Subj: cea paper to acrobatize Date: 5/14/2003 1:56:43 PM Eastern Standard Time From: Tom Velk To: Tom Velk Dear Curtis and other Colleagues: Following as part of this email is a more or less complete draft of the text of the paper to be presented in May/June 03 at the Ottawa meetings of the Canadian Economics Association (CEA). I may make additions, but you may post this on the website since any later changes will be minor. tom velk, 802 988 9669, tomvelk@aol.com, mcgill University econ. dept. 514 398 4832 Hume Across the Ocean: His influence upon Hamilton's Economic Policies Tom Velk, A. R. Riggs and Dov Zigler Hume is an American in his principles in the Sam Rayburn/ Lyndon Johnson tradition. Hume never ran for dogcatcher, and so he would not have met the Rayburn test for membership in the President’s Cabinet, but his practical ideas appealed to the most hard-headed of America’s founding fathers. No mere dogcatcher, but a former artillery colonel promoted to Cabinet rank, had been guided by Hume’s ideas since boyhood. That American strategist was Alexander Hamilton. Once in office, he used Hume’s blueprint to construct the core economic institutions of the new nation. In his essay 'Of Commerce,' Hume dichotomizes between 'manufacturing societies' and 'farming societies'. Manufacturing societies use their surplus agricultural produce to support artisans while farming societies use surplus agricultural produce to maintain armies. According to Hume, farming societies in antiquity were well-off and politically powerful while those devoted to manufacturing and occupied with the consumption of luxuries were weak (e.g., Sparta vs. Athens). He says the opulent societies of antiquity were 'soft' and therefore less competent in the art of war, even if they were technologically advanced. However, Hume argues that 'things have changed.' In Hume's time, manufactures allow for improved cultivation and therefore ever increasing agricultural surplus. Greater agricultural surplus in turn supports more manufacturers, leading to a virtuous circle of economic, political, civic and even military development. Eventually, the surplus becomes so great that 'manufacturing societies' are able to raise armies of such scale and strength as to overshadow agriculturally minded competitors. ("Minded" is the right word, as the economic foundations of a community profoundly effect community habits of mind in respect of consumption, production and governance -- a relationship critical to Hamilton's application of Hume's implied strategy of systemwide social development). Perhaps more significant for our purposes, Hume believes that a community whose economic core is constituted by manufacturers has a potential "superfluity of labor" which "in times of peace goes to the maintenance of manufacturers and the improves of liberal arts. But it is easy for the public to convert many of these manufacturers into soldiers and maintain them by that superfluity which arises from the labour of the farmers." This process yields the maxim: "Manufacturers encrease the power of the state only as they store up so much labour and that of a kind to which the public may lay claim without depriving any one of the necessaries of life. The more labour therefore, is employed beyond the mere necessaries, the more powerful is any state... Thus the greatness of the soevereign and the happiness of the state are, in a great measure, united with regard to trade and manufactures." We say Hume is not so much falling into the labor theory error as he is elaborating a theory of the community mindset needed for civic progress and development. It is this vision of the interaction between an economic background and its role in evolving a modern state, able to compete with the Motherlands beyond the Sea, that, we argue, motivates Hamilton's schemes for economic development, as found in his state messages on the Bank, assumption of the debt, the Mint, Trade and Manufactures. Even more important to Hamilton, we believe, is the capacity for national defence which mobile human capital provides. Like Hume, Hamilton believes the first obligation of government is survival. Hamilton frequently writes of the economic and political jealousy of America’s European competitors. He was intensely aware of the short run danger presented by restive revolutionary soldiers, whose unpaid war wages gave them a motive to remain in arms, threatening the stability of the new nation, still in its vulnerable infancy. In the long run, the United States would need her army to resist European adventures and to maintain peace at home -- Hume’s human capital based theory of development showed Hamilton how to obtain and then pay for internal and external defenses. Hume believes that the most significant capital is what we now call 'human capital.' Economic strength is measured in population quantity and quality. The more readily a state can shift labour from private use to public use, the greater the power of the state. "Trade and industry are really nothing but a stock of labour, which, in times of peace and tranquillity, is employed for the ease and satisfaction of individuals; but in the exigencies of state, may, in part, be turned to public advantage." Once again, Hume is not really a labor theory advocate, as he is proposing a state strategy of encouraging a more economically mobile form of human Capital -- the same grand purpose as Hamilton's. And so Hume's developmental theory of 'the (dynamic) natural value of labor' is distinguishable from Smith's more static assertions concerning 'labor value.' Particularly important to us is our belief that it is this vision of the need to encourage by policy a more mobile endowment of human capital which is the political motivation behind Hamilton's 'Report on Manufactures' for Congress, as well as his plans for the Bank, assumption of the debt, immigration, and the tariff. A critically important payoff for us is that our reading of Hume, which we think is also Hamilton's, allows us to square the radicalism of Hamilton's economic policies with the general 'conservatism' of Hume. Hamilton is certainly a radical if by that label we refer to the extraordinary degree of change he was advocating for his new nation. His actual United States was a skim of formerly distinct colonies, the wide Atlantic in front of them and a "desolate wilderness, full of wild beasts and wild men" behind them. It was a land of farmers, dependent upon the old world for manufactures and governance, obsessed with a dream of independence, but in fact burdened with an illiquid national debt, and lacking a domestic growth in the supply of labor adequate to its potential for industrial growth, or its needs for defense. To the extent there existed a de facto static plan for the future, it was Jefferson's -- who wished for a thousand generations more of such yeoman farmers, gradually expanding west, living simple rural lives, on small freeholds and in quiet villages, somehow protected from their envious, expansionist former colonial masters. Hamilton, we think, saw in Hume's arguments the strategic long run danger of this "conservative" dream of stasis, and he did his best to set the United States upon a much different strategic course of political and social action. Hume's teaching, that national greatness and public happiness are derivatives of "trade and commerce" is, we think reason enough for Hamilton to espouse his far-reaching radical transformation of US society and economy. What's more, Hume paints the ancient agricultural model as an unrepeatable historical incident not at all in touch with the circumstances of modernity and the movement of human history. A Jeffersonian agricultural state would not be conservative but instead would be a radical departure from the currents of human history, especially the British history of which the US is a part. In Hume's own words: "It is a violent method, and in most cases impracticable, to oblige the labourer to toil, in order to raise from the land more than what subsists himself and family. Furnish him with manufactures and commodities, and he will do it himself..." The "big economic idea" of the Jeffersonians was that property served the public interest best when it was equally distributed, and such a distribution was to be aggressively preserved, sought after or imposed some way. This utopian egalitarianism was said to be legitimized by natural rights, often found in an imagined original contract. Another part of Jefferson's big idea is stability: the yeomen simply reconstituted themselves, generation after generation. Hume's big idea, in contrast, was dynamic and inegalitarian. Property, and goods not so abundant as to be free in nature, were to be distributed by rules, perhaps those found in specific contracts, actually agreed to by parties to a particular action. Another species of contract, equally to be respected, consists in the habits, traditions and practices of the past, which allow us to form strong expectations about the rules by which we interact among ourselves, individually and corporately. If the rule-driven process of this kind of contractual exchange is orderly, predictable, uniform across persons, independent of superstition and resistant to fraud, it will exhibit Humean Justice. The final result may easily be an unequal distribution of wealth. Nonetheless, the riches and "instability" so engendered make for a better world. For Hume, the just rights of property were an (necessary) invention of mankind, artificial in that God took no hand in their design, nor was there to be found in real history any original contract to the contrary. Hamilton was a man in full agreement with Hume. Hamilton was in some respects a radical: he wished to create an America far different from the one in which he lived. He wanted big cities, active government, sophisticated financial markets, international trade and industry. We admit that because such dreams were in stark contrast with 18th century reality, they might be said to be distinctly non-Humean. But the goal that Hamilton was seeking by means of his dramatic proposals was profoundly Humean. It is, we think, Hume's promise of the benefits of material prosperity, and Hume's defeat of the argument that riches are best distributed when they are equally distributed that allowed Hamilton to advocate an urbanized, industrialized new order, inevitably containing a few persons of great wealth, those highly specialized persons being supported by their earnings in trade, finance and manufacturing. Hamilton needed to defend his vision against those who deplored the supposed immorality of great wealth, of earnings from "mere" trade, who questioned the morality of usury and finance, and who imagined there was special virtue in the simple economy of the farm and village. Hume offers a powerful counter-argument to the Jeffersonian claim that the rough egalitarianism of the yeomanry was the best guarantor of good government. Despite the resistance of Jefferson, both in to the particulars of the schemes and to the greater vision behind them, Secretary of the Treasury Alexander Hamilton, operating as a kind of Prime Minister, or at least as First Lord of the Treasury, put Hume's ideas into systematic practice. George Washington allowed him a free hand, in recognition of the great need for an end to the new nation’s economic tribulations. The people, whose Confederation Government had ended in financial disarray, seemed willing tolerate dramatic change. The Humean course set by Hamilton determined the future of the republic. By the time Thomas Jefferson became president the general plan was too entrenched to be changed. A paper that aspires to discuss the transfer of ideas—in this instance from David Hume to Alexander Hamilton—should properly contain a word of caution. Ideas can quickly become part of a stock of received wisdom, an unwritten consensus from which people, even on opposite sides of an issue—or an ocean—may draw at will. Furthermore, until very recently policy-makers and people in general who would not consider themselves plagiarists were reluctant oftentimes to give credit where credit was due. These and other factors make it extremely difficult to trace the progress of ideas. The recent case of John Locke, the seventeenth century Englishman once universally recognized as the spiritual father of the American Revolution, will illustrate our point. Today some reputable scholars claim that the history of the Revolution, including its ideological origins, could be written without a single reference to Locke, a state of nature or natural rights.1 John Locke’s name appears only once in the voluminous writings of Alexander Hamilton.2 Neither do Locke’s ideas figure prominently in Hamilton’s correspondence. On the other hand, he seldom mentioned David Hume by name either, but when he did his admiration for the Scottish philosopher seemed boundless. Hamilton’s debt to Hume begins early. Aged sixteen (others say he was, in fact, as old as eighteen), in what was his first published political debate, writing “The Farmer Refuted”, a response to Samuel Seabury, who had challenged the arguments found in Hamilton’s maiden publication, Hamilton quotes Hume as an enunciator of “political maxims, which will be eternally true”. Hamilton requested Hume’s works from his friend Timothy Pickering in April 1781, and he was particularly intrigued with Hume’s essays on economics. In 1775 Hamilton quoted the “celebrated author,” in 1782 he referred to the philosopher as “a very ingenious and sensible writer,” he relies upon Hume’s arguments in writing “The Continentalist No. V”, and at the Constitutional Convention of 1787 he praised Hume as “one of the ablest politicians.” Later, as Secretary of the Treasury, Hamilton would pattern much of his fiscal and monetary policy around the reasonings and observations of “the profound and ingenious Hume.”3 Hamilton’s intellectual debt to Hume went unrecognized for many years, and even as late as 1970 Broadus Mitchell’s fine single-volume biography did not mention the philosopher. In 1964, however, the late Clinton Rossitor, referring to The Federalist Papers, remarked that Hamilton’s debt to Hume “may have been larger than he realized even in his more humble moments.”4 Rossitor called Hamilton “the American Hume,” and Forrest McDonald, writing in 1979, agreed that “Hamilton repeatedly expressed Hume’s thoughts as his own.”5 Gerald Strourzh finds a significant debt to Hume in his “Alexander Hamilton and the Idea of Republican Government” (Stanford 1970.) Mark G. Spencer’s two volume edit (Thoemmes Press, 2002, Bristol, UK, isbn1 85506 934 2), entitled “Hume’s Reception in Early America” serves to remind us of the wide spread presence of Hume’s work in library collections, newspaper debates and even classrooms of early America, but David Hume’s genius was not universally applauded in the new nation, however. Hamilton’s celebrated rival in the first cabinet under George Washington, Secretary of State Thomas Jefferson (unappreciative of Hume’s support for America) called him “the great apostle of Toryism,”6 a “degenerate son of science,”7 a “traitor to his fellow man,”8 and one “who undermined the free principles of the English government.”9 This was because Hume’s History of England, a new venture in its field, did not properly condemn the Stuart monarchs of the seventeenth century. Furthermore, for American patriotic tastes Hume had laid out in his essays on economics a critique of English whig politicians that was unacceptable. In addition, his critical observations on mercantilism, the orthodox economics of the day, did not condemn with enough fervor the intervention of government in the marketplace. Hume had also rej ected the idea of disinterested virtue as a motivating force in those who presumed to govern, a first article of faith among British and American whigs. Passions induce people to action, affirmed Hume, and a wise government would avail itself of those primary motivators so that they would be forced to serve the public good.10 For people such as Jefferson this utilitarian idea, whether advanced by a Hume or a Hamilton, was tantamount to an endorsement of corruption in government.11 But the core of Hume’s economics, the set of ideas that appealed most to Hamilton, appeared in nine essays published in London in 1752 and entitled Political Discourses.12 In “Of Commerce” Hume rejected the idea that a nation can achieve greatness as an agricultural entity alone. In “Of Refinement in the Arts” he took issue with certain religious zealots who denoted luxury as evil. In “Of Money” he criticized those who thought that an injection of money into the economy would work long-term wonders, and in “Of Interest” he argued with those who claimed that abundance of money leads to low interest rates. “Of the Balance of Trade” and “Of the Jealousy of Trade,” two of his most important treatises, were directed against the protectionist policies of the reigning mercantilists. “Of Taxes” pleaded for moderation and rejected the French physiocratic single tax on land, and “Of Public Credit,” warning that the public is no blessing, deplored the expedients of Lord Oxford’s partisans to draw bills on posterity and imprudently use public credit to create paper riches. Finally, Hume addressed his essay “Of the Populousness of Ancient Nations” to exposing the doomsday thinking of the Reverend Robert Wallace of Edinburgh. In the following summary of Hume's economic aphorisms we think we find an outline of Hamilton’s beliefs as well. 1) a nation's strength lies in its productivity, which in turn is stimulated by variety and innovation; 2) trade, likely to be found in an active community of manufacturers, benefits everyone, state and pe ople, rich and poor; 3) luxury, economic growth and refinement in the arts are compatible, and complementary, even though they may be associated with an unequal distribution of wealth; 4) the flow of money from nation to nation is the instrument of economic evolution and progress, while economic isolation is a recipe for stagnation; 5) the rate of interest, and the associated state of the market for government debt is an indicator which, read by the experienced eye, tells of the health and growth in the economy; 6) free trade is to be desired, although national efforts to stimulate domestic industry are sometimes appropriate; 7) a country cannot become rich by beggaring its neighbor; 8) a government should not tax the rewards of effort lest it destroy the incentive to growth; 9) the public debt in the hands of judicious magistrates can have beneficial effects, but can also be dangerous; and 9) since no utopia existed in any past golden age it is unlikely that radical innovations in government, especially those produced by speculative projectors, are ever likely to produce the gains promised. In the economic essays, as in his other works, Hume’s prescriptions were always reformist, but moderate, balanced, carefully argued and conservative. He believed in freer trade, but he rejected the idea that unhampered pursuit of private gain would benefit society, and he never discounted the role of a strong government’s visible, directing hand on the economy. He believed in interdependence of nations and that international neighbors could grow rich together, with no need to exploit one another’s weaknesses. The engine that drives a society, he said, must be the production of goods and services, and no country could be happy, progressive or great without industrial development and the advancement of commerce.13 It will take no great leap of understanding to discern the immediate appeal of these Humean ideas to Alexander Hamilton, who became Secretary of the Treasury in September 1789. Disgusted with the weak Confederation government of the 1780’s, Hamilton was determined to follow whatever policy would promote solvency and national strength for the United States. Seizing upon a loose construction of the Constitution to accommodate his claim that “the goodness of a government consists in a vigorous execution,”14 he set out to make the government of the United States at least an equal partner with private enterprise in determining the nation’s future. His economic policy reports to Congress in the 1790’s show that he was indeed a disciple of Hume, but he lacked the pragmatism and the toleration of contrary ideas that distinguished the best efforts of his mentor. Hamilton submitted four major reports to Congress on the American economy between January 1790 and December 1791. They included the “Report Relative to a Provision for the Support of Public Credit,” January 9, 1790; the “Second Report on the Further Provision Necessary for Establishing Public Credit,” December 13, 1790; the “Report on the Establishment of a Mint,” January 28, 1791; and the “Report on the Subject of Manufactures,” December 5, 1791.15 Three of these are important to an analysis of Hamilton’s policy, the Report on the Mint being a technical treatise that will not be discussed in our paper. Hume says at least four important, insightful and original things about money, inflation and finance. He talks about the dynamic, actual and historical process played out as new money enters the economy. He also discusses, in the manner of a thought experiment, the logical, nonhistoric contrast between two imagined states of the world, one with a small amount of money and one with more. He also examines, partly in history, and partly by means of logic, the consequences of having in simultaneous circulation two qualitatively different kinds of money, gold and paper. Finally, Hume’s discussion of the specie flow mechanism, virtually unchanged from the way he first expressed it, is not only invariably credited to him, but is also a standard component of modern international trade theory, as well as being the core proposition of the so-called monetary approach to the balance of payments. All four views of money are part of Hamilton’s thinking as he proposes to create, for the new nation, a currency made uniform by the influence of a national bank. The bank would be possessed of the capital and influence required to organize and subsidize secondary markets in reserve assets, standardize bank practices, and moderate the temptation to inflate the currency, otherwise constantly on offer to elected officials. In other words, the Bank Hamilton builds in accordance with Hume’s blueprint is not only a governor on the ambitions and practices of the banking sector, such as it was in those times, but it would be a limiter upon promiscuous politicians as well. That it well-served in that latter capacity is evident in the fury with which it was later attacked by the Jacksonians. That Hume’s four big ideas about money and finance are not in conflict, but are mutually suppo rtive, is demonstrated by the way Hamilton combined them in his economic plan for the new nation. The first report on Public Credit may be studied as a counterpart to Hume’s earlier essay, “Of Public Credit.” The philosopher had listed the advantages and disadvantages of public borrowing, and the Secretary followed the pace and demeanor of the Hume essay. Hamilton read his mandate from Congress as a command to lay down rules for the provision of an optimal quantity of funded credit, a kind of treasury bill that could circulate as money. He argued that trade is extended by public credit, and agriculture and manufacturing stimulated by it. As foreign trade expands a reduction in interest rates results, the rate driven down by an increase in the quantity of money and the quickness of circulation.16 Hume had made the same points, in the same order, but qualified them extensively.17 Hamilton qualified very little. In the meanwhile, acting upon the report, Hamilton deflated the American bond market while restoring face value and even specie parity to securities that were almost worthless in purchasing power. Issuers of the securities—various government and quasi-government agencies, including army quartermaster units, state governments and the Continental Congress from the old Confederation government—had offered no financial security to the debts’ owners. The Secretary claimed that unilateral changes in the interest payment schedule would cut annual interest costs (or more accurately, annual interest obligations, since the nominal rates were not being paid fully) almost in half. Vigorous growth would follow.18 But Hamilton pointed out that he certainly did not believe that a public debt is a public blessing,19 despite the centralizing effect that assumption would have upon the states. On this point he showed some of the caution expressed by Hume. Hamilton proposed that to thwart the government’s temptation to spend, it should be forced to set aside a linked obligation to tax—to tie each spending item, and each existing evidence of past debt, to some particular revenue source.20 According to the Secretary a stable government securities market, a liquid money market and a responsible tax system would combine to stimulate domestic and foreign trade. Each merchant, keeping his capital in money and the securities market, instead of invested in landed estate, would promote commerce and manufacturing. The rate of interest would fall, partly as a result of increased public credit and in part as a result of increased riches, further stimulating economic activity.21 Again Hamilton’s argument was virtually identical to Hume’s, except Hamilton placed more emphasis upon additional money in reducing interest rates. Hamilton’s contention that a well-funded and contractually secure public debt would reduce the interest rate is compatible with Hume’s ideas, in his essay “Of Interest,” about the lowness of the interest rate following from “an increase of industry and commerce, not of gold and silver.”22 Hamilton buttressed his point by saying that an unfunded debt, by hurting confidence, would necessarily raise the interest rate.23 In the same vein he argued for rigorous adherence to the bond market’s rules of ownership and transfer, so that property rights, in the form of absolutely secure promises in the money market, be strictly observed. Thus the practical utility of enhanced economic growth would be realized.24 A utilitarian view of property rights, clearly discernible in Hamiltonian economics, may also be found in Hume. Hume’s contentions in “Of Money” seem also to have inspired Hamilton when he sat down to write his “Second Report on Public Credit,” sometimes referred to as the “Report on a National Bank.” Echoing Hume, the Secretary of the Treasury affirmed that the real wealth of a nation lies in men, manufactures, mines and farms. As long as these are at work the quantity of money would have a high potential level, a level that likely would eventually be supplied by the natural process of international trade.25 Hume had written in “Of Money,” “We may conclude, that it is of no manner of consequence, with regard to the domestic happiness of a state, whether money be in greater or less quantity.”26 Hamilton said the same thing and then gave an excellent summary of Hume’s best-known contribution to economics, that of the specie flow mechanism. It is the process whereby specie—the international stock of gold and silver—flows toward whatever country has the most active level of trade. The money remains in motion, however, to accommodate trading deals everywhere. This process redistributes money all over the world, making the global trading nations one vast market with one price level and a common money stock. Hamilton noted, A nation, that has no mines of its own, must derive the precious metals from others; generally speaking, in exchange for the product of its labor and industry. The quantity, it will possess, will therefore, in the ordinary course of things be regulated by the favourable, or unfavourable balance of its trade, that is, the proportion between its abilities to supply foreigners; and its want of them; between the amount of its exportations and that of its importations. Hence the state of its agriculture and manufactures, the quantity and quality of its labour and industry, must in the main, influence and determine the increase or decrease of its gold and silver.27 In the Second Report Hamilton linked the public banking system more closely to the state of agriculture and manufacturing than Hume had done.28 Hamilton’s proposed Bank of the United States would serve the state by concentrating capital, providing a secure source of funds in emergencies and a safe depository for federal funds, giving financial and technical aid to collection of taxes and payment of interest on the public debt. It would also provide a uniform circulating medium, help the treasury conduct foreign trade, aid in settling foreign debts, control private banks and multiply the financial capacity of the nation’s stock of gold and silver.29 Hume had complex feelings about public banks, because of a disastrous French experiment with one. In 1752 Hume felt no need to defend a public bank, since the bank of England, the model for Hamilton’s proposal, was long-established. In 1790, in the United States, however, many believed that the Constitution did not authorize Congress to create such a quasi-governmental agency. Hamilton was prepared not only to propose the institution, but also to defend its constitutionality in order to secure the President’s signature on the bill.30 Hamilton’s related views on the “implied powers” element in the American Constitution were eventually adopted by the Federalists on the Supreme Court, and profoundly shaped later juridical history. His bank was crucial for his larger program of industrialization of the country, in his view 200 years behind Europe’s advanced nations.31 Besides the bank, the other elements in Hamilton’s blueprint for industrial development were contained in his famous “Report on the Subject of Manufactures,” which was ultimately rejected by Congress but widely studied and admired. It is now generally considered his most important state paper. The report, two years in embryo, outlined a leading role for the federal government, for, as the Secretary said, “in a community situated like the United States, the public purse must supply the deficiency of private resource.”32 The “Report on Manufactures” quoted Adam Smith in his Wealth of Nations (1776), using the classical economist’s words to refute physiocratic notions concerning agriculture as the sole source of national wealth, but Hamilton did not endorse the concept of laissez-faire. He seemed to mention Smith’s arguments mainly in order to disagree, especially with those that advocated free and unfettered commerce.33 Strongly influencing this report instead was the skeptical thinking of David Hume, who always believed the carrot to be better than the stick, but who assumed as inevitable—although in some ways undesirable—the existence of energetic government to guide and direct economic activity. Hamilton in the “Report on Manufactures” also felt compelled to respond to those who believed that manufacturing was less efficient or less moral than agriculture. He emphasized value-added as the true and only measure of economic enterprise, a utilitarian, Humean view that neither made concessions to farmers as “the chosen people of God,” nor allowances for what items were to be produced. “It is very conceivable,” the Secretary wrote, “that the labor of man alone, laid out upon a work requiring great skill and art to bring it to perfection, may be more productive, in value, than the labor of nature and man combined.”34 Alluding to the potential relative national gain from the expansion of manufacturing versus agriculture, a discussion that may also be found in Hume’s essay “Of Commerce,” Hamilton exhibited a sophisticated understanding of the theory of value-added. He claimed categorically that manufactured products, often associated with frivolous luxury and national dissipation in contemporary thinking, were really beneficial to the state.35 Hume had spent an entire essay, “Of Refinement in the Arts,” on a consideration of this subject. He contended, as Hamilton did, that a state abounding in luxury, even of the venal kind, would be better off than one abounding in sloth and ignorance. Both argued that a state enjoying luxury would be more happy, free and even virtuous than one dependent on simple agriculture. Luxury items, said Hamilton, signal surplus production alienable by the state in times of emergency, a Humean idea also to be found in the essay “Of Commerce.”36 While fundamentally a free trader, Hume had noted in “Of the Balance of Trade” that “all taxes . . . upon foreign commodities, are not to be regarded as prejudicial or useless.”37 Hamilton seized upon this idea to argue that the state should provide a helping hand to infant industries. His plans for tariffs, bounties and subsidies were also based upon the need to combat regular practices of competing nations, who granted export subsidies, protection of technological expertise, bounties, premiums and other aids including the creation of public monopolies and private cartels. Mankind’s natural hesitation to take risks and enter into new pursuits could be overcome by government encouragement, Hamilton claimed.38 Would bounties and protective tariffs for new industry have the effect of creating permanent domestic monopolies, which might impose prices well in excess of those charged in international markets? Hamilton admitted that monopoly, and its attendant high prices, might be a transitory effect of creating a protected domestic market. But he argued, as Hume had in “Of the Balance of Trade,” that costs of production fall as domestic industry begins to operate with efficiency.39 Furthermore, he tells us that the monopoly status enjoyed by the first few entrants into the protected domestic market would not last beyond the time when others joined in, the whole process having the eventual effect of helping to create a competitive, worldclass domestic industry in the United States.40 A competitive, world-class industrial nation remained the main goal of Hamilton’s economic system. As Jacob E. Cooke, editor of Hamilton’s Reports has noted, “The deepest purpose of his whole financial program was to strengthen the new government.”41 The Secretary of the Treasury never lost sight of Hume’s contention that commerce, in promoting human happiness, simultaneously promotes the power of the state. “Can we expect, that a government will be well-modelled by a people, who know not how to make a spinning-wheel, or to employ a loom to advantage?,” wrote Hume.42 Development leads to less rebelliousness among a people, fewer factions, better government and even more liberty, because the middle class, traditional defenders of human rights, is augmented by heightened economic activity.43 Hume's analysis of the relationship between the quantity of labor, measured by population, and associated levels of national income and personal consumption was incompatible with the doomsday scenario commonly presented by advocates of a simple labor theory of value. Hamilton’s wish to stimulate immigration, so as to alleviate the shortage of labor and encourage manufactures in his fledgling nation was entirely consistent with Hume’s belief that prosperity and population growth are compatible with one another. "Wherever there are the most happiness and virtue, and the wisest institutions, there will also be the most people" (On the Populousness of Ancient Nations, page 112 of Rotwein). Elsewhere, Hume argues that since population growth is associated with rising income it should be encouraged. As farm productivity expands, and a demand for consumption goods appears, an urban civilization appears, and national power, and population size, advance together (On the Populousness of Ancient Nations, pages 108-112, esp. page 111 of Rotwein). Hume’s analysis of the connection between the employment status of labor and the level of income helps Hamilton to argue for the benefits of a stimulus to manufacturing, despite the possible costs in terms of income inequality. In the agricultural state, income is divided more or less equally; "Not to mention the great equality of fortunes among the inhabitants of the ancient republics, where every field, belonging to a different proprietor, was able to maintain a family, and rendered the numbers of citizens very considerable, even without trade and manufactures." (Of Commerce, page 9, Rotwein edition). But in such a land, without manufacturers, income however equal, is low. The soporific state is not a productive one: "Everything in the world is purchased by labour; and our passions are the only causes of labour. When a nation abounds in manufactures and mechanic arts, the proprietors of land, as well as the farmers, study agriculture as a science, and redouble their industry and attention. The superfluity which arises from their labour, is not lost; but is exchanged with manufacturers for those commodities, which men's luxury now makes them covet. By this means, land furnishes a great deal more of the necessaries of life, than what suffices for those who cultivate it." (Of Commerce, Rotwein edition, page 12). Once again, we see how Hume makes a connection between productivity and labor which is dynamic and developmental, rather than static and arithmetical, as it becomes for Smith, Malthus and others. Hume has a manner of analysis that helps Hamilton form a long run development scheme for America, linking immigration, urbanization, industrialization and growth. Hume’s essays in his Political Discourses are not the only source for Hamilton’s economic system, but we contend that they are the major source. To understand the progression of Hume’s ideas to Hamilton, wrote Clinton Rossitor in 1964, “One has only to lay his speculative musings as Publius side by side with Hume’s essays of a political nature.”44 Even more revealing as an exercise, because the Treasury Secretary was now in a position to put ideas into practice, is to lay Hamilton’s Reports to Congress side by side with David Hume’s essays on economics. Moreover, the basic features of Hamilton’s program, resurrected and restyled “Henry Clay’s American System,” were to provide an enduring alternative vision for the United States in the nineteenth century. Notes 1Within the past few years a considerable body of literature discounting Locke’s influence on the entire eighteenth century has been building up. See J. G. A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, N. J., 1975), p. 424, and his “Virtue and Commerce in the Eighteenth Century,” Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 3 (1972), pp. 130-131, 134. See also Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology (Ithaca, N. Y., 1978); his “Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited; Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., XLIII (1986), 3-19; and Joyce Appleby, “Republicanism in Old and New Contexts,” Ibid., 20-34. A dissenting voice is heard in both Appleby and Isaac Kramnick, “Republican Revisionism Revisited,” American Historical Review LXXXVII (1982), 629-664. 2Gerald Stourzh, Alexander Hamilton and the Idea of Republican Government (Stanford, Calif., 1970), p. 216, fn. 43. 3Harold C. Syrett and Jacob E. Cooke, eds., The Papers of Alexander Hamilton (New York, 1961-1979), I, 95; II, 595-596; Henry Cabot Lodge, ed., Hamilton’s Works (New York, 1904), I, 409 and “The Defence of the Funding System,” VIII, 459. 4Clinton Rossitor, Alexander Hamilton and the Constitution (New York, 1964), p. 120. 5Ibid., p. 182; Forrest McDonald, Alexander Hamilton (New York, 1979), p. 35. 6Thomas Jefferson to John Cartwright, June 5, 1824, in Saul K. Padover, ed., A Jefferson Profile as Revealed in his Letters (New York, 1956), p. 335. 7Ibid., p. 355. 8Ibid. 9Jefferson to William Duane, August 12, 1810, in Thomas Jefferson, Writings, Merrill D. Peterson, ed., (New York, 1984), pp. 1228-1229. 10Hamilton quoted Hume in a speech to the Constitutional Convention, June 22, 1787 (Robert Yates Version), Syrett and Cooke, eds., Papers of Alexander Hamilton, IV, 216-217. 11See Jefferson’s remarks in “The Anas,” Adrienne Koch and William Peden, eds., The Life and Selected Writings of Thomas Jefferson (New York, 1972), p. 126. 12David Hume, “Of Commerce,” Writings on Economics, Eugene Rotwein, ed., (Madison, Wisc., 1955), pp. 3-18. The rest of the essays mentioned are also in Ibid., pp. 19-183. 13“Of Commerce,” Ibid., pp. 5, 12; “Of Refinement in the Arts,” Ibid., pp. 23-24. 14Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787 (New Haven, 1966), I, 310. 15Alexander Hamilton, The Reports of Alexander Hamilton, Jacob E. Cooke, ed., (New York, 1964), p. vi. 16Hamilton, “Report Relative to a Provision for the Support of Public Credit, January 9, 1790,” Ibid., pp. 2, 5-6. 17Hume, “Of Public Credit,” Rotwein, ed., pp. 93-96. 18Hamilton, “Report,” p. 33. 19Ibid., p. 41. 20Ibid., pp. 32-40. 21Ibid., p. 23. 22Hume, “Of Interest,” Rotwein, ed., p. 49. 23Hamilton, pp. 2-3. 24Ibid., p. 22. 25Hamilton, “Second Report on the Further Provision Necessary for Establishing Public Credit, December 13, 1790,” The Reports of Alexander Hamilton, Jacob E. Cooke, ed., p. 58. 26Hume, “Of Money,” Rotwein, ed., p. 39. 27Hamilton, “Second Report,” p. 58. 28Hume had his doubts about banks and paper credit, but to achieve the benefits of development and control the quantity of paper credit, he recommended that “If the public provide not a bank, private bankers will take advantage of this circumstance . . . and therefore it is better. See “Of Money,” Rotwein, ed., p. 35. 29Hamilton, “Second Report,” pp. 48-52, 58. 30Jacob E. Cooke, ed., Alexander Hamilton: p. 78. A Profile (New York, 1967), 31In 1790 and 1791 the Secretary had sent out a questionnaire on the curre nt state of American manufactures. Hamilton, “Report on the Subject of Manufactures, December 5, 1791,” The Reports of Alexander Hamilton, Jacob E. Cooke, ed., p. 155. 32Ibid., p. 204. 33Ibid.., pp. 150, 157, 179-180. 34Ibid., p. 121. 35Ibid., pp. 115-116. 36Ibid.; Hume, “Of Commerce,” Rotwein, ed., pp. 11-12. 37Hume, “Of the Balance of Trade,” Rotwein, ed., p. 76. 38Hamilton, “Report on Manufactures,” pp. 141-143. 39Ibid., p. 158. 40Ibid., pp. 158-162. 41Hamilton, Reports, Cooke, ed., p. xiii. 42Hume, “Of Refinement in the Arts,” Rotwein, ed., p. 24. 43Ibid., pp. 25, 28-29. 44Rossitor, p. 120. Subj: cea paper to acrobatize Date: 5/14/2003 1:56:43 PM Eastern Standard Time From: Tom Velk To: Tom Velk Dear Curtis and other Colleagues: Following as part of this email is a more or less complete draft of the text of the paper to be presented in May/June 03 at the Ottawa meetings of the Canadian Economics Association (CEA). I may make additions, but you may post this on the website since any later changes will be minor. tom velk, 802 988 9669, tomvelk@aol.com, mcgill University econ. dept. 514 398 4832 Hume Across the Ocean: His influence upon Hamilton's Economic Policies Tom Velk, A. R. Riggs and Dov Zigler Hume is an American in his principles in the Sam Rayburn/ Lyndon Johnson tradition. Hume never ran for dogcatcher, and so he would not have met the Rayburn test for membership in the President’s Cabinet, but his practical ideas appealed to the most hard-headed of America’s founding fathers. No mere dogcatcher, but a former artillery colonel promoted to Cabinet rank, had been guided by Hume’s ideas since boyhood. That American strategist was Alexander Hamilton. Once in office, he used Hume’s blueprint to construct the core economic institutions of the new nation. In his essay 'Of Commerce,' Hume dichotomizes between 'manufacturing societies' and 'farming societies'. Manufacturing societies use their surplus agricultural produce to support artisans while farming societies use surplus agricultural produce to maintain armies. According to Hume, farming societies in antiquity were well-off and politically powerful while those devoted to manufacturing and occupied with the consumption of luxuries were weak (e.g., Sparta vs. Athens). He says the opulent societies of antiquity were 'soft' and therefore less competent in the art of war, even if they were technologically advanced. However, Hume argues that 'things have changed.' In Hume's time, manufactures allow for improved cultivation and therefore ever increasing agricultural surplus. Greater agricultural surplus in turn supports more manufacturers, leading to a virtuous circle of economic, political, civic and even military development. Eventually, the surplus becomes so great that 'manufacturing societies' are able to raise armies of such scale and strength as to overshadow agriculturally minded competitors. ("Minded" is the right word, as the economic foundations of a community profoundly effect community habits of mind in respect of consumption, production and governance -- a relationship critical to Hamilton's application of Hume's implied strategy of systemwide social development). Perhaps more significant for our purposes, Hume believes that a community whose economic core is constituted by manufacturers has a potential "superfluity of labor" which "in times of peace goes to the maintenance of manufacturers and the improves of liberal arts. But it is easy for the public to convert many of these manufacturers into soldiers and maintain them by that superfluity which arises from the labour of the farmers." This process yields the maxim: "Manufacturers encrease the power of the state only as they store up so much labour and that of a kind to which the public may lay claim without depriving any one of the necessaries of life. The more labour therefore, is employed beyond the mere necessaries, the more powerful is any state... Thus the greatness of the soevereign and the happiness of the state are, in a great measure, united with regard to trade and manufactures." We say Hume is not so much falling into the labor theory error as he is elaborating a theory of the community mindset needed for civic progress and development. It is this vision of the interaction between an economic background and its role in evolving a modern state, able to compete with the Motherlands beyond the Sea, that, we argue, motivates Hamilton's schemes for economic development, as found in his state messages on the Bank, assumption of the debt, the Mint, Trade and Manufactures. Even more important to Hamilton, we believe, is the capacity for national defence which mobile human capital provides. Like Hume, Hamilton believes the first obligation of government is survival. Hamilton frequently writes of the economic and political jealousy of America’s European competitors. He was intensely aware of the short run danger presented by restive revolutionary soldiers, whose unpaid war wages gave them a motive to remain in arms, threatening the stability of the new nation, still in its vulnerable infancy. In the long run, the United States would need her army to resist European adventures and to maintain peace at home -- Hume’s human capital based theory of development showed Hamilton how to obtain and then pay for internal and external defenses. Hume believes that the most significant capital is what we now call 'human capital.' Economic strength is measured in population quantity and quality. The more readily a state can shift labour from private use to public use, the greater the power of the state. "Trade and industry are really nothing but a stock of labour, which, in times of peace and tranquillity, is employed for the ease and satisfaction of individuals; but in the exigencies of state, may, in part, be turned to public advantage." Once again, Hume is not really a labor theory advocate, as he is proposing a state strategy of encouraging a more economically mobile form of human Capital -- the same grand purpose as Hamilton's. And so Hume's developmental theory of 'the (dynamic) natural value of labor' is distinguishable from Smith's more static assertions concerning 'labor value.' Particularly important to us is our belief that it is this vision of the need to encourage by policy a more mobile endowment of human capital which is the political motivation behind Hamilton's 'Report on Manufactures' for Congress, as well as his plans for the Bank, assumption of the debt, immigration, and the tariff. A critically important payoff for us is that our reading of Hume, which we think is also Hamilton's, allows us to square the radicalism of Hamilton's economic policies with the general 'conservatism' of Hume. Hamilton is certainly a radical if by that label we refer to the extraordinary degree of change he was advocating for his new nation. His actual United States was a skim of formerly distinct colonies, the wide Atlantic in front of them and a "desolate wilderness, full of wild beasts and wild men" behind them. It was a land of farmers, dependent upon the old world for manufactures and governance, obsessed with a dream of independence, but in fact burdened with an illiquid national debt, and lacking a domestic growth in the supply of labor adequate to its potential for industrial growth, or its needs for defense. To the extent there existed a de facto static plan for the future, it was Jefferson's -- who wished for a thousand generations more of such yeoman farmers, gradually expanding west, living simple rural lives, on small freeholds and in quiet villages, somehow protected from their envious, expansionist former colonial masters. Hamilton, we think, saw in Hume's arguments the strategic long run danger of this "conservative" dream of stasis, and he did his best to set the United States upon a much different strategic course of political and social action. Hume's teaching, that national greatness and public happiness are derivatives of "trade and commerce" is, we think reason enough for Hamilton to espouse his far-reaching radical transformation of US society and economy. What's more, Hume paints the ancient agricultural model as an unrepeatable historical incident not at all in touch with the circumstances of modernity and the movement of human history. A Jeffersonian agricultural state would not be conservative but instead would be a radical departure from the currents of human history, especially the British history of which the US is a part. In Hume's own words: "It is a violent method, and in most cases impracticable, to oblige the labourer to toil, in order to raise from the land more than what subsists himself and family. Furnish him with manufactures and commodities, and he will do it himself..." The "big economic idea" of the Jeffersonians was that property served the public interest best when it was equally distributed, and such a distribution was to be aggressively preserved, sought after or imposed some way. This utopian egalitarianism was said to be legitimized by natural rights, often found in an imagined original contract. Another part of Jefferson's big idea is stability: the yeomen simply reconstituted themselves, generation after generation. Hume's big idea, in contrast, was dynamic and inegalitarian. Property, and goods not so abundant as to be free in nature, were to be distributed by rules, perhaps those found in specific contracts, actually agreed to by parties to a particular action. Another species of contract, equally to be respected, consists in the habits, traditions and practices of the past, which allow us to form strong expectations about the rules by which we interact among ourselves, individually and corporately. If the rule-driven process of this kind of contractual exchange is orderly, predictable, uniform across persons, independent of superstition and resistant to fraud, it will exhibit Humean Justice. The final result may easily be an unequal distribution of wealth. Nonetheless, the riches and "instability" so engendered make for a better world. For Hume, the just rights of property were an (necessary) invention of mankind, artificial in that God took no hand in their design, nor was there to be found in real history any original contract to the contrary. Hamilton was a man in full agreement with Hume. Hamilton was in some respects a radical: he wished to create an America far different from the one in which he lived. He wanted big cities, active government, sophisticated financial markets, international trade and industry. We admit that because such dreams were in stark contrast with 18th century reality, they might be said to be distinctly non-Humean. But the goal that Hamilton was seeking by means of his dramatic proposals was profoundly Humean. It is, we think, Hume's promise of the benefits of material prosperity, and Hume's defeat of the argument that riches are best distributed when they are equally distributed that allowed Hamilton to advocate an urbanized, industrialized new order, inevitably containing a few persons of great wealth, those highly specialized persons being supported by their earnings in trade, finance and manufacturing. Hamilton needed to defend his vision against those who deplored the supposed immorality of great wealth, of earnings from "mere" trade, who questioned the morality of usury and finance, and who imagined there was special virtue in the simple economy of the farm and village. Hume offers a powerful counter-argument to the Jeffersonian claim that the rough egalitarianism of the yeomanry was the best guarantor of good government. Despite the resistance of Jefferson, both in to the particulars of the schemes and to the greater vision behind them, Secretary of the Treasury Alexander Hamilton, operating as a kind of Prime Minister, or at least as First Lord of the Treasury, put Hume's ideas into systematic practice. George Washington allowed him a free hand, in recognition of the great need for an end to the new nation’s economic tribulations. The people, whose Confederation Government had ended in financial disarray, seemed willing tolerate dramatic change. The Humean course set by Hamilton determined the future of the republic. By the time Thomas Jefferson became president the general plan was too entrenched to be changed. A paper that aspires to discuss the transfer of ideas—in this instance from David Hume to Alexander Hamilton—should properly contain a word of caution. Ideas can quickly become part of a stock of received wisdom, an unwritten consensus from which people, even on opposite sides of an issue—or an ocean—may draw at will. Furthermore, until very recently policy-makers and people in general who would not consider themselves plagiarists were reluctant oftentimes to give credit where credit was due. These and other factors make it extremely difficult to trace the progress of ideas. The recent case of John Locke, the seventeenth century Englishman once universally recognized as the spiritual father of the American Revolution, will illustrate our point. Today some reputable scholars claim that the history of the Revolution, including its ideological origins, could be written without a single reference to Locke, a state of nature or natural rights.1 John Locke’s name appears only once in the voluminous writings of Alexander Hamilton.2 Neither do Locke’s ideas figure prominently in Hamilton’s correspondence. On the other hand, he seldom mentioned David Hume by name either, but when he did his admiration for the Scottish philosopher seemed boundless. Hamilton’s debt to Hume begins early. Aged sixteen (others say he was, in fact, as old as eighteen), in what was his first published political debate, writing “The Farmer Refuted”, a response to Samuel Seabury, who had challenged the arguments found in Hamilton’s maiden publication, Hamilton quotes Hume as an enunciator of “political maxims, which will be eternally true”. Hamilton requested Hume’s works from his friend Timothy Pickering in April 1781, and he was particularly intrigued with Hume’s essays on economics. In 1775 Hamilton quoted the “celebrated author,” in 1782 he referred to the philosopher as “a very ingenious and sensible writer,” he relies upon Hume’s arguments in writing “The Continentalist No. V”, and at the Constitutional Convention of 1787 he praised Hume as “one of the ablest politicians.” Later, as Secretary of the Treasury, Hamilton would pattern much of his fiscal and monetary policy around the reasonings and observations of “the profound and ingenious Hume.”3 Hamilton’s intellectual debt to Hume went unrecognized for many years, and even as late as 1970 Broadus Mitchell’s fine single-volume biography did not mention the philosopher. In 1964, however, the late Clinton Rossitor, referring to The Federalist Papers, remarked that Hamilton’s debt to Hume “may have been larger than he realized even in his more humble moments.”4 Rossitor called Hamilton “the American Hume,” and Forrest McDonald, writing in 1979, agreed that “Hamilton repeatedly expressed Hume’s thoughts as his own.”5 Gerald Strourzh finds a significant debt to Hume in his “Alexander Hamilton and the Idea of Republican Government” (Stanford 1970.) Mark G. Spencer’s two volume edit (Thoemmes Press, 2002, Bristol, UK, isbn1 85506 934 2), entitled “Hume’s Reception in Early America” serves to remind us of the wide spread presence of Hume’s work in library collections, newspaper debates and even classrooms of early America, but David Hume’s genius was not universally applauded in the new nation, however. Hamilton’s celebrated rival in the first cabinet under George Washington, Secretary of State Thomas Jefferson (unappreciative of Hume’s support for America) called him “the great apostle of Toryism,”6 a “degenerate son of science,”7 a “traitor to his fellow man,”8 and one “who undermined the free principles of the English government.”9 This was because Hume’s History of England, a new venture in its field, did not properly condemn the Stuart monarchs of the seventeenth century. Furthermore, for American patriotic tastes Hume had laid out in his essays on economics a critique of English whig politicians that was unacceptable. In addition, his critical observations on mercantilism, the orthodox economics of the day, did not condemn with enough fervor the intervention of government in the marketplace. Hume had also rej ected the idea of disinterested virtue as a motivating force in those who presumed to govern, a first article of faith among British and American whigs. Passions induce people to action, affirmed Hume, and a wise government would avail itself of those primary motivators so that they would be forced to serve the public good.10 For people such as Jefferson this utilitarian idea, whether advanced by a Hume or a Hamilton, was tantamount to an endorsement of corruption in government.11 But the core of Hume’s economics, the set of ideas that appealed most to Hamilton, appeared in nine essays published in London in 1752 and entitled Political Discourses.12 In “Of Commerce” Hume rejected the idea that a nation can achieve greatness as an agricultural entity alone. In “Of Refinement in the Arts” he took issue with certain religious zealots who denoted luxury as evil. In “Of Money” he criticized those who thought that an injection of money into the economy would work long-term wonders, and in “Of Interest” he argued with those who claimed that abundance of money leads to low interest rates. “Of the Balance of Trade” and “Of the Jealousy of Trade,” two of his most important treatises, were directed against the protectionist policies of the reigning mercantilists. “Of Taxes” pleaded for moderation and rejected the French physiocratic single tax on land, and “Of Public Credit,” warning that the public is no blessing, deplored the expedients of Lord Oxford’s partisans to draw bills on posterity and imprudently use public credit to create paper riches. Finally, Hume addressed his essay “Of the Populousness of Ancient Nations” to exposing the doomsday thinking of the Reverend Robert Wallace of Edinburgh. In the following summary of Hume's economic aphorisms we think we find an outline of Hamilton’s beliefs as well. 1) a nation's strength lies in its productivity, which in turn is stimulated by variety and innovation; 2) trade, likely to be found in an active community of manufacturers, benefits everyone, state and pe ople, rich and poor; 3) luxury, economic growth and refinement in the arts are compatible, and complementary, even though they may be associated with an unequal distribution of wealth; 4) the flow of money from nation to nation is the instrument of economic evolution and progress, while economic isolation is a recipe for stagnation; 5) the rate of interest, and the associated state of the market for government debt is an indicator which, read by the experienced eye, tells of the health and growth in the economy; 6) free trade is to be desired, although national efforts to stimulate domestic industry are sometimes appropriate; 7) a country cannot become rich by beggaring its neighbor; 8) a government should not tax the rewards of effort lest it destroy the incentive to growth; 9) the public debt in the hands of judicious magistrates can have beneficial effects, but can also be dangerous; and 9) since no utopia existed in any past golden age it is unlikely that radical innovations in government, especially those produced by speculative projectors, are ever likely to produce the gains promised. In the economic essays, as in his other works, Hume’s prescriptions were always reformist, but moderate, balanced, carefully argued and conservative. He believed in freer trade, but he rejected the idea that unhampered pursuit of private gain would benefit society, and he never discounted the role of a strong government’s visible, directing hand on the economy. He believed in interdependence of nations and that international neighbors could grow rich together, with no need to exploit one another’s weaknesses. The engine that drives a society, he said, must be the production of goods and services, and no country could be happy, progressive or great without industrial development and the advancement of commerce.13 It will take no great leap of understanding to discern the immediate appeal of these Humean ideas to Alexander Hamilton, who became Secretary of the Treasury in September 1789. Disgusted with the weak Confederation government of the 1780’s, Hamilton was determined to follow whatever policy would promote solvency and national strength for the United States. Seizing upon a loose construction of the Constitution to accommodate his claim that “the goodness of a government consists in a vigorous execution,”14 he set out to make the government of the United States at least an equal partner with private enterprise in determining the nation’s future. His economic policy reports to Congress in the 1790’s show that he was indeed a disciple of Hume, but he lacked the pragmatism and the toleration of contrary ideas that distinguished the best efforts of his mentor. Hamilton submitted four major reports to Congress on the American economy between January 1790 and December 1791. They included the “Report Relative to a Provision for the Support of Public Credit,” January 9, 1790; the “Second Report on the Further Provision Necessary for Establishing Public Credit,” December 13, 1790; the “Report on the Establishment of a Mint,” January 28, 1791; and the “Report on the Subject of Manufactures,” December 5, 1791.15 Three of these are important to an analysis of Hamilton’s policy, the Report on the Mint being a technical treatise that will not be discussed in our paper. Hume says at least four important, insightful and original things about money, inflation and finance. He talks about the dynamic, actual and historical process played out as new money enters the economy. He also discusses, in the manner of a thought experiment, the logical, nonhistoric contrast between two imagined states of the world, one with a small amount of money and one with more. He also examines, partly in history, and partly by means of logic, the consequences of having in simultaneous circulation two qualitatively different kinds of money, gold and paper. Finally, Hume’s discussion of the specie flow mechanism, virtually unchanged from the way he first expressed it, is not only invariably credited to him, but is also a standard component of modern international trade theory, as well as being the core proposition of the so-called monetary approach to the balance of payments. All four views of money are part of Hamilton’s thinking as he proposes to create, for the new nation, a currency made uniform by the influence of a national bank. The bank would be possessed of the capital and influence required to organize and subsidize secondary markets in reserve assets, standardize bank practices, and moderate the temptation to inflate the currency, otherwise constantly on offer to elected officials. In other words, the Bank Hamilton builds in accordance with Hume’s blueprint is not only a governor on the ambitions and practices of the banking sector, such as it was in those times, but it would be a limiter upon promiscuous politicians as well. That it well-served in that latter capacity is evident in the fury with which it was later attacked by the Jacksonians. That Hume’s four big ideas about money and finance are not in conflict, but are mutually suppo rtive, is demonstrated by the way Hamilton combined them in his economic plan for the new nation. The first report on Public Credit may be studied as a counterpart to Hume’s earlier essay, “Of Public Credit.” The philosopher had listed the advantages and disadvantages of public borrowing, and the Secretary followed the pace and demeanor of the Hume essay. Hamilton read his mandate from Congress as a command to lay down rules for the provision of an optimal quantity of funded credit, a kind of treasury bill that could circulate as money. He argued that trade is extended by public credit, and agriculture and manufacturing stimulated by it. As foreign trade expands a reduction in interest rates results, the rate driven down by an increase in the quantity of money and the quickness of circulation.16 Hume had made the same points, in the same order, but qualified them extensively.17 Hamilton qualified very little. In the meanwhile, acting upon the report, Hamilton deflated the American bond market while restoring face value and even specie parity to securities that were almost worthless in purchasing power. Issuers of the securities—various government and quasi-government agencies, including army quartermaster units, state governments and the Continental Congress from the old Confederation government—had offered no financial security to the debts’ owners. The Secretary claimed that unilateral changes in the interest payment schedule would cut annual interest costs (or more accurately, annual interest obligations, since the nominal rates were not being paid fully) almost in half. Vigorous growth would follow.18 But Hamilton pointed out that he certainly did not believe that a public debt is a public blessing,19 despite the centralizing effect that assumption would have upon the states. On this point he showed some of the caution expressed by Hume. Hamilton proposed that to thwart the government’s temptation to spend, it should be forced to set aside a linked obligation to tax—to tie each spending item, and each existing evidence of past debt, to some particular revenue source.20 According to the Secretary a stable government securities market, a liquid money market and a responsible tax system would combine to stimulate domestic and foreign trade. Each merchant, keeping his capital in money and the securities market, instead of invested in landed estate, would promote commerce and manufacturing. The rate of interest would fall, partly as a result of increased public credit and in part as a result of increased riches, further stimulating economic activity.21 Again Hamilton’s argument was virtually identical to Hume’s, except Hamilton placed more emphasis upon additional money in reducing interest rates. Hamilton’s contention that a well-funded and contractually secure public debt would reduce the interest rate is compatible with Hume’s ideas, in his essay “Of Interest,” about the lowness of the interest rate following from “an increase of industry and commerce, not of gold and silver.”22 Hamilton buttressed his point by saying that an unfunded debt, by hurting confidence, would necessarily raise the interest rate.23 In the same vein he argued for rigorous adherence to the bond market’s rules of ownership and transfer, so that property rights, in the form of absolutely secure promises in the money market, be strictly observed. Thus the practical utility of enhanced economic growth would be realized.24 A utilitarian view of property rights, clearly discernible in Hamiltonian economics, may also be found in Hume. Hume’s contentions in “Of Money” seem also to have inspired Hamilton when he sat down to write his “Second Report on Public Credit,” sometimes referred to as the “Report on a National Bank.” Echoing Hume, the Secretary of the Treasury affirmed that the real wealth of a nation lies in men, manufactures, mines and farms. As long as these are at work the quantity of money would have a high potential level, a level that likely would eventually be supplied by the natural process of international trade.25 Hume had written in “Of Money,” “We may conclude, that it is of no manner of consequence, with regard to the domestic happiness of a state, whether money be in greater or less quantity.”26 Hamilton said the same thing and then gave an excellent summary of Hume’s best-known contribution to economics, that of the specie flow mechanism. It is the process whereby specie—the international stock of gold and silver—flows toward whatever country has the most active level of trade. The money remains in motion, however, to accommodate trading deals everywhere. This process redistributes money all over the world, making the global trading nations one vast market with one price level and a common money stock. Hamilton noted, A nation, that has no mines of its own, must derive the precious metals from others; generally speaking, in exchange for the product of its labor and industry. The quantity, it will possess, will therefore, in the ordinary course of things be regulated by the favourable, or unfavourable balance of its trade, that is, the proportion between its abilities to supply foreigners; and its want of them; between the amount of its exportations and that of its importations. Hence the state of its agriculture and manufactures, the quantity and quality of its labour and industry, must in the main, influence and determine the increase or decrease of its gold and silver.27 In the Second Report Hamilton linked the public banking system more closely to the state of agriculture and manufacturing than Hume had done.28 Hamilton’s proposed Bank of the United States would serve the state by concentrating capital, providing a secure source of funds in emergencies and a safe depository for federal funds, giving financial and technical aid to collection of taxes and payment of interest on the public debt. It would also provide a uniform circulating medium, help the treasury conduct foreign trade, aid in settling foreign debts, control private banks and multiply the financial capacity of the nation’s stock of gold and silver.29 Hume had complex feelings about public banks, because of a disastrous French experiment with one. In 1752 Hume felt no need to defend a public bank, since the bank of England, the model for Hamilton’s proposal, was long-established. In 1790, in the United States, however, many believed that the Constitution did not authorize Congress to create such a quasi-governmental agency. Hamilton was prepared not only to propose the institution, but also to defend its constitutionality in order to secure the President’s signature on the bill.30 Hamilton’s related views on the “implied powers” element in the American Constitution were eventually adopted by the Federalists on the Supreme Court, and profoundly shaped later juridical history. His bank was crucial for his larger program of industrialization of the country, in his view 200 years behind Europe’s advanced nations.31 Besides the bank, the other elements in Hamilton’s blueprint for industrial development were contained in his famous “Report on the Subject of Manufactures,” which was ultimately rejected by Congress but widely studied and admired. It is now generally considered his most important state paper. The report, two years in embryo, outlined a leading role for the federal government, for, as the Secretary said, “in a community situated like the United States, the public purse must supply the deficiency of private resource.”32 The “Report on Manufactures” quoted Adam Smith in his Wealth of Nations (1776), using the classical economist’s words to refute physiocratic notions concerning agriculture as the sole source of national wealth, but Hamilton did not endorse the concept of laissez-faire. He seemed to mention Smith’s arguments mainly in order to disagree, especially with those that advocated free and unfettered commerce.33 Strongly influencing this report instead was the skeptical thinking of David Hume, who always believed the carrot to be better than the stick, but who assumed as inevitable—although in some ways undesirable—the existence of energetic government to guide and direct economic activity. Hamilton in the “Report on Manufactures” also felt compelled to respond to those who believed that manufacturing was less efficient or less moral than agriculture. He emphasized value-added as the true and only measure of economic enterprise, a utilitarian, Humean view that neither made concessions to farmers as “the chosen people of God,” nor allowances for what items were to be produced. “It is very conceivable,” the Secretary wrote, “that the labor of man alone, laid out upon a work requiring great skill and art to bring it to perfection, may be more productive, in value, than the labor of nature and man combined.”34 Alluding to the potential relative national gain from the expansion of manufacturing versus agriculture, a discussion that may also be found in Hume’s essay “Of Commerce,” Hamilton exhibited a sophisticated understanding of the theory of value-added. He claimed categorically that manufactured products, often associated with frivolous luxury and national dissipation in contemporary thinking, were really beneficial to the state.35 Hume had spent an entire essay, “Of Refinement in the Arts,” on a consideration of this subject. He contended, as Hamilton did, that a state abounding in luxury, even of the venal kind, would be better off than one abounding in sloth and ignorance. Both argued that a state enjoying luxury would be more happy, free and even virtuous than one dependent on simple agriculture. Luxury items, said Hamilton, signal surplus production alienable by the state in times of emergency, a Humean idea also to be found in the essay “Of Commerce.”36 While fundamentally a free trader, Hume had noted in “Of the Balance of Trade” that “all taxes . . . upon foreign commodities, are not to be regarded as prejudicial or useless.”37 Hamilton seized upon this idea to argue that the state should provide a helping hand to infant industries. His plans for tariffs, bounties and subsidies were also based upon the need to combat regular practices of competing nations, who granted export subsidies, protection of technological expertise, bounties, premiums and other aids including the creation of public monopolies and private cartels. Mankind’s natural hesitation to take risks and enter into new pursuits could be overcome by government encouragement, Hamilton claimed.38 Would bounties and protective tariffs for new industry have the effect of creating permanent domestic monopolies, which might impose prices well in excess of those charged in international markets? Hamilton admitted that monopoly, and its attendant high prices, might be a transitory effect of creating a protected domestic market. But he argued, as Hume had in “Of the Balance of Trade,” that costs of production fall as domestic industry begins to operate with efficiency.39 Furthermore, he tells us that the monopoly status enjoyed by the first few entrants into the protected domestic market would not last beyond the time when others joined in, the whole process having the eventual effect of helping to create a competitive, worldclass domestic industry in the United States.40 A competitive, world-class industrial nation remained the main goal of Hamilton’s economic system. As Jacob E. Cooke, editor of Hamilton’s Reports has noted, “The deepest purpose of his whole financial program was to strengthen the new government.”41 The Secretary of the Treasury never lost sight of Hume’s contention that commerce, in promoting human happiness, simultaneously promotes the power of the state. “Can we expect, that a government will be well-modelled by a people, who know not how to make a spinning-wheel, or to employ a loom to advantage?,” wrote Hume.42 Development leads to less rebelliousness among a people, fewer factions, better government and even more liberty, because the middle class, traditional defenders of human rights, is augmented by heightened economic activity.43 Hume's analysis of the relationship between the quantity of labor, measured by population, and associated levels of national income and personal consumption was incompatible with the doomsday scenario commonly presented by advocates of a simple labor theory of value. Hamilton’s wish to stimulate immigration, so as to alleviate the shortage of labor and encourage manufactures in his fledgling nation was entirely consistent with Hume’s belief that prosperity and population growth are compatible with one another. "Wherever there are the most happiness and virtue, and the wisest institutions, there will also be the most people" (On the Populousness of Ancient Nations, page 112 of Rotwein). Elsewhere, Hume argues that since population growth is associated with rising income it should be encouraged. As farm productivity expands, and a demand for consumption goods appears, an urban civilization appears, and national power, and population size, advance together (On the Populousness of Ancient Nations, pages 108-112, esp. page 111 of Rotwein). Hume’s analysis of the connection between the employment status of labor and the level of income helps Hamilton to argue for the benefits of a stimulus to manufacturing, despite the possible costs in terms of income inequality. In the agricultural state, income is divided more or less equally; "Not to mention the great equality of fortunes among the inhabitants of the ancient republics, where every field, belonging to a different proprietor, was able to maintain a family, and rendered the numbers of citizens very considerable, even without trade and manufactures." (Of Commerce, page 9, Rotwein edition). But in such a land, without manufacturers, income however equal, is low. The soporific state is not a productive one: "Everything in the world is purchased by labour; and our passions are the only causes of labour. When a nation abounds in manufactures and mechanic arts, the proprietors of land, as well as the farmers, study agriculture as a science, and redouble their industry and attention. The superfluity which arises from their labour, is not lost; but is exchanged with manufacturers for those commodities, which men's luxury now makes them covet. By this means, land furnishes a great deal more of the necessaries of life, than what suffices for those who cultivate it." (Of Commerce, Rotwein edition, page 12). Once again, we see how Hume makes a connection between productivity and labor which is dynamic and developmental, rather than static and arithmetical, as it becomes for Smith, Malthus and others. Hume has a manner of analysis that helps Hamilton form a long run development scheme for America, linking immigration, urbanization, industrialization and growth. Hume’s essays in his Political Discourses are not the only source for Hamilton’s economic system, but we contend that they are the major source. To understand the progression of Hume’s ideas to Hamilton, wrote Clinton Rossitor in 1964, “One has only to lay his speculative musings as Publius side by side with Hume’s essays of a political nature.”44 Even more revealing as an exercise, because the Treasury Secretary was now in a position to put ideas into practice, is to lay Hamilton’s Reports to Congress side by side with David Hume’s essays on economics. Moreover, the basic features of Hamilton’s program, resurrected and restyled “Henry Clay’s American System,” were to provide an enduring alternative vision for the United States in the nineteenth century. Notes 1Within the past few years a considerable body of literature discounting Locke’s influence on the entire eighteenth century has been building up. See J. G. A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, N. J., 1975), p. 424, and his “Virtue and Commerce in the Eighteenth Century,” Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 3 (1972), pp. 130-131, 134. See also Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology (Ithaca, N. Y., 1978); his “Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited; Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., XLIII (1986), 3-19; and Joyce Appleby, “Republicanism in Old and New Contexts,” Ibid., 20-34. A dissenting voice is heard in both Appleby and Isaac Kramnick, “Republican Revisionism Revisited,” American Historical Review LXXXVII (1982), 629-664. 2Gerald Stourzh, Alexander Hamilton and the Idea of Republican Government (Stanford, Calif., 1970), p. 216, fn. 43. 3Harold C. Syrett and Jacob E. Cooke, eds., The Papers of Alexander Hamilton (New York, 1961-1979), I, 95; II, 595-596; Henry Cabot Lodge, ed., Hamilton’s Works (New York, 1904), I, 409 and “The Defence of the Funding System,” VIII, 459. 4Clinton Rossitor, Alexander Hamilton and the Constitution (New York, 1964), p. 120. 5Ibid., p. 182; Forrest McDonald, Alexander Hamilton (New York, 1979), p. 35. 6Thomas Jefferson to John Cartwright, June 5, 1824, in Saul K. Padover, ed., A Jefferson Profile as Revealed in his Letters (New York, 1956), p. 335. 7Ibid., p. 355. 8Ibid. 9Jefferson to William Duane, August 12, 1810, in Thomas Jefferson, Writings, Merrill D. Peterson, ed., (New York, 1984), pp. 1228-1229. 10Hamilton quoted Hume in a speech to the Constitutional Convention, June 22, 1787 (Robert Yates Version), Syrett and Cooke, eds., Papers of Alexander Hamilton, IV, 216-217. 11See Jefferson’s remarks in “The Anas,” Adrienne Koch and William Peden, eds., The Life and Selected Writings of Thomas Jefferson (New York, 1972), p. 126. 12David Hume, “Of Commerce,” Writings on Economics, Eugene Rotwein, ed., (Madison, Wisc., 1955), pp. 3-18. The rest of the essays mentioned are also in Ibid., pp. 19-183. 13“Of Commerce,” Ibid., pp. 5, 12; “Of Refinement in the Arts,” Ibid., pp. 23-24. 14Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787 (New Haven, 1966), I, 310. 15Alexander Hamilton, The Reports of Alexander Hamilton, Jacob E. Cooke, ed., (New York, 1964), p. vi. 16Hamilton, “Report Relative to a Provision for the Support of Public Credit, January 9, 1790,” Ibid., pp. 2, 5-6. 17Hume, “Of Public Credit,” Rotwein, ed., pp. 93-96. 18Hamilton, “Report,” p. 33. 19Ibid., p. 41. 20Ibid., pp. 32-40. 21Ibid., p. 23. 22Hume, “Of Interest,” Rotwein, ed., p. 49. 23Hamilton, pp. 2-3. 24Ibid., p. 22. 25Hamilton, “Second Report on the Further Provision Necessary for Establishing Public Credit, December 13, 1790,” The Reports of Alexander Hamilton, Jacob E. Cooke, ed., p. 58. 26Hume, “Of Money,” Rotwein, ed., p. 39. 27Hamilton, “Second Report,” p. 58. 28Hume had his doubts about banks and paper credit, but to achieve the benefits of development and control the quantity of paper credit, he recommended that “If the public provide not a bank, private bankers will take advantage of this circumstance . . . and therefore it is better. See “Of Money,” Rotwein, ed., p. 35. 29Hamilton, “Second Report,” pp. 48-52, 58. 30Jacob E. Cooke, ed., Alexander Hamilton: p. 78. A Profile (New York, 1967), 31In 1790 and 1791 the Secretary had sent out a questionnaire on the curre nt state of American manufactures. Hamilton, “Report on the Subject of Manufactures, December 5, 1791,” The Reports of Alexander Hamilton, Jacob E. Cooke, ed., p. 155. 32Ibid., p. 204. 33Ibid.., pp. 150, 157, 179-180. 34Ibid., p. 121. 35Ibid., pp. 115-116. 36Ibid.; Hume, “Of Commerce,” Rotwein, ed., pp. 11-12. 37Hume, “Of the Balance of Trade,” Rotwein, ed., p. 76. 38Hamilton, “Report on Manufactures,” pp. 141-143. 39Ibid., p. 158. 40Ibid., pp. 158-162. 41Hamilton, Reports, Cooke, ed., p. xiii. 42Hume, “Of Refinement in the Arts,” Rotwein, ed., p. 24. 43Ibid., pp. 25, 28-29. 44Rossitor, p. 120.