Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages Not Quite Supreme: The Courts and Coordinate Constitutional Interpretation by Dennis Baker. Montreal and Kingston: McGillQueen’s University Press, 2010, 219 pp. While Canadians have expressed interest in an enlivened legislative branch in Canadian politics, they continue to display a consistent, almost fawning deference to the courts as authoritative interpreters of constitutional writ. Assisted by media, legal, and academic elites, they accept as orthodoxy not simply that courts have a primary and natural role in applying the text of the Constitution, but that courts have an exclusive authority to do so. Dennis Baker’s thoughtful and tightly argued book offers a way to understand this paradox. Part of the answer, Baker argues, rests in our understanding of the nature of the Canadian Constitution. Most people coming of age in the Trudeau era identify the Constitution with the Charter. The Charter is about rights, and rights are the claims that persons make against state power they consider illegitimate. Courts are considered the obvious forums for the vindication of these rights. After all, the state is often a party to legal disputes, and the courts are an independent branch of government structured to challenge the overreaching of the others. And indeed the other branches cannot be counted on to resist one another because in the Canadian parliamentary scheme, the executive and legislature are fused. Executive domination is the watchword. The courts are our only hope for the vindication of rights. What follows from the fusion of powers is judicial supremacy. Baker finds judicial supremacy both wrong and dangerous. His book is a trenchant argument for a coordinate Canadian constitutionalism according to which all branches of government are equal in constitutional status and possess “partial agency” (that is, a share in the power principally allocated to other branches) to challenge the decisions of other branches (pp. 4-5). The paradigmatic example is found in sections 53 and 54 of the Constitution Act, 1867, concerning money bills. The legislature 401 cannot introduce legislation concerning the raising or spending of money; only the executive can do this. But each branch has determining power over the budget. The executive may often dominate the House of Commons and Senate, but it still must secure their approval and on occasion is denied it. Canada does have a true separation of powers, Baker insists. The problem is a lazy behaviouralism that formalizes as constitutional reality observations about informal practice. On the contrary, Baker argues (here relying upon Harvey Mansfield’s work on political executives), it is the interaction of informal and formal power that is the stuff of modern constitutionalism (Chapter 4). Institutions and their forms matter; they are what informal practice pushes against but never occludes. If Canada has a true separation of powers, then judicial supremacy is illegitimate. In its place Baker inserts coordinate constitutional interpretation. There ought to be no interpretive monopolies in Canada. Baker cites R. v. O’Connor (1995) in which a 5-4 majority of the Supreme Court ruled that a priest accused of sexual assault had a Charter right to access the complainant’s confidential counselling records so he could make a full and fair defence to the charge. Parliament then passed a new law based on the dissenting judges’ view, giving the privacy rights of victims a wider berth. When the Court eventually heard a constitutional challenge to the new law in R. v. Mills (1999), it had to decide essentially between its own 1995 precedent and the view of the dissenters in 1995, now backed by the will of Parliament. It chose the latter, illustrating for Baker the operation of coordinate constitutional interpretation in a Canadian separation of powers framework. The O’Connor-Mills sequence is heresy for the judicial supremacists who populate the bench and law schools; but for Baker it is the essence of constitutional government. Coordinate interpretation also means that when exercising judicial review, a court shall disregard the effect of the law in the case at hand only. Judicial supremacists hold that if a court invalidates a law, it shall apply to no one else, unless and until an Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010 402 Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages ultimate appeal restores it. For support, Baker refers to Abraham Lincoln’s reaction to Dred Scott (1857). Lincoln did not challenge what the Supreme Court decided in that case; he quarrelled with the extension of that decision to any other case (pp. 108-9). Court decisions bind parties, not branches. Other branches may legitimately disagree with the court’s interpretation of a right. They should be able to engage in a sort of tug-of-war over the interpretation of a right, and eventually a winning interpretation will emerge. This sounds chaotic and unseemly. And it seems to insert into constitutional government a crude majoritarianism. But Baker aptly reminds us that high courts also decide by majoritarian means: at the end of deliberations and after the circulation of drafts of opinions, it all comes to a vote. In a 5-4 or 6-3 decision, can we truly distinguish the decision of a coalition of personalities from the pronouncement of the Supreme Court as an institution? The political to and fro of coordinate interpretation helps us to make that distinction. The reader is given a succinct critique of Charter dialogue theory, which had a good run among academics and jurists in the 1990s and was used as a way to assuage critics concerned about a judicial imperium. But dialogue theory still preserves for the courts a monopoly on the interpretation of the Charter. This is no dialogue. Does not the s. 33 notwithstanding clause stand ready to do the work of coordinate interpretation? Baker considers it a dead letter because it is associated with legislative responses to judicial finding of a rights violation, when in fact for coordinate theory whether a law is contrary to a right is the critical question. It is too blunt an instrument for the extended politics of coordinate interpretation, he suggests. I am less sure. Section 33 concerns laws operating notwithstanding other constitutional provisions, not rights. All kinds of rights are protected by the common law, not written constitutional text. And s. 33 is part of the Constitution. How can it be illegitimate? This book invites questions about the larger political framework. For example, what is the relationship between judicial supremacy and judicial appointment? I would say that it promotes the politicization of appointments. Would coordinate interpretation de-politicize appointments? And while Baker concentrates on coordinate interpretation’s effects on rights jurisprudence, how does it work in connection to the division of powers? Is this where coordinate interpretation is a well-accepted practice, as I think it is? If so, is Baker’s main concern the hegemony of rights talk and not the role of courts? These questions arise because the book is short. I look forward to further examinations of the concept of coordinate constitutional interpretation, by Dennis Baker and others. Thomas M.J. Bateman, Political Science, St. Thomas University Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010 Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages Confronting the Shadow Education System: What Government Policies for What Private Tutoring? by Mark Bray. IIEP Policy Forum. UNESCO Publishing, 2009, 132 pp. In his latest book, Confronting the Shadow Education System, Mark Bray examines how the sheer size of the tutoring sector and its role in shaping schooling systems, the rhythms of family life, and the contours of social, economic, and educational inequality have been grossly underestimated by policy-makers. The term shadow education is meaningful. The term connotes not only how supplementary education follows the formal school system, but also how this largely unregulated sector has grown at a staggering rate with little notice from governments, policy-makers, and researchers. In this well-documented book, Mark Bray examines the scale, nature, and implications of the private tutoring sector in a number of countries. Marshalling an impressive array of research, he informs us that in many countries this sector is a multi-billion dollar industry that absorbs a substantial amount of household resources. In several countries an upwards of 50 to 90 percent of school-aged children attend some form of tutoring. The sector includes one-on-one tutoring, as well as supplementary education offered by off-duty teachers, mom and pop operations, and large multinational, Internet, and correspondence corporations. Beyond describing its sheer size and many forms, Bray describes the economic and social impact of the private tutoring sector. On a positive note, private tutoring may boost the performance of struggling and high-achieving students. Tutoring may also provide students with a constructive after-school activity, and tutors with supplemental income. It is conceivable that this sector contributes to economic growth by potentially enhancing language and numeracy skills. 403 Bray also outlines the darker side of the supplementary education sector. In countries with high tutoring rates, the social pressure to pay for supplementary education is enormous. Given the lower wages in some countries, tutoring is a crippling if not prohibited expense. Not surprisingly, national figures show that tutoring participation varies by social class; in some countries tutoring enrolment data also reveal huge rural and urban, gender, and racial and ethnic disparities. If these services give students a competitive advantage, supplementary education may widen social and economic inequalities. Equally problematic are tutoring systems that are married to the formal school system. In some countries teachers who use tutoring to supplement their pay have been known to purposefully withhold critical parts of lessons during the school day to encourage families to pay for their services after school hours. In other countries, initiatives such as No Child Left Behind provide monies for eligible parents to purchase private tutoring. These initiatives have been introduced with little accountability to monitor the efficacy of providers. Bray also notes that funds that are directed at private enterprises divert funds that might be used more efficiently by mainstream public schools. In the last part of the book, Bray identifies possible government responses, and makes important policy recommendations that are sensitive to a range of economic and social conditions. Bray argues that policy-makers need to take into account the SES profiles of students, cultural contexts, and any other important factors. The context of tutoring in the United States, Canada, and Australia for example (countries that tend to encourage tutoring for low achievers) is very different from that of Korea and Japan (where tutoring is more likely to be used by high achievers). In order to assess the types of tutoring that should be encouraged or discouraged, Bray suggests that policy-makers need to consider the nature of the sector and whether tutoring rates vary by income group, gender, ethnicity or race, and location. In the concluding chapter, Bray begins this dialogue Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010 404 Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages by outlining several key monitoring and evaluation “feedback loops” at the individual school level, district level, and national and international levels. to researchers in the fields of education, social and economic change, international trends, comparative research, and inequality. Overall, this book provides an accessible and balanced examination of this burgeoning sector. Beyond policy-makers, this book should be of interest Janice Aurini, Department of Sociology, University of Waterloo Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010 Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages Successful Societies: How Institutions and Culture Affect Health edited by Peter A. Hall and Michèle Lamont. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009. This book is the product of the “successful societies” program at the Canadian Institute for Advanced Research (CIFAR), which comprises a diverse group of social scientists (sociology, political science, history, epidemiology, and psychology) brought together by CIFAR to “think about what defines successful societies and the social conditions that sustain them.” This same organization (formerly known by the acronym CIAR) produced Why Are Some People Healthy and Others Not (Evans, Barer, and Marmor 1994), which was foundational to the population health movement in Canada and internationally. Though the two books are grounded in some of the same empirical observations (e.g., the social gradient in health), Successful Societies effectively builds on the earlier work by incorporating different but complementary disciplinary perspectives and emphases. The stated cross-cutting theme of Successful Societies is to explore the role of institutions and culture in producing (or detracting from) population health. “Institutions and culture” include a range of societal attributes such as administrative structures, social and economic models and programs, and cultural imaginaries (norms), which powerfully influence social relationships/resources and therefore health. Building on Sen’s capabilities theory, health (which is a function of the “wear and tear of daily life”) is viewed as dependent on one’s capacity to effectively negotiate life challenges. This capacity reflects not just material resources but also social resources (e.g., the ability to secure cooperation from others). These resources are not perfectly coupled, as suggested by the increasing number of outliers on the health-wealth graph (i.e., countries for which population health is better/worse than would be expected based on economic circumstances alone; see Evans, Chapter 4). 405 Although the idea that population health is more than economic circumstances is not new (e.g., see Wilkinson and Pickett 2009; World Health Organization 2008), the book effectively exploits diverse “case examples” to explore the role of institutions and culture in explaining such exceptions. For example, Swidler (Chapter 5) contrasts AIDS-related initiatives in Botswana where, despite wealth and capable government, efforts have largely failed; and Uganda, where success in prevention and treatment was achieved despite seemingly unfavourable economic and administrative conditions. The unexpected outcomes are seen as reflecting differences in the match or fit (strong in Uganda; weak in Botswana) between the prevention/treatment initiative—especially the way in which it was implemented—and the existing cultural norms and institutional frameworks. A related theme emphasized throughout the book is the importance of historical/comparative approaches for understanding the determinants of population health, which may be “macro” and “slow-moving” (Hertzman and Siddiqi, Chapter 1); for example, the cultural and institutional attributes of wealthy countries with steep versus shallow social gradients in health, over time periods (eras) bounded by definable events (e.g., the Quiet Revolution in Quebec, discussed by Bouchard in Chapter 7; World War II; or the fall of communism in Europe). This approach has clear research implications: the need for appropriate (long-term, comparable) data and analytic/interpretive tools from a range of disciplines. Certain chapters stand out. The book’s introductory chapter by Hall and Lamont is especially rich, which in some cases undermines subsequent chapters because the main point or best example from the chapter is provided in the introduction. Jenson (Chapter 8) tackles the important question of why—even in the face of scientific consensus— policy change does not always occur. Using as a case example the sanitary reforms in Victorian England, Jenson illustrates how the citizenship regime and its constituent elements (e.g., beliefs Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010 406 Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages about the responsibilities of state, market, families; definitions, both formal and informal, of citizenship) shed light on the implementation and impact of health initiatives. During this era, despite relative scientific consensus about the need to ensure clean water, clean streets, and adequate housing, full implementation of these standards was impossible due to a citizenship regime dominated by a belief in the prominent role of the market for provision of services. There was no incentive, however, for private companies to provide for those who could not pay. Further complicating the matter was the fact that, despite the libertarian flavour of the citizenship regime generally, authoritarian action (e.g., mandatory vaccination) was seen as acceptable for “non-citizens”: that is, for the non-propertyowning poor. Sewell (Chapter 10) provides a balanced, nuanced description of the institutional and cultural changes that accompanied the shift from a state-centric to a neoliberal capitalist paradigm. One of the interesting cultural transformations highlighted is the experience of marginalization among white men with the rise of multiculturalism and the women’s movement, which led many working-class white men in the United States to vote for Reagan, thus facilitating the rise of neoliberalism—a political orientation that in many ways worked against the interests of this demographic group. Although the political and economic circumstances of the neoliberal era engendered many potentially health-damaging processes including anxiety-producing economic volatility, rising income inequality, and decreasing public service provision, Sewell nonetheless concludes that neoliberalism has not directly caused poor population health so much as it has “depress[ed] the extent of improvement” otherwise expected. At its outset the book emphasizes the importance of local circumstances and the fact that there is no single path to success. That said, two general policy implications are evident. First, policies can (often unintentionally) erode social resources. For example, a policy that encourages recipients of unemployment benefits to gather at manpower centres facilitates “precisely the wrong sort of [social] ties,” whereas policies that provide work or training facilitate ties that may lead to employment. Thus, policies should be designed “with an eye to their network dimensions” (Hall and Taylor, Chapter 3). A second policy implication is the need, when designing policy content and implementation, to work within the existing cultural/institutional circumstance to maximize the policy-context fit. The cases presented in the book provide guidance in this regard. Because of the inherent complexity of cultural/institutional circumstances, it is essential to be attuned to the potential unintended consequences of social and economic policy and to incorporate built-in evaluation. References Evans, R.G., M.L. Barer, and T.R. Marmor. 1994. Why Are Some People Healthy and Others Not? The Determinants of Health Populations. New York: Walter de Gruyter. Wilkinson, R. and K. Pickett. 2009. The Spirit Level: Why Equality Is Better for Everyone. London: Penguin Books. World Health Organization. 2008. Closing the Gap in a Generation: Health Equity through Action on the Social Determinants of Health. Final Report of the Commission on the Social Determinants of Health. Geneva: World Health Organization. L indsay M c L aren , Department of Community Health Sciences, University of Calgary Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010 Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages I Do Solemnly Swear: The Moral Obligations of Legal Officials by Stephen Sheppard. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009. The central thesis of this book is that “legal officials ought to carry out their offices according to moral obligations, not just narrowly defined legal rules” (p. xv). In general terms, this is hardly problematic, at least as concerns matters in which the law leaves room for discretion. But the devil is in the details, and I don’t think the author gives the devil quite his due. To be sure, at the outset the author acknowledges that talk about legal officials having moral obligations arouses worry and suspicion across the spectrum of political views and ideologies. However, he does not engage the reasons for these concerns at any length or develop and qualify his thesis to address them. Readers who are worried about legal officials using their office to advance an extralegal vision of justice (i.e., their private or personal vision) will not be comforted by the author’s association of morality and justice and his advocacy of the view that officials ought to “pursue good and noble ends through the power of the law” (p. 189). The author is surely right that “there is no legal protection against tyranny, because laws may always be changed by law” (p. xxiv). However, it may be unreasonable, and perhaps even dangerous, to expect that morality can afford such protection. There are competing moral views that can be brought to bear on just about any given issue: Which among competing views is the official promoting, and by what right? A form of tyranny can also arise when self-righteous legal officials are tempted to subordinate the law to their conception of the just and good. The book covers a daunting number of sources in moral, political, and legal philosophy and a wide variety of cases and examples, from the Salem witch trials to the torture memos. And its thesis encompasses all categories of legal officials, from jailors 407 to judges. Its broad sweep is both a strength and a weakness. In some measure encyclopedic coverage comes at the expense of lack of sustained rigour and depth in the analysis of specific issues, such as ones that divide proponents of legal positivism, realism, natural law, and other legal theories. Similarly, extending the thesis to cover the generic moral obligations of all legal officials means that important differences between categories of officials get short shrift. The question of how moral obligations ought to figure in deliberation has importantly different nuances applied to a judge deciding a case than it does applied to a police officer deciding whether to issue a ticket to someone caught speeding. Given the wide range of literatures covered in the text, it is puzzling that the author gives so little attention to the extensive literature on professional ethics, particularly since this literature deals squarely with his subject matter. Moreover, in its matriculated branches it does so for just about every category of legal official and with reference to traditions, professional bodies, and codes of ethics and conduct specific to each. However, this omission appears to be quite deliberate. In the preface the author laments how “ethical duties have been cabined into special notions in philosophy or limited by professional codes” (p. xvii) and notes with disapproval that “lawyers prefer the safer idea of professional ethics” to “broad and public connotations of duty” (p. xvi). He says little to elaborate these value judgments, but for my part I think there is something reassuring about “limiting” the ethical duties of legal officials to professional codes, which have the merit of being publicly agreed upon, proclaimed, and challengeable (by contrast, “broad and public connotations of duty” hardly seem public at all!). And I don’t think it a bad thing to play it safe when it comes to the latitude we allow legal officials to shape their offices with reference to what they individually hold to be moral obligations in excess of what the law requires or enjoins. At any rate, professional codes and policy statements, and the unions, professional associations, and Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010 408 Reviews/Critiques d’ouvrages licensing authorities that proclaim and in some cases police them, play an important part in regulating the moral behaviour of legal officials. The author does discuss oaths of office (with surprising brevity given the title of the book), but the various professional infrastructures that govern legal officials are hardly mentioned. The author’s treatment of his subject is seriously incomplete for not building these codes into his analysis, or at least taking them into account, and more so even than for omitting to discuss the academic literature in professional ethics at any length. Overall, this book makes for a very interesting and engaging read. I expect that many readers will find themselves in disagreement with the author on this or that point, or at least wishing that he had said more about it, but that is to be expected for a book that covers as much ground as this one. Indeed, probably its chief virtue is to have brought together and synthesized such a wide range of literatures, issues, and cases. Michael Yeo, Department of Philosophy, Laurentian University Canadian Public Policy – Analyse de politiques, vol. xxxvi, no. 3 2010