483 Internat. J. Math. & Math. Sci. Vol. 8 No. 3 (1985) 483-496 ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES D. C. KENT and R. V AINIO Department of Pure and Applied Mathematics Washington State University Pullman, WA 99164-2930 (Received May I, 1985) ABSTRACT: This paper is concerned with the notion of "ordered Cauchy 2. is given a simple internal characterization in Section space" which It gives a discription and a of the category of ordered Cauchy spaces which have ordered completions, 4 through of the "fine completion functor" on this category. Sections construction ordered comple6 deals with certain classes of ordered Cauchy spaces which have not preserve does completion fine tions; examples are given which show that the From these such properties as uniformizability, regularity, or total boundedness. is needed. results, it is evident that a further study of ordered Cauchy completions uniformizability, KEY WORDS AND PHRASES: Ordered Cauchy spaces, ordered completions, regularity, total boundedness. 1980 AMS MATHEMATICS CLASSIFICATIONS CODES: 54A20, 5415. 0. INTRODUCTION. Cauchy spaces provide a completion theory much more general than that obtained from metric or uniform spaces, and much simpler than that arising from uniform convergence spaces. R. Ball [i], [2] has shown the applicability of Cauchy spaces in the study of lattice completions; the compatibility between lattice and Cauchy structures is obtained by requiring the lattice operations to be Cauchy-continuous. While this compatibility criterion is quite natural it is not appropriate for more general order structures, such as partial orders, and may be too restrictive even for some lattice applications. L. Nachbin [9] has defined an "ordered uniform space" by requiring that the uniform and order structures arise from a common source, that being a quasi-niform structure on the same underlying set. We adapt Nachbin’s method to define an "ordered uniform convergence space", and from this the definition of "ordered The resulting notion of "ordered Cauchy space" Cauchy structure" follows naturally. is given a simple internal characterization in Section 2. The development of a completion theory for ordered Cauchy spaces is compli- cated by the fact that some ordered Cauchy spaces do not have ordered completions. In Section 3, we describe the category of ordered Cauchy spaces which have ordered completions, and construct the "fine completion functor" on this category. The remaining sections examine certain classes of ordered Cauchy spaces which have ordered completions; examples are given which show that the fine completion does not preserve such properties as uniformizability, regularity, or total boundedness. From these results, it is evident that a further study of ordered Cauchy completions is needed. D. C. KENT AND R. VAINIO 484 - PRELIMINARIES. 1. Let X be a set, and F(X) the set of all (proper) filters on X. If G for all F E then D denotes the ,8 E F(X), and F N G # , F N G , A c X, A If {F N G: F generated by for some F X filter on <A> we denote by , }. G E G and some On the other hand, if U we say that fails to exist. the filter of all oversets of A; one departure from this convention are the fixed ultrafilters, which are denoted by for xEX. A. Compositions are defined as follows: A B {(x, y) X z there is H c X, then and addition, G E F(X x X) filters on {A(H): A 6 , X X x X are defined in the obvious way. If {y E H: (x, y) A for some x H}; if, in E .Q , (H), and () F(X) then A(), and {A(H): H denote the }, }, {A(H): A and }, respectively. H DEFINITION I.I. If A(H) generated by the sets A set of filters on X convergence structure on (u) (u 2) (u 3) (u 4) x E X} is designated A, B of X x X, (x, z) E A and (z, y) B}. Compo- for subsets such that sitions and inverses of filters on A c X x X {(x, x): X x X, the diagonal Turning to the product set by whenever 0 is called a quasi-uniform c__ 0 5, whenever and X x X if: 6 implies and = exists 6 satisfies the additional condition , (u 5) o -I implies is called a uniform then E o conver.gence X. structure on Quasi-uniform convergence structures are natural generalizations of quasiUniform convergence structures were introduced by Cook and Fischer uniformities. [3] another term often used for the same concept is "pseudouniforme Struktur" (see [6]). A subset @ ’ , of a quasi-uniform convergence structure @ is called a base for if, for each there is ’ for any quasi-uniform convergence structure Qu(X) The set c such that is One convenient : c__ < A >}. A of all quasi-uniform convergence structures on X complete lattice under the natural ordering (the dual of set inclusion). 0, Qu(X), then O j, j where for each ^E has for a base all finite compositions OA or j A" If o E uniform convergence structure on X induced by o. "^" (X), then I v -I formq If n is the The lattice operations "v" applied to quasi-uniform convergence structures (including uniform convergence structures) will always be taken relative to the lattice DEFINITION 1.2. (c I) x C A set for all of filters on x 6 X X is a Qu(X). Cauchy structure on X if: 485 ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES , If (c3) X, on implies C U exists, then and is a base for of a Cauchy structure A subset c such that in there is ! and C (c2) E F(X): there is associated the induced Cauchy structure }. x E if, for each With every uniform convergence structure On the other hand, one can associate with each Cauchy structure , with base consisting of all finite a finest compatible uniform convergence x intersections of filters of the form (one can show where that this set of finite intersections is closed under finite compositions). associated with a Cauchy structure C x defined by: If then f f: (X, in (XI, ) qc x E iff (X2, 2) Caucy-continuous if is Also q is the convergence structure X on is a function from one Cauchy space to another, C2 f() whenever We next consider the notation and terminology associated with an order We shall always assume that (X, on X. relation {(x, y) order relation with its graph (X, ). (X, ) be a poset" let ({x}), (A), and () Let (x) hull of A A is ^ (A) Indeed, it will usually rather than the more conventional F(X). X, and Then -I (x), -i (5), A, and A and A is convex if (X, ) A Cauchy space is The convex respectively. A ^ similar ^ convex if lo.call E C whenever (X I, i is increasing if 2. X x X. are the increasing hulls of x, -I(A), notation applies to filters. If X, A x The decreasing hulls are respectively. x (X,) be convenient to designate the poset by notation is a poset, and we identify the y} (X 2, and f( I 2 are posers, 2 (equivalently, a function if f(xl) f (X I, f(x 2) i / (X2, 2 x E whenever x2. ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES. Throughout this section, (X, ) will be DEFINITION 2.1. arbitrary poset. , be a uniform convergence space. Then (X, (X, is an ordered uniform convergence space if there is a quasi-uniform convergence D{: @}. on X such that <> structure and V is an DEFINITION 2.2. Let (X,) be a Cauchy space. Then (X, a is If o.c.s.) there uniform convergence ordered Cauchy space (abbreviated ) s an ordered uniform convergence space, on X such that (X, structure Let , = -I, , , and C C We see that (X, @, ) is an o.c.s, iff on X quasi-uniform convergence structure definitions). . and are both determined by some (in the sense described in the preceding We shall obtain a more precise chmracterization of of this concept by making use of a particular quasi-uniform convergence structure structed directly from and o= Let quasi-uniform convergence structure on X . F(X x X): generated by <> If o , conbe the is a Cauchy D. C. KENT AND R. VAINIO 486 (X, ), we define structure on uniform convergence structure be a poser. (X, ) Let LE4A 2.3. we also define the associated ,C ^ ,C (,C) v -I (,) , For arbitrary filters X, the on following statements are equivalent: (a) O() U exists. -i(.) (b) ; U (c) @() U exists. -I() exists. (d) (3x) U <@> exists. (e) (3 x (X, Let I in n X. a Cauchy structure on C If as follows: of filters exists. C be a poset and C defined on <x> <> C such that then < () U I A relation is iff there is a finite set U 80n) all exist. This relation is clearly reflexive and transitive, but not generally anti-symmetric. PROPOSITION 2.4. Let (X,)) be a poset, ,C where S PROOF: $ gn ( <> < j Assume I () < <,j, C x j): n. < in U all exist. C. <> [x] ,C o ,C o C) Then there is [l Thus n -1(,) C such that in ) <> <> l] x I [x c ,C ,C contains all filters of the indicated form. has a base of filters of the form <> < > of the form where x 6 Furthermore, < > < >, n that is, a finite intersection of filters I C is a basis filter for 6j C or Finite intersections of such filters are also in and so where each Then n})<> j =I exists; since each component filter in this composition is in either -I (5) x X. a Cauchy structure on 9-I(.j) ({ has a base of filters of the form C A straightforward set-theoretic argument shows @,C can be expressed in the form specified in that all such basic filters for the statement of the proposition. , Let PROPOSITION 2.5. If PROOF. -I () x iff Then C. () (X, ) x x Proposition 2.4, there are filters such that n j If x (x) U <@ > U(I() j, ( x) proof is complete. poser, C x ()) ,C I’’’’ Rn and is in x Then G,C i n in since @ by C with ({ exists, then exists. is clear. < This implies .j < Otherwise, for some .3 < and the | PROPOSITION 2.6. Let (X, @) C) is an o.c.s, iff Then (X, , X. be a poset and C a Cauchy structure on compatible is and U{ 6: ,C C with C- PROOF. X, and a Cauchy structure on the preceding proof shows that x Conversely, suppose j !R be a If the two conditions are satisfied, then Definitions 2.1 and 2.2. Conversely, assume that (X, , C) (X, , is an o.c.s., and let C) is an o.c.s, by be as in 487 ORDERED COUCHY SPACES Definition 2.2. U{A6: Then C and (X, ) If a Cauchy structure on X, then y. x implies With the help of Proposition 2.5, we have {(: ( x x x the conclusion follows from these observations. ,C x if T2-ordered A poser with Cauchy structure is defined to be y. This terminology coincides with the definition of x and the fact ,C C is a poset and x iff ,C PROOF. (x,y) thus the D CC are both compatible with PROPOSITION 2.7. U{N U{A 6: D The second follows because first condition holds. that } A implies "T2-ordered’ for convergence ordered spaces in [8] if we identify a convergence structure as a complete Cauchy structure. It foiiows from Proposition 1.2, [8] that if (X, ,) is closed in X x X. poser with Cauchy structure, then C) which is locally convex is said to (X, then and If C whenever satisfy Condition (0C) T2-ordered is a , . A poser with Cauchy structure (X, , C) < is said to satisfy Condition (0C)2 then we say that Condition (OC) T2-ordered , < (X, ), C) is Finally, if is satisfied. 3 An ordered Cauchy space satisfies conditions (OC) I, (OC) 2, PROPOSITION 2.8. and (OC) 3 PROOF. (X, Let be an ordered Cauchy space. C immediate consequence of Propositions 2.6 and 2.7. that and (OC) Also U -I < <> ),C v(,C )-i ^ < Finally, assume satisfied. are in x and -I ,^ x (x.) ,C being symmetric, is also in , n. c. (x) <>-- -I() () x -I) ((,C) I. ,,C< . .. ,and so ,C Let (X, @ be a is an o.c.s, iff Conditions and (OC) , poser (OC) I, B x B o, C implication first under the assumption that C x n -i(j) in ,C x with 8(j): < > there is an index j, j ~< j Sj)^ C j for n}) j K x with Cauchy structure. (OC2), and (OC) 3 implies C Then are satisfied. _ n In We prove this is a free filter; later, this j <>. such that n such that ’3 ~< ’3’ -I (j) and I’ x n and If K is an ultrafilter finer than contrary to our assumption that latter case we see easily that j C is compatible with then by Proposition 2.5 there are filters ,,C then either j x and this filter, restriction will be removed. I is when the three conditions are satisfied. O,C other words, we must show that ([ (o,C Thus In view of Propositions 2.6, 2.7, and 2.8, it remains only to show PROOF. that C is compatible with If (OC) Then, by Proposition 2.5, (.A) x (N) Since C () x | THEOREM 2.9. (X, ,C and Thus is an 3 this fact will be used to establish --< > C, then If 2. -I C is a compatible with ,C Condition (OC) Proposition 2.6 also asserts Sj x ~< j; (j) is free, or else x thus by (OC) K. In the and (OC)2, D. C. KENT AND R. VAINIO 488 {I,..., m} (m <_ n) be ultrafilter K finer than Without loss of generality, let if {I j (j) m x }, there is an E x K c (j) the preceding paragraph, Indeed, suppose than j, k such that either Zj exists for some conclusion that to conclusion when c_ Also, 6 c_ I 5< where (0C)2, Since I clude that ()] x C. and k are Since j c we conclude that 3) is necessarily of the form C ,C is not free, then by (OC) j finer k it follows that D )-I() K k) U C Either alternative leads to the Zk Z j C is free and x X. IThus C By our previous results, is the filter described earlier in the proof. -< U ( x I) exists or C, ()-l(j) x 9(j))U( x <I Either way, it follows that n. leads to the conclusion that x x x K x and as in Applying the same" reasoning with indices reversed leads <> implies ]I }, and by I exists for some j, c__ n (Kj K .)^ m} 5. j Kj Since exists, or else where x x c {l,...,m}, where I 6 j ,C x Zk and is a free filter in If such that C We next show that ={. j=l {I,..., m}. Then there are ultrafilters j < k Zj < Z k arbitrary indices in .. Z. U < > {I ) x Aj c _< j _< m, let For each j, the indices for which, i < Using (0C)2 | Starting with again, we con- and the proof is complete. The three conditions which characterize ordered Cauchy spaces are all quite The properties natural. "locally convex" and "T2-ordered" are commonly assumed in the study of ordered topological and convergence spaces, and the condition (OC) 2 of Definition 1.2. Cauchy is a natural extension to ordered spaces of axiom (C 3) structures intrinsic to distributive lattices and lattice ordered groups studied by Ball ([I], [2]) are examples of ordered convergence structures. Since Cauchy structures are primarily used as a means for constructing com- pletions and compactifications, it is natural to turn our attention now to completions of ordered Cauchy spaces. spaces have T 2 While it is well known that all T 2 Cauchy completions (indeed, a variety of different completions are described in the literature), it turns out that not all ordered Cauchy spaces have ordered In the remainder of this paper, we characterize those ordered Cauchy completions. Cauchy spaces which do have such completions, and examine several special cases. 3. A triple if , ORDERED CAUCHY COMPLETIONS. (X, ) (X, C) will be called a is a poset and C a T2-ordered poser with T2-ordered Cauchy structure on Cauchy structure (X, ). Thus a poset with T not (OC) ordered Cauchy structure is required to satisfy condition (OC) but 2 3 or (OC) An increasing, Cauchy-continuous function from one such space 2. to another will be called a morphism. The category having posets with T2-ordered Cauchy structures as objects and morphisms as maps will be designated PCS. , Let OCS be the full subcategory of PCS whose objects are the ordered Cauchy spaces. PCS, let C be the Cauchy structure compatible with the -I o v It follows from o,C ,C ,C Proposition 2.7 that (X, @C) is T2-ordered. Furthermore, If (X, C) , uniform convergence structure so by Proposition 2.6, (X, , is an o.c.s. We shall call ,C C ,C The ordered and ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES Cauchy modification of C relative (X, )). to 489 f: (X, ), C) If I’ C1 (X I, is f:(X, a map in PCS, then it is a simple matter to verify that is also a morphlsm. F(X, OCS defined for objects by F: PCS , OCS is a reflective subcategory of PCS relative to the PROPOSITION 3.1. reflector (X, ),)C) ) and fixed on maps. (X, ,C) in PCS is complete, then we shall refer to C as a X and (X, C as a convergence, s.pac. For complete If an object convergence structure on objects in OCS, the T2-ordered X x X. product convergence on property means simply that A complete o.c.s, is closed in the will be called an ordered cpnvergence space; the latter term has the same meaning as ordered pace" "T2-ordered convergence Let OCON be the full subcategory of OCS whose objects are [8]. in ordered convergence spaces. An ordered completion DEFINITION 3.2. , ) (X, (X I, O I, i ((X I, (Xl’ I ) ((X I, I’ CI) I,CI), and a morphlsm I’is CI)’ (X) ) is dense in X I). X* , of an o.c.s. @:(X, obviously a Cauchy completion of , (X, C), {[]: two filters C} -I . Starting with a T 2 X X* and j. []. Reed The completion Cauchy Let be the set of all Cauchy equivalence classes; let j(x) are , in C are equivalent if the natural injection, defined by standard form if ) and C), then (X, (X, C), and so it will be con- is an ordered completion of venient to review some aspects of Cauchy completions. space ) which is an ordered Cauchy embedding (meaning that one-to-one morphisms and If (XI’ is a complete o.c.s. X ((X I, CI), ) X* be is in [i0] showed that every Cauchy completion is equivalent (in the usual sense) to one in standard form. The same is, of course, true for ordered completions. The maln goal of this section is to determine which objects in OCS have ordered completions; the full subcategory of OCS determined by these will be denoted by , COCS. It is clear that (X, 9, C) COCS iff (X, ) is isomorphic to a Cauchy subspace of an object in OCON; we seek, however, an internal characterization of such objects. For this purpose, it is necessary to introduce a new order relation on the Cauchy filters of an o.c.s. Let U x (X, , , ,v C) be an o.c.s. For x}. Note that if X: Now, for or C < transitive subset define L> of I’’’’’ n I O 2 and 2 I [] and I in exists, or v I i also, if ]" L {x X: x -l(y) LN and and U (y). iff any one of the following is true: < > exists. Let be the smallest Cx C containing C such that C let C then U @ other words, n " then Note that I OI iff there are I 2 C implies for every Before proceeding further, we give an example to illustrate the difference between the relations and 2 EXA}LE 3.3. Let X R {(0,0)} be the Euclidean plane with the usual order and with the origin deleted. Let D(x) be the neighborhood filter at x with respect to the usual topology. Let be the filter on X generated by all sets of the form {(x,0): 0 < x < for n 6 N and let be generated by nil Gn Q in D. C. KENT AND R. VAINIO 490 X structure on i {(0,y): 0 < y < H sets of the form , D(x) which contains }. Let C for each be the smallest Cauchy x X in , along with that .. It and and B B i is easy to verify that (X, However both consist of the closed first quadrant (excluding, of and ’$ U C) is an o.c.s.; also note Q course, the origin), and consequently and We now introduce three conditions which are analogous to (OC) 3" we shall show that an o.c.s. (X, @, ) (OC)2, (OC) I, and has an ordered completion iff it satisfies these new conditions. E C implies (COC) (cot) (X, , C) * (X*, *) PROOF. < , all exist. Q 3 }. (X, ,) If * i []) ([,], []) ([3], ]) PROPOSITION 3.5. If I’ , Assume that ((x,, c), J). (COC) 2 If $, Proposition 3.4 that [3] partial order, If 3 (COC) X* x X*: 3 in < }. ([], [])6 If Furthermore, and consequently * , (X, ) (X, , C ,3 ) and Uj U >) U )71 Q, then (j(3) (-I(3) U < or U> is both closed and )I (COC)3. has an ordered Cauchy completion and ([3], []) [,]. O L> Since has an ordered Cauchy completion, then O < then it follows by @I since []) ! *(J(3) []). is a ([]’ []) @1 (j(3) j-l(,(j(.) [,]) L$ O3, ([], [3])E and By Proposition 3.4, []) D < implies It was shown that the o.c.s. (COC)2, ) n is in the closure of A direct argument shows that < , (X, is a completion of are all in (COC)I, (COC)2, satisfies PROOF. ((3) (COC) 2, then j: (X,@ i" transitive, C) as is satisfied, then all have traces on % x are all in ([ exists, then I(j(3) X* n n I"’’’ J () ! j) {([3], []) Thus 3 x (COC) on satisfies (COC)3 The proof is concluded by observing that if (X, * I" ! and there are !I [i]) I’ I )’ (X*, If First, let J (’)’ J , C is an order-embedding. standard form, then and so >) E L3 x _< y. X*; if, in addition, PROPOSITION 3.4. ([.], implies 3 and N < be an o.c.s., and define the preorder {([3], []) is a partial order on then O implies 3 Let follows: (-I() C,,Q, 2 (cot) (() N < U 3 >) CI, Q [,])) (3) < U > But and consequently > 6 C , (X, C) of Example 3.3 fails to satisfy and thus we see that COCS is a proper subcategory of OCS 491 ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES (COC)I, (COC)2, We next show that the conditions and (COC) are also sufficient 3 First, recall Wyler’s completion for the existence of an ordered completion. arbitrary T ), j) of an []: e}. ((X*, {j() THEOREM 3.6. (*C) (XI’ I’ CI) is (X*, *, morphism (X, Let ) satisfy (COC)I, (COC)2, (X, ), C). is an ordered completion of a morphism and (X*, *, f* , C) (X, ), defined by Cauchy space 2 I’ I I’ CI (XI’ (X I, and OCON, then there f such that , (COC)3. f:(X, If Then ) is a unique f* j. We have previously observed that conditions (COC) 2 and (COC) 3 (X, @) (X*, @) is an order embedding. It is also clear that j (X*, *C) is Cauchy-continuous, and that j(X) is dense in (X, C) -I is also X*. The fact that Cauchy-continuous follows from (COC) and the < result (used also in the preceding proof) that () U > j-l(, (j() [])) (along with the dual equality). PROOF. guarantee that Given a function f*([]) by y f as specified, let where C f() f* be the natural extension defined Then ) f*: (X*, (X1, C I) is Cauchy-continuous by the well-known extension properties of Wyler’s completion (see [5]), and To show that f($) f*: (X*, f* O f() *C) (XI, i) is Cauchy-continuous by Proposition 3.1. is increasing, we first note that I" in Since I $ in implies f() is complete, we have also that and it follows from Proposition 1.2, [8] that., f*([$]) yf() Yf(0 f(0, f*([])" | Henceforth, the ordered completion of (X, @, ) defined in Theorem 3.6 will be denoted by (X*, >*, C*) rather than (X* *) Following [4], we define an ordered completion ((X*, i, j) to be order-strict if, for any ordered completion ((X*, )’ j) in standard form, From Proposition 3.4, it follows that the ordered completion of ! * CI) 2’ 2 I 2" Theorem 3.6 is order strict. COROLLARY 3.7. For an o.c.s. , (X, C), the following statements are equivalent. , , () (x, (2) (X, O, ) satisfies conditions (COC)I (COC) 2, and (COC) 3. C) has an order-strict ordered completion. (X, ) (X* O* *) is an ordered completion of (X (3) (4) c0cs fi) , , Without repeating the relevant definitions here, we remark that, in the terminology of (X*, *, C*) [5], the functor K: COCS OCON, defined by K(X, C) is an order-strict completion functor, and consequently that COCS is a completion subcategory of OCS. as the fine ordered completion of , We shall henceforth refer to (X, C), and K ((X*, @*, C*), j) will be called the fine ordered completion functor. 4. UNIFOMIZABLE ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES. Let , (X, O, ) be a poset (X, @) equipped with a T . uniformity Then 2 if there is a quasiuniformity (X, ) is a uniform ordered space (Nachbin, [9]) g U g -I and g on X such that g; such a quasiuniformity is said to determine (X, ). The set of -Cauchy filters is denoted by , D. C. KENT AND R. VAINIO 492 (UOC) (3x3) (g(3) U and so (g-l(3) (UOC) 2 x (,)) S x 3 - , x 3 . in (X, g. D __D x g. 9__ g g() x -I __D S U S = __D S (x,y) , ) (X, g N y. x (X, is a uniform ordered space, then X that determines ,60,C 3 x c_ Conditions (UOC) ’2 2 and (OC) (X, , , is ). Let Clearly g generates and therefore (UOC) 3 thus imply follows from (UOC)I and the by Theorem 2.9. o.c.s, (X, @, C) is uniformizable if there is a T 2 uniform ordered space C such that THEOREM 4.3. Similarly, This implies that ,) An o.c.s. D x) g(,. D since But conditions (OC) and (OC) 3, respectively. 2 Thus (X, is an fact that g ! <O> , %{) g -I(3) S-l)) U (3 x @ )- S" S D Then, by Proposition 2.5, Thus ( g() x (S (,39 x D a quasiuniform convergence structure coarser than $ 3 N g D__ g 3 x 3 Likewise, gl()) be a quasiuniformity on Let PROOF. x x x If g. 3 __D S D then %( g and x THEOREM 4.2. x g-1 S U g () and (3) x g(3) x (S(@) U S() __c an o.c.s. < g and so 3 x (UOC) 3 3 _= 3 E __c x _< y. then g-l(,)) g(3)) x _ c (UOC) PROOF. g () g If g(3) C . cq-l(3)E then g (3) U E If 2 (UOC) 3 But Then the following conditions hold. C, If 3 ( (UOC) be a uniform ordered space determined by a (X, ,) Let PROPOSITION 4.1. quasiuniformity g Each uniformizable o.c.s, has an ordered completion. (X, ), C) , 7) be a compatible uniform ordered space; let g be a quasi-uniformity which determines Let PROOF. (X, ,). C Let 3 g (3) g ! and g(3) preceding proof that be a uniformizable o.c.s., and let U x Then 3 $ J x, and consequently < U @($), and therefore g() ! @(3) (3) c 8 (3) 0 < L 3 > forward argument shows that follow from (UOC) 2 and Thus g() (UOC)3, (COC) and it follows from the x ! 3 (X, U> g() ! > Similarly, follows from < (UOC)I. Also A straight- whenever 3 < ! respectively. and so (COC) and (COC) 2 3 The conclusion follows by Theorem 3.6. It is natural to ask whether the fine completion functor K, when restricted o.c.s.’s, to uniformizable the answer is no. preserves uniformizability. As the next example shows, The same example shows that the fine completion preserves neither regularity nor total boundedness. EXAMPLE 4.4. partial order: are E-related E Let E be the Euclidean plane with the usual topology and {(a,b), (c,d)): a c and b _< d}. iff they lie on the same vertical line. Note that the elements in {L n N} U Let Y n E 493 ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES {(0,0)}, {( Ln where }; y _< y): 0 (Y, O’, 4’) let be the compact, T z- ordered topological space (considered as an object in OCON) with order and topology inherited from E. Let Cauchy structures which , tively. (X, X N} n T2-ordered is a compact, respec- (X, O, ), completion of ((X*, 0., *), j) an obvious correspondence between the sets Let be the Frechet filter on be the corresponding filter on X*. is non-convergent relative to Y (X, O, ). of There is relative to which the Y X* and S correspond te the subset X* equivalence classes of non-convergent filters in Y. The order and and is a uniformizable o.c.s. Now consider the fine completion of Y- S. X and let are denoted by O Y inherits from (Y, 0’, ’) Since ) {( S ), and let ( converges to (0,0) in (Y, 4’), p ( X* is the equivalence class of the sequence Although (X*, *). If of filters converging in (X, ) to the origin, then the closure of the p-neighborhood filter in (X*, *) is nonconvergent, and so (X*, *) is not regular, and consequently not uniformizable. (Y, ’, ’) From the fact that is totally bounded (meaning that every ultrafilter on converges in ultrafilter finer than (X, is compact, it also follows that X ). is in , ) Since no (X*, *), we see that total boundedness is not preserved by the fine completion functor. Although no definition of "regularity" has been given for ordered Cauchy (X, O, 4) spaces, the space as an ordered Cauchy subspace of a T2-ordered, compact topological space, would be "regular" by any reasonable definition of that term. (X*, G*, ) Since convergence space sense) no is not regular (in the usual reasonable notion of regularity is preserved by the fine completion functor. TOTALLY ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES. 5. We begin with a simple condition which is sufficient for the existence of an ordered completion of an o.c.s. An o.c.s. DEFINITION 5.1. ) i < U, satisfies Condition (A) ] nonconvergent, there is is i , (X, such that O-I (I) c__ if, whenever < > and L > If (X, @, g) PROPOSITION 5.2. is an o.c.s, which satisfies Condition (A), then: (COC) (3) (COC) 2 (OC) 2 (COC) 3 (OC) 3 (X, @, ) has an ordered completion. (5) PROOF. (I) -l(y), and on coincide. (OC) Suppose < and U < > L follows < reasoning shows that implies < If exists. intmediately. Condition (A) guarantees that Q < The relations (2) (4) L Q (I) U -I() whenever U If converges to exists, and so < U > y, then is nonconvergent, exists. < Similar Thus it is clear that The converse is always true. Statements (2), (3), (4), and (5) are easy corollaries of (1). | D. C. KENT AND R. VAINIO 494 (X, ), C) x* x x*: Note that if {([], []) o* < }. (X, ,C ) PROPOSITION 5.3. (F) 0 G -I(F) () U PROOF. ~< ~< But A L. -I () t.o.c.s, -I c_ Condition (A). every ordered completion of () D exists, and so [], @() C be nonconvergent. L> (X, U If exists, which implies This, along with the dual argument, proves , , C) has an ordered completion, and (X, C) is totally ordered. The existence of an ordered completion follows immediately from PROOF. Proposition 5.2 and 5.5. (X*, *, C*) The completion is totally ordered by Proposition 5.3 and the remark following Proposition 5.2. @* . satisfies Condition (A). Every t.o.c.s. COROLLARY 5.6. 0 G []. be a t.o.c.s., and let < 5, and since < () Thus then )-I(F)) is impossible. assumed, so by (OC) 2, (X, @, C) Let PROOF. x E fails to exist, then is PROPOSITION 5.5. such that be a t.o.c.s, and exists, or else () D If X N G X, and G and ((F) U which means that -I(F) (X, O, C) Let COROLLARY 5.4. , G (F) U is nonempty, then either (X, @), are filters on a totally ordered set and -1() and F If is a total order. U exists. exists, or If both fail to exist, there is F E PROOF. Since for which @ (5)!J then either (abbreviated t.o.c.s.) will be used space The term totally ordered Cauchy for any o.c.s. (A), then is an o.c.s, satisfying Condition Since the total order is the smallest allowable order for an ordered completion in standard form, it is the only possible order for an ordered completion in standard form. 6. AN ORDERED COACTIFICATION. Every compactification of an ordered topological or convergence T2-ordered space can be regarded as the completion of a certain totally bounded o.c.s., and so the entire subject of T2-ordered present investigation. compactifications lies within the scope of our Our immediate goal, however, is rather modest; we shall formulate the ordered convergence compactification constructed in [8] as an ordered Cauchy space completion, thereby gaining some further insight into its properties. Let (X, the notation , +) be an ordered convergence space (i.e., an object in OCON); x" "7 relative to X consisting of all convergent filters [8]) let X’ be the set of all nonconvergent, (X, O, +). In [8] an ordered convergence space and (following maximal convex filters on (X, O, +) is defined to be strongly dual are satisfied: If x, T2-ordered, X’ and With each ordered convergence space structure Let C converges to x in this space. indicates that be the complete Cauchy structure on C U F(X): there is if the following property and its () exists, -I() c (X, @, +), we associate the Cauchy 6 X’ is the finest Cauchy structure compatible with such that G c }. Note that which is both totally 495 ORDERED CAUCHY SPACES bounded and locally convex relative to (X,N) A Cauchy completion of If X* the filter on [8] PROPOSITION 6.1. is a T 2 T2-ordered (X, ) F(X), let If Let F(X*): (X, +). , (X, A convergence ordered space PROPOSITION 6.2. iff 5}. }. A and For any ordered convergence space compactification of , X’ {: F generated by $ c }. such that $ in standard form is constructed as follows. X*: j(X) U {[] A c X, let (X, be there is , -), (X*, is strongly is an o.c.s, which satisfies Condition (A). (X, (9, ) is an o.c.s., then (X, (9, +), which is its associated convergence space, is clearly an ordered convergence space. It is also clear that )) implies the strongly Condition (A) applied to (X, property for PROOF. If , T2-ordered (x, (9, +). < Conversely, assume (X, relative to , ), where -, are both A convex, and either which is non-convergent is assumed to be maximal convex. straightforward argument based on the strongly T2-ordered property leads to exactly one of the following conclusions: (I) (2) (3) (4) X x, y There are There is x X There is y X Both $ and such that such that 5 such that (X, < I($I). L> 8/ y, is nonconvergent, and () c (OC)I, (OC) 2, and (OC) , N) is an o.c.s. @() ! l, or , Finally, if and of (X, , * it follows that (X*, *, *) which implies ((X*, @*, ), j) is an order-strict, (X, 8, -) which is the fine completion of [8], we obtain: +) is strongly T2-ordered compactification 4" is finer than If "* is also has an extension of the From Theorem 3 6 (X, @, ) totally bounded, then is also a compactification, and indeed T2-ordered of )* in this case. Under the assumptions of Theorem 6.3, compactification of When this happens, (X, (9, It is shown in [8] that, (X*, @*, (X, @, +) iff N* (X*, *, *) j) is is totally * ), j)[8]. coincides with the compactification constructed in under the assumptions of is the largest "relatively regular" There is not, in general, a largest T2-ordered , (X, If an ordered convergence space PROPOSITION 6.4. the largest (X*, *, are easily -). (X* (9* bounded. 3 is nonconvergent, I(), x equivalently Under the assumptions of Theorem 6.3, form (9() This, along with the dual argument establishes Condition (A). THEOREM 6.3. T2-ordered, c then statement (2) above x Combining the preceding results and Proposition 2.8, then () are nonconvergent, and is the maximal convex filter coarser than gives the result () is nonconvergent, and With the help of these results, conditions verified, and so y, and x, x, T2-ordered T2-ordered Theorem 6.3, (X*, *, (X, @, +). compactiication of compactification of a strongly convergence space as the concluding example shows. D. C. KENT AND R. VAINIO 496 This example is based on Example 4.4, and the same definitions EXAMPLE 6.5. , /) be the T2-ordered topological Let (X, is the relativization to X of (X, ,); in other words, is the finest locally convex the usual topology on E. It turns out that +). The compactotally bounded Cauchy structure on X compatible with (X, and notation will be used here. space compatible with , (X*, @* tification while the fine completion * Thus, in general, (X*, *, *) , and structure on (X, @, @’) is not totally bounded. There is no largest T2-ordered (I,0) instead of (0,0). Then (Y, ’, C") (X, @, +) which is neither larger nor smaller filters are assigned to converge to than of are distinct. ’ ). Indeed, suppose C" is the complete Cauchy (X, Y which agrees with ’, except that the filter and all finer compactificatlon of is a (Y, is equivalent to the compactification T2-ordered compactification of (Y’, @’, ’). By altering the order structure in the preceding example, one can get quite Suppose different results. by unchanged, but replacing (X, (X, +) i’ /) @i’ the is obtained by leaving X and It usual order of the Euclidean plane. and that is again the finest compatible totally bounded locally convex Cauchy structure. In this case the fine turns out that (X*, completion , Proposition 6.4, [8], @I’ is strongly T2-ordered *) of (X, @I, (X*, @, *) coincides and is the largest T2-ordered is totally bounded. Thus, by with the compactification constructed in compactification of (X, I’ +) REFERENCES Convergence and Cauchy Structures on Lattice Ordered Groups, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 259 (1980), 357-392. I. BALL, R.N. 2. BALL, R.N. Cut Completions of Lattice Ordered Groups by Cauchy Constructions, Groups, M. Dekker, Lecture Notes in Pure and Appl. Math. Vol. 62 (1980), 81-92. Ordered 3. Cook, C.H. and FISHER, H.R. Uniform Convergence Structures, Math. Annalen 173 (1967), 290-306. 4. FLETCHER, P. and LINDGREN, W. Quasi-uniform Spaces, Lecture Notes in Pure and Appl. Math. Vol. 77 (1982). 5. FRIC, R. and KENT, D.C. Completion Functors for Cauchy Spaces, Internat. J. Math. & Math. Sci. 4 (1979), 589-604. 6. GHLER, W. Grundstrukturen der Analysis, Band I, Akademie-Verlag, Berlin (1977). 7. KELLER, H.H. Die Limes-Uniformisierbarkeit der Limesrume, Math. Annalen 176 (1968), 334-341. 8. KENT, D.C. and RICHARDSON, G.D. 9. NACHBIN, L. 10. REED, E.E. Completions of Uniform Convergence Spaces, Math. Annalen (1971), 83-108. A Compactification for Convergence Ordered Spaces, Canadian Math. Bull. 27 (1984) 505-513. Topology and Order, Van Nostrand Math. Studies, No. 4, Princeton, N. J. (1965). 194