UNSOLVABLE PROBLEMS AND PHILOSOPHICAL PROGRESS American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (1982) 289–298 William J. Rapaport Department of Computer Science and Engineering, Department of Philosophy, and Center for Cognitive Science State University of New York at Buffalo Buffalo, NY 14260 rapaport@cse.buffalo.edu http://www.cse.buffalo.edu/∼rapaport ERRATA Missing epigraph, p. 289: Commitment is not an outcome, but a process. (Cited in Perry 1981b: 5.) p. 289, col. 1, p. 291, p. 294, col. 1, col. 1, para. 2, L. –4: L. –2: L. –3: L. 10: L. –3: L. 3: p. 295, col. 2, para. 0, L. –2: col. 2, ‘metaphyhsical’ ‘psuedo-’ ‘÷’ ‘miles’ ‘define’ ‘ontoloico-’ ‘coint’ ‘superceded’ 1 should be should be should be should be should be should be should be should be ‘metaphysical’ ‘pseudo-’ ‘×’ ‘feet’ ‘defend’ ‘ontologico-’ ‘coin’ ‘superseded’ American Philosophical 19, Number Volume Quarterly 1982 4, October Winning Entry in the 1982APQ Prize Essay Competition I. UNSOLVABLE PROBLEMS AND PHILOSOPHICAL PROGRESS WILLIAM J. RAPAPORT I. Problems and Solutions there unsolvable problems? Philosophy as a field sometimes been characterized are at unsolvable least, whose problems (or, are and this, in unsolvable), important problems turn, has often been taken to mean that there can in philosophy. It might indeed be no progress ARE whose ones, for surely all problems, merely purported even pseudo-problems, can have purported solu? tions. So: When is a purported solution a real or correct has a set of purported solutions to a problem, first eliminate the clearly wrong or irrele? vant ones. But one must still find a way to choose the correct one from the remainder. Consider the one must of determining the length of a side of a square plot of land whose area is 4 square miles, so that one might know how much fencing to pur? chase. The following might be a set of purported this if the only measure of progress in a field (over a period of time) is the number of problems I shall that have been solved (during that period). but argue that there can be progress in philosophy, problem is an overly answers: mean that such "success" one? Given {5 feet, 2 feet, -2 feet). Now, as a simple calculation shows, 5 feet is wrong?mathematical? is -2 feet wrong; but ly wrong. So, for that matter it is physically wrong (indeed, physically nonsen? so. Of course, itmight sical), not mathematically simplistic measure of it. Let us consider kind of unsolvable the problem of problems. One problem would be unintelligi? or otherwise ill ble, poorly stated, nonsensical, that it is even mathematically formed ones; these would be objected be unsolvable in the wrong, sense assumes was that not that it the lack solutions. Of course, //one they problem simple merely to to *2 = 4, but rather to: *2 = 4 find the solution(s) is not always a trivial matter to show that a given is of this kind, as a consideration we shall see, are and x>0. of the Such assumptions, problem on un essential to identifying attack the apparent solutions. logical-positivist of metaphyhsical As another example, consider '42' as the answer2 reveals. solvability problems to "the Ultimate the unsolvability of ill-formed of Life, the Universe, But, of course, Question as in Douglas does not guarantee and Everything," the solvability of Adams's The problems ones. well-formed to the Galaxy Hitch-Hiker's Guide (1979: 135). Are there, then, intelligible, of course, the humor of this answer lies in clearly stated, sen? Now, its very its category sible, or otherwise well-formed problems inappropriateness, ("real" one might say, as opposed to "pseudo-" But as Adams mistakenness. problems, cleverly goes on to that are unsolvable? an it Some philosophers be may problems) observe, only apparent inap? for example) have argued that (Benson Mates, there are, that "the traditional problems of phil? ... ... ab? are but osophy intelligible enough, insoluble" 1981: cf. solutely 3; (Mates ix, x).1 Before this position of "solvability examining it will prove worthwhile to consider skepticism," the nature of solutions. Just as we need to talk of real, not psuedo-, so we must speak of real solutions, not problems, for it may well be the question propriateness, that's at fault. Perhaps some ill-formed problems can be restated. But a restatement (or questions) should preserve the intentions of the original x "What is 7?" not be an 6 would problem. Thus, restatement case. in this appropriate Nor, for that matter should "What is 6 + 9?" be-yet '42' is ac? in the story as the answer (Adams 1980: 184)! And itmakes cepted 289 to that question perfect sense (as 290 far as anything can) i.e., both question in the context of that story; and and answer ?problem sense //one accepts the assump? the story. So, to object that a restated isn't the original problem may be as un? solution?make tions of AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY problem fair as the attitude of the child who wants to know the largest number is and whose father says he can't answer that because there is no largest: the but still want to know the child may acquiesce what answer to the original can lead persistence of discovery arithmetic?but question. (Of course, such to new insights ?e.g., the or transfinite of modular such an insight is probably not an answer intended to the question as originally stated.) II. The Solvability On to have Skeptic 'sArgument the surface, appears solvability skepticism a point. (A student once told me that he did was to give philosophers the to unanswerao/e Surely, questions.) Free Will problem does not seem to have a solu? or even scien? tion the way, say, mathematical, thought answers that what tific, problems and mathematical Even do. as-yet-unsolved have solu? problems we we haven't found like to believe: while tions, them yet, we believe that (with a few exceptions) we will find them, given enough time and more evidence. The exceptions, though, are not insignificant. Perhaps we will scientific never know the solutions to the problems of the origin of life or of what happened before the Big Bang, simply because the necessary One tends to feel, evidence has been destroyed. however, tion?that that that a practical limita? are not unsolvable in is merely such problems a well-formed problem would be un? Roughly, for solving it if the procedure solvable in practice a virtually what called be either might (a) requires amount of resources space, (time, requiring 10100 seconds to (b) information which once was but perform?or an irretrievably lost is no longer available?e.g., etc.) ?e.g., a calculation ?or (c) information which is exceeding? to obtain?e.g., the exact (impractical) ly difficult time at which I began writing this sentence. That but we cannot have such solutions, is, problems reasons as these. know them, for such practical a well-formed And, roughly, problem would in principle if there is no solution unsolvable be for us to know. Are there, are unsolvable which then, well-formed problems in principle? Well, perhaps the Big is unsolvable in principle, but that Bang problem that it can well serve as an exam? issue is so muddy In of unsolvable problem. ones do exist, notably in logic principle unsolvable the problem of whether the con? and mathematics: ple of both kinds But tinuum is true, for instance. hypothesis so that that mathematicians say stated, problem, Is is ill-formed. Restated, becomes: the problem or the continuum hypothesis logically implied by, with, the axioms of (say) ZF set answer is: Neither.4 the And theory? we But can't come up with even an philosophers is it inconsistent to the Free Will solution analogous problem, et al. do seem to be in general, Philosophical problems, of unsolvable while mathe? problems, paradigms are as para? in taken matical general, problems, ones. digms of solvable that there is no This is not to say, of course, to the Free Will problem. On the con? solution solutions. Why trary, there are lots of (purported) seem to accept (correct) solutions does everybody but not everybody to mathematical problems, agrees on a correct solution to the Free Will prob? lem? The solvability skeptic's point, roughly put, to philosophical is that there are no solutions problems solutions: What principle.3 infinite document because makes there are no generally ... the philosophical accepted problems so in? teresting, and what keeps them going, is the fact that, although each possible point of contact [i.e., defini? tion of a term, meaning and truth-value of a premise, step in an argument, etc.] is identified by somebody as the source of the difficulty, each is also exonerated by the great majority; and consequently no purported solution ever comes (Mates 1981: 5.) close to general acceptance. UNSOLVABLE PROBLEMS AND PHILOSOPHICAL PROGRESS 291 is not a sufficient But being generally accepted solution to count as a for a purported condition a proposition may be generally as true and being the solution accepted it is either even though (unknown to the accepters) Nor is general false or true-but-not-the-solution. correct solution: as being can be true, a proposition necessary: acceptance or a purported solution correct, even if it is not of mis- or perhaps because accepted, generally (or any number of other acciden? pre-conceptions The history of science is largely tal circumstances). the story of such cases: Newtonian physics may serve as an example of the former; the case of in geology as an ex? and plate tectonics Wegener ample of the latter. That there are lots of sources in of difficulty solution purported agreeing to accept a particular to as the solution?lots of options and choices and make about terms, logical premises, to (or the commitment that steps ?suggests acceptance of) a choices one makes solution depends the options among "points of contact." by the various The stucture of Mates's upon the presented of the skeptical solu? is to show that for each purported argument there are some tion to a philosophical problem, we just don't want to make or prin? assumptions ciples we don't want purported definition, accepted, solvable. version to give up ?that to accept any solution, (a unacceptable something a premise, etc.) would also have to be is un? the problem yet isn't. Hence, mean in But surely this must unsolvable not unsolvable in principle; and not practice, but because because of any lack of information, of a lack of general acceptability. is an Yet, as we have just seen, acceptability true criterion of solutionhood, being unacceptable nor sufficient It is neither necessary therefor. possible perhaps, Let me to get a solution, though at the price, a of cherished belief. But so what? illustrate my analysis of the solvability a brief con? with argument-structure skeptic's sideration of purported solutions to the Free Will I wish to define a certain In so doing, problem. thesis, tion: to which the following is a first approxima? Any purported solution, S, to a problem, P, is really the consequent of an implicit conditional solution, A-+S, where A is a conjunction of principles which, once accepted, make S a correct solution to P. un? an in-principle to this thesis, According there solvable problem would be one for which were no principles, A, which allowed or entailed a solution. Following Mates's analysis, there are four possi? to the usual statement of the ble opening moves of the notion Free Will (1) Replace problem: or causation by that of a functional relationship, else (2) deny the principle of universal causation, or else that (3) claim statistically events are or true, less caused is only principle that claim mental (4) ones. And than physical the else that (l)-(4) in? objections: distinctions (b) untenable or to explain fail that events, among (l)-(4) (c) are some free human actions (Mates why only there are three possible (a) ad hoc or volve 1981: 600 a can always be met: objections the back? distinction is ad hoc (a) only against a if ad hoc of theory; apparently given ground But such can be made to work elsewhere, they to be (merely) ad hoc. There is no a priori reason why the distinctions made in (l)-(4) could to work elsewhere, not be made though at the distinctions cease doubt too great?of other reshuffling price?no well-established categories. distinctions refer to "Untenable" (b) could a incorrect solution mak? ones; merely purported a distinction be such wrong, might simply ing But 'untenable' incorrect really means: our we are theory; if willing to against background pay the price of giving up our background theory, we can make the distinctions tenable. period. if the explanatory insight or ingenuity, And of failure failure then (c) is due to lack it is a contingent If it is a necessary and possibly reparable. failure, then the solution is either wrong or?more is only relatively failure necessary: likely?the relative to a background theory which could be given up, at a price. Such replies take the form of further premises or assumptions (which the skeptic rejects) having 292 AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY features: the following (I) They "straighten out" thus fitting the solution the knot of the problem, in with (some) background theory; and (II) they the become skeptic's next objec? to a different is moved loca? for focus the knot tion?i.e., tion, but that a knot which to a different point on an open keeps moving ended (or infinite) string eventually disappears; can the i.e., enough premises replace (become) a To continue the metaphor, theory. background if it could not problem would be truly unsolvable be unknotted; but (A) the skeptical argument doesn't show that, and (B) such a situation is very and the problem ill-formed. likely inconsistent, we should be for the that (But prepared possibility even the ultimate (Peircean) complete theory is in? be a may inconsistency have to accept in order to gain that consistent, i.e., premise we would at all.) solutions III. Solvability structure of the dialectic fault with all pur? finding But the solution ported solutions.) purported if these further principles were ac? would work universal objector, that solution claim proposers Indeed, cepted. these principles must be accepted because they ac? solution.5 cept the proposed The thesis of the last section more it is not merely but that conditional, general: always which "grow" background Any purported part of a theory, can now be made that solutions they theories: are solution, 5, to a problem, P, among Are whose other there no solutions simpliciter, uncondi? tional solu? solutions, non-theory-laden solutions, tions without As the skeptic might commitments? Arche put it, are there any solvable problems? as we've mathematical and noted, typically, (to a are solvable. lesser degree) scientific problems In? Mates discusses Zeno's deed, (1981: 7f) paradoxes as paradigms of solvable problems because they have a unique "locus": a "point of contact" which a generally enables solution accepted to come forth. is there a locus in Zeno's case? There is, a a locus solution that does min? perhaps, enabling imal damage to (and coheres well with) our world not necessarily view. But notice: our world-view, But Zeno's! If this between can be solvable seen is paradigmatic and unsolvable the that of difference the difference then it problems, concerns the of the purported solution and its atten? dant commitments with our (current) world-view. That is, the structure of the problem/solution dialectic is the same both for so-called solvable coherence vs. Unsolvability is always this: A is posed, and a purported is of? solution problem solution comes with strings fered; the purported or implications which an ob? attached?premises jector rejects. (The solvability skeptic is simply the The the problem, e.g., which has the theory entire problem.6 the it's still there. Note to "dissolve" may be necessary to give up the parts are (e.g., mathematical unsolvable (e.g., or scientific) and for so-called All philosophical) problems: are solutions conditional upon certain premises. The solutions of so-called solvable problems have are further commitments which (e.g., axioms) more acceptable (more coherent with our other than those of philosophical commitments) prob? But even they lems; that's the only real difference. don't have to be accepted; in fact, the more in mathematics and the philosophical problems sciences are usually unsolved precisely because of over assumptions. disagreement "seeds" IV. is really are Epistemological the background principles entailing 5 and the further principles (or commitments) entailed by 5. un? to this thesis, then, an in-principle According no solvable would be one for which problem this is the case, it theory contains a solution. When Intellectual Development and Progress A. Perry's Theory. The hardened skeptic may as support for his position: saying take these observations after all, haven't solutions that there are no absolute I been to any UNSOLVABLE PROBLEMS AND PHILOSOPHICAL PROGRESS 293 I think we may get a clearer picture of problems? the solvability skeptic's place in the epistemol to ogical scheme of things if we turn for a moment a striking parallel offered by William G. Perry's theories about college students' attitudes towards knowledge.7 form? Perry describes a sequence of "positions" a "scheme of cognitive and ethical develop? ing ment" that college students progress through. You will see how appropriate also appropriate larger scale. Position and, 1 is Basic it is for them; I think it is on a at least, illuminating Duality: There are answers to all questions, engraved in tablets sky, to which the teacher has access, and to which, through hard work, we (the students) will, too. (Cf. Plato, Position perhaps.) results when we realize 2, Dualism, authorities teachers, (notably English will do nicely) disagree on cor? but philosophers rect answers, while others and (mathematics that some the former must teachers) agree. Hence, their vi? clouds over their heads, obscuring sion of the tablets. But all is known; we just have to follow the right authorities. science have we take the In Position 3, Early Multiplicity, view that only most knowledge is known, but all is knowa?te. The answers are there, but we haven't found them all yet. (Positions 2 and 3, by the way, are said to be the positions of most college freshmen.) In Position 4 (4a, in Perry 1981a), Late Multi? it is felt that "Where Authorities don't plicity, know the Right Answers, everyone has a right to his own opinion; no one is wrong" (Perry 1981a: 79). "In some areas we knowedge [e.g., mathematics]. we really don't [e.g., philosophy] for sure" (Cornfield The which holds still have certainty In most about areas know anything and Knefelkamp, 1979). next Contextual position, Relativism, is viewed as a more "mature" position, that uAll knowledge is disconnected from any concept of Absolute Truth," though there are of adequacy" ?that standards?"rules theories must adhere to (Cornfeld and Knefelkamp 1979; my emphasis). "mature" positions, we in which the Position 6, Commitment Foreseen, seeker of knowledge realizes that he must make some commitments among theories; competing in Position this is accomplished ment; Position 7, Initial Commit? in Implications of Com? 8, Orientation in which one balances the several com? mitment, mitments in 6 and 7; and made in 9, Developing Commitment(s), it is seen that one must retrace "this whole Position which right in the to the most Progressing next find: journey over and over" (Perry 1970, 1981a). There are, in addition, three paths of "deflec? tend to occur before tions from growth," which 5 or 6, of which Position only one need concern us here: Alienation, "Escape. sibility. Relativism Exploitation for avoidance abandonment of of Multiplicity of Commitment" respon? and (Perry 1981a: 80, 90).8 B. The Skeptic's Position. to Mates, "traditional According ... skepticism held that we can only know how things seem to be; of how things really are is impossi? knowledge the skeptic considers ble.... Hence that the right attitude nature towards of the true questions concerning of judgment...." is suspension things (Mates 1981: ix). This is somewhere around Posi? tion 4, but it is also a form of Escape. According to the Perry scheme, a more "mature" Position would hold that all we can know is how things to certain would be were we to commit ourselves assumptions, theory-relative Solvability of problems i.e., to hold to a conditional view of solutions to problems. or "doubts that [the major ... are solvable or even [philosophy] and ... it argues that the reasons giv? skepticism 'dissolvable'; en on both sides of the issues are equally good (Mates 1981: ix). This is more than suspension ..." of a it is clearly to refrain from making judgment; For if 'judgment' is to be understood commitment. as elliptical for "rational judgment," then surely one could suspend that, yet make a commitment nonetheless. If, indeed, the "reasons ... on both AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 294 ... are equally good," then it doesn't seem ir? distinction, if any, is that the assumptions in the case are (almost) ac? in such a case on mathematical rational to make a commitment universally case. the basis of, say, the toss of a coint or ontoloico cepted, unlike the philosophical no dif? are there: At the very least, If it really makes But the assumptions aesthetic preferences. = 5' is true we one + '2 2 could that solution and attendant ference which say theory //one assumed sides to ?because each solution is ac? ourselves a and consistent by complete (or, at companied worst, equally incomplete and inconsistent) world commit view?then matter it shouldn't what of method choice we use. claim that the skeptical position is Perry Position 4a. At best, it is 5; more likely, it is an 4; cf. Escape (which happens at around Position the chart in Perry 1970). The skeptic is correct to a point: there are no right answers. There are only to some of which, relative ones, (conditional) we should commit ourselves, moving eventually, to Position 6, and beyond. one: there then, is an anti-skeptical but they are all theory-laden, hence And this is not Position 4, because theory-relative. I also claim that we must to commit ourselves My thesis, are solutions, some theory (thus siding with James's Will to Be? lieve, rather than Clifford's duty to suspend judg? ment).9 a philosopher be thus commited? After all, all is it not the philosopher's duty to question It all would commitments? examine assumptions, that we are stuck at Position appear 4, at Can But Philo? can which be 9, really a we can For for false multiplicity. mistaken (in? while remain? deed, must) question assumptions, to them (at least pro temp?re), as in ing committed Neurath's deceive: boat metaphor. V. Let appearances dit Position Problems, us return and ments to (or assumptions or properties, to distinction the the nature about) negation, of ob? etc. ?witness the 1978: Russell-Meinong (cf. Rapaport disputes is that 165f). But perhaps of most significance are theorems in conditional virtually always form ?a particular to a problem) claim (solution is true under certain "unconditional" axioms And and axioms the nature of the underlying logic. upon philosophical the nature of mathematical ob? are conditional about assumptions Even apparently conditional upon conditions. are theorems jects. claim parity be? (On the other side, one might on tween mathematics and philosophy the are that there that truths grounds philosophical are assumption-free: such first-person observation reports as "it seems to me that I am now experienc? ing red," say; but surely this claim is laden with theories about experiences, colors, the nature of "seeming," etc.) in mathematics There are, of course, problems which lack solutions because of a lack of agree? ment on assumptions these are (though, arguably, problems in the more philosophical The difference between ematics). of problems areas of math? these two kinds may be described by adapting of Kuhn's distinction between solutions; the ter? "prob? Ch. have Puzzles (1962, IV). have lots of problems possible, solutions. (un-)acceptable, purported are, roughly, what problems become when they are treated within a given "paradigm"; other? wise they are alike, for researchers within a given equally Puzzles between wherein the former and mathematics, philosophy the is viewed as presenting unsolvable problems, am a ones. is I solvable This, latter, suggesting, and mathe? false dichotomy; both philosophical but they are all matical have solutions, problems conditional example formulation (unique) Paradigms does. A better of Non-Contradiction, any of which involves one in commit? minology lems" and "puzzles" Puzzles, '4' ordinarily what is "the" Law jects, Iwould Multiplicity. sophers are that '5' denoted theory-relative solutions. The have agreed to accept the assumptions paradigm to have a solu? which allow the erstwhile problem Puzzles play the role in "normal" tion simpliciter. science science. that problems do in "revolutionary" UNSOLVABLE PROBLEMS AND PHILOSOPHICAL PROGRESS 295 of all those premises the conjunction Thus, to become whose acceptance permits problems whose acceptance prob? permits (i.e., puzzles have solu? I used the term earlier ?to lems?as activity consists in the develop? Sym-philosophical ment of philosophical theories, i.e., systematic hypotheses about the general structure of the world of and The experience.... ultimate com? is the aim tions) theories in order to parative study of maximal establish, through isomorphisms among them, a orientation. establishment of such isomorphisms and invariences is dia-philosophy. (1980: 14f.) is the fundamental axioms, as it were, of a or of the theory "grown" by the solu? paradigm tion?what Rescher (1978) calls a methodological Rescher's Indeed, philosophical ment about analysis disagreement the conditional and my Perrian of the structure of is in substantial structure agree? of solutions analysis: A philosophical position thus always has the implicit conditional form: given a certain set of commitments regarding the relevant cognitive values, such and such a position on the question at issue is the appropriate one. (Rescher 1978: 229.) [A] locally optimal (or adequate) for those to committed a certain solution...is cogent probative-value orientation. And given that...[this is the] perspective [which] is apposite, it follows that such "demonstra? tions" as there are in philosophy...[i]n effect take the form: IF you are prepared tomake certain procedural commitments..., THEN you will arive at a particular solution. A rational constraint is clearly at issue here, rather but it is basis-relative (or orientation-relative), than absolute. Yet it is not a matter of "anything (Rescher goes...." 1978: 232f.) Since "All that one can do in philosophy," or, I would add, in any field, "is to view the issues from one or another of a limited number of 'available' of system that entail the solu? assumptions And this is impossible, for there is to know that we have considered every question-begging tion simpliciter. no way to problems. more developed solutions all be Varying or less "Carnapian principle of tolerance: Let everybody in the system of his choice" must work be turns that is, "dia-philosophy to be feasible" out, empirically, (1980: 21). It is thus feasible, in a simple fashion, as soon as "if," superceded, there are a finite number theories. But of completed if one wants (or nearly complete results, then the reasons I have dia-philosophical given for the skeptic's failure to show that philo? are unsolvable?and hence to sophical problems completed) show that there cannot also theory?are complete be even one philosophical for thinking that such reasons dia-philosophical results cannot be forthcoming. VI. On Progress in Philosophy to my discus? is a potential objection I have missed the solvability skeptic's the thesis ismerely that there are point. Possibly, philosophical problems which don't, or will never, There sion?that accepted solutions, with no fur? about unsolva?/7/Yy intended. ill does bode for this the hopes of "success" admit of generally ther implications Casta?eda's tinctions According the to major each simultaneously, susceptible And he criticism only when completed 20). (1980: as view with the Perrian he calls agrees it, the that, Surely or progress to Casta?eda, and comparisons sees the task of philosophy theories which, then, can yield theory-relative theories must or set of assumptions.10 orientation, paradigm, This suggests, by the way, that there might be some a priori on Hector-Neri limitations It sug? program of "dia-philosophy": not but entail does this because his gests program does not assume that all theories be considered. Such also Thus, Casta?eda as constructing orientations" methodological (Rescher 1978: 232), it follows that truly to defend solvability skep? ticism, one would have to show that within each the issue at hand has orientation, methodological no resolution?i.e., each paradigm, that within the puzzle is unsolvable, that there are no non invariences. But Mates's ix-x); in philosophy, and supports the dis? between and mathematics. philosophy this thesis is not as astounding as, e.g., claims and about "don't" absolute insolubility seems too parochial, (1981: while AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 296 too pessimistic, though closer to not "there does appear to have position: one iota of progress toward a generally ac? is surely "never" Mates's been solution" of any major philosophical 1981: 7). (Mates problem If so, why Can there be progress in philosophy? ceptable not appear and science does philosophy do mathematics to progress, appear to? and why etc., by another. Science, though, paradigm, to be more than philosophy, revolutionary lending support to the belief that science doesn't. philosophy at its lower levels, Mathematics, Position-2 discipline?its "puzzles"?because at the higher pore tends thus "pro? is a Perry are really all "problems" the assumptions pro tem levels. Thus, all solutions are of or theory-relative at the lower to not do be: appear they really conditional level, though [G]iven the lengths of the sides of a rectangle, how one does find its area? A...better is, does problem every plane rectangle have associated with it a numerical quantity which can meaningfully be called an area?...[T]he problem previous cannot be solved unless the answer to this one is yes. Yet very little em? is put phasis mathematics. granted.... this last question upon seems obvious: Its answer [M]athematicians have in elementary it is taken for become extremely wary of taking anything at all for granted. Accepting something as 'obviously true* has led them astray too often. (Ogilvy 1972: 5.) At its higher levels, as philosophy: mathematics is as "open happens when makes a great advance, new insights mathematics are achieved regarding concepts which had long been taken for granted" (Wilder 1973: 175). On the other hand, philosophy, by its self ended" "As usually is nature, constantly questioning seem at makes it its This levels. all "open-ended" as if philosophy cannot progress because all at? but blocked; tempts at progress are immediately of "doing philosophy" ?of the process constantly conscious, challenging of progress. the very essence and questioning?is there being pro of the illusion Thus, in mathematics is due both philosophy nature of mathematics while there to a too-narrow is none in view of the and to the refusal to con? sider progress as other than "success." in philosophy, There can be (and is) progress the ap? for the central stumbling block?viz., of philosophical parent unsolvability prob? lems? There is a simple reason in the case of science. to which There is a sense of "progress" according to replace one to be "progress" it is viewed gresses" while gress is illusory. non-negative, sort Surely, of there can be a trivial, or an progress: out-and-out er? ror can be found in someone's theory, or one can one's own earlier writings. (Of course, the In a more earlier work might have been better!) correct whenever sense, philosophy progresses anyone builds upon or extends one's own work or turn the work of others. True, this may ultimately out to have been a wild-goose but until that chase, positive is known, it counts as progress: "the philosopher to who refines the Kantian imperative contributes to if that of the that shares group progress, only his premises" (Kuhn 1962: 161). And even if it has been a wild-goose chase, there may have been pro? senses in that we understand the the problem gress better and that we may have gotten interesting from our study of it. useful by-products and there is progress even if the only sense Finally, in which we understand the problem better is the we one know what won't work;11 that important was for learned about Hilbert's consider what inmathematics from G?dePs in? program there is progress theorem. But if we learn as a result what premises we especially have to accept if we want a solution.12 malistic completeness For would to know what won't work work // we were willing whose is to know what to accept those a solution. forestalls principles rejection to be such principles allows problems Accepting to the number of solutions solved (thus allowing of progress). be a measure must be for us what our commitments Knowing for philosophy to have solutions is progress, is con? are in the that its solvable such only problems or theory-relative sense, not in any ab? sense. But philosophy is not alone in this; in science, any discipline where there is progress?in as well as in philosophy?solu in mathematics, ditional solute UNSOLVABLE PROBLEMS AND PHILOSOPHICAL PROGRESS 297 and so all "progress" in tions are theory-relative, the same way, namely, within the framework of a of New State University at Fredonia York, College or a paradigm, orientation, set of commitments.13 methodological held commonly Received a 27,1982 January NOTES 1. I shall not distinguish articles: "insoluble," between "unsolvable" and "insoluble," though and Fowler 1965: 272f, "unsolvable;" "insolvable," a useful possibly distinction be made. could (on "in- and un-," 666 and p. 273; esp. Cf. the OED "unsolvable," resp.). 2. Nor I distinguish shall distinctions teresting assume that some 4. Alternatively, 1981: 470): solutions 5. As Wesley "mathematical Salmon have problems it, one man's MT has put and problems questions cf. Ogilvy one (inducing see Stent problem, ther principles feature of the theory not of itself Casta?eda answers, on depending or background by assumptions any other it would hence, of predication the model (MacLane of eliminating the apparent in? correspond or in conjunction with fur? open separately to sentences such principle could solve the problem. In this case, the that there are two (distinct) modes of predication which are such that a in two object (Meinongian) do not permit cf. the two modes for set theory" used that no be to give up the theory which answers) theory. by this one either entailed suppose the principles of a single and solutions in? I shall man's MPonens. principles But theory. by rejecting lead to inconsistency; itself, the predication of predication This ways. (distinct) the theory?the to a given property and?along of a given discussed in Dicker to the more accessible be to give up an essential would with 1981 or, more problem it spawned. item in both ways does in those discussed relevantly, 1972. 7. The locus classicus is Perry 1970, but I shall refer mainly versions in Perry 1981a and Cornfeld and 1979. Knefelkamp are also Transitions 8. There Randall if there were 10. Even 11. As Morton between out pointed Dipert tent orientations, 12. To and, two modes (There being 9. As the revised Meinongian can be predicated property with together be "dissolved" could problem single of 1981), there are 3, 5), but 1981: 36. the revised Meinongian 1978 appears to be inconsistent. The problem theory of Rapaport can a to solved not be the effect that all well-formed consistency (I believe) by adopting principle (cf. Rapaport 1972: between 6. E.g., properties no doubt, Here, "question." "question"; purpose. different is another and than a mere rather the former or are determined upon depend of the unsolvability or "problem" "answer" for the present unimportant twist on interesting and project," between correspondence these distinctions an 3. For "solution" as "research "problem" is a natural there makes which either between (e.g., some way paraphrase to ensure has often the famous while which, that all theories or assumptions paradigms, Schagrin the Positions, to the scheme, essential I have omitted for ease of exposition. to me. out pointed financier's had been classical ?plus itmight considered, still be impossible if one accepts inconsis? logic! to me. "Do you question, sincerely want to be rich?", we may ask: Do you want sincerely solution? 13. The idea for this paper Component ment Staff neth Lucey, of General-Liberal Symposium arose from discussions Education" in December Tibor Machan, David during my (Summer 1981; I am grateful Palmer, to Carol and Morton in an NEH participation 1981). An Schagrin draft was earlier Brownson, Randall Pilot Grant presented Dipert, Stephen for their comments. REFERENCES 1. Douglas Adams, The Hitch-Hiker's 2. Douglas Adams, The Restaurant Guide at the End to the Galaxy of (London: the Universe Pan (London: Books, Pan 1979). Books, at Fredonia at the Fredonia 1980). Knaster, on the "Humanistic Philosophy Marvin Depart? Kohl, Ken? a 298 3. Hector-Neri Casta?eda, 4. Hector-Neri Casta?eda, 5. J. L. Cornfeld March the Structure On Philosophical and Holland Stages Method of (1972), Student paper Stage Publications, and Type in the Design at the American presented vol. Philosophia, IN: Nous (Bloomington, "Combining Typologies;" the World" College 4 (1974): 3-40. 1980). of Learning An Environments: Personnel Association, at SUNY Fredonia, In? Los Angeles, 1979. 6. Georges press, on Necessary "Leibniz Dicker, 7. H. W. A Dictionary Fowler, and Contingent of Modern English paper Propositions;" 2nd Usage, rev. and ed., presented ed. by E. Gowers (New York: December Oxford 1981. University 1965). 8. Thomas S. Kuhn, 9. MacLane, Saunders vol. and "Thinking and L. L. Knefelkamp, of Perry tegration AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 88 (1981): 10. Benson U.C. The Structure "Mathematical Models: A Sketch (Chicago: University of Chicago University (Chicago: for the Philosophy of Mathematics," Press, 1962). American Mathematical Monthly, 462-72. Mates, Stanley Revolutions of Scientific Skeptical Essays Ogilvy, Tomorrow's Math: Perry, Jr., Forms of Intellectual Unsolved of Chicago Problems for Press, 1981). the Amateur, 2nd ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, (New York: Holt, 1972). 12. William Rinehart G. and Winston, 13. William Modern G. 14. William 15. Willaim Jr., Perry, American G. and Ethical Development Growth: The Making in the College Years: A Scheme 1970). College Jossey-Bass, to L. Copes, Jr., Letter Perry, and Ethical "Cognitive (San Francisco: J. Rapaport, "Meinongian J. Rapaport, "Meinong, in Perry 1981a): Network in A. (October 1981b): Newsletter and a Russellian Theories of Meaning," and Associates, Chickering The 76-116. Paradox," Nous vol. 3-5. 12 (1978): 153-80. Errata, Nous vol. 13 (1979): 125. 16. William Logic Colloquium, 17. Nicholas of Metaphysics, 18. G?nther 19. Raymond Wiener Rescher, vol. "Philosophical 32 (1978): "A Close S. Stent, L. Wilder, (New York: Defective Objects, and Paradox;" (Psycho-)Logical paper presented to the SUNY Buffalo 1981. October Encounter," "Relativity Scribner's, Disagreement: An Essay towards Orientational Pluralism inMetaphilosophy," The Review 217-51. 1973), New of Standards vol. Ill: York Review of Mathematical 170-77. of Books, Rigor," vol. 28 (3 December in Dictionary of 1981): the History 34-6. of Ideas, ed. by P. P.