LECTURE . PAIRS AND WALDHAUSEN ∞-CATEGORIES .. Exercise. Suppose X a quasicategory. Consider the cartesian fibration s : O(X) . X. Show that an edge σ : Δ1 . O(X) is s-cocartesian just in case the corresponding diagram (Λ20 ) ∼ = Δ1 × Δ1 . X is a colimit. Conclude that s is a cocartesian fibration if and only if X admits all pushout diagrams. is exercise suggests that cartesian fibrations that are also cocartesian have special significance. is is true! .. Definition. Suppose p : X . Δ1 a cartesian fibration, and suppose α : C . ∼ X0 and β : D . ∼ X1 are equivalences of quasicategories. en a functor g : D . C is said to be attached to p via α and β just in case there is a map G : D × Δ1 . X over Δ1 such that the obvious diagram D ×. Δ1 D. β D. α◦g G X.0 X.. X.1 Δ{0} . Δ.1 Δ{1} . commutes, and, moreover, such that for every vertex x ∈ D0 , the edge G({x} × Δ1 ) is a p-cartesian edge of X. We will show now that such attached functors exist and are essentially unique. .. Proposition. Suppose g : D . C a functor between quasicategories. (..) ere exist a cartesian fibration p : X . Δ1 and equivalences of quasicategories α : C . ∼ X0 and β : D . ∼ X1 such that g is attached to p via α and β. (..) Suppose p : X . Δ1 and p′ : X′ . Δ1 are cartesian fibrations, and suppose φ : X′ . X an equivalence of quasicategories over Δ1 . en g is attached to X′ via equivalences α′ : C . ∼ X′0 and β′ : D . ∼ X′1 if and only if g is attached to X via equivalences α := φ ◦ α′ : C . ∼ X0 and β := φ ◦ β′ : D . ∼ X1 . (..) Suppose p′ : X′ . Δ1 and p′′ : X′′ . Δ1 are cartesian fibrations. Suppose that g is attached to p′ via equivalences α′ : C . ∼ X′0 and β′ : D . ∼ X′1 , and suppose that g is attached to p′′ via equivalences α′′ : C . ∼ X′′0 and β′′ : D . ∼ X′′1 . en there exists a cartesian fibration p : X . Δ1 , equivalences α′ : C . ∼ X′0 and β′ : D . ∼ X′1 , and equivalences of quasicategories φ : X . X′ and ψ : X . X′′ over Δ1 such that g is associated to p via α and β, and the diagrams of equivalences . X.′0 C. . . X.0 X.′′0 . D. . . X.′1 X.1 X.′′1 and commute. Proof. To prove the first item, use the cartesian model structure on the category sSet+ to factor /Δ1 (D♮ × (Δ1 )♯ ) ∪D ♮ ×(Δ{0} )♯ C♮ . (Δ1 )♯ as a trivial cofibration followed by a cartesian fibration. On to the second item. In one direction, one may simply compose the map D × Δ1 . X′ exhibiting the attachment of g to p′ with φ to obtain a map D × Δ1 . X exhibiting the attachment of g to p. In the other direction, we aim to extend a map D × ∂Δ1 . X′ to a map D × Δ1 . X′ . Since this can be done in hsSet+ , and since X is /Δ1 fibrant and everything is cofibrant therein, the proof is complete. Finally, for the third item, consider the square (D × Δ1 ) ∪ . D×Δ . {0} X.′ C Δ1. , X. where the vertical map on the le hand side is the trivial cofibration from the first part, and the top map exhibits the attachment of g to p′ . One may prove directly that the top map is an equivalence. Now the li X . X′ exists, and the result is proved. □ Conversely, we have the following. .. Proposition. Suppose p : X . Δ1 a cartesian fibration. ere is a functor g : X1 . X0 attached to p via the identities. Moreover, any other functor g′ : X1 . X0 attached to p via the identities is equivalent to g. Proof. Consider the square X♭1 × (Δ . {1} )♯ . X.♮ X♭1 × .(Δ1 )♯ (Δ1.)♯ . e li exists, and the fiber of this li over Δ{0} is a map X1 . via the identities. We leave the unicity proof as an exercise. X0 . It’s easy to see that this a functor attached to p □ .. Definition. Suppose C and D quasicategories. An adjunction f: C . D: u is a map p : X . Δ1 that is both a cartesian fibration and a cocartesian fibration, along with equivalences α : C . and β : D . X1 such that u is attached to p via α and β, and f op is attached to pop via αop and βop . Let us now unpack this to explain how we may extract the unit id . this definition. ere exist maps F : C × Δ1 . X and U : D × Δ1 . u ◦ f of an adjunction f : C . X such that: X0 D : u from (A) F|(C × Δ{0} ) = idC ; (B) F|(C × Δ{1} ) = f; (C) for every object x ∈ C0 , the edge F({x} × Δ1 ) is p-cocartesian; (D) U|(C × Δ{1} ) = idD ; (E) U|(C × Δ{0} ) = u; (F) for every object y ∈ D0 , the edge U({y} × Δ1 ) is p-cartesian. Now consider the rectangle C × .Δ{1} C × Δ. {0,2} C × Δ. {1,2} . D × Δ. {1,2} . X.. F U is gives us a map H ′ : C × Λ22 . X with the property that for any x ∈ C0 , the edge H ′ ({x} × Δ{1,2} ) is pcartesian. Hence there is an extension of this map to a map H : C × Δ2 . X. e unit of the adjunction is then the natural transformation η := H|(C × Δ{0,1} ). You can prove directly for any x ∈ C0 and y ∈ D0 that the composite MapD ( fx, y) . MapC (ufx, uy) . MapC (x, uy) is an equivalence. .. Lemma. A cartesian fibration X . S is also a cocartesian fibration if and only if, for every edge s . attached functor Xt . Xs admits a le adjoint. t of S, an Let’s now move along to the study of the sorts of quasicategories that we will input into K-theory. We will at times hove to return to our foundations in what follows, but we’ve got enough now to get started. .. Definition. A pair of ∞-categories (C , C† ) is an ∞-category equipped with a subcategory C† ⊂ C that contains ιC . Morphisms of C† will be called ingressive or cofibrations. A functor of pairs (ψ, ψ † ) : (C , C† ) . (D, D† ) is a commutative square C.† (..) ψ† D.† . C. ψ D; . it is said to be strict if the diagram (..) is a pullback diagram in QCat. More generally, a functor D . C of quasicategories will be said to exhibit a pair structure on C if it factors as an equivalence D . E followed by an inclusion E . C of a subcategory such that (C, E) is a pair. .. Exercise. Show that a functor ψ : D . C of quasicategories exhibits a pair structure on C if and only if it is a homotopy monomorphism in QCat that induces an equivalence ιD . ιC. We write Pair∞ for the full subcategory of O(Cat∞ ) spanned by those functors D . C that exhibit a pair structure on C. We may also describe an ordinary category of pairs of ∞-categories, and declare a functor of pairs (ψ, ψ † ) : (C , C† ) . (D, D† ) to be a weak equivalence just in case both ψ and ψ † are equivalences. .. Example. Any quasicategory C can be endowed with a maximal pair structure (X, X) and a minimal pair structure (X, ιX). If we speak of a quasicategory as a pair without more comment, then we will assume that it is the maximal structure of which we are speaking. .. Example. Denote by Λ0 Q 2 the pair (Λ20 , Δ{0,1} ⊔ Δ{2} ): 0. 1. . 2. . Denote by Q 2 the pair ((Λ20 ) , Δ{0,1} ⊔ Δ{2,∞} ) ∼ = (Δ1 × Δ1 , (Δ{0} ⊔ Δ{1} ) × Δ1 ): 0. 1. . ∞. 2. ere is an obvious inclusion of pairs Λ0 Q 2 . Q2 . Roughly speaking, the cofibrations of a pair will be those along which pushouts are reasonable. To make this more precise, for any pair (C , C† ) be a pair. en the arrow quasicategory O(C ) admits a pair structure as well, given by a pullback O† (C . ) O(C . ) . C.† s C. . We are nearly ready to describe the basic inputs of K-theory. We only need one more notion. .. Definition. A zero object of a quasicategory is an object that is both initial and terminal. .. Exercise. Show that a quasicategory has a zero object if and only if it has an initial object ∅, a terminal object ∗, and an edge ∗ . ∅. Now we have our definition. .. Definition. A Waldhausen ∞-category (C , C† ) is a pair of essentially small ∞-categories such that the following axioms hold. (..) e ∞-category C contains a zero object. (..) For any zero object 0, any morphism 0 . X is ingressive. (..) e source functor s : O† (C ) . C† is a cocartesian fibration, and an edge η ∈ O† (C) is s-cocartesian only if t(η) is ingressive. Call a functor of pairs ψ : C . D between two Waldhausen ∞-categories exact if it satisfies the following conditions. (..) e underlying functor ψ carries zero objects of C to zero objects of zD. (..) In the diagram O† (C . ) sC C.† O† (ψ) . ψ† O† (D) . sD D.† , the functor O† (ψ) sends sC -cocartesian edges to sD -cocartesian edges. A Waldhausen subcategory of a Waldhausen ∞-category C is a subpair D ⊂ C such that D is a Waldhausen ∞-category, and the inclusion D . C is exact. e conditions demanded of a Waldhausen ∞-category (C , C† ) can be rephrased in the following manner: there is a zero object in C that is initial in C† , and pushouts of cofibrations exist and are cofibrations. is last point can again be rephrased as the condition that the morphism of pairs Λ0 Q 2 . Q 2 (.) induces an equivalence of ∞-categories Colim(Q 2 , C ) ×Fun(Q2 ,C ) FunPair∞ (Q 2 , C ) . FunPair∞ (Λ0 Q 2 , C ). An exact functor C . D is now one that preserves cofibrations, zero objects, and pushouts along cofibrations. .. Example. ere are many examples of Waldhausen ∞-categories; here’s a short list. (..) e ordinary category of pointed finite sets. e cofibrations are just monomorphisms. (..) e nerve of the relative category of pointed finite CW complexes, with its maximal pair structure. (..) e category of finitely generated projective R-modules with “admissible monomorphisms,” i.e., monomorphisms whose cokernels are projective. (..) e nerve of the relative category of perfect complexes with its maximal pair structure. Right away, we can prove Waldhausen’s approximation theorem in this context. .. eorem (Approximation). Suppose C and D two ∞-categories that become Waldhausen ∞-categories when equipped with the maximal pair structure. en an exact functor ψ : C . D is an equivalence if and only if it induces an equivalence of homotopy categories hC . ∼ hD. Proof. Since C and D admit all finite colimits and since ψ preserves them, it follows that ψ preserves the tensor product with any finite space. us for any positive integer n and any morphism η : X . Y of C , the map π n (MapC (X, Y), η) . π n (MapD (ψ(X), ψ(Y)), ψ(η)) can be identified with the fiber of the bijection π 0 MapC (X ⊗ Sn , Y) . π 0 MapD (ψ(X) ⊗ Sn , ψ(Y)) over [ψ(η)] ∈ π 0 MapD (ψ(X), ψ(Y)). Since this is a bijection, ψ is fully faithful, hence an equivalence. □