Math 437/537—Group Work #1—Solutions Wednesday, September 16, 2015

advertisement
Math 437/537—Group Work #1—Solutions
Wednesday, September 16, 2015
Both of the following facts are surprisingly useful in number theory proofs. Using the system of
axioms on the back of this page:
(a) Prove that there is no integer between 0 and 1.
(b) If a and b are positive integers with a | b, show that a ≤ b.
(a) We naturally interpret this question as: show that there does not exist an integer s with
0 < s < 1. But before we embark upon proving that, note that we assumed something
already—namely, that 0 < 1! And this inequality doesn’t appear to be part of the axioms.
So let’s start by proving that 0 < 1.
By Axiom 12, exactly one of the three statements 0 < 1, 0 = 1, and 0 > 1 is true; but
it can’t be 0 = 1 by Axiom 9. So all we have to do is prove that 0 > 1 is impossible.
Suppose, for the sake of contradiction, that 0 > 1. Let −1 denote an additive inverse of 1;
applying Axiom 14 to 0 > 1 yields 0 + (−1) > 1 + (−1), or −1 > 0 by Axiom 4 and
Axiom 5. Then (−1)(−1) > 0 by Axiom 15. But (−1)(−1) = 1, and so 1 > 0 which is a
contradiction to our assumption that 0 > 1.
(Why does (−1)(−1) = 1? Starting from 1 + (−1) = 0, multiply both sides by −1;
we obtain 1(−1) + (−1)(−1) = 0(−1), which by Axioms 9 and 10 is the same as −1 +
(−1)(−1) = 0, or equivalently −1 + (−1)(−1) = −1 + 1 by the definition of −1. Adding
1 to both sides (and using associativity, Axiom 2), we obtain (1 + (−1)) + (−1)(−1) =
(1 + (−1)) + 1, or equivalently 0 + (−1)(−1) = 0 + 1 which (by Axiom 4) is the same
as (−1)(−1) = 1. Lurking beneath the surface here is the more general deduction that
additive inverses are unique and can be obtained by multiplying by the special number −1.)
Finally, we can go about proving that there does not exist an integer s with 0 < s < 1.
Suppose, for the sake of contradiction, that such an integer s exists. There are two related
ways to use Axiom 16 (well-ordering) to derive a contradiction:
(i) Consider the infinite set S = {s, s2 , s3 , · · · } of integers, all positive by repeated use of
Axiom 15. By Axiom 16, S has a least element, say sk . But multiplying the inequality
s < 1 by the positive integer sk yields sk+1 < sk (using Axiom 9 for the right-hand
side), which contradicts the fact that sk is the smallest element of S.
(ii) Consider the set E of positive integers less than 1. Suppose, for the sake of contradiction, that E is nonempty. Then E possesses a least element e by Axiom 16. But
multiplying the inequalities 0 < e < 1 by the positive integer e yields 0 < e2 < e
(using Axiom 9 for the right-hand side and Axiom 10 for the left-hand side), which
contradicts the fact that e is the smallest element of E.
(continued on next page)
(b) Since a | b, there exists an integer m such that am = b. If m < 0, then multiplying
both sides by the positive integer a gives b = am < a · 0 = 0 by Axioms 9 and 15,
contradicting (thanks to Axiom 12) the hypothesis that b is positive; similarly, if m = 0
then b = am = 0m = 0 by Axiom 10, again contradicting Axiom 12. Since m < 0 and
m = 0 are both impossible, we conclude from Axiom 12 that m > 0. (Lurking beneath
the surface here is the general fact, derivable from the axioms just quoted, that x and ax
always have the same sign when a > 0.)
Knowing that m > 0, we conclude (from part (a)!) that m ≥ 1. Multiplying both
sides by a yields b = am ≥ a by Axiom 15 (or rather the variant of Axiom 15 where strict
inequalities are replaced by nonstrict inequalities; that variant is easily verified by checking
the cases of equality by hand).
Download