22S6 - Numerical and data analysis techniques Mike Peardon School of Mathematics Trinity College Dublin Hilary Term 2012 Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 1 / 22 Course content and assessment Assessment The course counts for 5 ECTS. The course will be examined in the summer in a two-hour paper. Homework assignments will be assessed. Your final mark will be 20% homework score, 80% exam performance. 1 Probability Review the basic ideas Conditional probability and Bayes’ theorem Random variables Distributions 2 3 4 Information from data: Statistics Numerical methods and algorithms Introduction to stochastic processes Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 2 / 22 Probability Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 3 / 22 Sample space Consider performing an experiment where the outcome is purely randomly determined and where the experiment has a set of possible outcomes. Sample Space A sample space, S associated with an experiment is a set such that: 1 each element of S denotes a possible outcome O of the experiment and 2 performing the experiment leads to a result corresponding to one element of S in a unique way. Example: flipping a coin - choose the sample space S = {H, T} corresponding to coin landing heads or tails. Not unique: choose the sample space S = {L} corresponding to coin just landing. Not very useful! Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 4 / 22 Events Events An event, E can be defined for a sample space S if a question can be put that has an unambiguous answer for all outcomes in S. E is the subset of S for which the question is true. Example 1: Two coin flips, with S = {HH, HT, TH, TT}. Define the event E1T = {HT, TH}, which corresponds to one and only one tail landing. Example 2: Two coin flips, with S = {HH, HT, TH, TT}. Define the event E≥1T = {HT, TH, TT}, which corresponds to at least one tail landing. Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 5 / 22 Probability measure Can now define a probability model, which consists of a sample space, S a collection of events (which are all subsets of S) and a probability measure. Probability measure The probability measure assigns to each event E a probability P(E), with the following properties: 1 P(E) is a non-negative real number with 0 ≤ P(E) ≤ 1. 2 P(∅) = 0 (∅ is the empty set event). 3 P(S) = 1 and 4 P is additive, meaning that if E1 , E2 , . . . is a sequence of disjoint events then P(E1 ∪ E2 ∪ . . . ) = P(E1 ) + P(E2 ) + . . . Two events are disjoint if they have no common outcomes Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 6 / 22 Probability measure (2) Venn diagrams give a very useful way of visualising probability models. Example: Ec ⊂ S is the complement to event E, and is the set of all outcomes NOT in E (ie Ec = {x : x ∈ / E}). C E E The probability of an event is visualised as the area of the region in the Venn diagram. S The intersection A ∩ B and union A ∪ B of two events can be depicted ... Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 7 / 22 Probability measure (3) A B The intersection of two subsets A ⊂ S and B ⊂ S A ∩ B = {x : x ∈ A and x ∈ B} A A B S A B 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 0000000000000000 1111111111111111 111111111 000000000 000000000 111111111 000000000 111111111 000000000 111111111 000000000 111111111 000000000 111111111 000000000 111111111 000000000 111111111 000000000 111111111 The union of two subsets A ⊂ S and B ⊂ S A ∪ B = {x : x ∈ A or x ∈ B} B S Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 8 / 22 Probability measure (4) The Venn diagram approach makes it easy to remember: P(Ec ) = 1 − P(E) P(A ∪ B) = P(A) + P(B) − P(A ∩ B) Also define the conditional probability P(A|B), which is the probability event A occurs, given event B has occured. Since event B occurs with probability P(B) and both events A and B occur with probability P(A ∩ B) then the conditional probability P(A|B) can be computed from Conditional probability P(A|B) = Mike Peardon (TCD) P(A ∩ B) P(B) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 9 / 22 Conditional probability (1) Conditional probability describes situations when partial information about outcomes is given Example: coin tossing Three fair coins are flipped. What is the probability that the first coin landed heads given exactly two coins landed heads? S = {HHH, HHT, HTH, HTT, THH, THT, TTH, TTT} A = {HHH, HHT, HTH, HTT} and B = {HHT, HTH, THH} A ∩ B = {HHT, HTH} P(A|B) = P(A∩B) P(B) Answer: = 2/ 8 3/ 8 = 2 3 2 3 Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 10 / 22 Conditional probability (2) Bayes’ theorem For two events A and B with P(A) > 0 and P(B) > 0 we have P(A) P(A|B) = P(B|A) P(B) Since P(A|B) = P(A ∩ B)/ P(B) from conditional probability result, we see P(A ∩ B) = P(B)P(A|B). switching A and B also gives P(B ∩ A) = P(A)P(B|A) . . . A ∩ B is the same as B ∩ A . . . Thomas Bayes (1702-1761) so we get P(A)P(B|A) = P(B)P(A|B) and Bayes’ theorem follows Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 11 / 22 Partitions of state spaces Suppose we can completely partition S into n disjoint events, A1 , A2 , . . . An , so S = A1 ∪ A2 ∪ · · · ∪ An . Now for any event E, we find P(E) = P(E|A1 )P(A1 ) + P(E|A2 )P(A2 ) + . . . P(E|An )P(An ) This result is seen by using the conditional probability theorem and additivity property of the probability measure. It can be remembered with the Venn diagram: A2 A4 E A1 Mike Peardon (TCD) A5 A3 22S6 - Data analysis S Hilary Term 2012 12 / 22 A sobering example With the framework built up so far, we can make powerful (and sometimes surprising) predictions... Diagnostic accuracy A new clinical test for swine flu has been devised that has a 95% chance of finding the virus in an infected patient. Unfortunately, it has a 1% chance of indicating the disease in a healthy patient (false positive). One person per 1, 000 in the population is infected with swine flu. What is the probability that an individual patient diagnosed with swine flu by this method actually has the disease? Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 13 / 22 A sobering example With the framework built up so far, we can make powerful (and sometimes surprising) predictions... Diagnostic accuracy A new clinical test for swine flu has been devised that has a 95% chance of finding the virus in an infected patient. Unfortunately, it has a 1% chance of indicating the disease in a healthy patient (false positive). One person per 1, 000 in the population is infected with swine flu. What is the probability that an individual patient diagnosed with swine flu by this method actually has the disease? Answer: about 8.7% Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 13 / 22 The Monty Hall problem When it comes to probability, intuition is often not very helpful... The Monty Hall problem In a gameshow, a contestant is shown three doors and asked to select one. Hidden behind one door is a prize and the contestant wins the prize if it is behind their chosen door at the end of the game. The contestant picks one of the three doors to start. The host then opens at random one of the remaining two doors that does not contain the prize. Now the contestant is asked if they want to change their mind and switch to the other, unopened door. Should they? Does it make any difference? Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 14 / 22 The Monty Hall problem When it comes to probability, intuition is often not very helpful... The Monty Hall problem In a gameshow, a contestant is shown three doors and asked to select one. Hidden behind one door is a prize and the contestant wins the prize if it is behind their chosen door at the end of the game. The contestant picks one of the three doors to start. The host then opens at random one of the remaining two doors that does not contain the prize. Now the contestant is asked if they want to change their mind and switch to the other, unopened door. Should they? Does it make any difference? P(Win)=2/3 when switching, P(Win) = 1/3 otherwise Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 14 / 22 The Monty Hall problem (2) This misunderstanding about conditional probability can lead to incorrect conclusions from experiments... Observing rationalised decision making? An experiment is performed where a monkey picks between two coloured sweets. Suppose he picks black in preference to white. The monkey is then offered white and red sweets and the experimenters notice more often than not, the monkey continues to reject the white sweets and chooses red. The experimental team concludes the monkey has consciously rationalised his decision to reject white sweets and reinforced his behaviour. Are they right in coming to this conclusion? Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 15 / 22 The Monty Hall problem (2) This misunderstanding about conditional probability can lead to incorrect conclusions from experiments... Observing rationalised decision making? An experiment is performed where a monkey picks between two coloured sweets. Suppose he picks black in preference to white. The monkey is then offered white and red sweets and the experimenters notice more often than not, the monkey continues to reject the white sweets and chooses red. The experimental team concludes the monkey has consciously rationalised his decision to reject white sweets and reinforced his behaviour. Are they right in coming to this conclusion? Not necessarily. Based on the first observation, there are three possible compatible rankings (B>W>R,B>R>W,R>B>W). In 2 of 3, red is preferred to white, so a priori that outcome is more likely anyhow. Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 15 / 22 Independent events Independent events Events A and B are said to be independent if P(B ∩ A) = P(A) × P(B) If P(A) > 0 and P(B) > 0, then independence implies both: P(B|A) = P(B) and P(A|B) = P(A). These results can be seen using the conditional probability result. Example: Two coins are flipped where the probability the first lands on heads is 1/ 2 and similarly for the second. If these events are independent we can now show that all outcomes in S = {HH, HT, TH, TT} have probability 1/ 4. Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 16 / 22 Summary Defining a probability model means choosing a good sample space S, collection of events (which all correspond to subsets of S) and a probability measure defined on all the events. Events are called disjoint if they have no common outcomes. Understanding and remembering probability calculations or results is often made easier by visualising with Venn diagrams. The conditional probability P(A|B) is the probability event A occurs given event B also occured. Bayes’ theorem relates P(A|B) to P(B|A). Calculations are often made easier by partitioning state spaces - ie finding disjoint A1 , A2 , . . . An such that S = A1 ∪ A2 ∪ . . . An . Events are called independent if P(A ∩ B) = P(A) × P(B). Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 17 / 22 Binomial experiments A binomial experiment Binomial experiments are defined by a sequence of probabilistic trials where: 1 2 3 4 Each trial returns a true/false result Different trials in the sequence are independent The number of trials is fixed The probability of a true/false result is constant Usual question to ask - what is the probability the trial result is true x times out of n, given the probability of each trial being true is p? Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 18 / 22 Examples of binomial experiments Examples and counter-examples These examples are binomial experiments: 1 Flip a coin 10 times, does the coin land heads? 2 Ask the next ten people you meet if they like pizza 3 Screen 1000 patients for a virus ... and these are not: Flip a coin until it lands heads (not fixed number of trials) Ask the next ten people you meet their age (not true/false) Is it raining on the first Monday of each month? (not a constant probability) Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 19 / 22 Number of experiments with x true outcomes Number of selections There are Nx,n ≡ n Cx = n! x!(n − x)! ways of having x out of n selections. Coin flip outcomes Example: how many outcomes of five coin flips result in the coin landing heads three times? Answer: Nx,n = 5! 3!2! = 10 They are: {HHHTT, HHTHT, HHTTH, HTHHT, HTHTH, . . . . . . HTTHH, THHHT, THHTH, THTHH, TTHHH} Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 20 / 22 Probability of x out of n true trials If the probability of each trial being true is p (and so the probability of it being false is q = 1 − p) ... and the selection trials are independent then... Probability of x out of n true outcomes Px,n = n Cx px qn−x ≡ n Cx px (1 − p)n−x We can compute this probability since we can count the number of cases where there are x true trials and each case has the same probability Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 21 / 22 Infinite state spaces The set of outcomes of a probabilistic experiment may be an uncountably infinite set Here, the distinction between outcomes and events is more important: events can be assigned probabilities, outcomes can’t Outcomes described by a continuous variable 1 If I throw a coin and measure how far away it lands, the state space is described by the set of real numbers, Ω = R 2 I could also simultaneously see if it lands heads or tails. This set of outcomes is still “uncountably infinite”. The state space is now Ω = (H, T) × R Impossible to define probability the coin lands 1m away. Events can be defined - for example, an even might be “the coin lands heads more than 1m away.” Mike Peardon (TCD) 22S6 - Data analysis Hilary Term 2012 22 / 22