The Controllability Principle in Responsibility Accounting Rick Antle; Joel S. Demski The Accounting Review, Vol. 63, No. 4. (Oct., 1988), pp. 700-718. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0001-4826%28198810%2963%3A4%3C700%3ATCPIRA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-X The Accounting Review is currently published by American Accounting Association. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/aaasoc.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Fri Apr 13 17:35:39 2007 THEACCOUNTING REVLEW Vol. LXIII, No. 4 Octobrr 1988 Frank H. Selto, Editor The Controllability Principle in Responsibility Accounting Rick Antle and Joel S. Demski ABSTRACT: The purpose of this paper is to examine controllability: the notion a manager should be evaluated based on that which she or he controls. We embed the managerial evaluation problem in a principal-agent setting and ask whether the optimal agency solution bears any logical relation to a casual definition of controllability. It does not. More to the point, the agency framework compels us to look at information content. This information content perspective, upon reflection, agrees with our intuition, with our anecdotal impressions of practice, and with the dictates of the principal-agent model. Moreover, there is a well-defined relation between information content and a notion of control. Thus, the information content perspective may be thought of as offering a precise definition of controllability. a manager be evaluated as the head of a cost center or a profit and intuitive center? Our analysis of this perennial question f0cuses on whether the manager controls cost and revenue. If so, the manager should be evaluated as the head of a profit center. If the manager only conirols cost, a cost center evaluation is appropriate. If the manager only controls revenue, a revenue center evaluation is appropriate, Analyzing this wisdom requires two specifications. First, we must be precise about what it means for the manager to "control" cost or revenue. Second, we must be precise about what it means to evaluate the manager "correctly" or in the "best possible manner." We use a principal-agent model to HOULD Helpful comments of Froystein Gjesdal, Bob Kaplan, Rick Lambert, KrishnaPalepu, FrankSelto, anonymous reviewers, and seminar participants at Harvard Business School, Mcblaster University, and Michigan State University as well as financial support from the National Science Foundation are gratefully acknowledged. Rick Antle and Joel S. Demski, Yale University. Manuscript received May 1986. Revisions received March I987 and January 1988. Accepted April 1988. Editor's Note: In compliance with a resolution of the Executive Committee of the American Accounting Association, no new manuscripts have been considered by Education Research since June 30, 1987. Editor Frank Selto indicates that this manuscript is the last to be published in Education Research. On behalf of the readers, reviewers, and authors of Education Research, 1 wish to thank Frank for his three years of exceptional service as Editor of the section. Antle and Demski provide a coherent framework for the evaluation exercise. This gives a setting where a nontrivial control problem is present, where evaluation of the manager can be explicitly modeled, and where managerial evaluation can be endogenously specified. In this way a control problem is modeled as an exercise in motivating a particular behavior by the manager, and performance evaluation as producing information relevant to the question of whether the desired behavior was supplied. The focus is on control of inputs, not outputs. Managerial evaluation, then, becomes framed in terms of inferring this supply of input. In turn, we specify what it means for the manager to "control" an evaluation statistic, such as cost or revenue, by asking whether his or her supply of inputs is able to affect the probability distribution of the output statistic. For example, if cost is characterized as a probability distribution, can the manager affect this distribution by altering her or his managerial inputs? This particular definition is highly stylized, but expositionally convenient. A result is that the principal-agent analysis leads to a focus related to, but distinct from, this notion of controllability. In particular, the principal-agent analysis leads us to ask whether the manager can affect the probability distribution of the output statistic conditioned on whatever other information is present. The intuition for this conclusion is best developed by beginning with a stylized notion of controllability, and then refining it to match the principal-agent conclusion. In this way the principal-agent paradigm is used to infer a formal definition of controllability. For exposition purposes, we refer to the performance evaluation dictates of the principal-agent model as the information content approach and the casual controllability definition as the (traditional) controllability approach. ' The paper is organized as follows: In Section I we present three numerical examples that explore the traditional controllability notion in a principal-agent setting. In Section I1 we introduce the information content perspective and use it to explain the anomalies in the earlier examples. In Section I11 we illustrate this perspective with a brief analysis of tournaments. Conclusions are offered in Section IV. Basic Model Consider a setting where an individual, termed a principal, owns a production function that offers uncertain cash flow prospects. Three items of cash flow are identified: cash inflow from customers (revenue), cash outflow for materials and overhead (cost), and cash outflow to compensate the supplier of labor (wage). The revenue and cost amounts depend on which state of nature obtains as well as whether labor supply is "LOW" or "HIGH." There are three equally likely states of nature. The possibilities are described in Table 1 (000 omitted). The principal faces two options, whether to input labor supply HIGH or LOW. She is risk neutral and, therefore, evaluates the options in terms of the expected value of the net profit they promise. To complete the analysis, we muse specify the labor cost, or wage. Labor is supplied by a second individual, termed an agent (or manager). Three characteristics of this second indiWe emphasize our particular controllability rhetoric is designed to build intuition. Earlier authors, such as Ferrara [1967], were not as narrow in their conception of controllability. On the other hand, we use the formality of the principal-agent paradigm to propose a precise notion of controllability. The Accounting Review, October 1988 TABLE1 REVENUE, COST, AND GROSSPROFIT FOR EXAMPLE 1 State SI LOW Labor Supply: s3 Revenue Cost, exclusive of labor Profit, exclusiveof labor cost HIGH Labor Supply: s2 Revenue Cost, exclusive of labor Profit, exclusiveof labor cost vidual are important. First, he is strictly risk averse, and values his wage compensation according to the expected value of [wage]y2. In this way, both individuals are important in the production process. The agent supplies labor, while the risk neutral principal supplies risk carrying capacity. Second, labor supply by the agent is personally costly. He prefers LOW to HIGH. In fact, his preference for wage (w) and labor supply ( 1 ) is given by the additive function [w]"- V(l), with V(L0W) =O and V(H1GH) =50. In this way the suppiier of labor is not an indifferent automaton. He and the principal are in conflict. She prefers HIGH, while he prefers LOW, other things equal.3 Third, the agent is not being held captive. He is free to work for the principal, or to work "elsewhere. " Working elsewhere nets the agent an expected utility of 250 utiles. (For example, it offers a wage of (250)2, and V(*)=O.) The principal must match this to secure the agent's employment. With these details in place, we can cal- 400 800 400 400 - culate the cost of labor. If the agent is to supply 1=LOW, he must face a wage, denoted wL, such that [wL]y2 -0 r250. Otherwise, he does better by working elsewhere. This implies W L ~ ( 2 5 0 ) ' =62,508. Similarly, to provide 1=HIGH, the principal must offer a wage, denoted Risk is noxious to the agent and a matter of indifference to the principal. Efficiency dictates the principal shoulder the risk. In this way we view the principal as a loose caricature of a capital market. More specifically, contrast the agent's thoughts about receiving $500 for certain or flipping a fair coin where with probability 1/2 he "wins" 1000 and with probability 1/2 he "wins" nothing: Concavity of [ * I f iguarantees the agent will reject fair gambles. He considers risk noxious. The principal, however, is indifferent between the two options: + 5 0 0 = 1/2[1oo0] 1/2[0]. ' The idea is the two individuals face some conflict in the employment relationship. In a larger model this might arise over human capital concerns, over taste for a particular style of administration or set of products, or whatever. The most straightforward way is to assume some type of nonpecuniary cost befalls the agent. We further model this in a separable manner, so the conflict does not interact with the agent's wage. While unrealistic, this allows us to examine the controllability dictates in a transparent setting. Antle and Demski WH, such that [wH]V2 -50 2250. This implies w ~(300)2 r =90,000a4 The principal, of course, will pay what the "market demands." Combining these labor cost calculations with the earlier (gross) profit data, we conclude with the following analysis of the principal's decision (000omitted). Labor Supply LOW HIGH - E(Revenue) Less E(Cost) 933.33' 466.676 933.33 433.33' E(Gross profit) Less Wage 466.67 62.50 500.00 90.00 E(Net profit) 404.17 410.00 -- Evaluation Context To this point there is little interest in evaluating the agent. The principal prefers labor supply HIGH, while the agent prefers LOW. But we have implicitly assumed the agent, in exchange for appropriate compensation, supplies the agreed upon amount. If this assumption is accurate, there is no interest in verifying the agent's labor supply. Now move to the opposite extreme and assume the agent operates in his self interest. Further assume only the realized cost (exclusive of labor payment) and revenue are jointly observable and verifiable. Thus, the contract with the agent can call for payment as a function of the gross profit, but not as a function of the labor input actually supplied. The actual labor input is not verifiable and, therefore, not available as a basis for contracting. This final verifiability assumption is important because it allows the agent room to maneuver in exploiting the natural conflict between principal and agent. In particular, suppose the principal offers a guaranteed wage of w, =90,000in fi exchange for supply of input HIGH. The agent can supply HIGH, with a resulting utility measure of [90,000] -50 =250 or supply LOW with a resulting utility measure of [90,000Ifi-0 =300 >250. In short, supply of HIGH under this compensation arrangement is not incentive compatible. Our original analysis, in other words, does not provide a practicable resolution of the labor contracting problem in this setting of self interested behavior coupled with limited observability and verifiability. We seek labor input, but cannot verify its supply. Only labor output, cost and revenue here, is observable and verifiable. Thus, we use the output to infer the input. We evaluate the agent, so to speak, based on his output. In this way output serves two roles: it is a source of value in the production process and it is a source of information for the control problem of motivating the self interested manager. This gets to the basic question: how should we use the information provided by output; do we want to use cost, revenue, or cost and revenue to evaluate the manager?s The question is interesting because the value and information components of the output are not coextensive. We cannot unambiguously infer the one from the other. It is efficient to compensate the agent with a constant wage. Otherwise, his payment is at risk while risk is noxious to him but not to the principal. ' (1/3)(800) +(2/3)(1000)=933.33. (1/3)(400) +(2/3)(500) =466.67. ' (2/3)(400) +(1/3)(500)=433.33. We sketch the story in terms of cost, revenue, or cost and revenue to provide a caricature of an institutional setting. The typical cost center setting would, however, focus on cost and physical output, as with a flexible budget. So the available information is perhaps better framed in terms of cost, physical output, and revenue rather than cost and revenue. The addition of an explicit output descriptor, though, needlessly complicates our setting. Similar comments apply to variances. The Accounting Review, October 1988 a = HIGH (1/3) Cost =400 w4 Cost =400 w4 Cost =SO0 Wa (113) (113) Cost =so0 - ws Cost = 500 Wa Cost=400 (113) (113) w4 elsewhere - Controllability Answer Consider the controllability prescription. If an output statistic such as revenue is used in the agent's evaluation then the agent should be able to control that statistic. Return to the data in Table 1. The revenue depends on which state nature supplies, but not the labor input. Conversely, the cost depends on both the state and labor. The agent, through conscious behavior, can influence the cost probability or lottery. The revenue probability or lottery is totally independent of what the agent does. We conclude, using this notion of controllability, our particular agent is best evaluated as the head of a cost center. He controls cost, but not revenue. Model's Answer Now ask the agency model the same question. First, suppose we observe only the cost outcome. What is the best way to contract for supply of HIGH? The trick is to design the agent's decision tree so his self interested behavior mirrors the principal's wishes. Let w, denote the - - agent's wage if cost =400 is realized and ws if cost =500 is realized. The agent's decision tree is shown in Exhibit l. Goal congruence demands the agent prefer HIGH to the other options. Thus, we must engineer the ugent's decision tree so HIGH is preferred. This requires: and The first inequality forces HIGH to be as good as "go elsewhere.. . ." The second forces HIGH to be as good as LOW. In this way self interest on the agent's part leads to choice of HIGH. Goal congruence is a constraint in designing the control system. We design the system so the preferred behavior is in the agent's self interest. But achieving goal congruence is only part of the principal's problem. Another concern is the cost of aligning the agent's behavior. Naturally, the principal will select the w4\wS combination that is least expensive. With the principal risk Antle and Demski (113) a = HIGH / *a Profit =600 8, Profit = 500 ws Profit =400 *4 Profit = 500 9s Profit =SOO 9s (113) a=LOW (113) (113) \ Profit =400 elsewhere ., neutral, least expensive means least expected payment to the agent when he is motivated to supply HIGH. The best combination is, therefore, located by the following program: Min 2/3 w,+ 1/3 w s w..W, subject to The solution is w 4= 122,500 and w s =40,000. The principal's evaluation is now: Contrast this with use of revenue and cost in the agent's evaluation. Recalling This solution can be developed in the following intuitive fashion. Suppose only the first constraint is binding. This is the setting where we have to induce the agent to work for the principal, without any concern for 3eiecting HIGH over LOW. With the principal risk neutral intuition correctly suggests w 4 = ws=90,000. But the second constraint is violated. Conversely, using only the second constraint requires [ w , ] h- [ w 5 ] % = 150. Minimizing the expected payment implies w,=O and w4=22,500, which violates the first constraint. By implication both constraints are binding. Solving two equations in two unknowns provides [w4]"=350 and [w,]" =200, or w e = 122,500 and ws=40,000. Alternatively, let v 4 = [w4]" and v s = [w,]". Substituting, our program is Min 2/3v:+ 1/3v: v., V, subject to Labor Supply LOW E(Revenue) Less E(Cost) E(Gross profit) Less E(Wage) E(Net profit) HIGH - - 933.33 466.67 933.33 433.33 466.67 62.5010 500.00 95.00L' 104.17 - 405.00 - This is a quadratic objective function with linear constraints and can be analyzed with standard optimization routines, such as LINDO.Alternatively, direct numerical methods using standard software packages, such as Borland's Eureka, can be used. l o The earlier solution of w,=w5=62,500 satisfies both constraints because there is no lower labor supply than LOW. (2/3)(122,500)+(1/3)(40,000)=95,000. The Accounting Review, October 1988 the data in Table 1, we see the possible (gross) profit realizations are 400, 500, and 600. Let C4 denote the agent's compensation if a profit of 400 is realized, P5 if a profit of 500 is realized, and so on. The agent's decision tree is shown in Exhibit 2. Engineering the agent's tree requires 1/3[$4] V2 + + 1/3[tir6]y2 1 / 3 [ ~ 5 ] ~ - 5 0 2250, and + 1/3[C4] '/'+ 1/3[@6IV2 1/3[6'5] -50 r 1/3[C4]V2+2/3[@s]R-0. The principal's program becomes Min 1/3ii.4+1/3~6+1/3+5 h,",,", subject to 1/3[C4]'/'+1/3[C6]y2+1/3[C~]V2-50 r 250 1/3[ii.4] '/' + 1/3[@6]'/'+ 1/3[*5]% -50 r 1/3[fi4]" +2/3[@5]''-0 fi4, * 5 , f5i16 2 0. The solution is fi4=90,000, fi5= 50,625, fi6 = 140,625.12 The principal's evaluation is now: Labor Supply LOW E(Revenue) Less E(Cost) E(Gross profit) Less E(Wage) E(Net profit) HIGH - - 933.33 933.33 433.33 466.67 - - 466.67 500.00 62.50 404.17 - 93.7513 406.25 P The principal is strictly better off using cost and revenue, as opposed to just cost, in the agent's evaluation. The agent, however, is indifferent. In either case his expected utility is 250. Revenue is a useful evaluation statistic, despite the controllability-based conclusion it is not controllable and, therefore, useless in the evaluation exercise. l 4 A Second Example Now consider a slight variation on this example. Everything is identical except the revenue structure is altered in Table 2 (000omitted). This makes the revenue lottery dependent on the agent's behavior. So a controllability approach would imply revenue is a useful evaluation statistic because the agent is able to influence which revenue result obtains. Further observe the revenue structure is constructed so a cost realization of 400 always is accompanied by a revenue realization of 1000; and a cost realization of 5 0 0 always is accompanied by a revenue realization of 800. l 5 Working through " Sonir may be troubled by the non-monotonicity of this contract, which calls for a higher payment to the manager for achieving a profit of 400 than a profit of 500.Before concluding this does not accord with schemes in practice, the following reinterpretation should be considered. The manager's contract is equivalent to a salary of 50,625, with a bonus of 39,375 for holding costs to 400. 1f costs are "controlled" (i.e., held to 400) while reveniie is "maintained" at 1000, the bonus is increased to 90.000. " Two important assumptions should be recalled. First we carefully chose an illustration in which the relationship between revenue and cost and revenue less cost is one to one. Otherkise, the precise pair of realizations is important, not just their algebraic difference. Second, we assume the principal is risk neutral. The agent, therefore, has no comparative advantage at carrying risk. If this were not the case we would always prefer a profit center evaluation simply because efficient risk sharing would dictate rhe principal and agent each have income at risk. Here, however, we focus exclusively on control considerations in examining how best to evaluate the agent. This is accomplished by neutralizing the demand for risk sharing with the agent. See Demski [1976]. I' This extreme case of a one-to-one association between cost and revenue makes the analysis transparent, but is not necessary for the point to hold. As is discussed later, the important feature is that the distribution of revenue conditional on cost does not vary with the agent's behavior. The distinction is one of equivalence in (conditional) distribution, not of "equality" in the guise of a one-to-one association. Of course, the latter implies the former. Antle and Demski TABLE 2 REVENUE, COST,AND GROSS PROFITFOR EXAMPLE 2 State Sa LOW Labor Supply: Revenue Cost, exclusive of labor Profit, exclusive of labor cost HIGH Labor Supply: Revenue Cost, exclusive of labor Profit, exclusive of labor cost the details of the agency framework will produce the following conclusions: (1) the principal prefers to implement a HIGH supply of labor; (2) the most efficient contracting arrangement is use of the cost outcome, accompanied by w4 = 122,500 and ws=40,000; and (3) revenue is of no use in evaluating the agent.16 Thus, we have a case where a controllability focus implies revenue is an important evaluation statistic while an agency analysis implies it is superfluous. A Third Example For a final example, change the revenue structure in our setting as described in Table 3 (000 omitted). As in the second example, revenue now depends on the agent's behavior and a controllability focus implies it is best to hold the agent responsible for the cost and revenue (or profit) outcomes. In turn, working through the details of the agency framework reveals: (1) the principal prefers to implement a HIGH supply of labor; and (2) the most efficient contracting arrangement is use of cost and revenue with payment to the agent of G=O when loo01 400 S2 800 500 Sn 800 500 - - 600 300 300 loo0 400 loo0 800 500 -. 400 - - 600 600 - - 300 - a profit of 200 obtains and *=90,000 otherwise. In this setting, a profit of 200 signals unmistakably the agent has supplied LOW. So the contract "penalizes" the maximal amount by paying 0 (dismissal?). This threat allows for an equilibrium payment of 90,000. We, thus, have an illustration where the controllability anti agency analyses agree. These examples, taken together, give settings wh~erea non-controllable item is useful, where a controllable item is useless, and where a controllable item is useful. The important question is what explains this schism between the common sense of the controllability notion and the deductive sense of the principalagent exercise. The answer is to be found in the probabilities of the revenue and cost outco~ne. More precisely, knowledge of cost implies knowledge of revenue and vice versa. So using only cost, using only revenue, or using cost and revenue are identical evaluation schemes. Also notice HIGH is preferred here because we have the same cost structure along with less revenue prospects under LOW. 708 The Accounting Review, October 1988 State LOW Labor Supply: HIGH Labor Supply: Revenue Cost, exclusive of labor SI SI s3 800 700 400 500 loo0 500 - - - Profit, exclusive of labor cost 500 200 500 Revenue Cost, exclusive of labor 800 400 1000 400 loo0 Profit, exclusive of labor cost To develop this point, notice the common structure in the above examples centers on two facts: First, there is inherent conflict because the principal wants to implement one labor supply (HIGH) while (other things equal) the agent wants to implement a different labor supply (LOW). Second, informational asymmetry is present since the cost and revenue outcomes do not necessarily reveal exactly what input the agent has supplied. Put differently, the principal seeks input from the agent, but cannot directly observe input. As a result, the parties contract on observable and verifiable output. In short, output is used as an imperfect indicator of input, and the information content of output becomes of concern. '' Information Content Information content is a subtle notion in this setting. We use the cost and revenue outcomes as indicators of what input was supplied. In particular, we use the statistical pattern of these outcomes. But since we are concerned about the agent's supply of input, we contrast the statisti- 400 - 500 - - 600 500 - - cal pattern under the assumption he supplies the desired input with the statistical pattern under the assumption he supplies some other input. To develop this theme, we contrast two probability statements: (1) the probability of revenue=R under inputs a =HIGH and a=LOW; and (2) the probability revenue=R under inputs a =HIGH and a=LOW conditioned on cost = C. Let f (R 1 a) denote the probability revenue =R when the agent supplies input =a. Also, let f (R C,a) denote the probability revenue =R when cost = C has been observed and when the agent supplies input =a. These probabilities, for the three examples, are displayed in Table 4. l 8 Notice, in particular, I l7 As mentioned earlier, the productive output provides value (here in the sense of profit) and information. In an extended setting, we would then design the productive process to balance these two types of output. As a result, we d o not model the setting as one of finding the least costly control system to implement the otherwise most efficient productionarrangement. The design problem does not separate. The easiest way to replicate these calculations is to construct the joint probabilities, f (R,Cla). These are displayed in the Appendix. By the laws of probability, we have f ( C i a )=f (7OO,Cla)+f (800,Cla) +f(lOOO,Cla) andf ( RjC.a)=f(R,Cla)/f (Cla). Antle and Demski 709 TABLE 4 MARGINAL AND CONDITIONAL PROBABILITIES -- ---- Example I Revenue Revenue 800 a=LOW a =HZGH Cost Cost 800 Revenue 1000 800 loo0 Example 2 f(Rla) a=LOW a=HZGH Revenue 800 loo0 f ( R I C,a) Revenue a=LOW a =HZGH Cost cost 800 loo0 the following differences among the three examples: example one: f ( R IHIGH) =f (R I LOW) and f (RI C,HIGH) ff(RI CLOW) example two: f( R ( HIGH) #f (R1 LOW) and f( R / C,HIGH) =f ( R I C,LOW) Revenue 800 loo0 example three: f (RI HIGH) #f (RI LOW) and f (RI C,HIGH) #f (R I C,LOW). l9 IP Two other points should be noted. First, an example where revenue is simply noise would provide a setting with f ( R /HIGH)=f( R [LOW) and f (R /C,HIGH) =f ( R / C,LOW). Second, there is nothing ~atholoaical about the examples. The data for exampie 2, fo; instance, exhibit perfect correlation between cost and revenue. But as mentioned in footnote 15, this is done to keep The Accounting Review, October 1988 710 Example 3 Revenue Revenue 700 a=LOW a =HIGH Cost cost 700 0 1/2 800 1 0 Revenue 400 500 700 0 0 800 1/2 0 loo0 1/2 1 Consider f (R I a), the marginal probability revenue =R under input supply a. f (R I HIGH =f (R I LOW) in the first example, while f (R I HIGH) ff (R I LOW) in the second and third examples. By conscious choice of input, the agent controls the revenue probabilities (or revenue lottery) in the latter two examples, but not in the first. This is the basis on which we applied the controllability notion. definition: The agent controls revenue iff (R I a) is a nontrivial function of a. the agent's compensation be denoted w=I(R,C). If revenue of R and cost of C are realized the agent is paid amount w=I(R,C). If for some value of C different values of R lead to different payment amounts, we then say the agent is held responsible for revenue. definition : The agent is held responsible for revenue (cost) under I(R,C) if I(R,C) is a nontrivial function of revenue (cost). 21 That is, we say the agent nue if he is able to affect the marginal probability of revenue through his behaviOr (i.e., his s l l ~ ~ labor l ~ NOWconsider the use of revenue (or cost) in the compensation arrangement. We say the parties use the revenue measure if the agent's compensation depends On the actual revenue realization. Let the illustration uncluttered. Consider a setting where revenue is either 1000 or 800. Let the revenue lottery depend only on cost, and be such that R = 1000 is more probable with one cost realization thananother. This will ensure f(R I HIGH) ;tf (R 1 LOW) and f (R 1 C,HIGH) =f (R I C,LOW). See the extended examplethat begins in footnote 26. ~ n ~ ~ ~ can~be made ~ ~about m controUing e n t 21 BYnontrivial we mean for some value_of C, say_e, we have distinct R1and R2suchthat I ( R L , C ) fI(R2,C). Antle and Demski From here we articulate the controllability notion as saying the agent should be held responsible for revenue if he controls revenue, for cost if he controls cost, and for profit if he controls revenue and cost.22By this principle, the agent should be held responsible for cost in each of the three examples, and for revenue (and, therefore, profit) in only the latter content in terms of inferring what the agent supplied. If this is the case, holding the agent responsible for revenue and cost is inefficient. It merely "noises up" the evaluation. Revenue variations are, in the presence of cost, pure noise. This suggests the following: definition : Revenue has information content in the presence of cost i f f (R I C,a) is a nontrivial function of a. Conditional Probabilities The conclusion above does not agree To understand this definition, suppose with the principal-agent solutions, where we already know cost and focus on the we find revenue a useful evaluation mea- conditional distribution of revenue, sure in the first and third examples.24 f (R / C,a). If the agent cannot influence This discrepancy arises because informa- this conditional distribution, we say revtion content and controllability are not enue has no information content in the coextensive. In the second example, for presence of cost. But if the agent can ininstance, the agent controls revenue, but fluence this conditional distribution, we revenue tells us nothing about the say revenue has information content in agent's input, provided we already are the presence of cost. Note well, informaobserving cost. In this case, f (R 1 C,a) tion content is related to our concept of depends only on cost; we may write control over revenue. The difference is f (R I C,a) =f(R I C). Given we are al- we now acknowledge the information ready using cost to evaluate the agent, content of cost. The focus is influence the conditional probability of revenue, over the distribution of revenue given f (R I C,a), cannot be influenced by the agent. Stated differently, the idea is the agent should be In contrast, the agent does influence held accountable for revenue if he controls revenue. Held the conditional probability of revenue in accountable, in turn, translates into I ( R , C ) is a nonthe other two examples. f (R IC,a) is a trivial function of revenue in this setting. l 3 Observe that the controllability principle can be nontrivial function of input a in these applied sequentially. If we are considering three varitwo cases. The explanation is, perhaps, ables, say labor cost, raw material cost, and revenue, we more clear if we factor the probability can assess whether the manager controls each of these variables without reference to theothers. In this way, one construction: 22 f(R,Cla)=f(RlC,a)f(Cla). If f (R I C,a) =f (R / C), we have a case where the random variation in revenue that is not explained by cost cannot be influenced in any way by the agent's behavior. Stated differently, if f (R [ C,a) =f (R 1 C) the random variation in revenue not explained by cost tells us nothing whatever about whether the agent supplied a=LOW or a =HIGH. Given we know cost, revenue has no information form of textbook exercise consists of the specification of the individual's position within the organization and a list of potential performance measures. The student is then asked to proceed down the list and suggest whether each variable is controllable by the identified individual. In this way, the student supposedly identifies the best subset of variables for evaluating the individual in question. 24 More precisely, we are indifferent between use of revenue or cost in the second example, but strictly prefer use of both variables in the first and third examples. As noted, the second example has a one to one relation between revenue and cost. An expanded version of the example, as sketched in footnote 26, would have cost strictly preferred to revenue, along with revenue being useless in the presence of cost for evaluation purposes. The Accounting Review, October 1988 cost is known. The key is f (R I C,a), not content in the presence of cost, factoring the probability provide^:^' Model Interrogation This shift in focus has intuitive appeal. Marginal and conditional distributions are not the same, and it seems we should focus on what we learn conditioned on what we are already observing. Moreover, the principal-agent analysis reinforces this intuition." " Holmstrom [I9791 and Shave11 [I9791 developed the generic argument that use of a monitor in the principalagent setting implies the monitor's conditional distribution is a nontrivial function of the agent's input. Subsequent studies, such as Baiman and Demski [1980], Baiman [1982], and Demski and Sappington 119861, have applied it to specific accounting questions. Baiman and Noel [I9851 examine a multiperiod setting where noncontrollable capital cost is useful as a proxy for anticipated capacity choices by the principal when the agent is induced to alter his input as a function of this proxy. Further recall we assume the principal is risk neutral. This means the agent is never used for risk sharing purposes. (By analogy, risk sharing is accomplished in the capital, not the labor, market.) If the principal were also risk averse here, simple risk sharing would dictate the agent always be held responsible for revenue and cost, since profit is at risk. l6 To illustrate, consider a setting identical to that in our earlier examples, except for the following relationship among states, acts, revenue, and cost (000 omitted): f (R I a). Claim: Suppose the agent is held responsible for revenue in the optimal solution to the principal-agent problem. Then revenue has information content. The assertion is nontrivial use of revenue (given cost is being used to evaluate the manager) can only arise in the principal-agent solution if revenue has information content. To explore the formal reasoning, suppose, to the contrary, we have a case where the agent is held responsible for revenue even though f (R I C,a) does not depend on input a. In our specialized setting, this means we have some Z(R,C) compensation scheme that satisfies the following constraints: 26 and The first constraint, recall, requires the agent weakly prefer accepting the contract terms and supplying HIGH to his other alternative, with a utility value of 8.The second requires the agent weakly prefer accepting the contract terms and supplying HIGH to accepting the contract terms and supplying LOW. Now, since revenue does not have information S, S, 5, 2/16 1/16 2/16 LOW labor supply: Revenue Cost Gross Profit 800 400 400 800 500 300 800 500 300 HfGH labor supply: Revenue Cost Gross Profit 800 800 800 loo0 1000 I000 loo0 400400500400400400500 4004003WMX,600600500 probab~lity S, $4 S6 S, 1/16 6/16 2/16 2/16 800 500 300 1000 400 600 loo0 500 MO 1000 500 500 Further assume the agent is held responsible for revenue and cost under the following I ( R , C ) payment arrangement: 1(1000,400)= 160,000, I(l000,500)= 40,000, 1(800,400) = 40,000, and 1(800,500) = 10,000. This payment arrangement meets the agent's required utility constraint (of 250 utiles). It also induces the agent to supply the HIGH labor input. Using the construction that follows in the text, however, we can show this is a wasteful arrangement because it ties the agent's pay to revenue, which has no information content in the presence of cost. Subsequent notes trace this construction. a' In the example in the previous footnote we have: f (800,400 1 LOW) =f (800 1400,LOW)f (400 1 LOW) =(.25)(.50) =.125, f (800,400 /HIGH)=f (800 1400,HIGH)f (400 /HIGH) = (.25)(.75) = .1875, f (800,500 ILOW) =f (800 1500,LOW)f (500 /LOW) =(.50)(.50) = .25, and f (800,500 I HIGH) =f (800 1500,HIGH)f (500 /HIGH) =(.50)(.25) = .125. Note, f (800 /400,LOW) =f (800 1400,HIGH) = .25 and Antle and Demski With this factoring, we rewrite the constraints as follows: ~R.CI[I(R,C)I 'Y(R I C)Jf (CI HIGH) V (HIGH) 2 0, and - I 2 c d , c t [ ~ ( ~ ; c )(R l ~ fC)l - f ( C I LOW) V(L0W). Each term enclosed within the t o ) brackets is identical. This allows us to express the constraints in the following fashion:18 CC(CR[I(R,C)I'/'~ (R I C)lf (CIHIGH) V (HIGH) r Q, and - 1 C)I f (Cl LOW) - V(L0W). From here we replace the common term with a payment that depends only on cost: l9 place I(R,C) with f(~).This replacement does not hold the agent responsible for revenue, has lower expected cost to the principal, delivers the same expected utility to the agent, and induces the agent to supply HIGHB30Put another way, the f (c) construction is possible because we are "filtering out" needless noise in the evaluation process. From Controllability to Information Content Thus, any solution that holds the agent responsible for revenue when revenue has no information content in the presence of cost can be improved. The key f (800 /5OO,LOW)=f (800 1500,HIGH)= 3 0 . W e also have f (10001LOW) = 10/16 and f (10001HIGH) =11/16. In the continuing example, these constraints become: 2 C,t~R[I(k,c)l'Y(R f(C) is that payment the agent would gladly exchange for the I(R,C) lottery. Since the agent is held responsible for revenue, we know <(R,C) is a nontrivial function of R. But I(C) does not depend on R. For each cost realization, tQeagent is indifferent between receiving I(C) for certain or engaging in the nontrivial I(R,C) compensation lottery. But since the agent is strictly risk averse, he is willing to pay a premium to unburden himself of this revenue risk: In this way, the principal is able to re- and (400(3/4)+200(1/4)1(3/4)+ [200(1/2)+ 100(1/2))(1/4) - 5 0 2 (400(3/4)+200(1/4))(1/2) [200(1/2) 100(1/2))(1/2)-0. 29 Continuing the example, we have the following constructions: + + and This is, in fact, theoptimal payment scheduleto motivate choice of HIGH in this example. It has an expected labor cost of 97,500. In contrast, the original I(R,C)arrangement has an expected labor cost of 103,750. By construction we have: z~,c[I(R'C)l'f (R,C I HIGH) - V(HIGH) r Zc[I(C)lSf(C1 HIGH) - V(H1GH)a U, and - ZR,c[I(R,C)l'f (R,CI HIGH) V(HIGH) r & [ f ( C ) l S f(CI HIGH) - V(HIGH) h ER,cjII(R,C)lfif ( R 1C)If ( R (LOW)- V(LOW) E Z , [ I ( ~ ) ] ~ ~ ~ ( C I L V(L0W). OW) - The Accounting Review, October 1988 insight is we use the agent's output (revenue and cost here) to infer his input. This inferential exercise compares the statistical properties of the agent's input when he supplies the desired input with those that arise when he supplies some alternative input. Given cost is already observed, an informative revenue output means the (conditional) statistical properties differ according to the agent's behavior. But an uninformative revenue output means the (conditional) statistical properties are independent of the agent's behavior. Holding the agent responsible for revenue in such a case has no effect other than making his compensation subject to purely random noise. In other words, the information content of revenue is signaled by the conditional probability being controllable. Use of an uninformative output statistic merely subjects the agent to noise. The definition of information content tells us precisely when we would want to "filter out" this noise in the agent's evaluation. In this manner we conclude from the principal-agent analysis that any use of revenue in the agent's evaluation implies revenue has information content in the presence of cost. Conversely, with additional regularity assumptions (as in Holmstrom [I9821 or Demski and Sappington [1986]), we could provide a setting where information content of revenue necessarily implies the agent should be heid responsibie for revenue. The important message, though, is no use of revenue is called for by the model unless revenue has information content in the presence of cost. The intuition for this conclusion parallels that for the original controllability notion. The single variation in the logic is to take account of what other information we already are observing. The key, in other words, is to define controllability in terms of the conditional proba- bility of the output statistic, thereby taking account of the available information. Stepping back from the examples and analysis somewhat, we are focusing on a setting where a list of performance variables is present and asking which elements on the list should be used in evaluating the manager (or agent) in question. Applying the controllability notion, we are led to a focus on marginal probabilities. Can the manager, through action, control the probability distribution of the variable in question. If so, the manager should be held responsible for that variable. Control begets responsibility in this framework. Adopting a more explicit information perspective, we ask what it is the manager is supposed to be doing and why we want to evaluate his performance. Moving to an agency setting, the answers are the manager is to supply personally costly labor inputs, the supply of this input is not observable, and we must use output (including the output of various performance statistics) as a noisy indicator of input. This allows us to be precise about the information content of an evaluation measure. The key principle turns out to be information content, a close cousin of controllability but one that adjusts for what other information is already being used. Controllability does not imply information content and information content does not imply controllability. Going still further, we now ask whether this insight of distinguishing controllability and information content helps us solve or understand real problems as opposed to numerical examples. This is not an easy task, because the information perspective demands we think in terms of probabilities and take explicit Antle and Demski account of what other information is being processed. A ready illustration is provided by tournaments. Familiar examples are sports bonus clauses (e.g., for achieving some type of all-star status) and sales contests (e.g., sales person of the year re~ognition).~' Grading on a curve is a common practice. Relative performance evaluation of high level executives, where compensation depends on performance relative to that of a peer (e.g., industry) group, is another illustration. In each case a primary consideration in the agent's evaluation is performance of a peer agent. When viewed from a controllability perspective this is perplexing. The agent in question has no control over the performance of the peer. When viewed from an information content perspective, this practice is far from perplexing. It is easy to imagine performance of another agent in similar circumstances could possess information content.32Each agent's performance is affected by the common environment. The peer's performance tells us something about that environment and, thus, indirectly something about the performance of the agent in question. Suppose two students take a common examination. The second student's score tells us nothing about the first student's performance. But the second student's score in conjunction with the first student's score typically does, by indirectly telling us something about the common environment. For the sake of argument, suppose the score of student i is determined by where effort, is the effort of the student in question, noisei is randomness in the examination environment that is idiosyncratic to our student, and instrument is randomness associated with the exami- nation instrument. Clearly, student i = 1 cannot control scorez. But score I scorez is an interesting statistic, because the instrument randomness has been factored out. In this way, scorez becomes useful in the evaluation of student i= 1, given we already know core^.^^ As another illustration, suppose we have two agents, each working in the environment described by Table 1. One agent's output tells us something about the state and, therefore, something about the other's environment and, indirectly, something about the other's input. In fact, agents working in perfectly correlated environments, an admitted extreme, is a case where one agent's output is unusually informative about the other agent, given we know that agent's output. - IV. CONCLUSIONS This paper offers a refined version of the controllability principle. The argument rests on the assumption managerial evaluation is aimed at producing information that reports on the managerial services or inputs supplied. If the manager can affect the statistical pattern of some particular variable, the manager controls that variable. If the manager can affect the statistical pattern condi- '' Halberstam [1986]describes extensive use of sales contests in the domestic automobile industry. 3' Baiman and Demski [1980]and Holmstrom [I9821 formalize this intuition in a principal-agent setting. Dye [I9841 provides a general discussion of problems generated by tournaments. Antle and Smith 119861 provides an empirical investigation, based on high level executive compensation practices. '' This vignette hints that an extension of our argument would have the agent's labor supply more generally characterized in terms of quantity and quality. Alternatively, in this particular setting the student's performance would depend on effort, skill, and luck. We then proceed as before, but in a manner aimed at information content with respect to quantity and quality of input, as opposed to quantity of input. The Accounting Review, October 1988 tioned on whatever else we know, the variable carries information content about the manager's behavior. The concept of information content falls out of a principal-agent analysis as being a central feature of valuable monitoring or evaluation information. In this sense, we offer the information content perspective as a refined version of the controllability principle. Whether the manager controls the variable in question is immaterial. Whether the manager controls (or influences) the variable in question, conditioned on whatever other information is present, is the key notion. That is, information content is a precisely defined controllability notion that accounts for other sources of information. The darker side to this refined principle is the added demand it places on the identification of a control problem. With the traditional controllability notion, we need only ask whether the man- ager can control the variable in question. With the conditional or information content notion, we must first specify what other information is being used in the evaluation process. Once this source of information is accounted for, we ask whether any new information is produced by the variable in question.34This manifests itself in the manager's conditional control of the variable in question. In short, we find the intuition of the information content perspective appealing, but we also recognize assessing information content is likely to be a difficult task. " Recent field studies by Merchant [I987 and Dent [I9871illustrate this difficulty. Each study reports viola- tions of the controllability principle. This is accomplished by documentation of various uncontrollable phenomena that are used in the evaluation process. In contrast, the information content perspective is not so amenable to investigation. It demands assessing information content in light of all information beingused in the evaluation process. The field investigator's task is dramatically complicated by the importance of identifying the conditioninginformation. Antle and Demski Example 1 Revenue a=LOW a =HZGH Cost Cost 800 Revenue 800 loo0 loo0 Example 2 Revenue 800 1 a=LOW a =HZGH Cost Cost 0 1 2/3 1 Revenue 800 loo0 Example 3 Revenue a=LOW a =HZGH Cost Cost 400 500 700 0 0 800 800 1/3 0 loo0 loo0 1 /3 1/3 700 Revenue REFERENCES Antle, R., and A. Smith, "An Empirical Investigation of the Relative Performance Evaluation of Corporate Executives," Journal of Accounting Research (Spring 1986), pp. 1-39. Baiman, S., "Agency Research in Managerial Accounting: A Survey," Journal of Accounting Literature (Spring 1982), pp. 154-213. , and J. Demski, "Economically Optimal Performance Evaluation and Control Systems," Supplement to Journal of Accoufiting Research (1980), pp. 184-220. ,and J. Noel, "Noncontrollable Costs and Responsibility Accounting," Journal of Accounting Research (Autumn 1985), pp. 486-501. Demski, J., "Uncertainty and Evaluation Based on Controllable Performance," Journal of Accounting Research (Autumn 1976), p p . 230-245. ,and D. Sappington, "Line-Item Reporting, Factor Acquisition, and Subcontracting," Journal of Accounting Research (Autumn 1986), pp, 250-269. - - 718 The Accounting Review, October 1988 Dent, J., "Tensions in the Design of Formal Control Systems: AField Study in a Computer Company," in W. Bruns and R. Kaplan, Eds., Accounting and Management: Field Study Perspectives (Harvard Business School Press, 1987), pp. 119-145. Dye, R., "The Trouble with Tournaments," Economic Inquiry (January 1984), pp. 147-149. Ferrara, W., "Responsibility Reporting versus Direct Costing-Is There a Conflict?" Management Accounting (June 1967), pp. 43-54. Halberstam, D., The Reckoning (Wm. Morrow, 1986). Holmstrom, B., "Moral Hazard and Observability," Bell Journal of Economics (Spring 1979), pp. 7491. , "Moral Hazard in Teams," Bell Journal of Economics (Autumn 1982), pp. 324-340. Merchant, K., "How and Why Firms Disregard the Controllability Principle," in W. Bruns and R. K a p lan, Eds., Accounting and Management: Field Study Perspectives (Harvard Business School Press, 1987), pp. 316-338. Shavell, S., "Risk Sharing and Incentives in the Principal and Agent Relationship,'' BeN Journal of Economics (Spring 1979), pp. 55-73, - http://www.jstor.org LINKED CITATIONS - Page 1 of 3 - You have printed the following article: The Controllability Principle in Responsibility Accounting Rick Antle; Joel S. Demski The Accounting Review, Vol. 63, No. 4. (Oct., 1988), pp. 700-718. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0001-4826%28198810%2963%3A4%3C700%3ATCPIRA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-X This article references the following linked citations. If you are trying to access articles from an off-campus location, you may be required to first logon via your library web site to access JSTOR. Please visit your library's website or contact a librarian to learn about options for remote access to JSTOR. [Footnotes] 14 Uncertainty and Evaluation Based on Controllable Performance Joel S. Demski Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 14, No. 2. (Autumn, 1976), pp. 230-245. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28197623%2914%3A2%3C230%3AUAEBOC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-K 25 Economically Optimal Performance Evaluation and Control Systems Stanley Baiman; Joel S. Demski Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 18, Studies on Economic Consequences of Financial and Managerial Accounting: Effects on Corporate Incentives and Decisions. (1980), pp. 184-220. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%281980%2918%3C184%3AEOPEAC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-U 25 Line-Item Reporting, Factor Acquisition, and Subcontracting Joel S. Demski; David E. M. Sappington Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 24, No. 2. (Autumn, 1986), pp. 250-269. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28198623%2924%3A2%3C250%3ALRFAAS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-A 25 Noncontrollable Costs and Responsibility Accounting Stanley Baiman; James Noel Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 23, No. 2. (Autumn, 1985), pp. 486-501. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28198523%2923%3A2%3C486%3ANCARA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Z NOTE: The reference numbering from the original has been maintained in this citation list. http://www.jstor.org LINKED CITATIONS - Page 2 of 3 - 32 Economically Optimal Performance Evaluation and Control Systems Stanley Baiman; Joel S. Demski Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 18, Studies on Economic Consequences of Financial and Managerial Accounting: Effects on Corporate Incentives and Decisions. (1980), pp. 184-220. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%281980%2918%3C184%3AEOPEAC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-U 32 An Empirical Investigation of the Relative Performance Evaluation of Corporate Executives Rick Antle; Abbie Smith Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 24, No. 1. (Spring, 1986), pp. 1-39. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28198621%2924%3A1%3C1%3AAEIOTR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-M References An Empirical Investigation of the Relative Performance Evaluation of Corporate Executives Rick Antle; Abbie Smith Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 24, No. 1. (Spring, 1986), pp. 1-39. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28198621%2924%3A1%3C1%3AAEIOTR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-M Economically Optimal Performance Evaluation and Control Systems Stanley Baiman; Joel S. Demski Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 18, Studies on Economic Consequences of Financial and Managerial Accounting: Effects on Corporate Incentives and Decisions. (1980), pp. 184-220. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%281980%2918%3C184%3AEOPEAC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-U Noncontrollable Costs and Responsibility Accounting Stanley Baiman; James Noel Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 23, No. 2. (Autumn, 1985), pp. 486-501. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28198523%2923%3A2%3C486%3ANCARA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Z NOTE: The reference numbering from the original has been maintained in this citation list. http://www.jstor.org LINKED CITATIONS - Page 3 of 3 - Uncertainty and Evaluation Based on Controllable Performance Joel S. Demski Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 14, No. 2. (Autumn, 1976), pp. 230-245. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28197623%2914%3A2%3C230%3AUAEBOC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-K Line-Item Reporting, Factor Acquisition, and Subcontracting Joel S. Demski; David E. M. Sappington Journal of Accounting Research, Vol. 24, No. 2. (Autumn, 1986), pp. 250-269. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8456%28198623%2924%3A2%3C250%3ALRFAAS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-A NOTE: The reference numbering from the original has been maintained in this citation list.