CHAPTER 0 General framework and notational conventions 0.1. Groups Throughout this section and the whole book G is a countable discrete group. Its identity element will always be denoted by e. 0.2. Probability spaces A measurable space is a pair (X, S) where X is a set and S is a σ-algebra of subsets of X. Members of S are called measurable sets. Given measurable spaces (X, S) and (Y, R), a map ϕ : X → Y is measurable if ϕ−1 (B) ∈ S for all B ∈ R. We say that the measurable spaces (X, S) and (Y, R) are isomorphic if there is a bijection ϕ : X → Y such that ϕ and ϕ−1 are both measurable, and such a map is called an isomorphism (of measurable spaces). If (X, S) is a measurable space and A is a measurable subset of X, then A itself is a measurable space when paired with the σ-algebra of all intersections of members of S with A. A measure on a measurable space (X, S) is a map µ : S → [0, ∞] such that (i) µ(∅) = 0, and S P∞ ∞ (ii) µ( ∞ A ) = n n=1 n=1 µ(An ) for every countable collection {An }n=1 of pairwise disjoint sets in S (countable additivity). Usually we speak of a measure on X, with S not being explicitly mentioned. The measure µ is finite if µ(X) is finite, and is called a probability measure if µ(X) = 1. It is atomless if µ({x}) = 0 for every x ∈ X. A measurable set A is null if µ(A) = 0 and conull if µ(X\A) = 0. By a measure space we mean a measurable space (X, S) along with a measure µ on (X, S). A measurable subset of a measure space is itself a measure space under the restriction of the measure. We will usually write a measure space as a pair (X, µ) and talk about measurable sets without explicitly naming the σ-algebra. When µ is a probability measure we refer to (X, µ) as a probability space. If (X, µ) and (Y, ν) are measure spaces then a map ϕ : X → Y is a measure isomorphism if it is an isomorphism of measurable spaces which satisfies ν(A) = µ(ϕ−1 (A)) for all measurable A ⊆ Y . A measure-preserving transformation of a probability space (X, µ) is an automorphism T : X → X of measurable spaces which satisfies µ(A) = 27 28 0. GENERAL FRAMEWORK AND NOTATIONAL CONVENTIONS µ(T −1 A) for all measurable A ⊆ Y (in other words, a measure isomorphism from X to itself). Usually this terminology is used without the assumption of invertibility, so that T is merely measurable and measure-preserving, but in the spirit of our main interest in group actions we make invertibility part of the definition, although some facts we discuss about measure-preserving transformations remain valid in the noninvertible case. 0.3. Measure algebras In ergodic theory we are mainly interested in phenomena which are most naturally expressed at the level of the measure algebra and its automorphisms. Weak mixing, compactness, and entropy all fall into this category, while the pointwise ergodic theorem could be regarded as an exception, although it too admits a measure algebra formulation. It is rarely imperative however to work with the measure algebra (although analysis in spaces like L2 and L∞ , which are effectively completions of the linearization of the measure algebra, is often vital), and we will adhere to the language of points and sets, as is customary. This is also important when trying to leverage any extra topological or geometric structure that the dynamics might have, for example via the Borel structure which actually grounds our definition of probability-measure-preserving action in Definition 0.2. Nevertheless, the measure algebra picture is helpful for motivating and understanding, among other things, the notion of standardness for probability spaces, as discussed further below. A Boolean algebra is a set containing distinguished elements 0 and 1 with operations ∨, ∧, and ¬ which satisfy the same axioms as union, intersection, and complementation do for subsets of a fixed set, with 0 and 1 playing the roles of the empty set and the whole set, respectively. A measure algebra is a pair (M, µ) where M is a Boolean algebra and µ is a map M → [0, ∞] such that (i) µ(A) = 0 if and only if A = 0, and W P∞ ∞ (ii) µ( ∞ n=1 An ) = n=1 µ(An ) for every countable collection {An }n=1 of elements in M which are pairwise disjoint in the sense that Ai ∧ Aj = 0 for i 6= j (countable additivity). Let (X, µ) be a probability space and S its σ-algebra. The collection of sets A ∈ S satisfying µ(A) = 0 (the null sets) forms a σ-ideal N in S, meaning that it is closed under taking countable unions and taking subsets within S. We define an equivalence relation on S by declaring that A ∼ B if A∆B ∈ N. Then the quotient S/N by this relation is a measure algebra when equipped with the map defined on equivalence classes by [A] 7→ µ(A). We call this the measure algebra of µ. We often speak of two measurable sets being equal modulo a null set, by which we mean that their equivalence classes in the measure algebra are equal. 0.4. STANDARD PROBABILITY SPACES 29 0.4. Standard probability spaces We will typically restrict our scope to probability spaces (X, µ) which are standard in the following sense, which is natural not only because it enables us to leverage tools from descriptive set theory at the level of the space and translates as separability at the level of the measure algebra (which is equivalent to the separability of L2 (X, µ)), but also because of the way it connects these two levels in the presence of dynamics through Theorem 0.5. This standardness is analogous to metrizability for a compact space Y (which is equivalent to the separability of C(Y )) and similarly allows us to avoid certain pathologies and additional technicalities, especially in discussions where factors, extensions, or equivalence relations are involved, or where spaces of actions come into play as in Section ??. The basic theory of Polish spaces and standard Borel spaces which underlies all of this is covered in Appendix A. The Borel σ-algebra of a topological space X is the σ-algebra B generated by the open subsets of X, and the members of B are called Borel sets (we may also refer to them as measurable sets if we are viewing (X, B) abstractly as a measurable space). A Borel probability measure on X is a probability measure on the Borel σ-algebra of X. A Borel space is a measurable space (X, B) such that there is a topology on X for which B is the Borel σ-algebra. If this topology can be chosen to be Polish (i.e., so that X is separable and admits a compatible metric under which it is complete) then the Borel space is said to be standard. For economy we usually just write X without naming the σ-algebra. If we wish to stress the special nature of (X, B) among measurable spaces then we will refer to the members of B as Borel sets instead of using the generic qualifier “measurable”. This will be the case when discussing equivalence relations (as in Section 3.7) where descriptive set theory and Polishness play an especially decisive role. The term “Borel space” is often used to mean the same thing as a measurable space, especially in older literature, but the definition above is more consistent with the expressions “measurable space” and “standard Borel space”, both of which are nowadays customary. In any case this terminological issue will not concern us as we will only be working with standard Borel spaces. There is little variety among standard Borel spaces. Indeed as soon as such a space is uncountable it is must be isomorphic (as a measurable space) to the unit interval with its usual Borel σ-algebra, as follows from Corollary A.5 and Theorem A.17. D EFINITION 0.1. A standard probability space is a probability space (X, µ) such that, denoting its σ-algebra by B, the pair (X, B) is a standard Borel space. For some purposes (although it will not be an issue for us) one might wish to work with measure spaces which are complete in the sense that the σ-algebra is closed under taking subsets of null sets. A measure space (X, µ) with σ-algebra S can be turned into a 30 0. GENERAL FRAMEWORK AND NOTATIONAL CONVENTIONS complete measure space by first noticing that the σ-algebra generated by S and the subsets of null sets in S consists of sets of the form A ∪ N where A ∈ S and N is a subset of a null set in S, and then extending µ to this larger σ-algebra by defining the measure of A ∪ N to be µ(A). In general a standard Borel space with a probability measure is not complete, such as the unit interval with Lebesgue measure on its Borel σ-algebra. The definition of standardness is often taken to include completeness and is in addition frequently expressed in a more concrete or even purely measure-theoretic way, but these formulations are invariably equivalent to the completion of a space as in Definition 0.1. The abstract Borel framework of Definition 0.1 has several advantages, as Appendix A illustrates. 0.5. Group actions By an action of the group G on a set X we mean a map α : G × X → X such that, writing the first argument as a subscript, αs (αt (x)) = αst (x) and αe (x) = x for all x ∈ X and s, t ∈ G. Most of the time we will write the action as G y X and not give it a name, with the image of a pair (s, x) written as sx. If we need to give some name α to an action, such as when needing to distinguish two or more actions, we will use the notation α G y X. For sets A ⊆ X and K ⊆ G and an s ∈ G we write sA = {sx : x ∈ A}, Kx = {sx : s ∈ K}, KA = {sx : x ∈ A and s ∈ K}. The G-orbit of a point x ∈ X is the set Gx. Our basic objects of study will be continuous actions on compact Hausdorff spaces and probability-measure-preserving actions, the latter of which we define as follows. D EFINITION 0.2. By a p.m.p. (probability-measure-preserving) action of G we mean an action of G on a standard probability space (X, µ) by measure-preserving transformations. In this case we will combine together the notation and simply write G y (X, µ). In the absence of an action we do not assume a probability space to be standard unless otherwise stated, but in order to avoid extra technicalities and because it covers all of our examples of interest we include standardness as part of the above definition of a p.m.p. action, whether or not it is actually necessary for a given result. Given an action G y X on a set, we say that a set A ⊆ X is G-invariant if GA = A, which is equivalent to GA ⊆ A. When the action is probability-measure-preserving and A is a measurable set, then we interpret G-invariance we mean GA = A modulo a null set, i.e., µ(sA∆A) = 0 for all s ∈ G. The natural notion of isomorphism for group actions on ordinary sets is conjugacy. Two such actions G y X and G y Y are conjugate if there is a bijection ϕ : X → Y such that ϕ(sx) = sϕ(x) for all x ∈ X and s ∈ G. Such a map ϕ is called a conjugacy. In 0.6. MEASURE CONJUGACY VS. MEASURE ALGEBRA CONJUGACY 31 the case of continuous actions or p.m.p. actions, the terms “conjugate” and “conjugacy” will be meant in a more restricted sense which is tailored to the structural context, as made precise in the following definitions. D EFINITION 0.3. Two continuous actions G y X and G y Y of the same group on compact Hausdorff spaces are said to be (topologically) conjugate if there is a homeomorphism ϕ : X → Y such that ϕ(sx) = sϕ(x) for all s ∈ G and x ∈ X. D EFINITION 0.4. Two p.m.p. actions G y (X, µ) and G y (Y, ν) of the same group are said to be (measure) conjugate if there are conull sets X ′ ⊆ X and Y ′ ⊆ Y with GX ′ ⊆ X ′ and GY ′ ⊆ Y ′ and an isomorphism ϕ : X ′ → Y ′ of measurable spaces such that ϕ(sx) = sϕ(x) for all s ∈ G and x ∈ X ′ and ν(ϕ(A)) = µ(A) for all measurable sets A ⊆ X ′ . In both of the above definitions, the map ϕ is called a conjugacy. In the case G = Z we can alternatively describe an action as a single transformation T : X → X, which corresponds to the generator 1 in Z and generates an action n 7→ T n through iteration. The T -orbit of a point x ∈ X is defined to be the set {T n x : n ∈ Z}, i.e., the orbit of x under the Z-action that T generates. For a set A ⊆ X we write T A for the set {T x : x ∈ A}. We say that A is T -invariant if T A ⊆ A. This does not mean that A is invariant for the associated Z-action, for we might have T −1 A 6⊆ A. However, if T is a measure-preserving transformation of a probability space (X, µ) and A is a measurable subset of X, then by measure-preservingness we see that the following are equivalent, with invariance now being interpreted modulo a null set (i.e., µ(T A∆A) = 0 in the case of T ): (i) A is T -invariant, (ii) A is both T -invariant and T −1 -invariant, (ii) A is invariant for the Z-action generated by T . 0.6. Measure conjugacy vs. measure algebra conjugacy Standardness for a probability space has the consequence that every measure-preserving action on the measure algebra essentially arises from a p.m.p. action on the space. To make this statement precise, which we do in Theorem 0.5, we first need to introduce some terminology. By an action on a measure algebra (M, µ) we mean a map G × M → M, written (s, A) 7→ sA, which satisfies s(tA) = (st)A, eA = A, and µ(sA) = µ(A) for all s, t ∈ G and A ∈ M. A conjugacy between actions of G on measure algebras (M, µ) and (N, ν) is a measure algebra isomorphism Φ : M → N (i.e., a Boolean algebra isomorphism satisfying ν ◦ Φ = µ) such that Φ(sA) = sΦ(A) for all A ∈ M and s ∈ G. A p.m.p. action G y (X, µ) induces an action on its corresponding measure algebra by the formula s[A] = [sA] for measurable sets A ⊆ X and s ∈ G. A conjugacy between two p.m.p. 32 0. GENERAL FRAMEWORK AND NOTATIONAL CONVENTIONS actions G y (X, µ) and G y (Y, ν) induces a conjugacy between the induced actions on the measure algebras: if X ′ ⊆ X and Y ′ ⊆ Y are G-invariant measurable sets with µ(X ′ ) = µ(Y ′ ) = 1 and ϕ : X ′ → Y ′ is a measure isomorphism satisfying ϕ(sx) = sϕ(x) for all s ∈ G and x ∈ X and ν(ϕ(A)) = µ(A) for all measurable A ⊆ X ′ , then setting Φ([A]) = [ϕ(A)] for all measurable A ⊆ X ′ defines a measure algebra conjugacy Φ. The converse is also true because of the assumption of standardness in the definition of p.m.p. action (and would be false in general without it): T HEOREM 0.5. Let G y (X, µ) and G y (Y, ν) be p.m.p. actions of the same group and let Φ be a conjugacy between the induced actions on the measure algebras. Then there is a conjugacy between the actions which induces Φ. P ROOF. It is enough to show that, given an isomorphism from the measure algebra MX of X to the measure algebra MY of Y , we can find a measure isomorphism h : X → Y which induces it. Clearly such an h is unique modulo sets of measure zero. On every measure algebra we have the canonical metric d(A, B) = µ(A∆B), where symmetric difference is interpreted via representatives. Since (X, µ) is standard, using Propositions A.18 and A.19 we see that MX is separable with respect to this metric, and so we can find a sequence {Pn } of finite partitions in MX such that the algebra they generate is dense in MX . Using the sequence {Pn } we will construct a standard probability space (W, µ′ ) and an identification of MX with the measure algebra MW of (W, µ′ ) such that there is a Borel measure-preserving map f : X → W which induces the identity map Q MW → MX . Define W to be ∞ with the product topology, under which it is n=1 Pn Q compact and metrizable. To a cylinder set ∞ W (i.e., a product set where An = n=1 An in T∞ S Pn for all but finitely many n) we assign the value µ( n=1 An ). This defines a measure on the algebra of all finite disjoint unions of cylinder sets. By Kolmogorov’s extension theorem this measure extends uniquely to a Borel probability measure µ′ on W . Q T∞ S By associating to a cylinder set ∞ An in MX , we obtain a n=1 An the class of n=1 measure-preserving algebra homomorphism from the algebra of all finite disjoint unions of cylinder sets in W to MX . Since the collection of finite disjoint unions of cylinder sets is dense in MW and the algebra generated by the partitions Pn is dense in MX , this homomorphism extends to an isometry from MW onto MX . As the algebraic operations (union, intersection, and complementation) are all continuous, they are preserved by this isometry. Define a map f : X → W by declaring f (x) to be the sequence whose nth term is the member of the partition Pn which contains x. Since the preimage under f of each cylinder set in W is Borel, the map f is Borel. As f preserves the measure on finite disjoint unions of cylinder sets, it also preserves the measure on the σ-algebra they generate, since the σ-algebra generated by an algebra of subsets is the smallest collection of subsets containing the algebra which is closed under taking increasing unions and 0.7. FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS 33 decreasing intersections indexed by N (Theorem 10.1(ii) of [82]). Thus f induces an isometric embedding MW ֒→ MX . Clearly f induces the identity map on the algebra of all finite disjoint unions of cylinder sets, and therefore induces the identity map MW → MX . Next, by Theorem A.17 we may assume that X is a compact metric space. So we may assume that the maximum diameter of the members of Pn converges to 0 as n → ∞, since we can always refine a given Pn to produce a partition whose members all have diameter as small as we like. The map f constructed above is injective. A standard result (Corollary 15.2 in [82]) then says that f (X) is a Borel subset of W and f is a Borel isomorphism from X onto f (X). Thus f is a measure isomorphism modulo a set of measure zero. Finally, we do the same for Y , starting from a sequence Pn′ of partitions of Y . By taking the join of Pn and Pn′ , we may assume that Pn is mapped to Pn′ under the given measure algebra isomorphism MX → MY . Then from Pn′ we also obtain (W, µ′ ). Now we can take the composition X → W → Y . 0.7. Functional analysis We will make frequent use of basic facts in integration theory and related aspects of functional analysis, for which we refer the reader to [43]. One of the most important of these is the dominated convergence theorem. T HEOREM 0.6 (Dominated convergence theorem). Let (X, µ) be a probability space, g : X → R an integrable function, and {fn } a sequence of real-valued measurable functions on X such that |fn | ≤ g a.e. R for all n ≥ 1 and R fn → f pointwise a.e for some function f . Then f is integrable and f dµ = limn→∞ fn dµ. We will frequently encounter the spaces L1 , L2 , and L∞ , whose definitions we recall. Let (X, µ) be a probability space and 1 ≤ p < ∞. For an integrable function f : X → C R we define kf kp = ( |f |p dµ)1/p . The set of all f for which kf kp < ∞ is a linear space whose quotient under the relation of equality on a set of full measure is a Banach space which we denote by Lp (X), or Lp (X, µ) if we need to emphasize the measure. We similarly write L∞ (X) or L∞ (X, µ) for the Banach space of equivalence classes of essentially bounded functions f : X → C with the essential supremum norm. Following custom we do not notationally distinguish between a function and its equivalence class in Lp (X), and often refer to and manipulate elements of Lp (X) as if they were genuine functions. We will thus frequently speak of equality and pointwise operations holding a.e. (almost everywhere), meaning on a set of full measure. Equipped with pointwise a.e. multiplication and complex conjugation as the involution, L∞ (X) is also a von Neumann 34 0. GENERAL FRAMEWORK AND NOTATIONAL CONVENTIONS algebra (see Appendix E). We write 1X or simply 1 for the function taking constant value one, which belongs to Lp (X) for every 1 ≤ p ≤ ∞. 0.8. Hilbert spaces, operators, and unitary representations Let H be a Hilbert space, which we will always assume to be over the complex numbers unless otherwise indicated. We write the inner product as h·, ·i, or h·, ·iH in case of possible confusion. We write B(H) for the algebra of all bounded linear operators on H, which possesses an involution a 7→ a∗ given by taking the adjoint. As discussed in Appendix E, this is a basic example of a von Neumann algebra. We write idH or id for the identity operator on H, or 1 if we wish to emphasize its algebraic role as the unit in the algebra B(H). Operators will be denoted by either lower or upper case letters, usually depending on whether or not the operator is being manipulated as an element of a specified subalgebra of B(H). An operator U ∈ B(H) is unitary if U ∗ U = U U ∗ = id. A unitary representation of G on a Hilbert space H is a map G → B(H) which is a homomorphism into the group of unitary operators on H. We write the codomain as B(H) instead of the unitary group since it is typically the algebraic interaction with other elements of B(H) which is of interest. For sets K ⊆ G and Ω ⊆ H we write π(K)Ω to mean the set {π(s)ξ : s ∈ K and ξ ∈ Ω}, and also write π(K)ξ and π(s)Ω with similar meanings in the case of a single vector ξ or group element s. A set Ω ⊆ H is G-invariant if π(G)Ω = Ω, or equivalently π(G)Ω ⊆ Ω. An operator T ∈ B(H) is compact if the image of the closed unit ball under T has compact closure in H. In this case the spectrum σ(T ) (i.e., the set of all λ ∈ C such that λ1−T fails to be invertible) is a countable set whose nonzero elements are all isolated and are eigenvalues for T . If T is in addition normal, i.e., T ∗ T = T T ∗ , then the Hilbert space H decomposes into a direct sum of eigenspaces for T . The compact operators form a closed ideal in B(H), and when H is infinite-dimensional and separable this is the unique nontrivial closed ideal in B(H). See Sections 1.4, 2.4, and 4.1 of [105]. Let B be an orthonormal basis√for H. An operator T ∈ B(H) is of trace class if P T ∗ T (as defined using the functional calculus for the ξ∈B h|T |ξ, ξi < ∞ where |T | = ∗ positive operator T T ), and the trace of such an operator is defined by X Tr(T ) = hT ξ, ξi. ξ∈B Using orthonormal expansions it is not hard to show that this sum is independent of the choice of B. The trace class operators form an ideal in B(H) which is a dense subset of the ideal of compact operators, and for all trace class operators T , bounded linear operators S, and unitary operators U on H we have Tr(ST ) = Tr(T S) and Tr(U T U ∗ ) = 0.8. HILBERT SPACES, OPERATORS, AND UNITARY REPRESENTATIONS 35 Tr(T ). On the space of trace class operators we have the norm kT k1 = Tr(|T |). See Section 2.4 of [105] for details. The direct sum π⊕ρ of two unitary representations π : G → B(H) and ρ : G → B(K) of the same group is the representation on H ⊕ K defined by ((π ⊕ ρ)(s))(ξ, ζ) = (π(s)ξ, ρ(s)ζ) for s ∈ G and ξ, ζ ∈ H. The trivial representation of G is the unitary representation on the one-dimensional space C in which every vector is fixed by every element of G. Two unitary representations π : G → B(H) and ρ : G → B(K) of the same group are (unitarily) equivalent if there is a unitary isomorphism U : H → K (i.e., a bijective inner-product-preserving linear map) such that ρ(s) = U π(s)U −1 for all s ∈ G. A subrepresentation of a unitary representation π : G → B(H) is a representation ρ : G → B(K) obtained by restricting π to a closed G-invariant subspace K ⊆ H. When ρ is unitarily equivalent to a subrepresentation of ρ then we say that π contains ρ. Given that π(G) is closed under taking adjoints it is clear that the orthogonal complement K⊥ of K is also G-invariant, so that π can be expressed as ρ ⊕ ρ′ where ρ′ is the restriction of π to K⊥ . To construct the Hilbert space tensor product H ⊗ K of two Hilbert spaces we first define an inner product on the algebraic tensor product by setting hξ1 ⊗ ζ1 , ξ2 ⊗ ζ2 i = hξ1 , ξ2 ihζ1 , ζ2 i on elementary tensors and extending (one can use orthonormal bases to show that this is well defined and positive definite), and then complete in the norm kξk := hξ, ξi1/2 . Note that if B and C are orthonormal bases for H and K, respectively, then the linear map ϕ : H ⊗ K → ℓ2 (B × C) given on elementary tensors by ϕ(ξ1 ⊗ ζ1 )(ξ2 , ζ2 ) = hξ1 , ξ2 ihζ1 , ζ2 i is isometric with dense image and hence is a unitary isomorphism. If U and V are unitary operators on H and K, respectively, then there is a unitary operator U ⊗ V on H ⊗ K determined on elementary tensors by (U ⊗ V )(ξ ⊗ ζ) = U ξ ⊗ V ζ. The tensor product π ⊗ ρ of unitary representations π : G → B(H) and ρ : G → B(K) is the unitary representation of G given by s 7→ π(s) ⊗ ρ(s). Let H be a Hilbert space. Its conjugate H is the Hilbert space which is the same as H as an additive group but with the scalar multiplication (c, ξ) 7→ c̄ξ for c ∈ C and inner product hξ, ζiH = hζ, ξiH . If U is a unitary operator on H, then the operator U on H which formally coincides with U is also unitary. Given a unitary representation π : G → B(H), its conjugate π̄ : G → B(H) is the unitary representation defined by s 7→ π(s). Let H and K be Hilbert spaces, and let B and C be orthonormal bases for H and K, respectively. Write HS(H, K) (or simply HS(H) if K = H) for the set of all bounded 36 0. GENERAL FRAMEWORK AND NOTATIONAL CONVENTIONS linear operators T : H → K such that XX (4) |hT ξ, ζi|2 < ∞. ξ∈B ζ∈C A simple exercise using orthonormal expansions shows that the above double sum, whether finite or infinite, is independent of the choice of B and C, and that it can be also exP P pressed as both ξ∈B kT ξk2 and ζ∈C kT ∗ ζk2 . We refer to the elements of HS(H, K) as Hilbert-Schmidt operators. The set HS(H, K) forms a linear subspace of the linear P space of bounded linear operators H → K and kT k2 = ( ξ∈B kT ξk2 )1/2 defines a norm on HS(H, K), as can be seen by applying the triangle inequality (i.e., Minkowski’s inequality) in ℓ2 (B × C). In fact we can endow HS(H, K) with the structure of a Hilbert space by identifying it with ℓ2 (B × C) via the linear map ϕ : HS(H, K) → ℓ2 (B × C) given by ϕ(T )(ξ, ζ) = hT ξ, ζi. This map is evidently isometric, and it is surjective (and hence a unitary isomorphism) because for every x ∈ ℓ2 (B × C) we can set X XX T cξ ξ = cξ x(ξ, ζ)ζ ξ∈B ζ∈C ξ∈B for all square-summable coefficients cξ , which defines a bounded linear operator T : H → K by virtue of the application 2 X X X XX X cξ x(ξ, ζ) ≤ |cξ |2 |x(ξ, ζ)|2 = kxk cξ ξ ζ∈C ξ∈B ζ∈C ξ∈B ξ∈B ξ∈B of the Cauchy-Schwarz inequality, and T clearly satisfies (4) and maps to x under ϕ. The inner product on HS(H, K) arising from this identification with ℓ2 (B × C) is then given by XX hS, T i = hSξ, ζihζ, T ξi. ξ∈B ζ∈C By passing through ℓ2 (B × C), we can now give a natural alternative description of the tensor product H ⊗ K of two Hilbert spaces as the space HS(K, H) of all HilbertSchmidt operators from K to H. The unitary isomorphism ϕ : H ⊗ K → HS(K, H) that sets up this identification sends the elementary tensor ξ ⊗ ζ to the rank-one operator η 7→ hη, ζiK ξ. Given unitary representations π : G → B(H) and ρ : G → B(K), the unitary isomorphism ϕ conjugates the tensor product π ⊗ ρ to the conjugation representation on HS(K, H), in which a group element s is represented as the unitary operator T 7→ π(s)T ρ̄(s)−1 . 0.9. THE KOOPMAN REPRESENTATION 37 It is readily seen that the Hilbert-Schmidt operators in B(H) form an ideal which is a dense subset of the ideal of compact operators. For more details on tensor products and Hilbert-Schmidt operators see Section 2.6 of [76]. 0.9. The Koopman representation Given a p.m.p. action G y (X, µ), its Koopman representation is the unitary representation κ : G → B(L2 (X)) defined by κ(s)f (x) = f (s−1 x) for all s ∈ G, f ∈ L2 (X), and a.e. x ∈ X. Note that the one-dimensional subspace C1X is always G-invariant and the restriction of the Koopman representation to it is the trivial representation. We will thus frequently focus our attention on the restriction of the Koopman representation to 2 2 the R orthogonal complement L (X) ⊖ C1, which consists of all f ∈ L (X) such that f dµ = 0. X