Reviews/Comptes rendus The Rights Revolution by Michael Ignatieff. Toronto: Anansi Press, 2000. Pp. xi, 170. $16.95. Michael Ignatieff says that his latest book, The Rights Revolution, is a “modest exercise in democratic education.” Its text was delivered originally in five parts for the famed Massey Lectures Series, and broadcast on CBC Radio in November 2000. In fact, this small book — it is only 141 pages long — grapples with some very big questions: How can a modern society reconcile political equality and social diversity? Do group rights jeopardize individual rights? Do individual rights weaken the idea of community? What is going on in Canada, and why have we seen so many constitutional and social crises in recent years? Just as ambitiously, the book tries to address two audiences simultaneously: political and legal academics who have made careers writing about such things, and an informed lay audience that wants to locate Canadian public life within a larger discussion of rights, democracy, and equality. None of this makes this dense and idiosyncratic book easy to read or easy to review. Yet Ignatieff’s snapshot of the state of modern Canada is too insightful to be ignored. Ignatieff’s book asks what, for Canadians, is the hardest question of all: whether or not the “rights culture” we have developed over the last generation will be enough to hold our society together, in the face of the many and profound cross-cutting forces that threaten to pull it apart. His conclusion — almost a year ago now — was hopeful, but open-ended. As the anniversary of the lectures rolls around, it is time to consider whether we know anything more about the answer to his question.1 Ignatieff sets the stage for his discussion by way of a sweeping, high-speed tour through Canada’s political and social landscape, highlighting such features as Quebec’s secession debate, Aboriginal self-government, the evolving nature of the family, and the impact of immigration. The image of the Canadian cultural environment that emerges looks like this (and both he and I are being impressionis- 515 tic here): first, the country bears the inheritance of three nations — the English, the French, and the Aboriginal — that, unlike other “minority groups,” assert collective political rights based on the fact that they were present when Canada was created such that its original legitimacy rested (or ought to have rested) on their consent. Second, those nations disagree profoundly with each other when it comes to central truths about Canadian history and identity. According to Ignatieff, this cuts deeper than just contested interpretations of a common experience in whose truth everyone ultimately believes. He argues that Canada’s constituent nations literally do not inhabit the same historical reality, even though they share a coincidence of time and place; they are three solitudes. Third, this historical Canada is being transformed by fundamental demographic shifts, particularly the presence of more recent immigrant populations that are not prepared simply to accept the “founding nations” mythology on which the federation’s original parties struck their bargain. For these new Canadians, the notion of Canada as a pact between founding nations undermines not only the rhetoric of multiculturalism, but also all Canadians’ legitimate claims to inclusion as equal, rights-bearing citizens. Ignatieff’s keen eye picks up how Canadians have longed at times to be a straightforward nation of individuals, freed from the encrustations of history and group allegiance. He argues, for example, that Trudeau’s bilingualism policy was really aimed at eliminating the political significance of one’s francophone or anglophone status, rather than at celebrating the country’s dual linguistic heritage. On the other hand, Ignatieff points to the persistent role that linguistic, religious, and educational group allegiances have played in Canada, and to the groupconscious political theory that Canadians like Charles Taylor and Will Kymlicka have produced.2 He argues that multinational, multi-ethnic states like Canada cannot be described accurately either as a nation of identical rights-bearing individuals operating within an undifferentiated political space, or as a patchwork quilt of distinct national collectives CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 516 Reviews/Comptes rendus contained in one state; they are both. The consequence is a continual tension between individual identity and group affiliation that has resurfaced in various guises throughout the country’s history. Ignatieff observes correctly that in this environment, the delicate Canadian federation traditionally has been kept up — for at least a century almost everyone seemed to believe, in good faith, that it could only be kept up — as a conscious, tightly choreographed political dance directed by a select few powerbrokers and constitutional specialists, with minimal input from, or accountability to, the citizenry. Enter, unexpectedly, a Rights Revolution. Beginning in the 1960s but reaching a zenith over the last decade, the struggles of women and minorities for full civil rights, and the struggle of Aboriginal peoples for self-government, have widened and deepened the scope of political debate. Rights talk has seeped into every conversation and even become something of a trump card, not only in the public, but also the social and private spheres. The arguments mustered in favour of expanded rights recognition have been compelling. As a result, Ignatieff argues (a bit prematurely, I think) that for the first time in their history western liberal societies are trying to make democracy work on conditions of total inclusion, not only of propertied men, or whites, or traditional dual-gender married couples, but of everyone. Greater inclusion is, of course, more just; yet the rights revolution has also been divisive and destabilizing. Certainly in Canada, the increasingly democratic and disputatious nature of political debate has made the country harder to govern by usual means. To switch to the author’s metaphor, the “high priests of federalism,” who for 125 years “interpret[ed] the sacred texts and wave[d] the incense of rhetoric in the direction of the congregation,” had lost control utterly of the “rituals of unity” by the time of the 1995 Quebec Referendum.3 The book’s most important question is how the explosion of rights talk is shaping a particularly Canadian neurosis: the view of our history as an unresolved struggle to fashion a common sense of CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, identity and place in the world. Ignatieff poses it squarely: the central question for Canada at this point in its rights revolution is whether a culture based on rights “is enough to hold the country together, whether it creates a sufficiently robust sense of belonging, and a sufficiently warm-hearted kind of mutual recognition, to enable us to solve our differences peacefully.”4 He does not try to finesse the answer; there are no satisfied nods to geography, “Good Government,” non-Americanness, or even beer commercials. 5 Ignatieff recognizes that the country faced alarming doubts in the 1990s, not only about what held it together as a state but also about what, other than necessity and historical accident, held Canadians together as a society. But Ignatieff’s most arresting observation is that in contemporary Canada, it is a rights culture or nothing, no Canada; this state cannot fall back on blood or culture or even common history. In an attempt to understand where events have taken us, the author looks at what recognizing rights actually means for a society. He distills his own concept of “rights” down to four key elements at the end of the book’s second chapter.6 First and most basically, rights mandate limits on the use of force against human beings. Second, rights create reciprocities, which are the bedrock of communities; they express not only individual but also collective values. Third, the supreme value that rights protect is human agency (which he defines as “the capacity of individuals to set themselves goals and to accomplish them as they see fit”7). Because individual agency manifests in uniqueness, not sameness, Ignatieff advocates the “recognition” of difference (as Charles Taylor uses the term), and a focus on reciprocity — that is, on a demonstrated give-and-take between parts of society — rather than on mirror-image identity of treatment. Fourth, rights are not abstractions. They represent the core of a society’s values, as forged by its own unique history and through the efforts of its own ancestors. Each of these observations receives sophisticated treatment in Ignatieff’s hands, but the second one is VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus the most relevant here. In claiming that reciprocal rights are community-creating, Ignatieff disagrees with Mary Ann Glendon, who coined the term “rights talk” and who would set rights and community in opposition to each other.8 Ignatieff argues that rights are not only dynamic themselves, but also have the potential to transform the landscape around them. Rights themselves can be a source of legitimacy and cohesion. By recognizing reciprocal rights, groups can create a particular kind of community, based on a “rights culture,” even where other cultural or historical ties may not pre-exist. That community is based on the principle that all individuals are deliberative equals, that no group may be excluded from the public forum simply by virtue of who its members are, and that the essential strategy and the ultimate goal are both to stay in the room and keep talking, no matter how large our differences may seem. Inevitably the political space of rights cultures will be conflictual and unfinished, but this is not a bad thing. For Ignatieff, the balance that just, pluralistic societies need to seek is one in which there is “just enough collective sense of purpose to resolve these disputes, but not so much as to force individuals into a communitarian straitjacket.”9 In his view, if the goal is to permit human agency and diversity, then this is as much unity as modern life can afford. Ignatieff finds it painful that outsiders do not recognize how significant and how promising the Canadian experiment is. Ours is not the only modern heterogeneous society facing the great challenge of “[reconciling] equality with diversity in an age of entitlement,” 10 but it is one of only a handful trying to do so within a political space so contested that continued national existence is at risk. Moreover, what Ignatieff calls Canada’s civic nationalist rights culture is remarkable for how much weight it gives to both group recognition and individual rights, both equality and human agency. Ignatieff argues compellingly that Canada’s political culture may even be the country’s most distinctive and unifying feature. The truth, however, is that we cannot yet be sure that the Canadian experiment will work here, 517 let alone be instructive to anyone else. Ignatieff has posed the burning question facing us — a hugely significant act — but he has not answered it. It is frustrating that there is so little how in this book. Ignatieff believes, as I do, that equal rights alongside ongoing, respectful dialogue between individuals and groups represent the most promising way forward for the country. We agree that where common history and experience are lacking, equal and reciprocal rights alone cannot create a community, but they can create trust. Yet the concept of equal rights is too vague to ensure an automatic progression to recognition, mutual trust, and community. Respectful dialogue does not just happen. The very least that can be said is that deep diversity, equal rights, and effective public deliberation relate in complicated ways. The next step for Canada has to be more work on the tricky details of turning a rights revolution into the foundation of a satisfying and sustainable community. Some important work already exists: even within the covers of this short book Ignatieff could have pointed to the work going on in the (foreignsounding but not actually that foreign) “civic republican” school of constitutional legal thought, to which his presentation owes a great deal.11 Modern civic republicanism, which emphasizes active citizen participation as a means of creating community and evolving social norms, could be an attractive approach for a country that nearly unravelled for lack of a common vision of itself. I would also have liked to see Ignatieff turn his mind more explicitly to bridging the gap — surely this work is not yet done — between liberalism, republicanism, and the Canadian “multicultural” school of thought with which he also identifies.12 Just as importantly, Ignatieff could have talked about the actual processes by which this rights revolution could be nudged in the direction of respectful community-building dialogue, processes that include ensuring that effective and accessible forums exist for democratic conversations about rights- CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 518 Reviews/Comptes rendus balancing; that public decision-making processes are demonstrably legitimate, accountable, and transparent; and that mechanisms are in place to recognize and build on the successful trust-building strategies that do evolve in practice.13 In truth, so much of the how is working itself out on the ground (or on the Internet or in the myriad other interstices of our networked and decentralized society). To come back to Ignatieff’s starting point, rights-consciousness has transformed the way we interact at every level, and the rights revolution has spilled far beyond the boundaries of the formal political sphere. Now that we have recognized this new reality, our goal must be to develop real-world strategies to channel this rights revolution into a community-building force. If Michael Ignatieff is right about the amount of consensus we can expect in a rights-based pluralistic society, then negotiable, contingent solutions are all we ever had anyway. So what if we are an improbable combination of three founding nations, and we do not always agree about deep things, and our collective destiny is not always manifest to us? It is not the end of history. Since the 1995 Referendum, we Canadians have been making our way back from the brink of disintegration not by grand design, but through an accretion of incremental, pragmatic accommodations by individual people and groups. The rights revolution offers us a renewed opportunity to build a sense of collective identity, as the-ones-whoworked-it-out-together. The hope — optimistic, but far from impossible — is that we can realize through practice what we may only be able to name, with pride, in retrospect: the foundation of a richer, more authentic, and more democratic Canadian community. NOTES 1 I have chosen to emphasize what I see as the book’s primary themes, which are national and political in orientation. At least one commentator has discussed the book’s international human rights themes in some depth: see Andres Kahar, “Michael Ignatieff’s Surprising Habits,” Peace Magazine (April/June 2001). At <http:// www.peacemagazine.org/0104/kahar.htm>. Ignatieff also CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, devotes the whole fourth of his five chapters to considering the effect of the rights revolution on the “private” sphere of the family, where Canadians continue to struggle with the balance between the personal drive toward “authenticity,” respect for others, and respect for the family as a unit. While it is gratifying to see the sphere of the family incorporated into this argument, the chapter is primarily an illustration, in a parallel factual context, of themes developed earlier in the book. 2 Even if some of these thinkers might not do so themselves, Ignatieff offers the idea that one could speak of a “Canadian school of rights thought” that includes Will Kymlicka, Charles Taylor, James Tully, Peter Russell, Stéphane Dion, and Guy Laforest. Ignatieff correctly identifies his heavy debt to Kymlicka, in particular Will Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (1995), and also to Charles Taylor, The Politics of Recognition, Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Amy Gutmann, ed. 1994). 3 Ignatieff, supra note 1 at 116. 4 Ignatieff, supra note 1 at 126. 5 See Jeff Jacoby, “The Unbearable Lightness of Being Canadian,” Boston Globe Frontpage Magazine, 20 April 2000. At <http://216.247.220.66/jacoby/2000/ jj04-21-00.htm>. 6 The fact that the author chose not to be more precise, earlier, about the term “rights” also makes the book slower going than it otherwise would be. For example, in a single chapter he talks about the tension between rights and democracy; about rights as indications of what we as citizens value; and about rights as the positive and negative entitlements citizens can lay claim to from the state. Ignatieff also weighs group and individual rights against each other at times as though they were comparable units of measurement and not, as some people believe, altogether different things. (None of this includes human rights, which he treats separately and at length by way of moving examples from international and refugee law and the history of war crimes.) There is something to be said for under-defining arguably over-theorized ideas, not only when lecturing on a radio show. Yet for those who have been trained to recognize each of his observations as shorthand for entirely separate conversations, the effect is disorienting. More importantly for his general audience, which may not have tried to reconcile equality with diversity from this perspective before, the result is a somewhat unwieldy “backpack” concept of rights to have to carry around. 7 Ignatieff, supra note 1 at 23. VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus 8 Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse, 1991. 9 Ignatieff, supra note 1 at 34. 10 Ignatieff, supra note 1 at 138. 11 This American school of political theory has nothing to do with either the political party of the same name, or the governmental structure that may be distinguished from constitutional monarchies like Canada’s. Modern civic republicanism’s fundamental assertion is that highly participatory political deliberation is indispensable to a well-functioning democracy. Like Ignatieff, the republicans emphasize a “romantic” view of human agency and the relationship between human agency and evolving public norms. “Active citizenship” is crucial as a means for ensuring that peoples’ rights are observed and for emancipating marginalized groups. Political participation is also intrinsically valuable, both because it demonstrates respect and recognition of the participants, and because inclusion produces bonds of community. Modern republicans assert that the respectful interaction of communities and individuals allows social norms to evolve and community to be created even where it does not pre-exist. In other words, they believe that democratic deliberation is what Frank Michelman calls “jurisgenerative.” Frank I. Michelman, Law’s Republic, 97 Yale L.J. (1988) 1493, 1495. See also Richard K. Dagger, Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism (1997); Cass R. Sunstein, Beyond the Republican Revival, 97 Yale L.J. (1988) 1539, 1566-71. On republicanism’s relevance to Canadian constitutional evolution, see Janet Ajzenstat and Peter J. Smith, Liberal-Republicanism: The Revisionist Picture of Canada’s Founding, in Canada’s Origins: Liberal, Tory, or Republican? ed. Janet Ajzenstat and Peter J. Smith (Ottawa: Carleton University Press, 1995). 12 The debates between liberals, civic republicans, and “multiculturalists” is beyond the scope of this review. Each school disagrees with the others on issues of varying magnitude; for example, Kymlicka’s main issue with republican 519 citizenship is that it is not neutral as between different cultural groups; see, for example, “Liberal Egalitarianism and Civic Republicanism: Friends or Enemies?” in Debating Democracy’s Discontent: Essays on Politics, Law and Public Philosophy, ed. Anita Allen and Milton Regan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), pp. 131-48. 13 Ignatieff observes that rights-balancing conversations in Canada traditionally have taken place in the courts, but I am not convinced that courts are the only, or the best, institutions for dealing with disputes of this scope and significance. My views are expressed in Cristie L. Ford, In Search of the Qualitative Clear Majority: Democratic Experimentalism and the Quebec Secession Reference, 39:2 Alberta Law Review 511 (Oct. 2001). In that article, I attempt to integrate direct democratic deliberation with the enforcement of constitutional norms in the context of the Quebec secession debate. I argue that, rather than attempting another referendum, the debate over Quebec’s future needs to be re-oriented by reference to the normative framework set out by the Supreme Court of Canada in the Secession Reference, combined with a renewed democratic process. In describing that renewed democratic process, I incorporate a non-Canadian constitutional model called “democratic experimentalism,” which proposes concrete mechanisms for ensuring legitimacy, participation, and accountability within heterogeneous, complex democratic systems. My conclusion is that democratic experimentalism is compatible with Canada’s constitutional values and traditions, and with the notion, emerging from the Secession Reference, of creating a “clear qualitative majority.” Creating the clear qualitative majority, as I have defined it, is precisely an act of community-building through ongoing and respectful democratic dialogue. CRISTIE L. FORD, Attorney, Davis, Polk & Wardwell, New York, and 2000–2001 Lecturer in Law, Columbia University School of Law CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 520 Reviews/Comptes rendus Toward a New Mission Statement for Canadian Fiscal Federalism edited by Harvey Lazar. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2000. Pp. xxii, 428. $24.95. The intersection of the set of people interested in fiscal federalism and those not yet jaded with talk about “mission statements” is probably very small, so one wonders about the choice of title for this book. In fact, of the 14 chapters in the book probably only two (those written by the editor and presumed title chooser) have much to do with mission statements. Rather, the book is another in the series of useful reviews of the state of the Canadian federation provided by Queen’s Institute of Intergovernmental Relations. The papers in the book fall into three categories: reviews of recent developments and recaps of current thinking; contributions by members of the “Queen’s school” of fiscal federalism — scholars who advocate a return to a more centralized and redistributive federation; and one innovative policy proposal. Topics in the first category include a review of economics literature (Boadway), and a recap of the transfer renewal of 1999 (Boucher and Vermaeten). Other papers discuss “small” transfer programs (Vaillancourt), recent trends in provincial taxation (Hale), provincial-local finance (Kitchen), and fiscal relations with Aboriginal governments (Prince and Abele). Rounding out the category are a comparison of Canada with other federations (Watts) and an invaluable chronology of events for 1998–99 (Garfin and Arsenault). The “Queen’s school” of fiscal federalism is ably represented in the second category. Harvey Lazar, in addition to his long introduction as editor, considers the impact of the Social Union Framework CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, Agreement on future fiscal relations. Norrie and Wilson defend the status quo of large federal cash transfers to provinces against the realignment of tax fields. Hobson and St. Hilaire argue against recent moves to reduce the amount of interprovincial redistribution inherent in the CHST and for the need for new mechanisms to increase the overall level of interprovincial redistribution. Osberg advocates a greater federal role in interpersonal redistribution. The final category contains a single paper. Bird and Mintz address the often neglected area of provincial-local fiscal relations with an innovative proposal for a “business value tax.” So what about the “mission statement”? At this stage in our history, Canadians do seem to lack a sense of overall purpose or direction for our country. Provinces have been able to construct a broad consensus for action from time to time — for example, the consensus on the need to eliminate deficits in many provinces in the 1990s. However, such a consensus has proven elusive at the federal level. Lacking a “mission” for the country, it is not surprising that we don’t have one for fiscal federalism. Who should read this book? Only the most ardent student of fiscal federalism would want to read the whole volume. Those who believe that Canada needs more federal-government-led redistribution and attending centralization will find the book comforting. More importantly, the review articles (and associated references) will provide all students of fiscal federalism with a valuable reference tool to guide their study of this important part of Canadian public policy. PAUL BOOTHE, Department of Economics, University of Alberta VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus Merger Mania: The Assault on Local Government by Andrew Sancton. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2000. Pp. 183. $24.95. Commissioned by the mayor of Westmount to provide a context for Montreal’s restructuring debate, Merger Mania will be read with interest long after the resolution of that debate. The book surveys recurring waves of forced local mergers in Canada — chiefly in Manitoba, Ontario, Quebec, and Nova Scotia. It also discusses similar experiences in the United Kingdom, Australia, New Zealand, and parts of continental Europe. This record is contrasted with the American experience, in which a century has passed since the last significant municipal amalgamation. Theoretical discussion is included where relevant. On occasion, Westmount’s agenda surfaces abruptly. For example, the chapter “Municipal Amalgamation in the United States, 1854–1942” contains a detailed chronology of annexations by the City of Montreal. The apparent purpose here is to confront Quebec readers with parallels as they arise, rather than rely on them to await a later chapter. Nonetheless, the prominence accorded to Montreal is no distraction overall — given the importance of that city region. When Merger Mania was published, the Montreal restructuring outcome was still uncertain; the Quebec government has since decided on amalgamated city status for the island of Montreal. Westmount is to become an internal arondissement (a borough without staff or taxing power). The book’s analysis of contrasting Canadian and American experiences is especially interesting. American municipalities have no special protection under the US Constitution, but have gained that protection anyway in many state constitutions. These constitutions, which are not easily amended, limit 521 the actions of state legislatures even in fields where the federal Constitution gives them free rein. As an aside to Sancton’s discussion of state constitutions, one could note that voters have used them to create a variety of tamper-resistant enactments. Examples include limitations on property tax assessments (California, Oregon) and urban growth boundaries (Portland region). Sancton observes that even in states without constitutional barriers to municipal mergers, state governments have avoided mergers because they would provoke new constitutional amendments to make them unconstitutional. American cities, suburbs, and counties have assurance they will not be merged against their will. A corollary is that the system appears overly rigid when it comes to setting up regional governments. Still, secure status for municipalities seems to encourage voluntary regional cooperation. Such cooperation may in turn make constitutional rigidity a less serious concern. In Canada, municipalities can be merged or dissolved on provincial whim, causing local insecurity in provinces where this power is used. Regional government systems can readily be created, but their value is compromised by municipal strategic behaviour aimed at reducing the other tier’s relative importance, a by-product of insecurity. Ontario’s two-tier system exemplifies these characteristics, and will be the primary focus of what follows below. Although regional government in Ontario had a promising start in the 1950s, Sancton offers a telling comment on its eventual evolution: The phrase “the status quo is not an option” has become a great cliché of our time ... With respect to regional governments in Ontario, the cliché happens to be true. Although two-tier regional government has its inherent problems, it is not completely unworkable. What is unworkable is a CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 522 Reviews/Comptes rendus system in which each tier has equal political status and in which each is at risk of being abolished (Merger Mania, p. 2). questions regarding this model, and suggests that it would be more difficult to apply if more than two municipalities were to be created. In May 2001, Ontario Municipal Affairs Minister Chris Hodgson met with the regional chair and mayors in Waterloo Region. He was there to advise them of a policy shift: the status quo is an option, at least for them and at least for now. Apparently the same message has been conveyed to the other surviving regional municipalities. Both the Haldimand-Norfolk and regionwide amalgamation models end the squabbling between tiers — by eliminating two-tier government itself. It remains to be seen whether the problems associated with these solutions amount to a cure worse than the disease and whether other workable models can be devised. Strategic behaviour is unlikely to end as a result of this policy shift, the permanence of which cannot be determined. Each tier of government has an incentive to spend more than necessary, given that the province has routinely cited the regions’ higher spending share to justify amalgamation at that level. To the extent that savings from regionwide amalgamations do materialize, the likely source is elimination of this aspect of the Ontario two-tier model. Leaving aside British Columbia and other provinces which have intervened with restraint — thus approximating the American model’s results informally — the experience described in Merger Mania raises an intriguing question. Would Canadian city regions be better off had there been provincial constitutions protecting municipalities from forced mergers? Not so long ago, any local government model with American origins would have been dismissed summarily in this country. However, dramatic revitalization of some US cities is lessening this superiority complex. While alternatives to regionwide amalgamation have been proposed in Ontario, and in one case implemented, regional services are difficult to subdivide once they have already been unified. If they are to remain unified, an agency to deliver them has to replace the regional government. Sancton notes that whatever such a proposed agency is called (e.g., services board), the proposal will be criticized as essentially semantic and not necessarily an improvement over the status quo. In the one case where a regional municipality was restructured without regionwide amalgamation (the former Haldimand-Norfolk, now Haldimand and Norfolk), the regional administration and its lower tier municipalities were regrouped into two singletier counties. Some regional services were subdivided, others are delivered by one county to the other, and police services came under the oversight of a joint board. Sancton notes some unanswered CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, The rationale for provincial intervention power is that it can improve city regions in ways not achievable by voluntary local cooperation. Several provinces have used this power extensively, but any resulting improvements are difficult to document — whether in comparison with other provinces or in comparison with a non-intervention scenario. At best, perhaps, recent interventions have mitigated problems created by earlier interventions. Meanwhile, transition costs have amounted to hundreds of millions of dollars, and never-ending debate has diverted energy from more fundamental problems. Anyone reading Merger Mania is likely to learn a great deal. We may regard it as part of the considerable legacy the City of Westmount is leaving behind. PETER TOMLINSON, University of Toronto VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus A State of Minds: Toward a Human Capital Future for Canadians by Thomas J. Courchene. Montreal: The Institute for Research on Public Policy (IRPP), 2001. Pp. xiv, 323. $24.95. In A State of Minds, Thomas J. Courchene draws on the breadth of his professional expertise to argue that globalization and the knowledge/information revolution — GIR in Courchene-speak — are producing a new global order. To stay prosperous, Courchene asserts, “Canada and Canadians must make the transition from a resource- and physicalcapital-based economy and society” to a humancapital-based one. Governance, social safety net, taxation, and other policies are recommended to speed the transformation. Courchene’s arguments often echo those of other socio-economic pundits such as Lester Thurow. However, Courchene adds details and speculative insights on Canadian development. The private sector in Canada is pictured as increasingly international and competitive, while the public sector is viewed as non-competitive, at the national level at least, and plagued by shrinking taxation options in a footloose GIR world. However, Courchene sees the subnational governments as benefiting from the discipline of “competitive federalism.” As examples of competitive federalism, Courchene cites Quebec for leadership in family policy and daycare, Ontario for early childhood development initiatives, and Alberta and Ontario for important personal and business income tax program initiatives, respectively. Courchene worries about the future of Canada. He writes, for instance, that: “We tend to downplay the fact that Canadian productivity lags the US by noting that the significant lag occurs only in two related industries — computers and informationrelated areas. But this is the new economy!” Courchene also asserts that there is an important difference between the American and Canadian concepts of interpersonal equity. He argues that the essence of the 523 American dream is the notion of upward mobility or the opportunity to have a better tomorrow. Courchene writes, “if most Canadians are like me, they are astounded by the degree to which apparently ‘down and out’ Americans remain committed to their system. I used to chalk this up to the more overt nationalism of the Americans and their melting-pot indoctrination of their citizenry. However, I have come to the view that ... the American notions of equity and income distribution are viewed temporally, not at any given point in time. The essence of the American dream is the notion of upward mobility, or the opportunity to have a better tomorrow. This feeds into other aspects we associate with the Americans. For one thing, Americans, much more than Canadians, tend to celebrate their entrepreneurs and success stories.” In contrast, Courchene claims “Canadians are more concerned with static or point-in-time income distribution.” He goes on to point out that Canada has put in place transfer payment and tax incentives that almost force citizens to focus on a static concept of income distribution. In my opinion, markets deliver rewards and punishments reflecting short-run information and vision. However, human dreams, pride and bonds of love for family, friends, profession, community, and country can provide longer term rewards, including incentives for risk-sharing. Courchene implies that the US may have superior institutions and traditions for fostering the long-term incentives and balancing these with the market incentives. Courchene is effective in stimulating thought on creating Canada’s advantage in the years to come. He neither really claims to be, nor is, effective at marshalling statistical or institutional evidence to back up his recommendations. For instance, on the American Dream, Courchene notes that the “dream” may be “more myth than reality” and that myths can matter regardless of their factual basis. However, the only references he makes to empirical evidence CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 524 Reviews/Comptes rendus on this point are to a year 2000 article in the International Herald Tribune. A State of Minds by Thomas J. Courchene is an IRPP volume that is worth reading and will hopefully be followed by other volumes and articles that offer consideration of the relevant evidence. There is CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, relevant evidence that would strengthen some of Courchene’s points and lead to a reconsideration of others. ALICE N AKAMURA, School of Business, University of Alberta VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus A State of Minds: Toward a Human Capital Future for Canadians by Thomas J. Courchene. Montreal: The Institute for Research on Public Policy (IRPP), 2001. Pp. xiv, 323. $24.95 A State of Minds is about Canada’s place in the new global economy of the twenty-first century. The new global economy is comprised of a trilogy of interactive forces that include globalization, trade liberalization, and the information technology and communications revolution. The author focuses his attention on two of those paramount economic forces of the twenty-first century — globalization and the revolution in information technology. This book is an articulate contribution to the academic and public debate about the challenges and opportunities for Canadian public policy in the new global economy. It provides a succinct argument for developing the mindset and providing the leadership and vision to transform Canada’s old economy with its strong natural resource base and adjacent industrial sector toward the new economy of information, communications, and knowledge-based industries. The central thesis of the book is captured in one sentence “Design a sustainable, socially inclusive and internationally competitive infrastructure that ensures equal opportunity for all Canadians to develop, to enhance, and to employ in Canada their skills and human capital, thereby enabling them to become full citizens in the informationera Canadian and global societies.” The book explores the linkages that will provide economic growth and social cohesion in Canada during the information age. More specifically, the author addresses the multidimensional policy issues involved in attaining Canada’s social and economic goals such as early childhood education, federal-provincial relations, tax policy, and income distribution. A State of Minds promotes the thesis that the preeminent objective of Canadian public policy in the twenty-first century should be the creation of knowledge and human capital. It argues convincingly for a massive investment in education and the need to 525 hold on to a highly skilled workforce. The author summarizes his vision in the following manner: “Overseeing all this, must be a state that recognizes its role as a knowledge and information intermediary — the organization of bureaucracy must shift away from the previous industrial production system, and toward a human capital production system.” However, the complexities of the brain drain are dealt with fleetingly. Furthermore, the proposal to lower income taxes and shift the burden of fiscal revenue to consumer taxes such as the GST as a means of curbing the exodus of our young and highly educated Canadians requires a more detailed analysis and further intellectual debate. The book emphasizes the need for public policy to acknowledge and implement the complementarity between economic policy and social policy. The decades of the 1970s and 1980s saw the development of economic policy and social policy on two different tracks that crossed very infrequently. The financial restraints and fiscal deficits of the 1990s forced governments to rethink the isolation of economic policy and social policy. However, this was done at the expense of social policy as funding and programs were cut to a bare minimum. The author provides a convincing argument for acknowledging the interdependence of economic policy and social policy in the twenty-first century. The author also discusses the issue of economic competitiveness. In this regard there appears to be a disparity in public policy between Canada’s international and domestic policy initiatives. Canada has taken a leadership role in promoting the benefits of trade liberalization starting with the Free Trade Agreement (FTA) between Canada and the United States, followed by the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA) which embraced a free trade zone between Canada, the US, and Mexico, to the contemporary phase and the pursuit of a Free Trade Agreement of the Americas (FTAA) to include all countries of the northern and southern hemisphere of the Americas except Cuba. This in sharp contrast to serious barriers to the movement of goods and people between provinces on the national economic landscape. CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 526 Reviews/Comptes rendus A State of Minds is a welcome addition to the growing list of recent publications on the new global economy. This book should be of special interest to academics and researchers in the area of economic and social policy. It should be required reading for CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, parliamentarians, legislators, policy wonks, civil servants, and private sector public policy consultants. CONSTANTINE E. PASSARIS, Department of Economics, University of New Brunswick VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus Opportunity and Uncertainty: Life Course Experiences of the Class of ’73 by Paul Anisef, Paul Axelrod, Etta BaichmanAnisef, Carl James and Anton Turrittin in collaboration with Fred Ashbury, Gottfried Paasche and Zeng Lin. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000. Pp. ix, 327. $24.95. The authors of this book report on an extensive 21year longitudinal study of the Class of 1973. The panel consists of a group of “late baby-boomers,” first contacted when they were in grade 12 classes in different regions of Ontario. Life-course and school-to-worktheories (rather than the human capital and status attainment theories that the authors used in previous works) are employed effectively. A sophisticated multimethod approach is used. Analyses at the beginning of the study in the 1970s were based primarily on surveys of over 2,000 members of the Class of ’73. In later stages of the research, follow-up surveys were supplemented with interviews and life-course analyses. In addition, some Canadian data from Statistics Canada and other sources are reported. Quantitative and qualitative results are integrated throughout and add to the richness of the findings. The book consists of an introduction to the Class of ’73, nine chapters, and an appendix on sample attrition. Chapter 1 introduces the two themes used throughout the book: “human agency” and “social structure.” The authors use life-course theory to study the relationship between the individual and the social order at both micro and macro levels. The world of grade 12 students in 1973 and changes in the Ontario school system are described in Chapter 2. Chapter 3 analyzes the educational trajectories of members of the Class of ’73 — focusing on the three main pathways of the panel: (i) directly into the labour market, (ii) to community colleges, and (iii) to university. Chapter 4 looks at the world of employment as experienced by the Class of ’73. The workplace that 527 the Class of ’73 entered was at the beginning of major changes in work and the way organizations were structured. The authors use the “spiral” and “transitory” career concepts of Venne (1996), instead of the traditional career concepts of “steady state” and “linear” due to the changes faced by the panel. The next chapter continues the authors’ examination of employment but turns to social, career, and geographic mobility. Chapter 6 focuses on the experiences of first-generation Canadians. The authors note that “there is little evidence in our data to suggest that being children of foreign-born parents posed any kind of handicap for members of the Class of ’73” (p. 177). Chapter 7 deals with family life. A number of changes in family structure are noted, but the importance of families to the Class of ’73 is evident. Chapter 8 is unique, containing five biographies of members of the Class of ’73. Chapter 9 provides the conclusion. The title Opportunity and Uncertainty is used to convey the dual nature of the future that the Class of ’73 faced in 1973: opportunities in a strong economy and dynamic postsecondary education system, but uncertainty, because of the changes underway in education, work, social norms, and the economy. Their uncertainty was justified: the authors note that by 1995 the members of the Class of ’73 had held an average of four full-time jobs. But there were many opportunities as well, for example, “overall, the respondents appeared to enjoy their work, with women enjoying a slight edge in job satisfaction” (p. 109). REFERENCE Venne, R.A. 1996. “Demographic and Career Issues Relating to Youth in Transition to Adulthood,” in Youth in Transition, Perspectives on Research and Policy, ed. B. Galaway and J. Hudson. Toronto: Thompson Educational Publishing, pp. 46-52. FREDERICK T. EVERS, Department of Sociology and Anthropology, University of Guelph CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 528 Reviews/Comptes rendus Northern Edge: How Canadians Can Triumph in a Global Economy by Thomas P. D’Aquino and David StewartPatterson. Toronto: Stoddart, 2001. Pp. 331. $37.95. The postwar synthesis of international economic liberalism and growing Keynesian welfare states helped to shape an intellectual and institutional framework for simultaneously promoting economic growth, distributive justice, social cohesion, and political stability throughout much of the industrialized world. This “embedded liberalism” has shaped public expectations of both the role and limits of government. At the same time, trends toward globalization have undermined the capacity of nation-states to pursue these goals without adapting their policy instruments and approaches to build a political consensus that responds effectively to the new realities. Northern Edge, by Thomas D’Aquino and David Stewart-Patterson of the Business Council on National Issues (BCNI), directly addresses the challenges of reconciling and promoting both economic growth and social cohesion in a twenty-first century update of the Keynesian compact. This book is the outcome of the BCNI’s “Global Leadership Initiative” — an internal consensus-building exercise dealing with the implications of current global trends for Canada in the next decade. The authors go well beyond the normal range of business concerns to address the social, human, and political implications of global trends in ways that come to terms with contemporary Canadian political realities. Indeed, much of their rhetoric is quite consistent with the recent speeches of Paul Martin, John Manley, and their senior officials. Any reader looking for a summary of the vaunted “corporate agenda” and the reasoning behind it can find them neatly packaged here. The authors address the issues thematically in seven chapters dealing with the challenges of globalization, priorities for governments, education, and human skills, “competing for talent,” promotCANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, ing innovation, building globally competitive companies, and foreign policy priorities. They argue that, whatever past successes, Canadians cannot afford to be complacent in a world of constant economic change, migrating capital, footloose corporate executives (including those of their own member companies), and skilled professionals. Increased prosperity depends on more than successful economic policy. It also requires a social consensus rooted in a widespread distribution of economic benefits and opportunities arising from technological change and entrepreneurial dynamism. To achieve either goal, policies intended to promote economic growth and social cohesion must be mutually reinforcing. Only a rapidly growing economy can pay for the maintenance and improvement of Canada’s aging welfare state. Enhancing and expanding access to education and needed skills are critical to innovation, productivity, and the capacity of citizens and workers to adjust to continuing economic change. Balancing these goals in a democratic society requires the active and responsible participation of governments, business, and citizens in a healthy, diverse, and autonomous civil society that gives citizens a sense of community and belonging alien to large, bureaucratic institutions or impersonal market forces. While Tom Courchene covers much of the same ground with a comparable outlook in his recent book, A State of Minds, D’Aquino and Stewart-Patterson provide a greater depth and detail of research and analysis. As a result, Northern Edge often reads like a compilation of literature reviews on topical policy issues. General readers may find it a hard slog. Policy specialists may choose to argue with particular emphases or omissions. However, it provides a useful service in linking different aspects of social and economic policy that are often discussed in relative isolation within a coherent intellectual framework that demonstrates the relevance of economic, social, and cultural factors to a broader view of human wellbeing and the public interest. The policy ideas outlined in Northern Edge reflect a healthy dose of self-interest, not least in VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus advocating wide-ranging negotiations for deeper North American economic integration. Their ultimate credibility will depend largely on the willingness of business leaders to back up their words with action by investing in innovation, education, train- 529 ing, and community development — in other words, in people. GEOFFREY H ALE, Department of Political Science, University of Lethbridge CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 530 Reviews/Comptes rendus Independence and Economic Security in Old Age edited by Frank T. Denton, Deborah Fretz and Byron G. Spencer. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press, 2000. Pp. vii, 380. $29.95. The editors of this valuable book, all economists at McMaster University, are leading researchers on the nature and implications of population aging in Canada. Yet, Independence and Economic Security in Old Age is about much more than economics and demographics. In fact, the book is as much about the aging process within and across generations as it is about the current elderly population in Canada. With a multidisciplinary cast of authors, this volume will be of interest to academics, advocates, and practitioners in economics, to be sure, but also in the fields of gerontology, sociology, social work, public policy, and women’s studies. In addition to the inevitable statistics on demographic projections, dependency ratios, and population age pyramids several chapters in the book contain qualitative research based on focus groups, literature reviews, and conceptual analysis. A number of chapters highlight the important role of social values, societal expectations, and public assumptions with respect to retirement, personal savings, and the division of care-giving roles and responsibilities within families. As its title suggests, the book examines the personal independence and economic security of the elderly population in Canada. The focus is on both today’s and tomorrow’s seniors which, in certain chapters, spans four cohorts. Personal independence is thoughtfully examined and interpreted as a contested, multi-dimensional and relative concept. Major determinants of independence include economic resources, health and functional ability, and the social and physical environment. All three determinants are addressed in the book, though the greatest attention is devoted to the issue of adequacy of financial resources. CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, Questions examined in the volume include: Is 65 still a reasonable definition for old age for the purpose of eligibility for various public and private benefits? How much aging of the Canadian population is likely over the next 30 years? What factors lead to involuntary retirement and what consequences are there for individuals and their families? Several chapters contain a significant gender analysis, in particular, addressing the economic status of older women, present and future. The gender analysis relates to a question that implicitly runs through most of the chapters, which is: What should be the balance between personal and collective responsibility for income security for Canada’s aging population? What of the future of economic security in old age? Carolyn J. Rosenthal and her associates conclude that it appears each successive cohort of older women will enter its retirement years in a stronger financial position that the earlier cohorts, in light of higher participation rates in the labour market, job-related pensions, and RRSPs. Yet, they also conclude that most of tomorrow’s older women, like today’s, will not be financially secure in later life unless they are married. Several other authors in the collection warn that any further move away from collective responsibility to personal responsibility for retirement preparations — that is, further cuts to the Old Age Security or to the Canada Pension Plan — would likely result in an increase in economic insecurity and poverty among Canada’s elderly. This is the most fundamental social policy lesson from this significant book. Contrary to our selfcongratulatory rhetoric, poverty among today’s seniors has not been eliminated. Many seniors, especially retired widows, continue to live in precarious and straitened circumstances financially. If we are not thoughtful and take action, poverty among seniors may actually experience a boom among the aging boomers. MICHAEL J. PRINCE , Lansdowne Professor of Social Policy, University of Victoria VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001 Reviews/Comptes rendus Beyond the Nass Valley: National Implications of the Supreme Court’s Delgamuukw Decision edited by Owen Lippert. Vancouver: The Fraser Institute, 2000. Pp. xvi, 544. The Supreme Court handed down the Delgamuukw decision in December 1997. The Fraser Institute held two conferences, the first in July 1998 and the second in April 1999, to help assess the national significance of that decision. This book contains the papers presented at those two events along with an edited transcript of some of the discussions. Lippert divides the book into eight main parts: (i) basics of decision, (ii) impact in British Columbia, (iii) impact in Alberta, Saskatchewan, and Manitoba, (iv) impact in Ontario, (v) impact in Quebec, (vi) impact in the Maritimes, (vii) overall economic impact, and (viii) a final part entitled “All Still Here and All Looking Ahead.” Notably absent from this line-up is any assessment of the impact of the decision in the three northern territories. The volume contains 28 papers of varying lengths and quality. There are lots of essays by lawyers, both academic (Slattery, McNeil, Henderson, Zlotkin, and Monahan) and practising (Howard, Joffe, Lowes, Lutes, McDonald, Plant, Roberston, Bud Smith and Mel Smith, Strother, Tyler, Woodward, and Wilkins). Thankfully, there are other disciplines and perspectives represented here with contributions from political scientists (Flanagan and Tenant), historians (McNab), anthropologists (Tanner and von Gernet), columnists (Cayo and Gibson), a pollster (Bricker) and an economist (Lippert). Some of the essays are well footnoted and referenced (Wilkins, von Gernet, and Joffe are especially useful) while others are unsupported (e.g., Cayo’s essay focusing on the economic and social realities of First Nations or Mel Smith’s two contributions). Despite the volume’s title, the contributions are not always centred on the implications of Delgamuukw. Sometimes this is useful as in Joffe’s efforts to locate Delgamuukw in the broader context of both international human rights law and the court’s decision in the Quebec Secession Reference. On other occasions, as in Gibson’s 531 two contributions, the result is a panegyric to liberal individualism and an assessment of all that is wrong with the treaty-making process in British Columbia, while Howard treats us to an unfocused survey of everything from analytical positivism to the CLS movement. There is much that is predictable in this volume, once you know the authors’ backgrounds and other writings but there were some surprises too. For example, I was encouraged to read Bud Smith’s assessment (former attorney-general in British Columbia) that Delgamuukw is here to stay and that we should just get on with “the everunfinished tasks of building our community” and the apparent willingness of Gordon Gibson and Chief Herb George to engage in a dialogue (they talk but do they hear each other?). Notwithstanding the authors’ varied backgrounds, there are some common themes and even areas of agreement. Not surprisingly there is universal agreement that Delgamuukw was an important decision for the court. Some want to describe it as an “audacious departure” (Mel Smith) in an effort to undermine its authority and to support the charge that the Court has exceeded its adjudicatory role and trespassed on the legislative function. Others (mainly the legal academics, but also Bud Smith) emphasize how rooted the decision is in existing precedents (especially St. Catherine’s Milling) and how the Court was merely drawing out, in a logical way, the implications of existing lines of decisions. There is also substantial agreement (somewhat paradoxically given the importance of the decision) as to how little the Court actually decided here. After all, it did not decide that the Gitskan and Wet’suwet’en First Nations had an Aboriginal title; the case has gone back to trial on this point with guidance offered as to how to evaluate the evidence, especially the oral history evidence led by the plaintiffs. Similarly, the Court did not reject the self-government claims of the plaintiffs although it did say that they needed to be framed less globally if they were to succeed. The participants in the two conferences also agreed that Delgamuukw was of national signifi- CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE P OLITIQUES, VOL . XXVII, NO . 4 2001 532 Reviews/Comptes rendus cance and should not be confined to British Columbia. First, and most obviously, the decision applies to those parts of Canada where there have been no treaties (e.g., Labrador) a point made by Tanner but also to those parts of Canada where the treaties did not include land surrenders (the Maritimes) a point made most strongly by Henderson in his review of the Mikmaq treaties. Second, the contributors acknowledge that Delgamuukw will also influence the judicial approach to the so-called numbered treaties of the Prairies with their blanket extinguishment clauses. In the main this will flow from the Court’s instruction to trial judges to give appropriate weight to oral histories. This will require that courts ascertain the extent to which the written text of the treaties properly reflects the agreement between the parties. Some, such as Flanagan, seem to have little sympathy for this approach, while others such as Zlotkin welcome it, or at least (Tyler), recognize its inevitability. Themes running through the volume include property rights, the negotiation vs. litigation debate and compensation questions. Property was a central feature of the Delgamuukw litigation. Some of the authors (e.g., McNeil and Slattery) chose to emphasize the legal protections that flow from the Court’s recognition of Aboriginal title. The title will bind the world, can be vindicated in competition with that of the province, and will serve to found a claim to compensation if interfered with by government. For these authors, property is a set of entitlements and a space within which Aboriginal governments may develop. Others choose to emphasize what they see as the negative economic implications of Delgamuukw. Flanagan refers to this as “an awkward duplication of property rights” (p. 180) while Lippert decries the idea of sui generis property rights (p. 407) and thinks that, from an eco- CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, nomic perspective, it would have been better if the Court had recognized an individual fee simple entitlement. Gibson, not surprisingly, advocates a similar approach to treaty settlements. Despite the plea for negotiation with which Chief Justice Lamer concluded his judgement, the general consensus of the commentators represented here is that, at least in the short run, the result of Delgamuukw will be more litigation. In part this is because we simply need more guidance from the courts in concrete cases on a range of issues: proof of Aboriginal title versus rights; the circumstances under which actual consent will be required and not just consultation; and the circumstances under which compensation will be payable and the calculation of that compensation. In part it will be because (and this has turned out to be a major driver) provincial governments will not extend the benefits of the Delgamuukw duty to consult unless and until First Nations obtain a declaration of title. The volume’s production values are generally high, but the editing is not of a uniform quality. Lippert’s own introductory essay contains a number of obvious errors, for example, Treaty 8 does not “cover” Alberta (p. 6), and it is awkward to describe the same treaty as applying to “the lower eastern part” of British Columbia (p. 5) — perhaps a treaty map would have helped! For inexplicable reasons, Henderson’s essay is replete with typographical and grammatical glitches. But these are relatively minor detractions from a useful volume that, while lacking any agreed public policy prescriptions, offers considerable diversity of views on a series of important questions. NIGEL BANKES, Faculty of Law, University of Calgary VOL. XXVII , NO . 4 2001