Do Not Delete 11/20/2015 3:40 PM ARTICLE COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE IN THE DIGITAL INFORMATION SOCIETY: “THREE STEPS” TOWARD INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY SOCIAL JUSTICE Lateef Mtima ABSTRACT Copyright law and policy makers around the world have proven quite adept at identifying, exploiting, and promoting the social utility benefits made available through advances and innovations in digital information technology. Courts have played a critical role in achieving this progress, particularly through the use of various copyright social balancing mechanisms such as the fair use doctrine. Courts have thus allowed digital innovations and applications such as Internet search engines, “snippet-search indices,” and data-mining information extraction and re-purposing methodologies to proceed as public uses of copyrighted material, and concomitantly promote socially balanced perspectives toward “digital copyright.” However, while digital information technology has been generally applied in the service of copyright social utility, the unprecedented opportunities it presents for the advancement of Professor of Law, Howard University School of Law; Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice. I would like to thank Craig Joyce, Greg Vetter, and the 2015 IPIL/Houston Symposium of the Institute for Intellectual Property & Information Law, University of Houston Law Center for their invaluable support. I would also like to thank the Symposium participants, Irene Calboli, Meg Boulware, Margaret Chon, Daniel Gervais, Alessandra Grace, Leah Chan Grinvald, Peter Harter, Patricia Judd, Irene Kosturakis, Sapna Kumar, Amy Landers, Jacqueline Lipton, Connie Nichols, Michael Olivas, Eric Priest, and Cathay Smith for their many helpful comments. I would also like to acknowledge Anaek Johal and Taylor Moore for their excellent research assistance. 459 Do Not Delete 460 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 copyright social justice remain largely unexplored. Globally mobilized, digital information technology can democratize access to information, knowledge, and learning, and otherwise enhance the participation of IP-marginalized and underserved groups and communities throughout the copyright system. The recent decision by the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit in Authors Guild, Inc. vs. Hathitrust portends how Fair Use and other copyright social balancing mechanisms can be used to facilitate digital (and other) use of copyrighted works to promote social justice. In Hathitrust the court expressly considered the objectives of the federal Americans with Disabilities Act in its assessment of the pertinent copyright interests, and ultimately concluded that unauthorized digitization of copyrighted works for the purpose of making them accessible to the blind must be permitted as a Fair Use. Building upon the decision in Hathitrust, this article offers a three-step framework for determining when the unauthorized use of copyrighted (and other intellectual property) works should be permitted in the interest of social justice. Under the proposed “IP social justice assessment” framework courts would consider (i) whether permitting an unauthorized use will further the objectives of a specific law or governmental policy; (ii) whether there is some nexus between the social objectives underlying that law or policy and the social objectives which underlie intellectual property protection; and (iii) whether permitting the use would undermine intellectual property social utility as a whole. As discussed herein, the proposed “IP social justice assessment” framework is particularly compatible with Fair Use and the other prevailing copyright social balancing mechanisms, all of which permit courts to consider the social impacts of unauthorized uses of copyrighted works. Moreover, the proposed framework is also consistent with the TRIPS “Three Steps” test, in that the framework allows for only “special” (i.e., “government-compelled”) uses that do not unreasonably conflict with the legitimate interests of rights holders (in that it requires a nexus between IP and non-IP social objectives), and that do not conflict with the normal commercial exploitation of such works (in that the unauthorized use must be appropriately respectful of IP social utility). Accordingly, the framework is amenable to a variety of national copyright regimes and consistent with the mandates of international IP comity. Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 461 TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ..................................................................... 462 II. DIGITAL COPYRIGHT AND THE COPYRIGHT SOCIAL UTILITY BALANCING MECHANISMS ..................................... 466 A. The Fair Use Doctrine .................................................. 469 B. Fair Use and Digital Copyright ................................... 471 C. Copyright Limitations and Exceptions: The European Union .................................................... 473 D. EU Copyright Limitations and Exceptions and Digital Copyright ......................................................... 475 E. Fair Dealing ................................................................. 478 F. Fair Dealing and Digital Copyright ............................ 479 III. INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY SOCIAL JUSTICE IN THE DIGITAL INFORMATION SOCIETY .......................................... 480 IV. COPYRIGHT SOCIAL UTILITY IN THE COURTS: PROMOTING SOCIAL INTEROPERABILITY.............................. 487 V. DERIVING JUDICIAL STANDARDS FOR PROMOTING INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY SOCIAL JUSTICE ........................ 492 A. “Three Step” Framework for Assessing IP Social Justice .......................................... 496 1. Step One: Alligate IP Social Justice Goals to Express Law or Governmental Policy ................... 496 2. Step Two: Identify a Nexus Between the Relevant IP and Non-IP Social Utilities .............. 498 3. Step Three: Determine Whether Allowing the IP Social Justice Use Would Be Wholly Antagonistic to IP Social Utility ........................... 498 B. Applying the Social Justice Assessment Framework: Copyright Social Balancing ......................................... 499 C. IP Social Justice Assessment and TRIPS.................... 501 VI. CONCLUSION ......................................................................... 504 Do Not Delete 462 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW I. [53:2 INTRODUCTION That digital information technology has immeasurably enhanced contemporary copyright social utility is a fact that cannot be gainsaid. From advances in computer software technology to the proliferation of the Internet, copyright owners and users alike enjoy expanded frontiers through which to imagine, explore, and share creative expression. However, whereas the benefits of digital information technology have been universally embraced and applied in the cause of copyright social utility, the unprecedented opportunities such advances offer to promote copyright (and other intellectual property) social justice remain largely unexplored. In this regard, the greatest social boons of the Information Age may yet to be discovered.1 Intellectual property social justice contemplates the precepts of socially equitable access, inclusion, and empowerment as both intrinsic and essential to the fulfillment of the goals of intellectual property social utility.2 Digital information technology has the potential to democratize access to information, knowledge, and learning throughout the world. Underserved groups and communities in developed nations can utilize these capabilities to enhance their participation in intellectual property development and dissemination, while developing nations can deploy them to gain a genuine stake-hold in the global intellectual property system. 3 Moreover, the 1. Social Justice, PURE, http://purecities.org/social-justice/ (last visited Nov. 20, 2015). 2. See, e.g., Anupam Chander & Madhavi Sunder, Foreword: Is Nozick Kicking Rawls’s Ass?, 40 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 563, 578–79 (2007); Rita Heimes, Trademarks, Identity, and Justice, 11 J. MARSHALL REV. INTELL. PROP. L. 133, 148–55 (2011); Steven D. Jamar, Copyright and the Public Interest from the Perspective of Brown v. Board of Education, 48 HOW. L.J. 629, 648–54 (2005); Lateef Mtima, Copyright Social Utility and Social Justice Interdependence: A Paradigm for Intellectual Property Empowerment and Digital Entrepreneurship, 112 W. VA. L. REV. 97, 121–22, 135 (2009). 3. See Doris Estelle Long, Deviant Globalization and the Rise of Diverse Interests in the Multilateral Protection of Intellectual Property, in DIVERSITY IN INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY: IDENTITIES, INTERESTS, AND INTERSECTIONS 58, 60 (Irene Calboli & Srividhya Ragavan eds., 2015) (“Digitization has similarly empowered the introduction of new interests into the multilateral [IP treaty] process. While earlier multilateral processes largely featured the interests of authors and content providers . . . NGOs now actively represent the interests of end-users, Internet service providers (ISPs), and other third-party intermediaries . . . in such proceedings. One clear indication of the power of such civil societies is the acceptance, and growth in number, of NGOs accredited as observers at the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO) proceedings.”); Lateef Mtima, Introduction, Symposium on Intellectual Property and Social Justice, 48 HOW. L.J. 571, 572 (2005) (“[T]he digital revolution and similar technological advances present unheralded opportunities though which to confront [intellectual property social inequity] Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 463 potential benefits of an intellectual property social justice perspective toward “digital copyright” are far from one-sided: as fully incentivized participants on the intellectual property playing field, the “IP marginalized” will both increase their contributions to the global intellectual property storehouse and develop concrete reasons to respect the prevailing rules of intellectual property engagement and exchange. While courts throughout the leading copyright legal regimes employ various copyright social balancing mechanisms (such as fair use) as an important means for promoting digital copyright social utility, courts generally have eschewed their application toward issues of copyright social justice. Perhaps the most significant impediment to judicial pursuit of digital copyright (and other intellectual property) social justice may be the lack of discernible, concrete, and consistent standards for balancing social justice objectives against intellectual property economic incentives. Rights holders who appreciate the need for social balance in intellectual property protection, as well as the courts who must implement and preserve that balance, require assurance that the recognition of social justice obligations in the intellectual property law will not open floodgates that will all but sweep away the economic rights and incentives that play a role in the stimulation of intellectual property production. A recent decision by the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit in Authors Guild, Inc. v. HathiTrust4 may offer an analytical lodestar toward the development of legal standards for adjudicating copyright and other intellectual property social justice claims. In HathiTrust, the court held that unauthorized digitization of copyrighted works for the purpose of improving access for people with certified print disabilities must be permitted as a fair use.5 The court based its decision in part upon the Americans with Disabilities Act (“ADA”),6 and thereby explicitly from a socially redeeming vantage point. . . . [T]he new technologies can provide the apparatus through which to achieve a more equitable distribution of the benefits of creative endeavor. In order to attain these goals, however, it is necessary to reorient our construction and application of the intellectual property law toward the aspiration of social justice.”); Ruth Okediji, Givers, Takers, and Other Kinds of Users: A Fair Use Doctrine for Cyberspace, 53 FLA. L. REV. 107, 108 (2001) (“[I]nformation technology has empowered ordinary users to become a part of the creative process both by its interactive nature and the very architecture of the pennon of the information society, the Internet.”). 4. Authors Guild, Inc. v. HathiTrust, 755 F.3d 87, 90–91 (2d Cir. 2014). 5. Id. at 101. 6. Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990, 42 U.S.C. § 12101 (2012); HathiTrust, 755 F.3d at 102. Do Not Delete 464 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 invoked non-copyright law in its assessment and balancing of the relevant copyright (and other) social utilities. In explicating how the social objectives promoted by the ADA can be relevant in elucidating the social mandates of copyright protection, the HathiTrust decision delineates the functional interdependence between copyright social utility and copyright social justice: the pursuit and achievement of certain social justice objectives can be beneficial, even essential, to the full effectuation of the goals that underlie intellectual property protection. The invocation of non-IP law in order to balance competing intellectual property rights and interests offers a foundation for constructing standards for evaluating IP social justice claims and objectives. By anchoring IP social justice-oriented claims to specific laws and express governmental policies, social justice advocates ground their arguments in society’s collective and verifiable social objectives, and not merely the views or agenda of individual clients or interest groups. Moreover, such invocation of non-IP law and policy objectives in the interpretation of copyright and other intellectual property law has not been limited to courts in the United States. Accordingly, analysis of HathiTrust and similar decisions can help to identify ecumenical legal standards for pursuing copyright and other intellectual property social justice in the digital information age. This Article will explore how courts can develop standards for achieving digital copyright and other intellectual property social justice and will focus on how courts can employ and supplement the principal copyright social balancing mechanisms of fair use and fair dealing and copyright limitations toward achieving this goal. Part II will briefly review the prevailing copyright social balancing mechanisms and discuss how they are typically used by courts to promote digital copyright social utility. Part III will summarize the basic precepts of intellectual property social justice and explore their importance in the digital information society. Part IV will examine judicial decisions that assess non-copyright law and policy objectives, particularly in concert with copyright social balancing mechanisms, in the adjudication of copyright infringement disputes. Finally, Part V will offer a proposal for deriving legal standards for promoting copyright (and other intellectual property) social justice through the courts. Utilizing common themes and methodologies from the cases discussed in Parts II and IV, the proposal will proffer a three-step framework for evaluating the unauthorized use of intellectual property in the cause of social justice. The proposed “IP social justice assessment” framework is comprised of (i) the identification of an express law or Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 465 governmental policy that would be furthered by an unauthorized use of copyrighted (or other intellectual property) material; (ii) confirmation of a nexus between the policy objectives that underlie said law or policy and the policy objectives that underlie intellectual property protection; and (iii) a judicial finding that the specific unauthorized use is not antagonistic to intellectual property social utility as a whole. As discussed below, the proposed framework is especially compatible with the leading copyright social balancing mechanisms, particularly fair use, which invite courts to consider the social impact of allowing or precluding an unauthorized use of protected works.7 Perhaps most important, however, is that the proposed framework is also consistent with the Three Steps test set forth in the TRIPS Agreement,8 in that it arguably allows for only “special” (i.e., “government sanctioned”) uses, which do not unreasonably conflict with legitimate interests of rights holders (in that the framework requires a nexus between the subject IP and non-IP social utilities) or with the “normal” commercial exploitation of intellectual property (in that the use must be adjudged as not antagonistic to intellectual property social utility). The IP social justice assessment framework can thus be applied in a variety of intellectual property regimes and contexts, and can provide a measure of predictability and certainty to all intellectual property stakeholders, as courts undertake to balance rights holder interests against other societal needs in the digital information society. 7. Deepa Varadarajan, Trade Secret Fair Use, 83 FORDHAM L. REV. 1401, 1405 (2014). 8. See Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights arts. 19, 21, 24, 26, Apr. 15, 1994, Marrakesh Agreement Establishing the World Trade Organization, Annex 1C, 1869 U.N.T.S. 299 [hereinafter TRIPS]; see also Daniel J. Gervais, Towards a New Core International Copyright Norm: The Reverse Three-Step Test, 9 MARQ. INTELL. PROP. L. REV. 1, 13–14 (2005) (“The Berne Convention contains a general rule, known as the ‘three-step test,’ which guides national legislators . . . with respect to the right of reproduction. . . . [T]he so-called three-step-test allows exceptions to the reproduction right: (1) in certain special cases; (2) that do not conflict with the normal commercial exploitation of the work; and (3) do not unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of the author. . . . The three-step test has become the cornerstone for almost all exceptions to all intellectual property rights at the international level. It has been used as the model for exceptions to all copyright rights in the TRIPS Agreement (Article 13), to the rights created by the WIPO Copyright Treaty (Article 10), and the WIPO Performances and Phonograms Treaty (Article 16). Interestingly, in the TRIPS Agreement, it is also the basis for exceptions to industrial design protection (Article 26(2)), and patent rights (Article 30).”). Do Not Delete 466 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 II. DIGITAL COPYRIGHT AND THE COPYRIGHT SOCIAL UTILITY BALANCING MECHANISMS Since the latter decades of the twentieth century, the advent of digital information technology has presented novel socio-legal challenges to copyright law.9 Almost from the very outset of the information age, digital information capabilities dissolved the practical impediments to unauthorized engagement in virtually all of the uses of copyrighted material that have been traditionally reserved as exclusive to copyright owners.10 While these 9. See BENJAMIN GIBERT, THE LISBON COUNCIL, THE 2015 INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY GROWTH INDEX: MEASURING THE IMPACT OF EXCEPTIONS AND LIMITATIONS IN COPYRIGHT ON GROWTH, JOBS AND PROSPERITY 2 (2015), http://innovationeconomics.net/component/attachments/attachments.html?id=268&task=v iew (“The rise of digital technologies has irrevocably transformed the global economy by revolutionising modes of production, distribution and innovation. . . . These days, disruptive innovations are creatively destroying older business models at an increasing rate with little concern for national borders. . . . Yet, intellectual property—and copyright in particular—is increasingly seen as restricting innovation in other key areas such as content delivery, collaborative research and decentralized creative processes. . . . Ensuring that copyright law stimulates creativity in this new innovation environment is not an esoteric policy concern. Copyright, whether we like it or not, is now at the very heart of economic policy in general and innovation strategy in particular. Today’s policy decisions will determine whether we shackle our innovation system, or equip it with the tools it needs to thrive in the unpredictable digital future.”); Paul Belleflamme & Martin Peitz, Digital Piracy: Theory, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF THE DIGITAL ECONOMY 489, 489 (Martin Peitz & Joel Waldfogel eds., 2012) (“Over the last two decades, the fast penetration of the Internet and the digitization of information products (music, movies, books, and software) have led an increasing number of consumers to copy and distribute information products without the authorization of their legal owners, a phenomenon known as ‘digital piracy.’ Content industries (with record companies at the forefront) were quick to blame digital piracy for huge revenue losses and to take legal actions against file-sharing technologies and their users. Policy makers also reacted by gradually reinforcing copyright law. In general, digital technologies and the Internet have deeply modified the interaction between copyright holders, technology companies and consumers . . . . As importantly, a public policy perspective has to be taken; here, the main issue is to evaluate the extent to which social interests are aligned with the interests of copyright owners.”). 10. See, e.g., Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 249, 254 (1996) (“Digitization allows users to easily retransmit materials. Users may use scanners to digitize photos or texts that are published in a traditional form . . . . Retransmission through digitized versions is both easy and inexpensive. Everything digitized may be reproduced in seconds and at low cost.”); Lateef Mtima, The Changing Landscape of Internet Use and Dissemination of Copyrighted Works: New Tools, New Rules, or the Same Old Regime?, COMPUTER & INTERNET LAW., Oct. 2007, at 1, 4 (“[U]ntil the digital . . . revolution, the . . . division between the copyright holder’s exclusive rights and the public uses and privileges worked relatively well. . . . [H]owever, the real reason that members of the public were not likely to infringe upon a copyright holder’s exclusive rights . . . was one of basic practicality. Making multiple copies or engaging in the mass distribution of copyrighted material was an expensive undertaking, and one that was difficult to conceal. With the advent of digital technology, however, the practical obstacles to surreptitious copyright infringement largely disappeared. Today, possession of a single digital copy enables reproduction and distribution of a copyrighted work to an infinite number of people and all AND ECONOMIC Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 467 developments undermined many of the prevailing business models for the commercial exploitation of copyrighted works, they also opened new frontiers of copyright social utility for the public as a whole.11 Consequently, copyright law and policy makers throughout the globe have worked to adapt their copyright regimes to accommodate the social benefits of digital information technology, while at the same time undertaking to preserve rights holder economic incentives and related interests.12 As a threshold matter, lawmakers adopted various, socially balanced amendments to the copyright law. In the United States, Congress extended copyright protection to computer software programs, while concomitantly adopting section 117 of the Copyright Act, which permits users to engage in certain of the copyright owner’s exclusive rights in connection with the ordinary use of such works.13 Congress would later pass the Digital Millennium Copyright Act,14 from the privacy of a personal laptop.”); Wendy M. Pollack, Note, Tuning in: The Future of Copyright Protection for Online Music in the Digital Millennium, 68 FORDHAM L. REV. 2445, 2445–46 (2000) (“Digitization of copyrighted materials permits instantaneous, simplified copying methods that produce nearly perfect copies of originals. These copies can be digitally delivered to thousands of Internet users. Decentralization and anonymity in cyberspace have allowed for the widespread dissemination of copyrighted materials without permission from their owners.”). 11. See, e.g., Michael J. Madison, Social Software, Groups, and Governance, 2006 MICH. ST. L. REV. 153, 153, 160 (“The ‘personal computing’ technology paradigm of the last twenty years has done much to expand the scope of individual agency in the context of law and policy. Computers help individuals to create and consume information at unprecedented scale and at unprecedented speed.”); Hannibal Travis, Building Universal Digital Libraries: An Agenda for Copyright Reform, 33 PEPP. L. REV. 761, 763 (2006) (“With the widespread use of personal computers and the Internet, it has finally become feasible to create open access, efficiently searchable, infinitely reproducible digital libraries on the scale of the world’s great physical libraries.”). 12. See, e.g., Belleflamme & Peitz, supra note 9, at 491–92. 13. See N AT ’L COMM’ N OF N EW TECH . USES OF COPYRIGHTED W ORKS, FINAL REPORT AND RECOMMENDATION (1978), reprinted in 5 COPYRIGHT, CONGRESS & T ECHNOLOGY : THE P UBLIC RECORD 32–39 (Nicholas Henry ed., 1980); MELVILLE B. N IMMER & DAVID NIMMER, N IMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 2.04[C][1], at 2-50 to 2-51 n.26 (2015) (“[The] CONTU [Final Report] concluded that ‘it was clearly the intent of Congress to include computer programs within the scope of copyrightable subject matter in the Act of 1976.’ [The Report] further recommended that such protection for computer programs should be continued, with appropriate changes in 17 U.S.C. § 117. . . . Congress amended the current Act via the Computer Software Copyright Act of 1980.” (internal citations omitted)). 14. 17 U.S.C. § 512 (2012). The DMCA was passed in part to bring the United States in compliance with the WIPO Copyright Treaty (WCT), promulgated in 1996 to address questions of digital copyright not covered by the Berne Convention. The Treaty expressly notes “the need . . . to provide adequate solutions to the questions raised by . . . the profound impact of the development and convergence of information and communication technologies on the creation and use of literary and artistic works . . . .” WIPO Copyright Treaty pmbl., Dec. 20, 1996, S. TREATY DOC. No. 105-17 (1997) [hereinafter WCT]. Among other things, the Treaty extends copyright protection to computer software programs as literary works, grants authors the exclusive right of communication of their works to the Do Not Delete 468 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 which, among other things, balances the interests of copyright owners and users, including Internet Service Providers (ISPs), with respect to Internet use of copyrighted material. Similarly, the European Union issued various directives to bring software programs within the ambit of copyright protection,15 to resolve the question of ISP liability for subscriber copyright infringement,16 and to otherwise balance digital copyright owner and user interests.17 Indeed, the initiatives to accomplish the socially balanced incorporation of digital information advances have by no means been restricted to Western copyright regimes. The Copyright Law of the People’s Republic of China includes a body of independent statutory provisions that similarly implement copyright protection for software programs, regulate Internet use of copyrighted material, and address a number of other digital copyright issues and developments.18 Some of the most important balancing of digital copyright interests, however, has taken place in the courts. Employing traditional copyright social balancing mechanisms, courts are able public, and grants authors of software programs, cinematographic works, and phonograms an exclusive rental right. Id. arts. 2, 4, 6–7. 15. See Directive 2009/24/EC, of the European Parliament and of the Council of Apr. 23, 2009, on the Legal Protection of Computer Programs, 2009 O.J. (L 111) 16. 16. See Directive 2001/29/EC, of the European Parliament and of the Council of May 22, 2001, on the Harmonisation of Certain Aspects of Copyright and Related Rights in the Information Society, 2001 O.J. (L 167) 10 [hereinafter Directive 2001/29/EC]. 17. See, e.g., Directive 2004/48/EC, of the European Parliament and of the Counsel of Apr. 29, 2004, on the Enforcement of Intellectual Property Rights, art. 3, 2004 O.J. (L 157) 45, 61 (requiring Member States to adopt “effective, proportionate and dissuasive” measures, procedures and remedies to counter digital infringement activity, and further requires that such measures be “fair and equitable” and not be “complicated or costly,” nor act as barriers to trade). Pursuant to 2000/278/EC, the Council of the European Union approved the WCT on behalf of the European Community, and the EU Member States are also individual signatories to the Treaty. Council Decision 2000/278/EC of Mar. 16, 2000, on the Approval, on Behalf of the European Community, of the WIPO Copyright Treaty and the WIPO Performances and Phonograms Treaty, arts. 1, 3, 2000 O.J. (L 89) 6, 6–7. 18. See Decree of the State Council of the People’s Republic of China No. 468 [Regulations for Protection of the Right of Communication through Information Network] (promulgated by the Premier, Wen Jaibao, May 18, 2006, effective July 1, 2006) WIPO, http://wipo.int/edocs/lexdocs/laws/en/cn/cn064en.pdf; Decree of the State Council of the People’s Republic of China No. 339 [Regulations on Computer Software Protection] (promulgated by the Premier, Zhu Rongji, Dec. 20, 2001, effective Jan. 1, 2002) WIPO, http://wipo.int/wipolex/en/details.jsp?id=13396. The Measures for the Administrative Protection of Internet Copyright and the Regulations on the Protection of the Right to Network Dissemination of Information provide a variety of rights to authors, performers, the producers of phonograms, and others with respect to Internet use of their works, including the exclusive right of communication through information networks, which includes the Internet as well as broadcasting and mobile networks. Measures for the Administrative Protection of Internet Copyright (promulgated by the National Copyright Administration, the Ministry of Information Industry, Apr. 29, 2005) (China); The Criminal Law of the People’s Republic of China, 73 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 138 (1982). China has also adopted the WCT. Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 469 to undertake ad hoc assessments of the social utilities implicated by digital innovations. Most copyright law and policy makers and commentators consider fair use, particularly as practiced in the United States, to be the most flexible of the copyright social balancing mechanisms, in that it provides for an intentionally non-exhaustive list of factors to be considered in determining whether an unauthorized use should be allowed.19 At the other end of the spectrum is the copyright limitations and exceptions approach, which provides for an exhaustive enumeration of specific uses of copyrighted material that can be undertaken without the copyright holder’s permission.20 The third prevailing approach to copyright social balancing, that of fair dealing, might be considered a combination of fair use and copyright limitations, in that it provides for both an exhaustive list of specific, permitted unauthorized uses, but further requires judicial consideration of certain factors in the determination as to whether it would in fact be “fair” to permit a particular unauthorized use.21 Courts throughout the global copyright system have utilized copyright social balancing mechanisms to accommodate the benefits of digital information technology. The characteristics of the three leading approaches, and their application in digital copyright disputes, are briefly summarized below. A. The Fair Use Doctrine Fair use originated as a creature of common law in the United States, in accordance with which courts permitted the unauthorized use of copyrighted material for certain purposes that further the overarching objectives of the copyright law.22 In the United States, the fundamental purpose of copyright protection is to promote the progress of the arts and sciences to advance American learning and culture.23 One means by which this is accomplished is the statutory grant of specific and exclusive 19. See, e.g., 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2012). 20. See, e.g., Directive 2001/29/EC, supra note 16, art. 5, at 16–17. 21. See, e.g., Canadian Copyright Act, R.S.C. 1985, c C-42, § 29. 22. See, e.g., Folsom v. Marsh, 9 F. Cas. 342, 348–49 (C.C.D. Mass. 1841) (No. 4901). 23. See Twentieth Century Music Corp. v. Aiken, 422 U.S. 151, 156 (1975) (“The immediate effect of our copyright law is to secure a fair return for an ‘author’s’ creative labor. But the ultimate aim is, by this incentive, to stimulate artistic creativity for the general public good.”); see also Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 558 (1985); Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, 464 U.S. 417, 428–29 (1984). See generally Craig Joyce, Intellectual Property in the United States, in 3 OXFORD INTERNATIONAL ENCYCLOPEDIA OF LEGAL HISTORY 265, 265–74 (Stanley N. Katz ed., 2009). Do Not Delete 470 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 property rights to authors, so as to provide them with economic incentives to produce copyrightable expression. Another means, however, is to limit those exclusive rights, as necessary, to ensure that the fundamental purpose of the law is served. Consequently, early in the development of American copyright law, courts recognized an inherent public privilege to make “fair use” of copyrighted material, and thus to intrude upon an author’s exclusive property rights for such purposes as educational and literary discourse and comment.24 Fair use has since developed into the predominant judicial tool in American copyright law for balancing author exclusive rights against the broader social utility objectives of the copyright law.25 Fair use allows courts to account for those situations in which the unauthorized use of copyrighted material will serve important social utilities, while causing little, or at least justifiable, detriment to an author’s economic incentive interests. Accordingly, rather than predetermine a list of particular activities in which members of the public may engage without the copyright holder’s permission, fair use instead permits courts to weigh the following four statutory factors in evaluating whether an unauthorized use should be permitted as a fair use: (1) the purpose and the character of the use, including whether the use is a transformative one; 26 (2) the nature of the 24. See, e.g., Pamela Samuelson, Fair Use for Computer Programs and Other Copyrightable Works in Digital Form: The Implications of Sony, Galoob and Sega, 1 J. INTELL. PROP. L. 49, 56–57 (1993) (“Courts have often relied upon fair use to resolve disputes when recognition of broad rights in publishers or authors would have frustrated achievement of the societal purposes of copyright law. In the American tradition, the ultimate purpose of copyright is not the maximization of financial rewards to copyright owners . . . but fostering the creation and dissemination of literary and artistic works in order to enhance the public’s access to knowledge. The grant of exclusive rights to authors enabling them to reap a portion of the value derived from their creative contributions is a means to this larger end.”). 25. See PATRICIA AUFDERHEIDE & PETER JASZI, RECLAIMING FAIR USE: HOW TO PUT BALANCE BACK IN COPYRIGHT 24–25 (2011); see, e.g., Field v. Google, Inc., 412 F. Supp. 2d 1106, 1117 (D. Nev. 2006) (“The fair use doctrine ‘creates a limited privilege in those other than the owner of a copyright to use the copyrighted material in a reasonable manner without the owner’s consent,’ . . . and ‘permits courts to avoid rigid application of the copyright statute when, on occasion, it would stifle the very creativity which that law is designed to foster.” (internal citations omitted)); see also Sega Enters. Ltd. v. Accolade, Inc., 977 F.2d 1510, 1520–27 (9th Cir. 1992); Madison River Mgmt. Co. v. Bus. Mgmt. Software Corp., 387 F. Supp. 2d 521, 535–37 (M.D.N.C. 2005); Samuelson, supra note 24, at 51 (“Fair use has historically served as a flexible and adaptable mechanism for balancing the interests of copyright owners, their competitors or potential competitors, and the public to fulfill the larger purposes of copyright law which have traditionally been understood to be promoting the production and dissemination of knowledge.”). 26. See Pierre N. Leval, Toward a Fair Use Standard, 103 HARV. L. REV. 1105, 1110 (1990). In his seminal article exploring the social objectives underlying fair use, Judge Leval Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 471 copyrighted work, that is, whether it is primarily a creative work, such as a fiction novel, or a factual work, such as a news article; (3) the amount and substantiality of the work used without the author’s permission; and (4) the effect that allowing the unauthorized use is likely to have on the commercial market for the copyrighted work. 27 B. Fair Use and Digital Copyright In the United States, fair use has been critically important in assessing the social utility potential of digital applications for copyrighted material.28 For example, in Kelly v. Arriba Soft Corp.,29 the defendant compiled a searchable database of more than two million thumbnail versions of copyrighted images that were already available on the Internet. By utilizing defendant’s search engine, a user could retrieve a visual index of these thumbnail images, which also contained hyperlinks to the full size images at the originating websites. By clicking on a thumbnail image, the user could automatically link to the website where the original image actually resided—in short, defendant provided a means for locating images on the Internet. The plaintiff in Kelly owned the copyrights in some of the images recreated as thumbnails in defendant’s database, and thus brought suit alleging that this unauthorized use of his works constituted proposed that in order to be a fair use “the use must be of a character that serves the copyright objective of stimulating productive thought and public instruction without excessively diminishing the incentives for creativity.” Id. In keeping with these objectives, fair use “protects secondary creativity as a legitimate concern of the copyright law.” Id. Judge Leval therefore further proposed that these goals can be assured by assessing whether the unauthorized use is transformative, meaning, does the use further the purpose of copyright by transforming the work toward new expression, or utilizing the work for a different copyright purpose than that intended by the author. See, e.g., Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 574–77, 579 (1994). 27. See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2012); Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 549 (“Fair use was traditionally defined as ‘a privilege in others than the owner of the copyright to use the copyrighted material in a reasonable manner without his consent.’ . . . The statutory formulation of the defense of fair use in the Copyright Act reflects the intent of Congress to codify the common-law doctrine.” (internal citation omitted)); see also Sony, 464 U.S. at 448–51; SunTrust Bank v. Houghton Mifflin Co., 268 F.3d 1257, 1264 (11th Cir. 2001); Rogers v. Koons, 960 F.2d 301, 308 (2d Cir. 1992). 28. Early in the development of digital copyright jurisprudence, American courts permitted a variety of unauthorized digital uses of copyrighted material as fair uses. See, e.g., Sega, 977 F.2d at 1527 (holding that unauthorized copying of a software program solely for the purpose of studying its structure and to design new programs is a fair use); Evolution, Inc. v. Suntrust Bank, 342 F. Supp. 2d 943, 956 (D. Kan. 2004) (holding that unauthorized copying undertaken in order to extract unprotected material constitutes a fair use of protected code); see also Samuelson, supra note 24, at 56. 29. Kelly v. Arriba Soft Corp., 77 F. Supp. 2d 1116, 1116–17 (C.D. Cal. 1999), modified, 336 F.3d 811 (9th Cir. 2003). Do Not Delete 472 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 infringement of his exclusive reproduction and derivative work rights.30 In response to plaintiff’s claims, the defendant argued that its use was a transformative fair use. The court agreed. The most significant factor favoring Defendant is the transformative nature of its use of Plaintiff’s images. . . . Plaintiff’s photographs are artistic works used for illustrative purposes. Defendant’s visual search engine is designed to catalog and improve access to images on the Internet. The character of the thumbnail index is not esthetic, but functional; its purpose is not to be artistic, but to be comprehensive.31 Concluding that the remaining fair use factors also favored allowing defendant’s use, the court held for the defendant.32 Similarly, in Authors Guild, Inc. v. Google, Inc.,33 the court held that the Google Books Project, which undertook digital scans of books in several university libraries in order to enhance public access to, scholarly research in, and archival preservation of these books, also constitutes a transformative fair use. Google’s use of the copyrighted works is highly transformative. Google Books digitizes books and transforms 30. Kelly, 336 F.3d at 815–17. 31. Kelly, 77 F. Supp. 2d at 1119 (internal citation omitted). 32. Kelly, 336 F.3d at 822. See also Perfect 10, Inc. v. Amazon.com, Inc., 508 F.3d 1146, 1165 (9th Cir. 2007), wherein plaintiff was the proprietor of an Internet site that provided images of nude women to paying subscribers. Plaintiff alleged that by using co-defendant Google’s search indices, users could not only locate plaintiff’s images but they could also locate sites that posted infringing copies of plaintiff’s photographs. Nonetheless, the court concluded that the instant search engine also qualified as a transformative Fair Use. Google’s use of thumbnails is highly transformative. In Kelly we concluded that Arriba’s use of thumbnails was transformative because “Arriba’s use of the images serve[d] a different function than Kelly’s use—improving access to information on the [I]nternet versus artistic expression.” . . . Although an image may have been created originally to serve an entertainment, aesthetic, or informative function, a search engine transforms the image into a pointer directing a user to a source of information. Just as a “parody has an obvious claim to transformative value” because “it can provide social benefit, by shedding light on an earlier work, and, in the process, creating a new one,” . . . a search engine provides social benefit by incorporating an original work into a new work, namely, an electronic reference tool. Indeed, a search engine may be more transformative than a parody because a search engine provides an entirely new use for the original work, while a parody typically has the same entertainment purpose as the original work. . . . In other words, a search engine puts images “in a different context” so that they are “transformed into a new creation.” Id. (internal citations omitted). 33. Authors Guild, Inc. v. Google, Inc., 954 F. Supp. 2d 282, 291 (S.D.N.Y. 2013), aff’d, No. 13-4829-cv, 2015 WL 6079426 (2d Cir. Oct. 16, 2015). Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 473 expressive text into a comprehensive word index that helps readers, scholars, researchers, and others find books. Google Books has become an important tool for libraries and librarians and cite-checkers as it helps to identify and find books. The use of book text to facilitate search through the display of snippets is transformative. The display of snippets of text for search is similar to the display of thumbnail images of photographs for search or small images of concert posters for reference to past events, as the snippets help users locate books and determine whether they may be of interest. Google Books thus uses words for a different purpose—it uses snippets of text to act as pointers directing users to a broad selection of books. Similarly, Google Books is also transformative in the sense that it has transformed book text into data for purposes of substantive research, including data mining and text mining in new areas, thereby opening up new fields of research. Words in books are being used in a way they have not been used before. Google Books has created something new in the use of book text—the frequency of words and trends in their usage provide substantive information.34 In general, courts in the United States have proven quite adept at employing fair use to promote digital copyright social utility.35 C. Copyright Limitations and Exceptions: The European Union The copyright law of the European Union36 provides the seminal model of copyright limitations and exceptions. EU 34. Id.; see also Lateef Mtima, The Promise of Information Justice, in CYBERSPACE LAW: CENSORSHIP AND REGULATION OF THE INTERNET 54, 64–70 (Hannibal Travis ed., 2013); Travis, supra note 11, at 820–24. 35. Authors Guild, 2015 WL 6079426, at *8–9 (“We have no difficulty concluding that Google’s making of a digital copy of Plaintiffs’ books for the purpose of enabling a search for identification of books containing a term of interest to the searcher involves a highly transformative purpose. . . . [T]he purpose of Google’s copying of the original copyrighted books is to make available significant information about those books, permitting a searcher to identify those that contain a word or term of interest, as well as those that do not include reference to it. In addition, through the ngrams tool, Google allows readers to learn the frequency of usage of selected words in the aggregate corpus of published books in different historical periods. We have no doubt that the purpose of this copying is the sort of transformative purpose described . . . as strongly favoring satisfaction of the first [fair use] factor.”). Many legal scholars and commentators have supported these trends. See, e.g., Matthew Sag, Orphan Works as Grist for the Data Mill, 27 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 1503, 1526 & n.112, 1548 (2012) (arguing that copying for non-expressive or “non-consumptive” purposes, such as the automated extraction of data, should not be considered infringing conduct). 36. The European Union is a political–economic union of several European nations, the origins of which can be traced to the aftermath of World War II and the establishment Do Not Delete 474 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 copyright law is the product of a multi-national initiative to harmonize the copyright laws of the participating European nations (the Member States), many of which have copyright regimes that are centuries old and which can vary significantly, particularly between common law and civil law countries. Building upon the provisions of the Berne Convention,37 to which all of the Member States are signatories, the European Union has issued various directives38 that obligate the Member States to enact into their individual copyright regimes additional common features, rights, and limitations, including rights and limitations pertinent to digital information technology, and to incorporate the judgments of and legal principles formulated by the European Court of Justice (ECJ).39 Accordingly, the copyright law of the European Union “begins” with the Berne Convention, which provides the basic prerequisites to and elements of copyright protection, and which further permits its signatories to provide for specific limitations upon or exceptions to the rights afforded thereunder. The EU Copyright Directive and other EU directives then build upon the Berne “baseline,” incorporating additional rights and limitations, which collectively harmonize, and to some extent modernize, the copyright laws of the Member States. Neither the Berne Convention nor the EU directives provide for a flexible “fair use” mechanism through which the public may make unauthorized use of copyrighted works. Instead, the Berne Convention and the EU directives collectively enumerate specific limitations and exceptions in connection with the copyright owner’s exclusive rights, which provide for the unauthorized use of copyrighted works, typically under circumstances that promote of the European Coal and Steel Community in 1952. The European Union was formally established by the Maastricht Treaty in 1993, which also introduced the mechanism of European Citizenship. See Treaty on European Union, Feb. 7, 1992, 1992 O.J. (C 191) 1–2, 7. 37. Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works, Sept. 9, 1886, 1161 U.N.T.S. 3 (amended Sept. 28, 1979). The European Union Copyright Directive was adopted by the European Union mutatis mutandis with the Berne Convention, meaning that EU copyright law is effectively comprised of the provisions of Berne, which provide the baseline elements of EU copyright, such as the prerequisites to protection, as supplemented or added to by the EU copyright directives. 38. See, e.g., Directive 2001/29/EC, supra note 16 (expanding previous directives of the EU to apply in the “information society” context). 39. The European Court of Justice is the highest court in the European Union with respect to the interpretation of European Union law, and among other things, it ensures the consistent application of EU law by the Member States. Although it is not possible to appeal a decision of a national court of a Member State to the ECJ, national courts refer questions of EU law to the ECJ, and in turn apply the Court’s interpretation of EU law. See Karen J. Alter, Who Are the “Masters of the Treaty”?: European Governments and the European Court of Justice, 52 INT’L ORG. 121, 124–25 (1998). Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 475 the public interest in advancing science, education, and culture. For example, pursuant to Article 5 of the European Union Copyright Directive, Member States are permitted to adopt limitations that allow for unauthorized non-commercial reproduction of copyrighted material for private use and by public libraries, educational institutions, or archives; unauthorized use in connection with teaching or scientific research; unauthorized uses directly related to a disability; unauthorized use for press reviews and news reporting, and quotations for purposes of criticism or review; caricature, parody, or pastiche; unauthorized use in connection with the demonstration or repair of equipment; and for incidental inclusion in another work.40 In accordance with the Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS), any such limitations and exceptions must only be applied in special cases and in ways that do not conflict with the normal exploitation of the work, and do not unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of the copyright owner.41 D. EU Copyright Limitations and Exceptions and Digital Copyright In as much as EU copyright law only provides for enumerated copyright limitations and exceptions, any unauthorized engagement in a copyright holder’s exclusive rights (digital or otherwise) must fit within a recognized limitation or exception in order to be allowed. For example, in Infopaq International A/S v. Danske Dagblades Forening,42 the defendant conducted a “media monitoring and analysis business” in connection with which it prepared “summaries” of selected articles from newspapers and periodicals. The summaries were prepared by making automated scans and then printing snippets of the articles, which were 40. Additional possible limitations include uses for the purposes of public security or in administrative, parliamentary, or judicial proceedings; uses of political speeches and extracts of public lectures, to the extent justified by public information; uses during religious or official celebrations; preservation of recordings of broadcasts in official archives; reproductions of broadcasts by social, non -commercial institutions such as hospitals and prisons, provided compensation is paid to the copyright holder; uses of works, such as architecture or sculpture, which are located permanently in public places; use for the advertisement of the public exhibition or sale of art; use of a protected work (e.g., plans) for the reconstruction of a building; and communication of works to the public within the premises of public libraries, educational institutions, museums, or archives. Directive 2001/29/EC, supra note 16, art. 5, at 16–17. Member States also are permitted to retain limitations that were in effect as of June 22, 2001. Id. art 1.2, at 15. 41. See TRIPS, supra note 8, art. 13; see also Directive 2001/29/EC, supra note 16. 42. Case C-5/08, Infopaq Int’l A/S v. Danske Dagblades Forening, 2009 E.C.R. I-06569. Do Not Delete 476 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 converted into digital files and then provided to defendant’s customers. The plaintiff, a professional association of newspaper publishers, sued for copyright infringement, and in response, defendant argued that its activities fell within a recognized exception which permits temporary acts of reproduction.43 The court began its analysis by observing that: [Defendant’s] data capture process . . . involves two acts of reproduction: the creation of a TIFF file when the printed articles are scanned and the conversion of the TIFF file into a text file. In addition . . . this procedure entails the reproduction of parts of the scanned printed articles since the extract of 11 words is stored and those 11 words are printed out on paper.44 The court then determined that the dispute presented three questions for disposition: whether defendant’s activities constituted reproduction within the meaning of the EU copyright directives, and if so, whether they involve protectable expression, and finally, whether such activities fall within the exception provided for certain temporary acts of reproduction.45 With respect to whether defendant’s practice involved the use of protectable expression, the court held that, consistent with the Berne Convention, whether the extracted snippets were sufficient to constitute copyrightable expression was a question for the Member State to determine.46 The court further held, however, 43. Article 5 provides: 1. Temporary acts of reproduction referred to in Article 2, which are transient or incidental [and] an integral and essential part of a technological process and whose sole purpose is to enable: (a) a transmission in a network between third parties by an intermediary, or (b) a lawful use of a work or other subject-matter to be made, and which have no independent economic significance, shall be exempted from the reproduction right provided for in Article 2. Directive 2001/29/EC, supra note 16, art. 5.1, at 16. 44. Infopaq, E.C.R. I-06569, para. 24. 45. Id. paras. 26–53. 46. Id. paras. 34, 45–48 (“It is . . . apparent from the general scheme of the Berne Convention, in particular Article 2(5) and (8), that the protection of certain subject-matters as artistic or literary works presupposes that they are intellectual creations. . . . Regarding the elements of such works covered by the protection, it should be observed that they consist of words which, considered in isolation, are not as such an intellectual creation of the author who employs them. It is only through the choice, sequence and combination of those words that the author may express his creativity in an original manner and achieve a result which is an intellectual creation. . . . That being so . . . the possibility may not be ruled out that certain isolated sentences, or even certain parts of sentences in the text in question, may be suitable for conveying to the reader the originality of a publication such as a newspaper article, by communicating to that reader an element which is, in itself, the expression of the Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 477 that assuming arguendo that protectable matter was involved, defendant’s practice involved reproduction within the meaning of the EU directives, in that “an act occurring during a data capture process, which consists of storing an extract of a protected work comprising 11 words and printing out that extract, is such as to come within the concept of reproduction . . . .”47 Accordingly, to the extent that defendant’s “data capture process” involved copyrightable material, it could only be permitted if it fell within the subject exemption. The Court finds . . . those acts of reproduction must not exceed what is necessary for the proper completion of that technological process. Legal certainty for right holders further requires that the storage and deletion of the reproduction not be dependent on discretionary human intervention, particularly by the user of protected works. . . . In the light of the foregoing, the Court finds that an act can be held to be ‘transient’ within the meaning of the second condition laid down in Article 5(1) of Directive 2001/29 only if its duration is limited to what is necessary for the proper completion of the technological process in question, it being understood that that process must be automated so that it deletes that act automatically, without human intervention, once its function of enabling the completion of such a process has come to an end. . . . It is common ground, however, that, by the last act of reproduction in the data capture process, [defendant] is making a reproduction outside the sphere of computer technology. It is printing out files containing the extracts of 11 words and thus reproduces those extracts on a paper medium. . . . In those circumstances, the Court finds that the last act in the data capture process . . . is not a transient act within the meaning of Article 5(1) of Directive 2001/29.48 Thus in accordance with the provisions of the Berne Convention, it is left to each Member State to determine whether “search-snippets” meet the threshold for copyright protection; however, if they constitute protectable expression, even if the court intellectual creation of the author of that article. Such sentences or parts of sentences are, therefore, liable to come within the scope of the protection provided for in Article 2(a) of that directive. In the light of those considerations, the reproduction of an extract of a protected work . . . is such as to constitute reproduction in part within the meaning of Article 2 of Directive 2001/29, if that extract contains an element of the work which, as such, expresses the author’s own intellectual creation; it is for the national court to make this determination.”). 47. Id. para. 51. 48. Id. paras. 61–70. Do Not Delete 478 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 considers the digital innovation of “snippet-search” and indexing as falling within the exception for temporary or transient reproduction, the “analogue” hard-copy (and thus non-transient) print outs would not fit within the exception. E. Fair Dealing Fair dealing can sometimes be regarded as a combination of copyright limitations and exceptions with “fair use type” factors, the latter serving to ensure that where a specific activity fits within a recognized limitation or exception, allowing the activity to proceed will in fact lead to socially equitable and beneficial results.49 Depending upon how this “second step” in the fair dealing assessment is approached, fair dealing might be considered more flexible than strict copyright limitations and exceptions, or it could in practice prove to be more restrictive, given that even a use that fits within a recognized category of limitation could still be precluded by a court as being subjectively inequitable or unfair. In Canada for example, fair dealing is codified at section 29 of the Copyright Act, which enumerates research or private study, criticism or review, news reporting, and parody or satire as activities of fair dealing. If a use is found to fit within one of these categories, the court then will proceed to determine whether allowing it would be fair under the circumstances. To take advantage of the exceptions set out above, a defendant must show that its dealings have been fair. What will constitute fair dealing is not defined in the Act and depends on the facts of each case. The elements of fairness are malleable and can be tailored to each unique set of circumstances.50 Among the factors to be considered in determining whether a defendant’s dealings should be allowed as fair are (1) the purpose of the dealing; (2) the character of the dealing; (3) the amount of the dealing; (4) alternatives to the dealing; (5) the nature of the work; and (6) the effect of the dealing on the work. Fair dealing preserves copyright social utility by recognizing 49. See JOHN S. MCKEOWN, CANADIAN INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY LAW AND STRATEGY 289–90 (2010). “Unlike the American approach of proceeding straight to the fairness assessment, we do not engage in the fairness analysis in Canada until we are satisfied that the dealing is for one of the allowable purposes enumerated in the Copyright Act.” Soc’y of Composers, Authors & Music Publishers of Can. v. Bell Can., [2012] 2 S.C.R. 326, 337 (Can.). The Copyright Act also provides for other exceptions in addition to fair dealing. 50. MCKEOWN, supra note 49, at 290. Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 479 rights in copyrighted material on behalf of both copyright owners and users. The Supreme Court of Canada has made it clear that the fair dealing exception should not be restrictively interpreted. The fair dealing exception like other exceptions in the Act, is a user’s right. In order to maintain the proper balance between the rights of a copyright owner and a user’s interest, it should be given a fair and balanced reading applicable to remedial legislation.51 F. Fair Dealing and Digital Copyright In Society of Composers, Authors and Music Publishers of Canada v. Bell Canada,52 the plaintiff rights holder organization sought royalty payments in connection with the use of its members’ works by the defendant to provide online music “previews,” which consisted of 30 to 90 second excerpts, and which enabled defendants’ customers to sample material before deciding whether to purchase it. The defendant argued that its activities fell within the fair dealing exception for research or private study. In finding for the defendant, the court noted that the exception should be interpreted broadly, and assessed with the benefits that digital previewing affords in mind. The purpose of the fair dealing analysis under the Copyright Act is to determine whether the proper balance has been achieved between protection of the exclusive rights of authors and copyright owners and access to their works by the public. . . . The first step is to determine whether the dealing is for the purpose of either “research” or “private study”, the two allowable purposes listed under 51. Id. at 290–92. See, e.g., Law Soc’y of Upper Canada v. CCH Canadian Ltd., [2004] 1 S.C.R. 339, 342 (Can.) (“Under s. 29 of the Copyright Act, fair dealing for the purpose of research or private study does not infringe copyright. ‘Research’ must be given a large and liberal interpretation in order to ensure that users’ rights are not unduly constrained, and is not limited to non-commercial or private contexts. Lawyers carrying on the business of law for profit are conducting research within the meaning of s. 29. The following factors help determine whether a dealing is fair: the purpose of the dealing, the character of the dealing, the amount of the dealing, the nature of the work, available alternatives to the dealing, and the effect of the dealing on the work. Here, the Law Society’s dealings with the publishers’ works through its custom photocopy service were research-based and fair. The access policy places appropriate limits on the type of copying that the Law Society will do. If a request does not appear to be for the purpose of research, criticism, review or private study, the copy will not be made. If a question arises as to whether the stated purpose is legitimate, the reference librarian will review the matter. The access policy limits the amount of work that will be copied, and the reference librarian reviews requests that exceed what might typically be considered reasonable and has the right to refuse to fulfill a request.”). 52. Bell Canada, [2012] 2 S.C.R. at 327 (Can.). Do Not Delete 480 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 s. 29 of the Copyright Act. The second step assesses whether the dealing is “fair”. . . . The purpose of “research” should be analyzed from the perspective of the consumer as the ultimate user, not the online service provider. The Board properly considered the previews from the perspective of the consumer’s purpose, namely, conducting research to identify which music to purchase. “Research” need not be for creative purposes only. Permitting only creative purposes to qualify as “research” would ignore the fact that one of the objectives of the Copyright Act is the dissemination of the works themselves. Limiting “research” to creative purposes would also run counter to the ordinary meaning of “research,” which includes many activities that do not require the establishment of new facts or conclusions. The fair dealing exception must not be interpreted restrictively and “research” must be given a large and liberal interpretation. 53 The court then easily decided that defendant’s dealings were fair, in that the previews were brief and transitory, and that there were no alternatives available that would provide online users the opportunity to sample music before making the decision to purchase. The foregoing cases illustrate how courts use copyright social balancing mechanisms to accommodate the benefits of digital information technology as a new technological use for copyrighted works. As discussed in the next section, digital information technology also offers unprecedented and thus far largely untapped opportunities to promote copyright social justice and thereby further enhance the social utility of the law. III. INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY SOCIAL JUSTICE IN THE DIGITAL INFORMATION SOCIETY Intellectual property protection, including copyright law, is a social ordering mechanism promulgated to serve a variety of social utility functions, not the least of which being the advancement of culture and the stimulation of innovation.54 The intellectual 53. Id. at 327–28. 54. See Belleflamme & Peitz, supra note 9, at 490 (“Intellectual property (IP) refers to the legal rights that result from intellectual activity in the industrial, scientific, literary and artistic fields. Most countries have adopted laws to protect intellectual property, with the objective to promote innovation and aesthetic creativity.”); Jane C. Ginsburg, International Copyright: From a “Bundle” of National Copyright Law to a Supranational Code?, 47 J. COPYRIGHT SOC’ Y USA 265, 267 (2000) (“[Copyright law] express[es] each sovereign nation’s twin aspirations for its citizens: exposure to works of authorship, and participation in their country’s cultural Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 481 property law as actually applied, however, does not always fully effectuate these objectives, and may sometimes even frustrate these goals. In some situations, intellectual property protection presents institutional barriers to knowledge, information, and education. The continuing lack of widespread access to copyrighted material for the visually disabled is one important example. [T]he inability of the blind and other visually impaired people to have access to printed . . . copies of books . . . should be the copyright civil rights issue of our time. In the wealthiest countries, only some 5 percent of published books are made accessible in formats the visually impaired can use; this figure drops to less than 1 percent in poorer countries. Copyright laws are the principal reason for this scandal.55 patrimony.”). But see Doris Estelle Long, “Democratizing” Globalization: Practicing the Policies of Cultural Inclusion, 10 CARDOZO J. INT’ L & COMP . L. 217, 217 (2002) (“Culture and intellectual property appear to have gotten a divorce during the latter decades of the Twentieth Century.”). While intellectual property regimes rooted in natural law further recognize the objective of protecting creators’ rights to their productions, promoting broader social benefits to society is a compatible and complimentary goal in such regimes. See, e.g., Steven D. Jamar, A Social Justice Perspective on the Role of Copyright in Realizing International Human Rights, 25 P AC. MC GEORGE GLOBAL BUS. & DEV . L.J. 289, 296–97 (2012) (“Natural rights . . . are subject to limitations for the overall public good—indeed, serving the public good is an obligation under the social contract between a society and its citizens. . . . Intellectual property—even if founded on natural law—is properly subject to similar limitations for the public good. As with core human rights like freedom of expression, intellectual property rights cannot be so absolute that they unduly impinge on other rights . . . or undermine the public good. . . . Thus, a natural rights perspective is not necessarily antithetical to crafting intellectual property law, policy, and adm inistration to encourage innovation and entrepreneurship; balancing interests is the key.”); Jorn Sonderholm, Ethical Issues Surrounding Intellectual Property Rights, in N EW F RONTIERS IN THE P HILOSOPHY OF INTELLECTUAL P ROPERTY 110, 117 (Annabelle Lever ed., 2012) (“The natural right of appropriation central to libertarianism has an important proviso . . . which is an ‘enough and as good’ clause on original appropriation. . . . Where resources are scarce, one cannot legitimately stake a claim to something by annexing one’s labour to it. . . . If the resource is necessary for the continued well-being of others, then the fact that x was the one who developed or improved the resource does not give x exclusive rights over it. x’s entitlement to reward for her labour is overridden by the entitlement of others to that which is necessary for their survival.”). See generally International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights art. 15(1), Dec. 16, 1966, 993 U.N.T.S. 3; Adam Mossoff, Who Cares What Thomas Jefferson Thought About Patents? Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege” in Historical Context, 92 CORNELL L. REV. 953, 971–73 (2007). 55. W ILLIAM P ATRY , H OW TO F IX COPYRIGHT 10 (2011). Recently some important progress has been made toward rendering copyrighted works accessible to the blind. The Marrakesh VIP Treaty, formally the Marrakesh Treaty to Facilitate Access to Published Works by Visually Impaired Persons and Persons with Print Disabilities , was signed by fifty-one nations on June 28, 2013. The treaty provides for copyright exceptions to facilitate the creation of accessible versions of books and other Do Not Delete 482 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 Where individuals who lack such access fail to achieve and exploit their full potential, it is ultimately society as a whole that is deprived of the foregone contributions to its intellectual property inventory. In other situations, the rules of intellectual property protection are systemically misused toward socially counterproductive ends. Marginalized groups in the developed world as well as communities in many developing nations perennially suffer the misappropriation and inequitable exploitation of their indigenous knowledge and cultural expression, often at the hands of established intellectual property stakeholders, who in turn insist upon the utmost respect and protection for their own rights and interests. 56 The copyrighted works. The ratification of twenty nations is needed for the treaty to go into effect. See Marrakesh Treaty to Facilitate Access to Published Works for Persons Who Are Blind, Visually Impaired, or Otherwise Print Disabled arts. 3, 4, June 27, 2013, 52 I.L.M. 1312. 56. See Keith Aoki, Distributive and Syncretic Motives in Intellectual Property Law (with Special Reference to Coercion, Agency, and Development), 40 U.C. DAVIS L. REV . 717, 773–74 (2007) (“The first multilateralism, from the 1500s to 1945, suggests that, even prior to the end of the nineteenth century, many territories in Africa, Asia, and the Pacific were already subject to IP conventions and regulations implemented through formal and informal European control. . . . These arrangements unsurprisingly had a European flavor, due in no small part to a self-perceived superiority and attendant ‘responsibility’ to ‘civilize’ the non -Europeans. The consolidation of formal colonial rule in which IP laws were an integral part soon followed. IP laws were extended to colonies during this period, in part to advance colonial strategies of assimilation, incorporation, and control. . . . [T]he second multilateralism, from 1945 to the 1990s, accompanied the demise of colonialism and attendant debates as to the appropriate role for developing countries in the international IP system. New sovereign states were first recognized, and then conditions were constructed for their participation in international fora without interrogation into the appropriateness or value of IP laws in their respective domestic settings. The result was a legitimization of developing countries’ adherence to colonial-era legislation under the guise of an international legal system wholly unrelated to domestic priorities and constraints. Meanwhile, treaties used for the effective subjugation of non-Europeans in the colonial period continued to be the formal tool of choice to facilitate the developed countries’ strategic exercise of power.”); Cynthia M. Ho, Biopiracy and Beyond: A Consideration of Socio-Cultural Conflicts with Global Patent Policies, 39 U. MICH . J.L. REFORM 433, 435–36 (2006) (“[M]any developing countries have argued that . . . Western countries engage in their own piracy—’biopiracy’—by taking genetic resources and associated traditional knowledge from biodiverse developing countries without permission, then patenting related inventions, but failing to share any of the resulting commercial profits. The process of obtaining private rights over products derived from third world resources or knowledge that is considered sacred or beyond private ownership is considered to be morally offensive to many citizens of developing countries, as well as those with sympathetic interests in other countries. Moreover, many of these citizens view Western countries and companies with great suspicion since usurpation of resources harks back to colonial imperialism.”); Lateef Mtima, What’s Mine Is Mine But What’s Yours Is Ours: IP Imperialism, the Right of Publicity, and Intellectual Property Social Justice in the Digital Information Age, 15 SMU SCI. & T ECH . L. REV. 323, 332–36 (2012); see also Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 483 failure of the intellectual property regime to address such abuses not only discourages intellectual property development and dissemination by exploited groups and communities, but also fosters antagonism and disrespect toward intellectual property protection on a fundamental level. 57 Where the application and enforcement of the intellectual property law does not encompass redress for social injustice, the result can be impairment of the law’s overarching social utility objectives. Evaluating problems of intellectual property social injustice for their impact on intellectual property social utility acknowledges that certain social deficiencies gnaw at the very foundations of intellectual property protection.58 In such cases, it is not only doctrinally appropriate to re-envision the intellectual property law as a tool for social justice, it is doctrinally imperative that the law be interpreted and applied to correct these social Stephen R. Munzer, Corrective Justice and Intellectual Property Rights in Traditional Knowledge, in N EW F RONTIERS IN THE P HILOSOPHY OF INTELLECTUAL P ROPERTY, supra note 54, at 58, 58–59, 61. 57. See Susan Tiefenbrun, A Hermeneutic Methodology and How Pirates Read and Misread the Berne Convention, 17 W IS. I NT ’ L L.J. 1, 1 (1999) (“Economics alone cannot explain why a country chooses to steal books, cassettes, movies, and computer programs rather than obey the law. The causes and effects of intellectual property piracy are intricately connected to, and affected by, a multiplicity of factors including the economy of the country in which the piracy is committed, the political history and ideology of the pirating nation, the culture of the people engaged in the piracy, and the adequacy of the legal system to enforce domestic and international intellectual property laws.”); see also J OHANNA G IBSON , C REATING S ELVES : I NTELLECTUAL P ROPERTY AND THE N ARRATION OF C ULTURE 4–6 (2006); Christine Haight Farley, Registering Offense: The Prohibition of Slurs as Trademarks, in D IVERSITY IN INTELLECTUAL P ROPERTY : I DENTITIES , I NTERESTS , AND I NTERSECTIONS , supra note 3, at 105, 110, 111–12 (“Recent psychological evidence demonstrated the negative effects associated with stereotypical and derogatory references to Native American people. . . . Besides this psychological harm, an additional and more symbolic harm occurs when someone’s cultural identity is literally, and legally, owned by another entity. . . . By trademarking a racial referent, the message is that the referent is owned, and the owner has the leg al right to use the racial term; perhaps even the obligation to use it. . . . And by going into business under harmful words, the owner causes others—fans and consumers— to endlessly utter them.”). 58. The body of work that explores and delineates the social justice obligations of intellectual property law has become extensive and continues to develop. See, e.g., Aoki, supra note 56; Chander & Sunder, supra note 2; Margaret Chon, Intellectual Property and the Development Divide, 27 CARDOZO L. REV. 2821 (2006); Julie E. Cohen, Creativity and Culture in Copyright Theory, 40 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 1151 (2007); Brianna Dahlberg, The Orphan Works Problem: Preserving Access to the Cultural History of Disadvantaged Groups, 20 S. CAL. REV. L. & SOC. JUST. 275 (2011); Heimes, supra note 2; Neela Kartha, Digital Sampling and Copyright Law in the Social Context: No More Colorblindness!!, 14 U. MIAMI ENT. & SPORTS L. REV. 218, 219, 225–26 (1997); Lateef Mtima, Introduction, Symposium on Intellectual Property and Social Justice, supra note 3; Lateef Mtima & Steven D. Jamar, Fulfilling the Copyright Social Justice Promise: Digitizing Textual Information, 55 N.Y.L. SCH. L. REV. 77 (2010). Do Not Delete 484 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 inequities, in deference to the social ordering objectives of intellectual property protection.59 A social justice perspective toward intellectual property law contemplates socially equitable access, inclusion, and empowerment as essential and intrinsic to intellectual property social utility. From this perspective, intellectual property social utility is therefore best served when the precepts of intellectual property social justice are affirmatively acknowledged and pursued. With respect to copyright, socially equitable access to copyrighted works ensures that the widest possible audience of minds and hearts will find the inspiration to conceive, express, and disseminate. Moreover, socially just application and enforcement of copyright law protects the interests and incentives of all stakeholders, and thereby maximizes the social efficiency and productive impact and output of the copyright system. The advent and proliferation of digital information technology has made comprehensive access to the global store of copyrighted works an almost routine aspect of modern life for some. Many copyright users enjoy revolutionary means and options to use and appropriately reuse copyrighted content, and to make their own contributions to the copyright storehouse. Digital information 59. I have argued elsewhere that in this sense, the pursuit of social justice is an inherent obligation of intellectual property protection. See Lateef Mtima, From Swords to Ploughshares: Towards a Unified Theory of Social Justice, in INTELLECTUAL P ROPERTY ENTREPRENEURSHIP AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 265, 26970 (Lateef Mtima ed., 2015) (“Intellectual property social justice [is based on a] core premise . . . that the principles of equitable access, inclusion, and empowerment are intrinsic to intellectual property protection as a social ordering mechanism. A particular benefit of this approach is that the instances in which intellectual property protection is permitted to obstruct critical social welfare imperatives are not addressed as independent IP social maladies, but rather as symptoms of an IP-systemic malaise, engendered and perpetuated by a misconstruction of and consequential imbalance in the intellectual property regime. Intellectual property social justice therefore prioritizes holistic revitalization of the intellectual property infrastructure over localized responses to its symptomatic ills. In this sense, intellectual property social justice is perhaps more aptly described as a theory of IP social restoration, as opposed to IP social reform.”); see also Margaret Chon, Global Intellectual Property: Governance (Under Construction), 12 THEORETICAL INQ. L. 349, 358 (2011) (“Even if promoting creation and innovation is the premier value of intellectual property, the rights-maximizing agenda pursued by intellectual property-exporting states has resulted not only in power asymmetry but arguably in policies that are not welfare -maximizing even for domestic industries within those states. Access for the purpose of fo llow-on innovation—in other words, for maximizing returns on the public good of knowledge itself—is a critical policy component within the overall intellectual property regulatory framework. Moreover, access to knowledge for purposes of maximizing other global public goods such as basic education, food security and disease control implicates both fairness and growth.”). Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 485 technology has also democratized the distribution channels for copyrighted expression.60 If these resources can be better focused toward the needs of the “IP-marginalized,” universal copyright access and participation could become an immediate reality. However, notwithstanding these unprecedented opportunities through which to provide for socially equitable access to and dissemination of expressive works, as well as for the socially progressive use, reuse, and exploitation of copyrighted material, some prevailing notions about copyright continue to frustrate and impede the application of digital innovations to achieve these goals.61 Consequently, many copyright law and policy makers, scholars, social activists, and rights holders advocate for more socially responsive amendment, interpretation, and application of copyright law in the digital information age. In the interest of intellectual property social utility, law and policy makers can and should embrace the unique opportunities presented by digital information technology to advance intellectual property social justice. [T]he network is illustrative of the way in which the law must develop in concert with the very means and practices available within society to ensure the ongoing development of knowledge and the transfer of that knowledge among and between citizens. The opportunity for dissemination of quality materials for education, research, and development by engaging novel regulatory systems, rather than attempting to limit through intellectual property these transformations in ways to deal with knowledge, is an opportunity of not only social and cultural significance, but also economic. To continue to focus on conceptualising 60. Embracing new opportunities for “Digital Entrepreneurship,” many creative artists from IP-underserved communities have established thriving, Internet-based business concerns that cater to the needs and interests of their communities, while at the same time bring works that are often ignored by more established content providers to new and larger audiences. See, e.g., About, TERI WOOD PUBLISHING, http://teriwoodspublishing.com/about-teri-woods/ (last visited Nov. 20, 2015); About Us, LEE & LOW BOOKS, https://www.leeandlow.com/about-us (last visited Nov. 20, 2015); About Us, SOULECTION, http://soulection.com/about-us/ (last visited Nov. 20, 2015). 61. See, e.g., William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, An Economic Analysis of Copyright Law, 18 J. LEGAL STUD. 325, 327–28 (1989). But cf. Daniel J. Gervais, Intellectual Property and Human Rights: Learning to Live Together, in INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND HUMAN RIGHTS 3, 14 (Paul L.C. Torremans ed., 2008) (“[N]ow that intellectual property has entered the house of trade law, it may not be possible to [dethrone economic analysis]. Yet, in the very spirit of law and economics, it may be useful to question the monopoly of economic analysis on the theoretical discourse surrounding the foundations and evolution of copyright policy.”); Joseph E. Stiglitz, Economic Foundations of Intellectual Property Rights, 57 DUKE L.J. 1693, 1701, 1716–19 (2008) (discussing how economic-incentive approaches that restrict IP access can impede innovation). Do Not Delete 486 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 these relations within the simplistic transactions imagined by intellectual property is to continue limiting significant economic and cultural potential. 62 Assessed through the lens of intellectual property social justice, digital information technology can be fully deployed to meet the challenge stated in the preamble to the WIPO Copyright Treaty, which acknowledges “the need to introduce new international rules and clarify the interpretation of certain existing rules in order to provide adequate solutions to the questions raised by new economic, social, cultural and technological developments.”63 In general, the leading copyright social balancing mechanisms are somewhat agnostic toward intellectual property social justice. As discussed in the next section, however, some courts have begun to acknowledge concrete social justice mandates in the copyright law, by invoking non-copyright law and policy in their use of copyright social balancing mechanisms to adjudicate copyright disputes, including controversies that shape the contours of digital copyright. 62. GIBSON , supra note 57, at 27; see also GIBERT, supra note 9, at 7–9 (“Actors in [the creative content] industry group have consistently pushed for stronger copyright law on the basis that this enables them to extract maximum value from their investments in audiovisual content. This may have been the case 20 years ago. However, the proliferation of digital technologies and social networks has dramatically changed the way people engage with content online. Strong copyright law with few exceptions may have helped promote the growth of these industries in an industrial era where most people were never more than passive consumers of content on analogue devices. In a digital era, access to content and the ability to hyperlink, mix, remix, copy—and particularly to share—is fundamental to the ways in which we interact with content. In this digital environment, a copyright system with limited exceptions may actually diminish the value of audiovisual content to consumers and simultaneously inhibit their ability to promote it within their social networks. The very notion of passive consumers of content is being displaced by notions of co-creation, remix culture and user-generated content in an attention economy where awareness of the product is an increasingly important source of value.”); Daniel J. Gervais, Making Copyright Whole: A Principled Approach to Copyright Exceptions and Limitations, 5 U. OTTAWA L. & T ECH . J. 1, 5–6 (“[C]opyright protection should cease to apply once the goal of maximizing welfare by ensuring that new works are created without stifling the potential for new ones . . . . This would seem to mesh rather well also with economic analyses of copyright that look for a (measurable) optimal protection point at which creation and dissemination of new works is not negated by deadweight and other welfare losses.”). 63. See WCT, supra note 14, pmbl. See generally Michael Gollin et al., Intellectual Property Social Justice in Action: Public Interest Intellectual Property Advisors, in INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY, ENTREPRENEURSHIP AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 163 (Lateef Mtima ed., 2015) (discussing international pro bono legal representation to promote IP social justice). Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 487 IV. COPYRIGHT SOCIAL UTILITY IN THE COURTS: PROMOTING SOCIAL INTEROPERABILITY The U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit was recently confronted with a dispute that involved one of the most socially ambitious undertakings of the digital information age. In Authors Guild, Inc. v. HathiTrust,64 a group of universities agreed to allow Google to make digital scans of the books in their institutional libraries, so as to render them amenable to digital research (including “data mining,” the process of using computers to extract aggregate information from multiple works), accessible to persons with certified print disabilities, and for purposes of archival preservation. The owners of the copyrights in many of the subject works brought copyright infringement litigation, claiming that these unauthorized uses infringed their exclusive rights. In adjudicating the plaintiffs’ claims, the court of appeals affirmed the finding of the district court that the digitization project constituted a fair use of the books in the universities’ libraries. Turning to the first [fair use] factor, we conclude that the creation of a full-text searchable database is a quintessentially transformative use . . . . [T]he result of a word search is different in purpose, character, expression, meaning, and message from the page (and the book) from which it is drawn. Indeed, we can discern little or no resemblance between the original text and the results of the HDL full-text search. There is no evidence that the Authors write with the purpose of enabling text searches of their books. Consequently, the full-text search function does not “supersede[ ] the objects [or purposes] of the original creation” . . . .65 With respect to making digital scans in order to render the works accessible to the blind, while the court did not consider this use to be transformative, it nonetheless found it also to be a fair use, in accord with the district court’s observation of “the unprecedented ability of print-disabled individuals to have an 64. Authors Guild, Inc. v. HathiTrust, 902 F. Supp. 2d 445, 448 (S.D.N.Y. 2012), aff’d, 755 F.3d 87 (2d Cir. 2014). 65. HathiTrust, 755 F.3d at 97 (alterations in original). The court thus concluded that this was a transformative use and reached the same conclusion as to the purpose of archival preservation. The court further concluded that the remaining fair use factors also favored allowing these uses. Do Not Delete 488 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 equal opportunity to compete with their sighted peers.”66 The court based its holding in part upon the Americans with Disabilities Act and thereby expressly considered federal law and public policy to enhance opportunities for the physically disabled in its assessment of the copyright social utilities. “Congress declared that our ‘[n]ation’s proper goals regarding individuals with disabilities are to assure equality of opportunity, full participation, independent living, and economic self-sufficiency for such individuals.’”67 In explicitly relying upon federal disability law and policy as a basis for its decision, the court adopted a social-justice oriented approach to the calibration of digital copyright social utility. Copyright does not exist in a socio-legal vacuum; it can best achieve its social function when it is applied so as to enable all citizens to participate in the rising and advancement of the societal culture. Put differently, one way to perceive the rationale of HathiTrust is that it presupposes that at least one of the purposes of the federal mandate to empower the physically disabled is to enable these citizens to contribute their fair share to the nation’s copyright repast. Moreover, the decision in HathiTrust is by no means a judicial outlier. With this decision, the Second Circuit joins other courts that have expressly considered the relationship of copyright social utility to other socio-legal objectives. In Deckmyn v. Vandersteen,68 the author of a cartoon illustration brought suit when the defendant used the work to prepare a political flyer that contained racially offensive content. In response, the defendant argued that the use was permitted under the recognized exception to undertake unauthorized parodies of copyrighted works. 69 In analyzing plaintiff’s claims, the court not only reviewed the relevant copyright directives and exceptions, but further cautioned that the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union should also be considered in resolving the issues. In order to determine whether, in a particular case, the application of the exception for parody within the meaning of Article 5(3)(k) of Directive 2001/29 preserves [a] fair 66. HathiTrust, 902 F. Supp. 2d at 464. 67. HathiTrust, 755 F.3d at 102. 68. Case C‑201/13, Deckmyn v. Vandersteen, 2014 EUR-Lex CELEX LEXIS 62013CC0201, paras. 7–10, 11 (Sept. 3, 2014). 69. Directive 2001/29/EC, supra note 16, arts. 2, 3, 5, at 16–17. Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 489 balance, all the circumstances of the case must be taken into account. Accordingly, with regard to the dispute before the national court, it should be noted that, according to [plaintiffs], since, in the drawing at issue, the characters who, in the original work, were picking up the coins were replaced by people wearing veils and people of colour, that drawing conveys a discriminatory message which has the effect of associating the protected work with such a message. If that is indeed the case, which it is for the national court to assess, attention should be drawn to the principle of non-discrimination based on race, colour and ethnic origin, as was specifically defined in Council Directive 2000/43/EC . . . implementing the principle of equal treatment between persons irrespective of racial or ethnic origin and confirmed, inter alia, by Article 21(1) of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union. In those circumstances, holders of rights provided for in Articles 2 and 3 of Directive 2001/29 . . . have, in principle, a legitimate interest in ensuring that the work protected by copyright is not associated with such a message.70 In Productores de Música de España (Promusicae) v. Telefónica de España SAU,71 the plaintiff, a nonprofit organization of music producers and publishers, sought an order directing the defendant ISP to disclose the identities and physical addresses of certain of its subscribers, based on the allegation that said subscribers had used the Kazaa peer-to-peer file exchange program in order to illegally share copyrighted music files. The defendant argued, among other things, that the relief sought by the plaintiff is only available in criminal proceedings or proceedings that involve the public safety. The court began its analysis by observing that the dispute involved issues that went beyond the question of proper enforcement of intellectual property rights, and that it was 70. Vandersteen, 2014 EUR-Lex CELEX LEXIS 62013CC0201, paras. 28–31 (internal citation omitted). For a discussion of this issue in the context of the tension between the First Amendment and the copyright owner’s “right not to speak” see Deidré A. Keller, “What He Said.” The Transformative Potential of the Use of Copyrighted Content in Political Campaigns—or—How a Win for Mitt Romney Might Have Been a Victory for Free Speech, 16 VAND. J. ENT. & TECH. L. 497, 513–17 (2014). 71. Case C-275/06, Productores de Música de Espana (Promusicae) v. Telefónica de España SAU, 2008 E.C.R. I-271, I-272. Do Not Delete 490 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 obligated to consider all of the social utilities implicated in the dispute. By its question the national court asks essentially whether Community law, in particular Directives 2000/31, 2001/29 and 2004/48, read also in the light of Articles 17 and 47 of the Charter, must be interpreted as requiring Member States to lay down, in order to ensure effective protection of copyright, an obligation to communicate personal data in the context of civil proceedings. Even if, formally, the national court has limited its question to the interpretation of Directives 2000/31, 2001/ 29 and 2004/48 and the Charter, that circumstance does not prevent the Court from providing the national court with all the elements of interpretation of Community law which may be of use for deciding the case before it, whether or not that court has referred to them in the wording of its question.72 Acknowledging that “the fundamental right to property, which includes intellectual property rights such as copyright and the fundamental right to effective judicial protection constitute general principles of Community law,” the court further noted that: [T]he situation in respect of which the national court puts that question involves, in addition to those two rights, a further fundamental right, namely the right that guarantees protection of personal data and hence of private life. . . . Article 8 of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms . . . guarantees the right to respect for private life, and Article 8 of the Charter expressly proclaims the right to protection of personal data.73 The court concluded that while it was within the discretion of the Member States to reconcile these competing rights, proper deference must be given to the need to balance the range of social utilities at issue. 72. Id. at I-337 (internal citation omitted). 73. Id. at I-344 to -345 (internal citation omitted). Here the court does not restrict the consideration of non-IP law toward the interpretation or application of a specific copyright limitation or exception, but rather, concludes that consideration of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms and certain, related EU Directives is necessary to interpreting the relevant EU Copyright Directives as whole, and in the balancing of the rights and interests arising thereunder against the obligation to protect private life. Consequently, even upon an ultimate determination that the balancing of these rights favors the release of customer identities, said customers could then interpose the applicability of specific limitations or exceptions, the interpretation of which could in turn trigger a new round of inquiries into pertinent non-copyright law. Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 491 The present reference for a preliminary ruling thus raises the question of the need to reconcile the requirements of the protection of different fundamental rights, namely the right to respect for private life on the one hand and the rights to protection of property and to an effective remedy on the other. The mechanisms allowing those different rights and interests to be balanced . . . provides for rules which determine in what circumstances and to what extent the processing of personal data is lawful and what safeguards must be provided for . . . . .... That being so, the Member States must, when transposing the directives mentioned above, take care to rely on an interpretation of the directives which allows a fair balance to be struck between the various fundamental rights protected by the Community legal order. Further, when implementing the measures transposing those directives, the authorities and courts of the Member States must not only interpret their national law in a manner consistent with those directives but also make sure that they do not rely on an interpretation of them which would be in conflict with those fundamental rights or with the other general principles of Community law . . . .74 The foregoing decisions are more than merely examples of copyright disputes that involve or implicate rights and interests in addition to those arising under intellectual property law; the 74. Id. at I-345 to -346; see also Ante Wessels, Copyright Law and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, I NFO JUSTICE . ORG, http://infojustice.org/archives/32035#more -32035 (“The Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (CESCR) clarifies in its authoritative interpretation General Comment No. 17, that it is important not to equate intellectual property rights with the human right recognized in ICESCR article 15, paragraph 1 (c): ‘Human rights are fundamental as they are inherent to the human person as such, whereas intellectual property rights are first and foremost means by which States seek to provide incentives for inventiveness and creativity, encourage the dissemination of creative and innovative productions, as well as the development of cultural identities, and preserve the integrity of scientific, literary and artistic productions for the benefit of society as a whole. . . . Whereas the human right to benefit from the protection of the moral and material interests resultin g from one’s scientific, literary and artistic productions safeguards the personal link between authors and their creations and between peoples, communities, or other groups and their collective cultural heritage, as well as their basic material interests which are necessary to enable authors to enjoy an adequate standard of living, intellectual property regimes primarily protect business and corporate interests and investments. Moreover, the scope of protection of the moral and material interests of the author provided for by article 15, paragraph 1 (c), does not necessarily coincide with what is referred to as intellectual property rights under national legislation or international agreements.’” (alteration in original)). Do Not Delete 492 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 courts in these cases recognize a judicial obligation to consider non-IP social utilities in the placement of copyright (and potentially other intellectual property) protection in the total political economy.75 Whether invoked by an IP rights holder, an IP user, or sua sponte by a court, intellectual property law must adhere to a mandate of “social interoperability” with other legal and social ordering mechanisms. These decisions therefore not only reposition the parameters of copyright social utility, they also suggest an analytical framework for realigning copyright and other forms of IP protection to calibrate for intellectual property social justice. V. DERIVING JUDICIAL STANDARDS FOR PROMOTING INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY SOCIAL JUSTICE The twentieth century gave witness to unprecedented advances in pharmacology, bio-farming, digital information technology, and the proliferation of the Internet. 76 Despite 75. See, e.g., VINCENT M OSCO , T HE P OLITICAL ECONOMY OF COMMUNICATION 24 (2d ed. 2009) (“One can think about political economy as the study of the social relations, particularly the power relations, that mutually constitute the production, distribution, and consumption of resources.”); John C. Reitz, Political Economy as a Major Architectural Principle of Public Law, 75 T UL. L. REV . 1121, 1125 (2001) (“Each country’s principle of political economy . . . is a normative statement reflecting the conception that predominates within that country of what the appropriate relationship between the individual and the state should be.”). See generally Case C-145/10, Eva-Maria Painer v. Standard VerlagsGmbH and Others, 2011 E.C.R. I-12533, I-12628 (construing application of the copyright exception for fair quotation to unauthorized re-publication of a photograph in the public interest); Chon, supra note 59, at 359 (“The most classic form of intellectual property governance is national-level public ordering in which, at least in the United States, industries (non-state actors) vie for negotiated compromises within a legal framework monopolized by the state. Within this traditionally and territorially bounded domestic frame, the traditional policy balance weighs the temporary exclusive rights to induce innovation against access by different non -rights-holders for different purposes, including user-based innovation. In copyright, for example, this balance is famously encapsulated by the section 107 fair use exception to the section 106 rights, which are the basic bundle of exclusive rights in U.S. copyright law. Fair use is thought to promote goals such as follow-on innovation, as well as to facilitate education, scholarship and scientific research. All of these access facilitated activities promote more, and arguably better, innovation both directly and indirectly.”). 76. See, e.g., Ronald P. Rubin, A Brief History of Great Discoveries in Pharmacology: In Celebration of the Centennial Anniversary of the Founding of the American Society of Pharmacology and Experimental Therapeutics, 59 PHARMACOLOGICAL REVS. 289 (2007); BENJAMIN R. LAWLOR, THE AGE OF GLOBALIZATION: IMPACT OF INFORMATION TECHNOLOGY ON GLOBAL BUSINESS STRATEGIES 1 (2007), http://digitalcommons.bry ant.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1000&context=honors_cis; Computers Timeline, NAT’L ACAD. OF ENG’G, http://greatachievements.org/?id=3975 (last visited Nov. 20, 2015); Famous Inventions of the 20th Century, HUBPAGES, http://hassam.hubpages.com /hub/Famous-Inventions-Of-The-20th-Century (last updated Oct. 22, 2011). Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 493 these achievements, widespread famine, pandemic disease, and stifling illiteracy still persist throughout much of the world, as the fruits of innovative and creative progress have yet to reach many of those who need them most. Although by no means the sole impediment to the pervasive uplift of the global social welfare, the intellectual property system is often cited as a critical stumbling block to socially beneficent development. If the instrumental mandate of intellectual property law is truly to increase knowledge for positive purposes, then there must be fuller consideration of the provision of basic needs and other global public goods such as food security, education, and health care. Undernourished, diseased, dying, undereducated, or extremely impoverished populations are viewed by many as negative externalities both qualitatively and quantitatively more serious than the danger of under-incentivizing authors and inventors. The latter is the externality to which intellectual property law devotes its exclusive attention. This disjuncture over priorities has highlighted an increasingly untenable intellectual solipsism of the intellectual property policymaking framework, as intellectual property globalization encounters ethical concerns associated with development.77 77. Chon, supra note 58, at 2912; see also Irene Calboli & Srividhya Ragavan, Recognizing Diversity in Intellectual Property, in D IVERSITY IN I NTELLECTUAL P ROPERTY : IDENTITIES , INTERESTS , AND INTERSECTIONS , supra note 3, at 1, 1–2 (“Despite the rise of diversity to an internationally relevant topic of attention, . . . a disturbing trend of denial of resources continues to be commonplace with respect to minorities and certain marginalized groups. In particular, racial, gender, and religious-based minorities or groups of people from specific countries or regions of the world continue to have limited access to resources, opportunities, or simply knowledge and information. . . . [I]ntellectual property rights . . . can serve as an important tool to achieve some of the goals of promotion and protection of diverse interests. Forms of intellectual property rights are critical . . . to the creation and wide dissemination of knowledge and information.”); Mtima, supra note 59, at 265– 66 (“Like all other social ordering mechanisms, intellectual property protection is but one function within a complex and organic social system designed to promote the well-being of the societal body as a whole. As intellectual property has moved to the forefront of daily life, however, scholars, activists, and policy makers have called for a greater harmonization of intellectual property protection with other important social mechanisms and objectives. Toward this end, leading ‘IP social reformists’ have argued that prevailing intellectual property norms can and should be socially rehabilitated by resorting to appropriate extrinsic disciplines, such as human rights jurisprudence and critical legal theory, so as to infuse the intellectual property regime with a progressive social consciousness.”). See generally AMARTYA S EN, D EVELOPMENT AS F REEDOM (1999). Do Not Delete 494 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 Legal scholars such as Keith Aoki,78 Margaret Chon,79 Daniel Gervais,80 Madahavi Sunder,81 and others have advocated for the importation of human rights theory and discourse in the divination of intellectual property social utility to correct this social imbalance. They have cogently argued that human needs must be assessed in conjunction with contemporary human 78. See Keith Aoki, Neocolonialism, Anticommons Property, and Biopiracy in the (Not-So-Brave) New World Order of International Intellectual Property Protection, 6 IND. J. GLOBAL LEG. STUD. 11, 18–20 (1998). 79. See Chon, supra note 58, at 2885–86, 2905–06 (“In the current rule-generating and rule-interpreting environment of intellectual property globalization, the presumption has been that intellectual property is good because it promotes economic growth. But as the area of development economics shows, economic growth is not synonymous with economic development. Intellectual property can no longer afford to be insular, as if it does not affect or is not affected by the provision of other global public goods. Explicit connections must be made between intellectual property and other global public goods addressing basic development needs, including food, education as well as the already highly publicized health care sector. Intellectual property, after all, cannot ‘take root’ absent a basic national capacity, which can only be developed with a population that has its essential needs met. . . . It bears keeping in mind that much of the world’s population lacks access to essential nutrients, basic education, and basic health care. Basic needs have been underemphasized in much of the debate about what to do about intellectual property globalization. . . . Some international human rights treaties directly address intellectual property, and this increasingly is an area that may be a source of emerging equality norms. While human rights treaties and the soft law mechanisms that have been deployed to challenge intellectual property norms are ancillary to WTO and WIPO treaties, they can be viewed as additional evidence of substantive equality norms that should be incorporated into the intellectual property calculus through the language of development.”). 80. See Gervais, supra note 62, at 3, 14 (“Intellectual property and human rights must learn to live together. Traditionally, there have been . . . two dominant views of this ‘cohabitation,’ namely a conflict view, which emphasizes the negative impacts of intellectual property on rights such as freedom of expression or the right to health and security, and a compatibility model, which emphasizes that both sets of rights strive towards the same fundamental equilibrium. . . . [T]he dualist view [is] that both are right, though there is, and should be, much more truth to the second approach in the coming years. . . . [H]uman rights principles and analogies are able to provide normative boundaries to the age-old quest for intrinsic equilibrium in copyright policy: the protection of interests resulting from expressed creativity, on the one hand, and the right to enjoy and share the arts and scientific advancement.”). 81. See MADAHAVI SUNDER, FROM GOODS TO A GOOD LIFE: INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND GLOBAL JUSTICE 1 (2012) (“[I]ntellectual property laws have profound effects on human capabilities . . . . Intellectual property incentivizes pharmaceutical companies to innovate drugs that sell—hence we are flooded with cures for erectile dysfunction and baldness, but still have no cure for the diseases that afflict millions of the poor, from malaria to tuberculosis, because these people are too poor to save their lives.”); Stiglitz, supra note 61, at 1718 (“One of the problems of being poor is that you do not have any money and therefore cannot spend a lot of money on drugs, even though if you do not buy the drugs you may die. There is clearly a strong potential demand for these drugs from poor countries, but the poor do not have the income to convert this potential demand into a real demand. The drug companies, of course, realize this; some of them have been very upfront about it. They admit that the patent system does not provide incentives for developing cures or vaccines for the diseases that afflict the poor, especially the poor in developing countries.”); see also LAURENCE R. HELFER & GRAEME W. AUSTIN, HUMAN RIGHTS AND INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY 32–33 (2011). Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 495 accomplishment in the calibration of human rights. Put differently, once the means to address critical social deficiencies become manifest, the recognition of fundamental human rights requires that such advances be deployed as necessary to alleviate human suffering, degradation, and social inhibition.82 Moreover, in the digital information age, the need for a more socially balanced intellectual property system is self-evident, as intellectual property use and interaction have become unavoidable and often even essential aspects of everyday life. “For centuries, no one much thought about copyright in daily life. Now, we don’t have a choice.”83 Indeed, the mandates of intellectual property protection can affect almost every dimension of human self-actualization and fulfillment. A cornerstone of the human rights movement is access to information. Civil and political rights—like freedom of expression, free exercise of religion, meaningful participation in government—require an educated citizenry with access to information. Economic, social, and cultural rights—such as the right to an education, to health care, to economic development, to a clean environment, and more generally to participate in the social and cultural life of a nation—also depend upon access to information in a general way, for education, as well as in a more particular way for each of the domains listed; i.e., information about health, disease, medicines, and treatments; information about business methods, the economy, and know-how including intellectual property; information about the environmental consequences of various actions; and information about, and in some sense even constituting, the arts and culture. Thus the right to access information is not only an important right in and 82. See Ruth Okediji, The Limits of Development Strategies at the Intersection of Intellectual Property and Human Rights, in INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY, TRADE AND DEVELOPMENT: STRATEGIES TO OPTIMIZE ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT IN A TRIPS-PLUS ERA 355, 355–79 (Daniel J. Gervais ed., 2007); Mary W. S. Wong, Toward an Alternative Normative Framework for Copyright: From Private Property to Human Rights, 26 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 775, 830 (2009) (“Many . . . scholars share the belief that the current international IP regime does not adequately accommodate concerns of distributive social justice, and . . . does not easily allow for non-economic developmental considerations that are emphasized by human rights jurisprudence and norms, and that are socially beneficial objectives that IP regimes ought to incorporate. Alongside specific proposals for addressing these inadequacies, the[se] scholars . . . support (either explicitly or implicitly) a broader approach that incorporates social and cultural theory, and that more clearly maps to less utilitarian objectives such as self-actualization, freedom of choice, and human development.”). See generally GIBSON, supra note 57. 83. AUFDERHEIDE & JASZI, supra note 25, at 7; see also Gervais, supra note 62, at 11 (“For the first time in copyright’s 300-year-history, individual end-users, who until recently have rarely had encounters with copyright law (no one need sign a license when buying a copy of a book at a bookstore or a CD at a record store), suddenly have to learn rules about what they can or cannot do legally with pictures, music, videos, images, etc.”). Do Not Delete 496 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 of itself, but it is important for how it supports other human rights.84 As discussed in Part IV, courts adjudicating intellectual property disputes are giving greater consideration to how intellectual property mechanisms and dictates affect and interconnect with other important social objectives, including universal conventions regarding human rights. As courts become increasingly sanguine in their consideration of non-IP law and policy objectives to construe intellectual property social utility, particularly in the context of intellectual property social balancing mechanisms, they develop a body of judicial precedent from which standards for achieving intellectual property social justice can be derived. Collectively, these decisions suggest a framework for evaluating the unauthorized use of intellectual property in the cause of social justice. A. “Three Step” Framework for Assessing IP Social Justice 1. Step One: Alligate IP Social Justice Goals to Express Law or Governmental Policy. In many cases where courts balance intellectual property rights against other social utilities, the said non-IP social objectives are embodied within a specific law, convention, or treaty.85 In such cases, these countervailing considerations do not represent the social priorities of a few individuals or of a special interest group, but rather reflect the collective values of society as a whole. As such, courts have both a legal and moral obligation to respect these choices and weigh them against any intellectual property rights or interests also at issue.86 Accordingly, where an unauthorized use of intellectual property is undertaken in the cause of social justice, courts can 84. Jamar, supra note 54, at 289–90; see also Calboli & Ragavan, supra note 77, at 2 (“[I]ntellectual property norms and the current culture revolving around these norms impact questions related to equality, access, personal freedoms, privacy, wealth distribution, and allocation and exercise of social and economic power.”). See generally Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, 2000 O.J. (C 364) 1, 13. 85. See, e.g., POM Wonderful LLC v. Coca-Cola Co., 134 S. Ct. 2228, 2230 (2014) (discussing the intersection of trademark law and FDA regulations); Lasercomb Am. Inc. v. Reynolds, 911 F.2d 970, 977 (4th Cir. 1990) (discussing the intersection of the patent and antitrust laws). 86. See, e.g., Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S. Ct. 2584, 2617 (2015) (“‘The doctrine that . . . due process authorizes courts to hold laws unconstitutional when they believe the legislature has acted unwisely,’ we later explained, ‘has long since been discarded. We have returned to the original constitutional proposition that courts do not substitute their social and economic beliefs for the judgment of legislative bodies, who are elected to pass laws.’” (quoting Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U.S. 726, 730 (1963))); Missouri v. Jenkins, 515 U.S. 70, 133 (1995) (“As Alexander Hamilton explained [in the Federalist No. 78] the limited authority of the federal courts: ‘The courts must declare the sense of the law; and if they should be disposed to exercise WILL instead of JUDGMENT, the consequence would Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 497 begin the “IP social justice assessment” by determining whether allowing the use will further the social objectives of a specific law or express governmental policy.87 While any use of intellectual property to benefit social justice is commendable, not every such use is supported by or implicates specific law or governmental mandates. Consequently, where intellectual property social justice conduct is anchored by an express law or governmental policy, the court is assured that permitting the use will accommodate social priorities sanctioned by society as a whole. Moreover, it promotes the social interoperability of intellectual property protection within the total political economy.88 equally be the substitution of their pleasure to that of the legislative body.’”); see also Day-Brite Lighting, Inc. v. Missouri, 342 U.S. 421, 423 (1952) (“[W]e do not sit as a super-legislature to weigh the wisdom of legislation . . . .”). 87. As discussed above, intellectual property protection mechanisms can affect a wide range of individual rights and interests. See Gervais, supra note 62, at 4 (“[C]opyright is increasingly sparring with rights outside of its own sphere, such as the right to privacy, human rights principles of free expression and cultural diversity and cultural development, the right to information, the right to education, and the nascent right to development, each of which implies striking a balance in intellectual property protection.”). Whereas legislative bodies can articulate directly collective societal values and choices through legislation, they can also accomplish this indirectly, such as through delegation of rulemaking and other authority to government agencies, which can in turn promulgate express regulations or policies designed to achieve the legislative intent. See, e.g., Overview and Mission Statement, U.S. DEP’T OF EDUC., http://ed.gov/about/landing.jhtml?src=ft (last visited Nov. 20, 2015); Our Mission, U.S. DEP’T OF LABOR, http://dol.gov/opa/aboutdol/mission.htm (last visited Nov. 20, 2015) (setting forth the mission statements and policies of federal education and labor agencies). In appropriate cases, reference to express governmental policy in support of social justice use of intellectual property can therefore serve the same legitimizing function as reference to specific laws. See, e.g., Yates v. Hendon, 541 U.S. 1, 18 (2004) (observing that federal agency interpretation of law that the agency implements “reflects a ‘body of experience and informed judgment to which courts and litigants may properly resort for guidance’” (quoting Skidmore v. Swift & Co., 323 U.S. 134, 140 (1944))); id. at 24 (Scalia, J., concurring) (“[A]uthoritative interpretations of law by the implementing agency, if reasonable, are entitled to respect.”). See generally Susy Frankel, Interpreting International Intellectual Property Agreements and Supporting Diversity Goals, in DIVERSITY IN INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY: IDENTITIES, INTERESTS, AND INTERSECTIONS, supra note 3, at 17, 24 (“Intellectual property rules do not exist in a vacuum. Effects of the rules come about through the diverse actors in the intellectual property system. These actors include creators and owners of intellectual property . . . domestic legal regimes and administrative bodies and international institutions.”). An operative consideration in such invocation of governmental policy will be the degree of specificity in the articulation of public objectives and sanctioned methods for achieving these goals. 88. See AUFDERHEIDE & JASZI, supra note 25, at 151 (“Articulate constituencies need to be developed for limitations and exceptions—not because these serve special interests but because the public interest is at stake here.”). For a similar argument that where a use essentially falls within but does not technically satisfy a category of exception specified in the Copyright Act, that fact should have a favorably “powerful gravitational pull” on the First Fair use factor, see Jonathan Band, The Impact of Substantial Compliance with Copyright Exceptions on Fair Use, 59 J. COPYRIGHT SOC’Y U.S.A. 453 (2012). Do Not Delete 498 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 2. Step Two: Identify a Nexus Between the Relevant IP and Non-IP Social Utilities. While IP social justice advocates add ballast to their arguments by connecting them to specific laws or governmental policies, it may be that all but the most socially abstract claims will satisfy this requirement. This is because many, if not most, social justice needs or uses can be construed to implicate at least some express law or governmental policy. Moreover, the mere identification of such peremptory but countervailing social utilities provides little guidance to a court as to how these conflicting social goals should be reconciled. Consequently, additional evaluative steps are needed to ensure that intellectual property social utility is not arbitrarily subordinated to other social goals and policies. As discussed above, courts seeking to balance IP and non-IP social utilities often achieve reconciliation by identifying an overlapping or commonality of purpose between intellectual property protection and the competing law or policy. For example in HathiTrust, the court showed how copyright and the ADA are each respectively concerned with promoting widespread participation in the production and use of expressive works. By identifying such commonalities, courts mitigate and sometimes even dissolve an apparent conflict between the pertinent social objectives: they demonstrate how deferring to the subject non-IP social dictates and allowing the unauthorized use will in some way further or benefit the overarching goals of intellectual property protection. Accordingly, as the second step in evaluating an IP social justice use, courts should determine whether there is some nexus between the referenced non-IP social objectives and the social objectives that underlie intellectual property protection. Illustrative examples of such a nexus might include improving opportunities to contribute to intellectual property production, the intersection between intellectual property rights and freedom of expression, or balancing tensions between the preservation of intellectual property interests and protecting anonymous speech. By identifying such a nexus, courts give proper deference to the goals of intellectual property protection, and also ensure that the prerequisite reference to an express law or governmental policy is more than a chimeric assessment threshold. 3. Step Three: Determine Whether Allowing the IP Social Justice Use Would be Wholly Antagonistic to IP Social Utility. Finally, courts assessing unauthorized IP social justice use should consider whether allowing the use would directly contravene or be Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 499 antagonistic to core intellectual property protection imperatives. For example, an unauthorized use of a copyrighted work that satisfies the first two steps but involves the wholesale reproduction and wide dissemination of a newly published work would likely fail this requirement. This final evaluative step can not only provide additional succor to rights holder economic expectations, it can also serve to broaden the assessment of resulting harms and benefits to the rights holder. Creators want to make a living from their work, but they also want their work to be read, listened to, or performed. Following this logic, creative artists want to be recognized in the first place. If a literary critic discusses a novel, the author will not be bothered to know whether the critic bought the book in a shop or picked it up in a public library. Especially with respect to real fans who do not have the means to buy an expensive copy, artistic creators somehow lose their artistic soul when they blame illegal downloading.89 In applying this step, courts should thus consider the effect upon all of the rights holder’s incentives and benefits—non-economic as well as economic—in determining whether an unauthorized use should be deemed wholly antagonistic to intellectual property protection. Where an unauthorized use satisfies the foregoing first two steps and causes only minimal or trivial commercial harm while providing substantial non-economic benefits to the rights holder, the court should permit the use to proceed.90 B. Applying the Social Justice Assessment Framework: Copyright Social Balancing The IP social justice assessment framework should serve to supplement and even refine various existing IP social balancing mechanisms. For example, the framework complements each of 89. Geert Demuijnck, Illegal Downloading, Free Riding and Justice, in NEW FRONTIERS IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY, supra note 54, at 261, 277. 90. See generally GIBSON, supra note 57 (discussing esteem and attribution as creator incentives and objectives); Margaret Jane Radin, Property and Personhood, 34 STAN. L. REV. 957 (1982); Stiglitz, supra note 61, at 1695–96 (“Like most academics, I have ambivalent feelings about intellectual property . . . . At [a conference in Taiwan], I knew that intellectual property rights were not always strictly enforced there. During a break in the conference, I had a little time to go to a bookstore. As I went to the store, I had a debate in my mind about what I hoped to see when I arrived. On the one hand, there was the possibility that they had stolen my intellectual property, that they had pirated one or more of my books. . . . The other possibility was that they had not pirated one of my books and stolen my intellectual property, that they had ignored me. . . . I came to the conclusion that being ignored is far worse than having one’s property stolen, and I resolved that I would actually be much happier if they had stolen my intellectual property than if they had ignored me. When I got to the bookstore, they had in fact stolen it, and I was relieved.”). Do Not Delete 500 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 the leading copyright social balancing mechanisms. With respect to the fair use doctrine, the first two assessment steps would identify a legal or governmental basis for social justice-oriented conduct and a nexus to copyright social policy, which assessments in effect provide standards for determining whether the specific social justice purpose satisfies the first fair use factor. The third assessment step actually broadens and refines the analysis that is the subject of the fourth fair use factor.91 The IP social justice framework is also compatible with fair dealing. The framework can be of use in construing the breadth of a specific fair dealing exception, i.e., would a proper construction of a copyright exception require the exclusion of activities encouraged by law and that also have a nexus to copyright? Alternatively, where a social justice use falls within a recognized exception, the framework could be used to assess whether permitting the use would be fair under the particular circumstances. Finally, the IP social justice framework could also be used to supplement copyright limitation and exception systems. As with fair dealing, the framework could be used to construe the purpose or parameters of a specific limitation or exception. Perhaps most important, courts following the framework would build a body of precedent for interpreting and applying limitations and exceptions to social justice needs. Such precedent would not only aid subsequent courts in addressing questions of IP social justice, but the analyses in these opinions could ultimately provide the basis for the adoption of an express “social justice exception” or limitation in the national copyright law.92 91. I am indebted to Professor Margaret Chon for the observation that the social justice assessment steps could also be considered additional or alternative fair use factors under section 107 of the Copyright Act. See, e.g., Richard Dannay, Factorless Fair Use? Was Melville Nimmer Right?, 60 J. COPYRIGHT SOC’Y USA 127, 133 (2013) (“As the Supreme Court described . . . the fair use doctrine not only permits—it requires—courts to avoid rigid application of the statute when, on occasion, it would stifle the very creativity the law is designed to foster. . . . This scheme is embedded in the statute itself, with its several preamble purposes and four factors that are non-exclusive, illustrative, and that begin the analysis the analysis but do not necessarily exhaust it.”). 92. See, e.g., Wessels, supra note 74 (“In emerging economies, there are serious access to knowledge and culture deficiencies. . . . [R]elative to local incomes in Brazil, Russia, or South Africa, the price of a CD, DVD, or copy of Microsoft Office is five to ten times higher than in the United States or Europe. There is no distribution of legal CDs and DVDs outside the capitals. Up to 90 percent of the people in emerging economies can only turn to illegal media copies. Such problems also exist in eastern European emerging economies. . . . ’Torrent sites such as Zamunda and Arena are the most popular websites in Bulgaria. The reason for that is not just the enormous amount of music, films, software, and books that they make available to anybody for free. . . . These torrent sites are technically in violation of all sorts of copyright laws but what they offer has no alternative Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 501 C. IP Social Justice Assessment and TRIPS In the latter decades of the twentieth century, various commercial IP industries and interests urged that the question of international comity for intellectual property rights should be resolved as a matter of international trade law.93 These efforts reached their apogee with the adoption of the TRIPS Agreement.94 Today, more than 150 nations are signatories to TRIPS,95 and while there remain legal scholars and commentators who question the compatibility of international trade policy with intellectual for the people in Bulgaria for the time being given the country’s social and economic development.’ . . . In Bulgaria, digital technology helps to solve deficiencies in access to knowledge and culture, but EU law harms this access. In Bulgaria, and other countries in similar circumstances, EU law nullifies or impairs the rights to access to knowledge and culture for many, this is neither compatible with the second condition of article 4 ICESCR, ‘compatible with the nature of these rights’, nor with the third, ‘promote the general welfare in a democratic society’. The EU needs an underserved market exception.” (internal citation omitted)); see also KEI Intervention on Education Exceptions in SCCR 30, KNOWLEDGE ECOLOGY INT’L (July 3, 2015), http://keionline.org/node/2270 (advocating for an exception to permit access to educational materials in developing nations). Indeed, courts in some copyright limitation and exception systems have already interpreted the law to recognize a general principle to curtail copyright when necessary to the public interest. See, e.g., Hyde Park Residence Ltd. v. David Yelland, [1999] EWHC (Pat) 247 [39], (Eng.) (“[T]here is a public interest defence [to copyright] available in principle. That is not to say it is of wide scope, even though it cannot be more precisely defined than ‘just cause or excuse’. It is unlikely that the defence will succeed unless the court can be reasonably certain that no right-thinking member of society would quarrel with the result. It is difficult to imagine the defence arising except in the context of the communication of what is essentially information—information clothed in copyright. Before it can arise it must be shown that there is a genuine public interest in that information being disclosed.”). 93. See, e.g., Long, supra note 3, at 59 (“The major actors in earlier stages of multilateralism could be divided roughly into three groups: the creators of intellectual property, the distributors of intellectual-property-based goods and services, and the governments that largely represented the interests of the members of the first two groups.”). 94. See Gervais, supra note 62, at 6–7 (“The progressive alignment of trade and intellectual property policy started in the United States in the 1980s through successive amendments to section 301 of the Trade Act, which allowed the U.S. Administration to impose trade-based sanctions on countries which, in the view of the United States Trade Representative, did not adequately protect intellectual property rights of United States citizens and companies. . . . There ensued a well-documented push by the United States government, supported by the European Commission and the Japanese government, to link intellectual property and trade rules in the World Trade Organization (WTO) as part of the Uruguay Round of Multilateral Trade Negotiations, which ended in Marrakesh in April 1994 with the signing of the Agreement Establishing the WTO, Annex 1C of which is the TRIPS Agreement. While critics opined that intellectual property was not proper subject matter for the WTO, enter the house of trade it did, wholesale.”). See generally DANIEL GERVAIS, THE TRIPS AGREEMENT: DRAFTING HISTORY AND ANALYSIS (4th ed. 2012) (examining the history and analyzing specific sections of TRIPS). 95. See IP-related Multilateral Treaties, WORLD INTELL. PROP. ORG., http://wipo.int/wipolex/en/other_treaties/parties.jsp?treaty_id=231&group_id=22 (last visited Nov. 20, 2015) (listing signatory countries of TRIPS). Do Not Delete 502 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 property social utility,96 for better or worse, TRIPS is now the “IP Magna Carta” for the international community.97 Accordingly, while it is essential that any mechanism intended to promote IP social justice prove compatible with national intellectual property social balancing mechanisms, it is equally important that any such mechanism also be consistent with the pertinent dictates of TRIPS. In accordance with TRIPS, its signatories are free to adopt limitations and exceptions to intellectual property rights, provided that such limitations and exceptions satisfy the TRIPS Three Steps test. The Three Steps test requires that limitations or exceptions (i) apply only in special cases, (ii) do not unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of the rights holder, and (iii) do not conflict with the normal commercial exploitation of the intellectual property work.98 On its face, the proposed IP social justice assessment framework is at least consistent with the TRIPS Three Steps test. At the initial stage, the framework is directed towards identifying a particular category of “special cases”—cases that involve the mandatory balancing of intellectual property rights against express, albeit differing and even conflicting, public directives. 96. See, e.g., Chon, supra note 59, at 361 (“Although global intellectual property has always been an exotic flavor of international economic law, the brute fact is that the WTO is a trade treaty rather than a specialized treaty dealing with ‘industrial property’ or ‘literary and artistic works’. Thus we now have the unfamiliar phenomenon of trade economists weighing in on the intellectual property relatedness of TRIPS and finding it lacking by economic welfare measures.”); Ho, supra note 56, at 469 (“The TRIPS agreement can be seen as the ultimate act of imperialism to the extent that it forces countries opposed to patents to nonetheless tolerate and grant patents within their own countries. Not only do many indigenous communities oppose patent rights, but also the scope of patentable subject matter under TRIPS. In particular, many communities object to patent rights over any type of life forms, regardless of the amount of human intervention involved. This objection reflects their philosophy that life is sacred. However, their philosophies are inherently irreconcilable with the mandatory language under TRIPS that plant and animal varieties must be granted protection.”); Robert J. Gutowski, The Marriage of Intellectual Property and International Trade in the TRIPS Agreement: Strange Bedfellows or a Match Made in Heaven?, 47 BUFF. L. REV. 713, 744–45, 747–51 (1999) (“While Western, industrialized countries employ the value-laden language of ‘piracy’ and ‘counterfeiting’ to describe lax protection of IP in the developing world, lesser developed and newly industrialized countries find a moral foundation for weak IP protection. . . . From the developing countries’ point of view, weak protection of IP can serve to protect life itself by ensuring a supply of essential goods, particularly in the fields of education and medicine, for both sustenance and development. A survey of the literature about what is variably termed the ‘North–South debate’ reveals two distinct lexicons—one of politics and economics and another of sociology and cultural anthropology, with developed nations employing the former and developing countries the latter.”). 97. See, e.g., Frankel, supra note 87, at 21–24; Gutowski, supra note 96, at 714, 753– 57. 98. See TRIPS, supra note 8, art. 13. Do Not Delete 2015] 11/20/2015 3:40 PM COPYRIGHT AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 503 Next, by confirming the presence of a social utility nexus between intellectual property protection and the referenced non-IP law or policy, the framework arguably precludes unauthorized use that would unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of rights holders. Under the framework, rights holders’ interests are curtailed only to the extent necessary to reconcile competing public mandates regarding common or overlapping subject matter. Thus, the framework would allow only reasonable restrictions on legitimate intellectual property interests, or put differently, preclude only the illegitimate prioritization or expansion of IP interests over other domains. Finally, the impact of an unauthorized social justice use upon the normal commercial exploitation of intellectual property would be a consideration in determining whether the use is antagonistic to intellectual property social utility. The fact that a court could also consider any benefits to the rights holder merely results in a more comprehensive commercial impact analysis.99 As with national intellectual property limitation and exception mechanisms, courts utilizing the IP social justice framework could build a body of precedent for applying the Three Steps test in cases that involve social justice needs and interests. As Professor Daniel Gervais observes: Indeed, at the level of national laws, the three-step test could be refined by enumerating certain specific cases, or by providing additional guidance on the interpretation of the three steps. It remains a flexible test which could, however, be used by courts in cases where no such specific exception exists, if allowed to do so under domestic law.100 The framework could thus aid courts in demonstrating how social justice applications of IP social balancing mechanisms are consonant with TRIPS, which would further support the adoption of discreet IP social justice limitations and exceptions in to national intellectual property regimes.101 99. See, e.g., Gervais, supra note 8, at 14–19. For a comparison with an in-depth analysis of the explicit and implicit obligations arising under each of the TRIPS Three Steps, see Gervais, supra note 62, at 8–10. 100. Gervais, supra note 62, at 11; see also Frankel, supra note 87, at 19 (discussing the impacts of dispute resolution on treaty interpretation, and noting how such “impacts are not necessarily only confined to the disputes, but also affect those who rely on the outcome of disputes to guide their national law making”). 101. See Gervais, supra note 62, at 30 (“It would thus be theoretically possible to consider a provision allowing courts not to enforce copyright when a countervailing public interest justification supports this application.”); see also AUFDERHEIDE & JASZI, supra note 25, at 149–50 (“[T]here is increasing interest in expanding the utility of limitations and exceptions . . . . Copyright policy internationally, just as in the United States, is grounded Do Not Delete 504 11/20/2015 3:40 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [53:2 V. CONCLUSION Along with the well-recognized and widely accepted benefits to copyright social utility, digital information technology has also opened new vistas through which to perceive and promote copyright and other intellectual property social justice. The proposal herein is one means by which courts can embrace these opportunities and balance social justice interests against digital copyright and other intellectual property rights. The proposed IP social justice assessment framework is not intended to supplant other intellectual property social balancing mechanisms, but rather to supplement and adapt such mechanisms as necessary to meet the challenges of the Information Age. In achieving a socially just equipoise, copyright and other forms of intellectual property protection mature into global systems of development and exchange in which all can participate and share mutual respect. in the public interest . . . . Monopolies given to creators are necessarily tempered with other measures—limitations and exceptions—that limit that monopoly. . . . Wherever copyright reform is under discussion, expanding exemptions . . . is one of the important issues debated.”). Indeed, at least one important study suggests that greater flexibility in copyright limitations and exceptions propitiously impacts copyright economic rates of growth and overall outputs, including decentralized/user-generated creative activity, and also spurs growth in the information technology, education, and other major socio-economic sectors. See GIBERT, supra note 9, at 3–4, 6.