the rich in the absence of will taxation, but if = (tj Therefore, to accumulate while others do. part of the assvmiption on the other hand guarantees that of no taxation will also ensure that taxation will never be severe enough to stop accumulation. 3.3 Preferences over tax rates Suppose agent i is the decisive voter, then he would set the tax rate to maximize: max {(1 - Tt)A, Let us explain this expression. B} hi + TtAHrin), The (6) decisive voter will take into account the fact that by taxing incomes (human capital), he will be taxing himself, and this is the first term. The 'max' operator individual will invest in the market or home has the higher return. The second term realizing that the amount is takes into account that the sector depending Tt solved out on which one from equation of investment in the market sector will (4), depend on the tax rate (also recall that transfers cannot be person specific). Therefore, the optimal tax rate of the decisive voter will depend on the form of the function H^{Tt) and on It is how large hi clear that a rich agent, is relative to who has 20 h^ > H^. H'^, would hurt himself by taxing, and poor would inelastic, a capital H^{Tt) (1 — would choose a tax rate therefore, like to choose a positive tax rate. poor agent would choose predetermined, and is is Tt)A its B. = 1. If — Tt)A > = 0. In contrast, the H^{Tt) were perfectly However, since the amount of only alternative use perfectly inelastic for {1 < r^ t^ B, but is in the informal sector, it is perfectly elastic for This immediately yields the preferred tax rate of a poor agent: and implies that aU himian capital wiU be invested in the market sector, i.e. Equilibrium Dynamics 4 We now make convenience, first a taxonomy of different cases in detail and for expositional we ignore the revolution constraint until the next section. two types of equilibriiun dynamics tax rate will be Tt = t^ = 0. will have the eUte in power, thus the Since the minority these cases are non-democratic. In the accumulate capital, and the economy first, The is in power (A > 1/2), we wiU have the poor unable will exhibit increasing inequality. In to the second, there wiU be decreasing inequality as the poor will also accumulate. These two cases wiU also tend to different levels of steady state output. next case will have democracy so that the median voter redistributes from the is The a poor agent who we only rich to the poor. In aU of these case, we want the elite to accimiulate, consider initial conditions such that: 21 thus will >K> ilA)-' h'ss where hgg is the steady state value of the rich agents' part of the inequality ensures that first human ital). capital, thus there will The second of non-convexity, offspring. all We (8) with start less capital. The than steady state be growth (rather than decumulation of cap- inequality ensures that rich agents are and are able to also we human beyond the point leave positive educational bequests to their assume that Hq > (7 A)" so that , if agents could accumulate, but with income inequality, Hq = = h^ Hq, then not guaranteed it is that the poor will be able to accumulate. Case 4.1 Since (7^)" will Autocracy and Only the Rich Accumulate 1: we have autocracy , (no democracy), then given Assumption not be able to accumulate. and the human capital 1, hU, = we have that The dynamics Tt rich for this 0. /if = Suppose 1 Vi > 0. on the other hand group also that h^ < Thus the poor will accumulate will follow: = Z{elf = Zi^Ahlf. This dynamic equation has a unique steady hss Since (7-B) What Z> will 1 = {{lAf Z)"^ hy Assumption happen state: 1, and (9) . A> B, we have that hgg to inequality along the equilibrium path? > 1. Since the proportions of poor and rich agents do not vary over time, inequality can be 22 X measured by the income ratio of the rich to the poor: ^ , and this is given as: Because on the way to the steady state h^ increases, inequahty we can Finally, in this also calculate the steady state level of aggregate economy which ^ss Case 4.2 2: Suppose that the and also still Tt is given —A /iq > {1 - \) {{^Af zy-' + Autocracy and All Agents Accumulate initial capital = 0. Then we {'yA)~ Hq , is distributed such that h^ Therefore, this and less is is it is > (7^)" , /if > 1 Vt. This state, hss- Since converge to the same decreasing. The steady state simply given by: economy converges to a more equal also to a higher level of aggregate output ^Moreover, same steady human capital and along this equilibriimi path, inequality income Hq = zi^Ahir the poor will be able to acctmiulate with the poor by definition start with level of aggregate > have: implies that both groups will converge to the level, income as: hi^, Since rises too. distribution of income than the previous straightforward to check that the growth rate of output, 23 case.* -^ — 1, of an . Case 4.3 Democracy 3: We now consider the dynamics Accumulation Tt = jf = -^ dynamics are then given . hl^, = maj, {l,Z{^ [{A /i?+i = niax{l,Z {^[{A- B)Ht to ensure that the first that in this case as: -B)Ht + Bhl]f} note that the second part of Assumption First, We know under democracy. 1, + BhP,]f} (7-B) equation in (10) will always give thus taxation wiU not stop accumulation by the (10) rich. Z> hl_^_-l 1, is > sufficient 1 for /i^ > 1, This does not however guarantee that the poor will be able to accumulate thanks to redistribution. If /iq > (7^)~ so that in the absence of redistributive taxation the poor ) would be able to accumulate, then they receive transfers. Therefore, will also be able to do so when they we wiU only analyze the case of h^ < {'jA) in detail. To tion level start with, suppose that transfers are not enough to ensure accumula- by the poor. Then, we have hgg which satisfies h^s = iZ /if = positive value, there is and h^ converges to the steady-state the equation, [(A(l - A) + XB) h^ss + This equation follows directly from from the origin and the 1, RHS is (10). (^ - B)\]^ Since the LHS is a straight line a strictly concave function starting from a a unique h'^g that satisfies this equation, straightforward to see that h^g < and it is hss- Let also Y^g denote the steady-state economy which starts with capital Ho equally distributed (i.e. in case 2) is always higher than the growth rate of the same economy with human capital distributed unequally (i.e. in case 1). 24 output in this case; thus Y^g level of —A A + — (1 which Xjh^g is clearly than Y^s and Ygg. less Whether the economy is in this case, or equivalently, wiU ever be able to accumulate Condition 7 [{A - B) 1: ((1 capital depends - \)h^s This condition states that when from taxation will this note that the household with h^ the first and h^ term = is be \: = /i^^, the redistribution poor to accumulate. it is 7 is greater than 1 is also violated, there exists To see the post tax income of a poor is human the total per person transfer in this economy the poor. Moreover, Condition is = /i^ 1 he receives 5, after tax, on his hgg. This term multiplied by When it and 1 in square brackets poor household, and when poor. on the following condition: + a) + b] > sufficient to enable the term = /t^ whether the poor capital when /if and = 1 the education expenditure of a 1, there wiU be accumulation by necessary for accumulation by the no hi < hgg that tax revenue to enable accumulation by the poor. will generate When enough the poor accumulate thanks to redistributive taxation, the economy converges to Ygg with both the poor and the rich converging to hss- Although there capital in this economy, because the stock of capital there is no aggregate When is is taxation of the unaffected by taxation, 'cost' of taxation. the poor do not accumulate, inequality, again measured as yl f, X) _ {A-B){{l-X)hl + + Bhl {A-B){{l-\)hl + X) + B ' will increase despite the fact that there are also increased transfers to the poor. In contrast, when the poor accumtilate, inequality will decrease over time, as in the previous case. Therefore, when Condition 25 1 holds, the poor will start accumiilating at some point, and inequality will eventually decline. Whether inequality ever increases depends on whether the poor to start accumulating = from period t Condition 2: 0. 7 The necessary condition - B) [{A This condition is ((1 - = f The term first + Bhl] > we need 0, the savings rate (7) to be greater than this. \hl) is: 1. quite straightforward to understand: from time start accumulating + A)/^^ for this in square bracket 1, is for the their after tax thus 7^0 > 1- poor to income times Condition 2 ensures the transfer and the second term is the net wage (after tax) income of a poor household. Also notice that since /iq < 4.4 It is hgg and ^0 ^ Condition 1; Summary more 1 is of Equilibrium useful at this stage to restrictive than Condition 2. Dynamics summarize the equilibriimi dynamics form in the of a proposition (proof in the text). Proposition 1 Suppose that where hss is given in we have — and: i- Tt U ^0 — (7^) ^ (9), Assumption and ^^^'^ /if 1 holds, that h^ € ((7^)" that the political system is autocratic. = 1 > Vi 0, , hss) Then, hi converges monotonically to hss, aggregate output converges to Ygg, and inequality increases mono- tonically. 2. If ho > (7A)~\ then both /if and gregate output converges to Ygg h^ converge monotonically to hss, > tonically. 26 Ygg, and inequality decreases (ag- mono- Proposition 2 Suppose where hss is we have = "^^ 1. Tt given in Assumption that (9), and 1 holds, that h^ 6 {{'yA)~^ , hgg) Then that the political system is democratic. and; IfhQ> {^A)~ then both hf and hi converge monotonically to hss, ag- , gregate output converges to Y§g > Yg^, and inequality decreases mono- holds, then inequality decreases mono- tonically. 2- < if ho and Condition 2 (7^)~ tonically, and h^ and converge to hss, aggregate output converges h^ to Vis- 3- < If hg and Condition {'yA)~ monotonically, /if = 1 output converges to Y^^ 4- U ho < . Inequality < t* , to hgg, and aggregate yj^. such that 1 holds and Condition 2 fails to hold, = /if increasing until is then inequality increases and h^ converges 0, and Condition (7^)" then there exists t* > Vf 1 fails to hold, t* 1 Vt < i*, and and decreases /if is growing \ft > thereafter. Aggregate output converges to Ygg. There are a nuraber of things that are important to note. 1. In this model democracy is good for economic performance if it enables accirmulation by the poor, but detrimental otherwise. In the absence of democracy, /iq < (7-A)~ condemns the economy to the lower level of steady state output Yg^ because the poor do not have enough wealth to start accumulating. In contrast, with democracy, the conditions for 'stagnation' are rich is much more stringent because part of the redistributed to the poor. However, 27 income of the when democracy does not enable the poor to accTimulate, the economy converges to Y^g which even less than Y^g because the income of the accimiulating, good for is growth reduced. The result that rich, who democracy are the only ones im.ambiguously is enables accimiulation by the poor if it is is special; it hinges on the fact that there are no 'allocative' costs of redistributive With some taxation. (1994) of the costs as and Persson and TabeUini ambiguous effect even in emphasized by Alesina and Rodrik (1994), democracy would have an this case: the positive effect of redistribution on himian capital accumulation by the poor may be offset by slower accimiulation by the rich. Therefore, the empirical results that show no robust correlation between democracy and growth should not be too surprising. 2. In the absence of redistributive taxation, there inequality is always increasing or decreasing. Kuznets curve with redistributive taxation is is no Kuznets curve: The that intuition for the when the rich are not sufficiently wealthy, the transfers from them to the poor will not ensure accumulation, and this leads to increasing inequality. But enough, transfers increase and the poor start the rich become 'rich' accimiulating as weU and taxation is inequality cieties falls. Therefore, redistributive key in this model for the Kuznets curve. configuration of the Kuznets curve argued when earlier, it is plausible to is However, this not totally compelling because as suppose that most of the Western so- were not democratic when incomes started rising nor was there any redistributive taxation. arise for a larger set of of revolution We wiU see that the Kuznets curve will parameter values when we add the possibility and franchise extension to an economy with the 28 elite in power, and this we believe is a much more plausible explanation for the Kuznets curve. 3. For a given level of capital Hq, an unequal distribution development. When the poor have h^ > (7^)" , the it may income Ygg. between inequality and prosperity applies both harmful to economy converges to the higher steady state Ygg, whereas otherwise in the lower steady state with per capita is for get stuck This relation a democracy and an autocracy. The Threat 5 We will now of Revolution analyze an economy which starts with the the revolution constraint never becomes binding then the equilibriimi dynamics of Proposition hand revolution becomes elite in power. If is very small), 4.1 will apply. If on the other (e.g. if fj, a real threat, the rich have to redistribute to the workers in order to prevent a revolution, and in our model the only method of credible redistribution 7). is Therefore, when is to extend the franchise (see below and section the revolution constraint becomes binding, the franchise extended and the dynamics of Proposition 4.1 are replaced with those of Proposition 4.2 where the median voter The revolution constraint, when AK> is a poor agent. the rich are in power, can be written Af,[{l-X)hl as: + XhP,] A or ^< ^(^-^) (11) 29 The hand left side of the first inequality the absence of revolution at time and the t what a poor agent gets is a poor agent after the revolution. In words, this total output divided will be no revolution among at time constraint are as foUows: constraint which (11); this is when In case 1, the share of When fi of (11) holds, there the tighter is /x, is is is the revolution A, the less tight is to takeover the wealth of them with the same income from revolution Revolution Conditions: cumulate (Case 1) 5.1 is equal to a fraction Second, the higher there are fewer of side points to note about this revolution the higher is fairly intuitive. given), the return is Two t. first, is the poor agents, A.^ because the benefit of the revolution the rich and hi all hand right in level (i.e. falls. When Only the Rich Ac- the economy converges to Ygg with increasing inequality on the way with the poor stuck at /if = 1. If (11) not binding at the point of is steady state (which has maximal inequality), it will never bind. Thus we have: Condition If 3: hss > j^E^)- Condition 3 holds, the revolution threat wiU become effective at some point during the course of accumulation by the we can ^It some is rich. If it fails to hold, then ignore the revolution constraint. assumed that the rich get nothing after revolution, but clearly, positive amount, none of our results would be 30 affected. if they receive The important point it is When Revolution Conditions: mulate (Case 2) 5.2 highest at time Condition If 4: § t = cumulate hn > 1, then in Case 2 there satisfied, since inequality The threat. of interest (which is a non-empty thus T^ is no revolution threat lower after this point, there is < set of at if never and 4 hold is the poor are excluded some point they wiU want If is parameters since when the poor ac- In this case, hss)- resources to themselves by force. to redistribute on the other hand, they are mulating along the development path, they 5.3 decreasing, thus case in which both Conditions 3 from the accumulation process, worthwhile is = 0. Then we have: t is and any revolution that in this case inequality is < ^g^. Condition 4 at time to note All Agents Accu- will also accu- not perceive revolution as a activity. What Happens When the Revolution Constraint Binds? In this case, the elites realize that without some redistribution, they will lose all their income. However, by assumption, they are unable to redistribute before the revolution decision of the workers, and tribute in the future, this will not be credible. state in the hands of the their minds. This is elite, there elite they promise to redis- With the apparatus no guarantee that they will of the not change captured in the timing of our model: workers have no revolution choice after taxation, a result, the is if it is only before the taxation decision. As have no means of committing to redistribution other than cease to be the political elite, that is extend the franchise. 31 The next question to ask whether the extension of the franchise is sufficient to stave off a revolution. to 1, workers would more condition still One can imagine prefer a revolution. to ensure that taxing the rich that if is fj, is very close Thus, we need to impose one is a better option for the poor than a revolution. Hence, we need: (A - B) ((1 - X)hl + A/i?) + B/if > -4/^ [(1 - y? + ^^?] A whenever the revolution constraint binds. Clearly the hand side is what the worker gets after redistributive taxation, and the right hand side is what We he gets with revolution. left are particularly interested in the case when the revolution constraint holds while the poor are not accumulating Condition off 3), and the revolution Assumption to ensure that in this case franchise extension will stave sufficient to it is ' 2: (\_,),^f We (cfr. wiU suppose in what assume > that: f- follows that Assumption 2 holds which means that extending the franchise will be sufficient to stop a revolution. Intuitively, this assimiption requires B not to be too large relative to A. Otherwise, the poor would not be able to tax the rich sufficiently, and they would prefer revolution to democracy. 6 Implications For Growth and Democrati- zation In this section, outline some Assumptions we put the analysis of the previous two sections together possible paths of development. 1 and 2 hold. 32 and Throughout we assume that Kuznets Curve 6.1 Suppose that starts at the elite in power, and initially, with the rich, and inequality some point the revolution increases. we are in case 1. Accumulation Now if Condition 3 constraint will bind, and the holds, then rich will realize that they can only prevent revolution by extending the franchise (since they cannot commit to other forms of redistribution given the timing we have assumed). Therefore, in this case, the economy wiU follow the path of increasing and the poor not accvimulating inequality with the rich accumulating some time t. At t, as the rich will bind, the franchise will And become 'rich until enough', the revolution constraint be extended, the tax rate will be set at Tt = '^^^• as long as Condition 1 holds, the redistribution will enable the poor to and aggregate output start accumulating, thus inequality will start falling wiU converge to Y§g. In our view, this sequence of events corresponds to the experience of Britain where, after a period increasing inequality, social unrest forced the extension of the franchise, then schooling and redistribution went up rapidly and inequality this pattern of events An is declined. Suitably interpreted, useful for understanding the US we also feel that case. interesting recent case which also mirrors this experience Under autocratic military regimes Brazil grew rapidly is Brazil. in the late 1960's 1970's (for example the average annual growth rate of real GDP and 1968-1978 was 9.1%, see de Castro and Ronci, 1991). Inequality widened from a Gini of 0.53 in 1960 (Fields, 1995) to an average Gini of 0.60 in the period 1981- 1990 (Campos and Root, 1996), and as the social unrest against the military regime grew, Brazil witnessed a transition to democracy (interestingly at around the same value for the Gini coefficient that Britain 33 had in 1870). East Asian Miracle 6.2 Instead suppose we start with the ehte in the previous case inequahty economy the is satisfied, will grow with is power but in case falling inequality, the threat of revolution will never degreem sharing Compared and arise. as long as Condition 4 This is because along some are, at least to in the benefits of rising average per-capita income, therefore do not find to hmited, and the poor can accumiilate. Then, development path, the poor segments of the society this 2. and worthwhile to create social unrest. This case reminds it us of Taiwan and South Korea which, in the post war period, experienced fast growth but no democratization.^" 6.3 Autocratic Disaster In our final configuration, the economy again starts in case due to the absence of a weU-developed (that is, 1, but this time society or other factors, civil /i is small the poor will have a hard time organizing, therefore a revolution would be very costly for inequality will increase them) and Condition 3 and the poor will is violated. In this case never accumulate and the economy wiU converge to the low steady state Ygg with high inequahty. The interesting point to note is that the only difference between this case, reminiscent of the Philippines during the post-war period, and the development path of the ^°We are of course aware that a process of democratization is now occurring in South Korea and Taiwan. This can be because at some level of development, the masses may demand richer, fi representation for other reasons than pure redistribution, or that as the poor get may increase because they can afford to organize. We think for the purposes of the present study it is interesting to understand the prolonged autocratic regimes in these countries as opposed to the experiences of it is much faster democratization in Britain. Also, interesting that in line with the prediction of our model, inequality feU to in these economies. The average Guii South Korea and 0.32 for the period 1981-1990, see coefficient over the period some degree 1965-1970 weis 0.34 for Taiwan, and these averages fell to 0.33 and 0.30 respectively Campos and Root, 1996, Table 1.1. 34 for Kuznets curve with democratization and higher growth /i were large so that revolution became a real threat, is the size of this If yu. economy could democratize, redistribute to the poor, and possibly reach a higher level of income. Thus, whether a good 'revolution technology' hinders or enhances growth depends on which case the economy is in (see also the discussion in the next section). Finally, the main difference between this case and the East Asian miracle of South Korea and Taiwan by Lucas (1993), while the Philippines stagnated. is the starting level of inequality. As noted South Korea and Taiwan experienced fast growth, but Korea, Taiwan and the Philippines were in similar situations in 1960, except that the Gini coefficient of income inequality was 0.34 in 1965 in South Korea and 0.31 in 1964 in Taiwan whereas 0.45 in Phihppines in 1957 (see Fields, 1995). more equal economy with /iq > it was Li terms of our model, a (7^)~ would again fail to democratize, but because the poor would be able accimiulate, the level of income and the growth rate would be 7 greater. Extensions In this section we will informally discuss some extensions and how some of the simplifying assimiptions can be relaxed. 7.1 Why Are Other Methods of Redistribution Non- Credible? Our assumption that other forms of redistribution are non-credible, embed- ded in the structure whereby agents after the revolution decision, is live for extreme. 35 one period and taxes are set The example of Bismarck who at- tempted to stop the rise of social instituting the welfare state democracy and socialism is telling. It is also in Germany by possible to envisage different models whereby the threat of future revolution by long-lived agents sufficient to To see may be support a repeated game equilibrium with redistribution.^^ why our assumption cost of redistribution is be convex likely to ^^^ would be rate higher than reasonable, is first (as it note that in general, the is in our case since a tax very costly). Therefore, to compensate the poor enough to avoid a revolution would require redistribution not only day but also in the future. However, this will run into problems. to- First, the promise of future redistribution to a group excluded from political power problematic. it would The elite more invest would redistribute some today but in the army or other and thus weaken the revolution constraint distributions. Alternatively, in the mean is time, methods of pacifying the poor, in the future, avoiding future re- we can imagine that [i foUows a Markov process over time, capturing the idea that some periods are more appropriate for collective action and social unrest not take place in 1789, would it than others (if the French Revolution did have done so in 1795?). In both cases, the poor would anticipate that the revolution constraint would not necessarily bind in the future, would not trust promises of future transfers, and the would be forced for to extend the franchise (see elite Acemoglu and Robinson, 1996 such a model with repeated interactions). 7.2 Why and Can is the Extension of the Franchise Credible Irreversible? the extension of the franchise be reversed? be no, or at any 'Though rate, We believe the answer to not without major political upheaval and costs. Part typically such a threat would not be renegotiation-proof. 36 of the reason away is probably sociological, that the 'endowment (i.e. cannot easily be taken 'rights' Moreover, once a certain segment of effect'). the population starts taking part in elections, they economy and are better organized, thus excluding instance, the impact of the Trade Unions class them is much harder movement on the (for British working during the nineteenth century). More General Production Functions 7.3 We know more about the have followed the standard practice in this type of model whereby Hq is fixed, and then inequaUty can be thought of as the distribution of this stock of assets among which is different agents. However, what matters the level oi poverty oi the masses. This we had the aggregate production to scale it would be inequality is for development is /iq, not a general conclusion. If function as F{Ht) with decreasing returns than absolute poverty of (or relative rather the masses) that mattered because a higher level of h^ for a given h^ would reduce the marginal product of human capital and thus the earnings of the poor. 7.4 Distortionary Taxation In order to make our point in the simplest model, taxation to be without distortions. assumption an income is It is we assumed straightforward to see that relaxed, then a democratic society level Y^s depend on a number < Y^s- Whether of other features redistributive if this would actually tend to this inequality is which are not crucial strict or for not wiU our story but would strengthen the conclusion mentioned above, that the lack of robust correlation between democracy and growth may not be 37 surprising. Revolution and Political Instability 7.5 In our analysis so This path. is far, a revolution not a general never observed along the equilibrium is result. First, if Assumption 2 relaxed, the is extension of the franchise would not be sufficient to stop a revolution. particular, an economy where this problem. It is European and this B high relative to is interesting to speculate that suffer from compared to many other in Russia, have increased the relative attraction of a revolution. Another possibihty is to have a stochastic revolution technology where an attempted revolution succeeds with probability cation of this case would be that may would was probably much harder countries, taxing the rich may A In when the elite it. The additional impli- n to be small, they judges not want to extend the franchise, and instead, use other methods to prevent the revolution. In this case a revolution could again occur 'along the equilibriimi path'. What the empirical growth literature 1996) actually measures as political instability may closely to actual instances of revolution or efforts (e.g. Alesina et correspond by the al., much more elites to prevent revolution rather than the revolution constraint triggering redistribution in our economy. Forward-Looking Behavior by the Elite 7.6 In our model capital accumulation is 'myopic' because agents live only one period and do not care about the dynamics after they more general kinds may die. If of altruism or long horizons for the agents, the elite accumulate slower than otherwise in order not to constraint. assets we introduce Intuitively, the elite may worth H* the revolution threat realize that will 38 become if hit the revolution they collectively have active and they will have to redistribute, reducing their net income. at some level less requires eUte is Thus they may stop accumulating than H*. However, the important point to note some kind of coordination from the 'state'. If each is that this member of the deciding individually, he would ignore his impact on the aggregate stock of assets, and thus would 'free-ride', members would take the economy to H*. and such behavior by aU the Conclusion 8 This paper has offered a model which links democracy, redistribution, equahty and growth. Our analysis is in- motivated by the political and economic events of the nineteenth century, especially in Britain. In our economy, political power is initially concentrated in the hands of a rich elite. Under some parameter configurations, inequality starts to increase with growth and triggers social unrest ated by growth. The by the masses who are not sharing social unrest and the threat by a commitment to future redistribution sion in the in the gains gener- of revolution are prevented form of a franchise exten- democratization). Democratization opens the (i.e. way to taxation public schooling, and therefore enables a reduction in inequality, but also this and may improve economic performance because the masses are now able to ac- cumulate for the human Overall, our capital. Kuznets curve, an explanation model proposes a new explanation for the radical poUtical reforms of the nineteenth century, and a novel view of the origins of redistributive policies. The parameter only possibihty. equality is it configuration which lead to the Kuznets curve If the economy can grow with no increase starts all social in inequality, from an initial is not the position of greater classes accumulating. In this case, there no threat of revolution, 39 and hence no democra- tization. Finally, and get stuck it is possible for the to start with high inequality in a low output steady state before the revolution constraint becomes binding. Such an autocratic had a more developed state economy disaster could civil society to force be avoided if the country democratization before the steady was reached. Overall, the 1. two key innovations of our approach the modelling of the political system with an constrained by some 2. 'exit' are: elite in power which is technology of the rest of the society. a formal analysis of political reform and its interaction with economic performance. We believe that both of these features are highly relevant to an under- standing of the political economy of development and deserve future research. In particular, coim.tries if we are to uncover why performed so badly while the have to understand why African and some Latin American rest of the world grew rapidly, we these countries were subject to a lot of turmoil, to 'bad policies' and to highly inefficient redistributive efforts. This question requires a framework where there are elites with a disproportionate share of the political power, competition for political power also a model of the presence or absence 40 among social classes, of political reform. and Bibliography 9 Acemoglu, D. and and When to Have It: J. On A. Robinson (1996) "When Form the to Eat the of Redistribution" in progress. Ades, A. (1995) "Economic Development with Endogenous Participation," Economics and nomic Development and Social Polarization DELTA, of Elites: Eco- in Rent-Seeking Societies," Un- Paris. Aghion, P. and P. Bolton (1995) "A Trickle-Down Theory and Development with Debt Overhang," forthcoming nomic Political Politics, 7, 93-117. Ades, A. and T. Verdier (1993) "The Rise and FaU published Paper, Cake in the of Growth Review of Eco- Studies. Alesina, A., S. Ozler, N. Roubini and P. Swagel (1996) "PoHtical Instability and Economic Growth," forthcoming in the Journal of Economic Growth. Alesina, A. and D, Rodrik (1994) "Distributive Politics nomic Growth," Quarterly Journal of Economics, Anand, A S. and R.M. Kanbur (1993) and Eco- 109, 465-490. "Inequality and Development: Critique," Journal of Development Economics, 41, 19-44. Bcddwin, P. (1990) The European Welfare Politics of Social Solidarity: Class State, 1875-1975, Banerjee, A. and A.F. Cambridge University Newman Bases of the Press, Cambridge. (1993) "Occupational Choice and the Process of Development," Journal of Political Economy, 101, 274-298. Banerjee, A. and A.F. ization" MIT Newman Mimeo. 41 (1996) "Development and Modern- Barro, R.J. (1995) "Democracy and Growth," Journal of Economic Growth, 1, 1-28. Benabou, R. (1996a) NBER and Growth," forthcoming "Inequality in the Macroeconomics Annual. Benabou, R. (1996b) "Unequal Societies," NBER Working Paper #5583. Briggs, A. (1959) The Age of Improvement, Penguin, London. Ccimpos, J.E. and H.L. Root (1996) The Key Making Shared Growth ern Europe, George Cowling, M. Asian Miracle: Brookings Institution, Washington DC. Credible, A.M. (1980) A Carstairs, to the Short History of Electoral Systems in West- AUen and Unwin, London. Disraeli, Gladstone (1967) 1867: and Revolution, Cam- bridge University Press, Cambridge. Crafts, N.F.R. (1989) "Real Wages, Inequality and Economic Growth in Britain, 1750-1850: A Review of Recent Research," in P. SchoUiers ed. Real Wages in Nineteenth and Twentieth Century Europe, Berg, Oxford. Crotty, W.J. (1977) Thomas Crowell Company, de Castro, in Brazil," in R. Political New Reform and the American Experiment, York. RR. and M. Ronci Dornbusch and (1991) "Sixty Years of Populism Edwards S. eds. The Macroeconomics of Populism in Latinamerica, University of Chicago Press, Chicago IL. Darvall, F.O. (1934) Popular Disturbances and Public Order in Re- gency England, MacMillan, London. EasterUn, R.A. (1981) "Why Isn't The Whole World Developed?" Journal of Economic History, 41, 1-19. Evans, E.J. (1983) The Forging of Britain, 1783-1870, the Longman, New York. 42 Modern State: Early Industrial Feinstein, C. (1988) "The Rise and FaU of the Williamson Curve," Journal of Economic History, 48, 699-729. Fields, G.S. (1995) "The Kuznets Curve: A Good Idea, But..." Un- published Working Paper, Department of Economics, Cornell University. Fields, G.S. and G.H. Jakubson (1994) "New Evidence on the Kuznets Curve," Unpublished Working Paper, Department of Economics, Cornell University. Flora, P. and A. J. Heidenheimer (1981) "The Changing Boundaries of the Welfare State" Core and Historical in Flora, P. and A. J. Heiden- heimer, The Development of the Welfare State in Europe and America, Transaction Books, 1981 Galor, O. and D. Tsiddon (1996) "Income Distribution and Growth: The Kuznets Hypothesis Revisited," Economica, 63, S103-S118. GcJor, O. and J. Zeira (1993) "Income Distribution and Macroeconomics," Review of Economic Studies, 60, 35-52. Goldin, C. (1994) "How America Graduated from High School: 19101960," NBER Working Paper #4762. Goldin, C. and L. Katz (1996) "The Origins of Technology-SkiU Complementarity," NBER Working Paper #5657. Grossman, H.I. (1991) "A General tions," American Economic Review, Grossman, H.I. (1993) Equilibriimi Theory of Insurrec- 81, 912-921. "Production, Appropriation and Land Re- form," American Economic Review, 84, 705-712. Harrison, R. (1965) Before itics, 1861-1881, Routledge Heidenheimer A. in & the Socialists: Studies in Labour Kegan Paul, London. J. (1981) "Education Europe and America" in Flora, P. and Pol- and A. 43 and Social Security Provisions J. Heidenheimer, The Devel- opment of the Welfare State in Europe and America, Transaction Books, 1981 Helliwell, J. (1994) "Empirical Linkages Between Democracy and Eco- nomic Growth," British Journal of Political Science, 24, 225-248. Kaelble, H. (1986) Social Mobility in the 19th and 20th Centuries: Europe and America in Comparative Perspective, St. Martin's Press, New York. Lee, S.J. (1994) Aspects of British ledge, Political History, 1815-1914, Rout- London. Lindert, P.H. (1986) "Unequal English Wealth since 1670," Journal of Political Economy, 94, 1127-1162. Lindert, P.H. (1989) "Modern Fiscal Redistribution: A Preliminary- Essay," University of California at Davis, Agricultural History Center, Work- ing Paper No. 55. Lindert, P.H. (1994) "The Rise in Social Spending, 1880-1930," Explorations in Economic History, 31, 1-37. Lindert, P.H. (1996) "What Limits Social Spending?", Explorations in Economic History, 33, 1-34. Lindert, P.H. and J.G. Williamson (1985) "Growth, History," Explorations in Lucas, R.E. Jr. Economic Equality and History, 22, 341-377. (1993) "Making a Miracle," Econometrica, 61, 251- 272. Mitch, D. (1992) The Rise of Popular Literacy The Influence of Private Choice and Public in Victorian England: Policy, University of Pennsylva- nia Press, Philadelphia. Mitch, D. (1993) "The Role Revolution," in J. Mokyr ed. of Human Capital in the First Industrial The British Industrial Revolution: 44 An Eco- MIT LIBRARIES 3 9080 01428 3029 nomic Perspective, Westview Mokyr, J, Press, San Francisco. (1993) "Introduction," in trial Revolution: An Economic J. Perspective, Mokyr ed. The British Indus- Westview Press, San Francisco. Muller, E.N. (1988) "Democracy, Economic Development and Income Inequality," American Sociological Review, 53, MuIIer, E.N. and tions," American M.A. Seligson (1987) "Inequality and Insurrec- Political Science Review, 81, 425-451. North, D.C. £Uid B.R. Weingast (1989) "Constitutions and Commitment: Evolution of the Institutions Governing Public Choice in 17th Century England," Journal of Economic History, 49, 803-832. Perotti, R. (1996) "Growth, Income Distribution and Democracy," Journal of Economic Growth, 1, Persson, T. and G. Tabellini (1994) "Is Inequality Harmful for Growth? Theory and Evidence," American Economic Review, 84, 600-621. Przeworski, A. and F. Limongi (1993) "Pohtical Regimes and Economic Growth," Journal of Economic Perspectives, 7, 51-69. Ringer, F. (1979) Education and Society in Modem Europe, Indiana University Press, Bloomington. Roemer, of Lenin J.E. (1985) "Rationalizing Revolutionary Ideology: and the Tsar," Econometrica, A Tale 53, 85-108. Rodrik, D. (1994) "King Kong Meets GodziUa: The World Bank and the East Asian Miracle," C.E.P.R Discussion Paper No. 944. Rueschemeyer, D., E.H. Stephens and J.D. Stephens (1992) Capitalist Development and Democracy, University of Chicago Press. Saint-Paul, G. (1995) "The Dynamics of Exclusion and Fiscal Conservatism," C.E.P.R. Discussion Paper No. 998. 45 Saint-Paul, G. and T. Verdier (1993) "Education, Democracy and Growth," Journal of Development Economics, 42, 399-407. Schofield, R. (1973) "Dimensions of Illiteracy, 1750-1850," Explorations in Economic History, 10, 437-454. Simon, B. (1960) Studies in the History of Education, Lawrence and Wishart, London. Stevenson, J. (1979) Popular Disturbances in England, 1700-1870, Longman, New York. Tampke, through?" in J. (1981) "Bismarck's Social Legislation: W.J. Mommsen ed. Britain and Germany, 1850-1950, Trevelyan, G.M. (1937) After, 1782-1919, A Genuine Break- The Emergence of the Welfare State in Groom Helm, London. British History in the Nineteenth Century and Longman, Green and Co. Publishers, London. Williamson, C, (1960) American Suffrage: Prom Property to Democ- racy 1760-1860, Princeton University Press, Princeton. Williamson, J.G. (1985) Did British Capitalism, Breed Inequality? Allen and Unwin, Boston. Williamson J. G, and P.H. Lindert (1980) American Macroeconomic History, Academic Press, New Inequality: A York. Wright, D.G. (1970) Democracy and Reform 1815-1885, Longman, London. 46 5232 Mg