209 Internat. J. Math. & Math. Sci. (!987) 209-216 Vol. i0 Nc. 2 ORDER COMPATIBILITY FOR CAUCHY SPACES AND CONVERGENCE SPACES D.C. KENT Department of Pure and Avvlied Mathematics Washington State University Pullman, WA 99164-2930 and REINO VAINIO BO AKADEMI Matematiska Institutionen Fnriksgaan 3 SF-20500 BO 50 Finland Received July 28, 1986) A Cauchy structure and a preorder on the same set are said to be compat- ABSTRACT. Howover, ible if both arise from the same quasi-uniform convergence structure on X. there are two natural ways to derive the former structures from the latter, leading to "strong" and "weak" notions of order compatibility for Cauchy spaces. These in turn lead to characterizations of strong and weak order compatibility for convergence spaces. Preordered Cauchy space, preordered convergence space, weakly preordered space, quasi-uniform convergence space. KEY WORDS AND PHRASES. 1980 MATHE4ATICS SUBJECT CLASSIFICATION CODE. 54A20, 54E15, 54F05 INTRODUCTION L. Nachbin, [3], introduced order compatibility between a uniform structure and a preorder @ on the same set X by requiring the existence of a quasi-uniformity g on X such that gU g-I [2], An analogous procedure was used by to define order compatibility between a Cauchy on X; the principal deviation from Nachbin’s and a partial order structure g. and @ the authors in an earlier paper, definition is the replacement of "quasi-uniformity" by "quasi-uniform convergence structure". However we required in [2] . that the quasi-uniform convergent structure employed be coarser than that generated by the order If the latter restriction is removed, a weaker form of order compatibility is obtained. This paper examines both types of order compatibility for Cauchy spaces. "strong" version is the subject of Section assuming that I; here we extend the results of @ is a preorder rather than a partial order. derived from a "preordered Cauchy space" is called a The [2] by A convergence space "preordered convergence space", and these are shown to be precisely the locally convex convergence spaces for "hich the preorder is closed. In Section 2, we consider the "weak" form of order compatibility, a topic not previously studied. The characterization of "weakly preordered Cauchy spaces", is given in two forms, the first of which provides a convenient comparison with the D.C. KENT and R. VAINIO 210 preordered Cauchy spaces of Section I. The second leads to a simple characterization of weakly preordered convergence spaces. l’ne terminology and noaio of reference. [2] will be used ill his paper inhou further is a preorder However we shall always assume in this present paper that (i.e., a transitive, reflexive relation). PREORDERED CAUCHY SPACES (STRONG COMPATIBILITY). From Definitions 2.1 and 2.2 of [2], we obtain the definitions of preordered is uniform convergence space and preordered Cauchy space by simply ussuming that I. a preorder instead of a partial order. The latter term will be abbreviated "p.c.s". is a partial order is called an ordered Cauchy pace ) for which A p.c.s. (X, ), we have "strong" compatibility (abbreviated "o.c.s.") In a p.c.s. (X, because of the requirement in Definition 2.1, [2], that the filter between @ and , <> , The relaxation of this requirement leads to be in o. on X x X generated by the "weak" compatibility studied in the next section. In this section, we consider triples of the form (X, @ ,C ), where (X, is a is a preordered set and C a Cauchy structure on X. In determining when (X, ,C [2], 486, on defined p. as Cauchy of < filters, C set on the p.c.s., the preorder plays a vital role since it is required in formulating two of the following conditions (see also p. 487, (OC)I (OC) If 2 , , < and , C; then implies x _< y. x < (0c) 3 C whenever < C [2]): The first condition defines "local convexity" for a Cauchy structure on a preordered The second condition is the convex hull of () D set; recall that -I) ^ is antisymmetric relative to Cauchy equivalence asserts that the preorder < on classes, and the third turns out to be equivalent to the order being closed in XXX. It was shown in Theorem 2.9, an o.c.s, iff conditions we show that when (OC) I, [2], (0C2), is a preorder, (X, is a partial order, that when and (OC) 3 are all satisfied. , (X, , ) is In this section C) is a p.c.s, iff the same conditions This task is made easier by the fact that all lemmas and Propositions in is a Section 2, [2] prior to Theorem 2.9 remain valid under the assumption that hold. preorder rather than a partial or_der. Whereas the statement of Theorem 2.9, [2] is a preorder, the proof of this theorem must be altered, remains valid when since it makes explicit use of the assumption that particular Proposition 2.8, [2] is valid when is antisymmetric. Since, in is a preorder, the principal theorem (0C)2, , (OC)3 and of this section reduces to showing that (OC) I, imply that (X, is a p.c.s. Thus for the remainder of this section we assume that (X C is a preordered set with Cauchy structure which satisfies (OC)I’ (OC)2’ and (OC) 3. the elements of X is defined as )= an mquvalne rlan {y ( X: x y} be the equivalence Let E y iff (x,y) ( follows: x x > be the filter of oversets of E class containing x, and let <E Given (Y. -I. ORDER COMPATIBILITY FOR CAUCHY SPACES AND CONVERGENCE SPACES LE4A I.I. <E > For each x <Ex> X, ( y in (X,q C) for all y ( C. x It is obvious that E PROOF. (y) N Y y, the conclusion follows by (OC) and LEMMA 1.2. such that Ex PROOF. If Furthermore, (C and for all y { X. x <> In particular, Since E E x y N -I. then there is x qc y in (X, such that F x F Choose F Ex. I. is a filter on X such that " ( -l(y), 211 X Ex. for all y clearly x ( F implies F c E The second statement follows by Lena 1. From Lemma 2 and , E x my LEMMA 1.3. <> c (OC)3, the next lemma follows easily. , Assume that and E x (i) E (2) n, (3) <8> c ( y . <> are filters on X such that: c The following statements are equivalent: C (:x) N (x:) (X, THEOREM 1.4. , C) (OCI) (OC)2 is a p.c.s, iff conditions and (OC) 3 are satisfied. PROOF. As we have noted previously, it is enough to prove that the three conditions are sufficient. we see that (X, ,C) C, where compatible with and v (,C) ,C to show that -i j=l ,C x j) [2] A [2], K1 _c < 2’ 2 K1 hl x and E Since K I 2 2 y K1 K2 and K2 KI. But then D from Lemma 3 that E x K < 2’ and , ,C ’’ n. j > K. x both finer than K2, If E X. for some x 2hen there must Otherwise, there must such that and, for nonequivalent elements x and y, E x x D 6, one can show that and K2 (OC) 2 I requires that 1N K K2 { If : I finer than K }, a contradiction. finer than I we conclude that such that and i ( <> [2] x K leads to Thus if C Assume instead that there is an ultrafilter for some and so E 6 Then < > c x X the proof is complete. such that A C, and it follows The argument given in paragraphs 2 and 3 of the proof of Theorem 2.9, ( K for all ( C such that the conclusion that there is I 2.4, [2] where for all x E be the set of all ultrafilters ( is C implies x x such that < x > 5 Suppose finer than x o,C <@>, and be (by Lemma ) ultrafilters Let and is characterized in Proposition we may assume by Lemma i. be an ultrafilter <> _c C ,C In view of Proposition 2.7, [2], it is sufficient C In other words, we must show, as in the x that j)) C x ( X, then ,C (,C)-I. By Proposition 2.4, @ U(: is compatible with proof of Theorem 2.9, n From Proposition 2.6, (generalized to preordered sets), is a p.c.s, iff D.C. KENT and R. VAINIO 212 X by Lemma 2. x A repetition of a previous argument shows that every such ultrafor the same x X. If ]L is the set of all such must contain E filter ultrafilters and X N{ ’2 : IL it follows that E I It remains only to show that K and are in C K can deduce that < statement C 2 Let 2’ and so ]L. 6 ]( and Then K, from which it follows by (OC) 2 that X N C C, and the proof is complete. If (X, PROPOSITION 1.5. PROOF. N ( As in an earlier paragraph of the proof, we G D < and IN 2 Thus X and x , C) is a p.c.s., then X. is closed in X It is shown in Proposition 2.7, [2], that (OC) is equivalent to the 3 U{Q is closed under Since <> @, o@,C and : compositions @=U{Do <> o: o,C the last equality follows from 4.1.5, p. 301, to the product convergence structure on X on X compatible with where the closure being taken relative X derived from the convergence structure [I], the latter convergence qc structure is precisely Let (X,q) [I], By Proposition 2.6, ,C o,C ,C <> U{ be a convergence space (in the sense of Fischer), let q C be the set of all q-convergent filters, and let q(x) be the set of all filters which q-converge to x. It is well known that the following statements are equivalent: (a) (b) There is a Cauchy structure C on X such that q q C is a Cauchy structure on X. (c) For x, y ( q c X, q(x) and q(y) are either equal or disjoint. If (X,) is a preordered set and q a convergence structure on X, we define the triple (X, @, q) to be a preordered convergence space if there is a Cauchy structure C on X such that (X, ,C qc be a preordered set, q a convergence structure on Let (X, PROPOSITION 1.6. X. is a p.c.s, and q C q) is a p.c.s. q) is a preordered convergence space iff (X, C be a Let (X, @ q) be a preordered convergence space, and let (X, Then (X, @ PROOF. p.c.s, such that q q Note that c q D C. From the fact that (X, @, C) satisfies (X, @, cq) has the same properties. (OC) and (OC) 3, Furthermore the latter space also satisfies (OC) 2, since for complete spaces (OC) 2 follows immediately from (OC) 3. it is easy to deduce that The converse argument is trivial. Let (X, ) be a preordered set, q a convergence structure on X. q) is locally convex q) is a preordered convergence space iff (X, THEOREM 1.7. Then (X, , , and @ is closed. PROOF. Using Proposition 1.5, it is a simple matter to verify that the two properties specified for (X, satisfies (OC) and (OC) 3. , , q) are equivalent to the assertion that (X, @, Since (X, q) q) is complete, Theorem 1.4 and Proposition 1.6 imply the desired conclusion. 2. WEAKLY PREORDERED CAUCHY SPACES (WEAK COMPATIBILITY). a preorder on X, and As before, we assume that X is a set, structure on X. (X, , a Cauchy C) is defined to be a weakly preordered Cauchy space if there is a quasi-uniform convergence structure on X such that: (I) the uniform 213 ORDER COMPATIBILITY FOR CAUCHY SPACES AND CONVERGENCE SPACES convergence structure (2) U{ }. v j -I derived from = has C as its set of Cauchy filters; This definition differs from that of preordered Cauchy space only in the condition < which is required for the latter but not for , > our present definition. We abbreviate weakly preordered Cauchy space by "w.p.c.s.". on X, let be the quasi-uniform convergence structure on Given a preorder Y X with base consisting of all finite filter intersections of the form 0{x i x Yi n}. If, in addition, C is a Cauchy structure i (xi’ y’) on X, let where the lattice meet i taken in the lattice of all T,C ^ ’ quasi-uniform convergence structures on X. C in as follows: Q fl iff or there is (x,y) fl As we shal see, that o,C Finally, we define a preorder on filters I,C 9 C and and such that Qplay the same role in the theory of weak compatibility respectively, play in that of strong compatibility. and PROPOSITION 2.1. Let (X,) be a preordered set with Cauchy structure has a base of sets consisting of all finite intersections of the form j n}, where j n. Y, { j xj j PROOF each I 2 " n fl where i and i (I) "i i C (i.e., 3i C )" By i i fom and there are two possibilities for i i (xi, yi) where j, Consider a composition of the x Then , or (2) i’ i and examining four possible cases, it is easy to verify that the existence of the composition i Q i+l" implies that we obtain for the entire chain of compositions i i+l Thus if Q I n’ and and 61 %0...0 %. We thus see that filters of the form indicated in the proposlton are in and a base for involves taking finite compositions and intersections of YC such Y,C It can be shown by a straightforward set theoretic argument that any filters. finite composition of filters of the indicated form can again be written as a finite intersection of filters of the same form, which is the desired conclusion PROPOSITION 2.2. and C is compatible with PROOF. , A triple (X, , T,C C) v is a w.p.c.s, iff (T,) (X, , U{ : , }, T, -I C) is a w.p.c.s, according to the definition of this term. Conversely, assume that (X, C) is a w.p.c.s, derived from a quasi-uniform convergence structure v and let be the associated Given the two conditions, , uniform convergence structure and since u{ne : C ^ are compatible with C u} a u{ne:e so is ,e , s-I Then it is easy to see that Also C since (x,y) D{0 x x : C 6 @ and o} T, We next introduce conditions on a triple (X, ,C which lead to a characterization of a w.p.c.s, similar to that given for a p.c.s, in Theorem 1.4. It turns out that only two such conditions are needed to (OC) 2 and (OC)3, respectively. (woc)2 and (woc) which are analogous 3 There is no form of "local convexity" involved in the characterization of weak compatibility, and so we shall later use (woc) to describe a single condition (not related to and (wo) 3 (OC)p which can replace both (woc) 2 D.C. KENT and R. VAINIO 214 (woc)2 (woc) , If W @ 3 @, are in C, Q and WA then C. implies (x,y) E @. If (X, ,) PROPOSITION 2.3. satisfied. is a w.p.c.s., then (woc) and (woc) 2 are 3 , Q, and Q. Then, by Proposition 2.1, C x Thus () x and T, T,C () and by Proposition 2.2, x) x By Proposition 2.1, x y i, and so (x,y) is a w.p.c.s, iff conditions (woc) and (woc) are THEOREM 2.4. (X, ,C 2 Assume PROOF. x r, 3 satisfied. Using Proposition 2.2, we must show: PROOF. =P’ (2) : U{ }. T,c T,c x implying Te, If (x,y) N, Let -1 j x.j _ so that N which implies x x Q E ,e implies T ,e x (.j j)) _DG= then x x and so (x,y) , , "i j@ j. N x,i c. @ and @N and ZG (woe)3" by By where x, be distinct ultrafilters finer than indices i, j such that This implies , G for some f By Proposition 2.1, Proposition 2.1, we may assume l,...,n. (Te, C T, It is sufficient to show (2) for j V @, then x If (x,y) (I). (x,y) , where P j Q j, Then there are and i@"i Thu where by (woc)2. Rearranging the indices if necessary, let l,...,m be the indices such that, if , j _< m, then there are ultrafilters where j @ ’3 in g Let j finer than and 7 _m H Thus such that jlj. preceding paragraph leads to the conclusion that ultrafilter H { which implies We now introduce the condition (woc qC(x) q(y) iff (x,y) { D__ for a triple (X, , for every is ). -i. It is significant that this condition is formulated entirely in terms of q the convergence structure derived from is a w.p.c.s, iff condition (woc) is satisfied. (X, In both directions of this proof, we use the characterization of a THEOREM 2.5. PROOF. w.p.c.s, given in Theorem 2.4. . Assume that x" qe y in (x,y) A @ argument, established. (X,. , x satisfies (woc) n e, -iThus If (x,y) By (woc) 2, q(y) implies and. 2 implies x which_l and A A (woc) q(x), and so 3. and then If qC(y), ?(x)By (woc) 3, @ and then x. (q(y). qC(x) qC(y). implying q(x), j, j The reasoning of the 1 and that N C and the proof complete. (woc) x m A By the symmetric Thus (woc) is and 215 ORDER COMPATIBILITY FOR CAUCHY SPACES AND CONVERGENCE SPACES Conversely, assume that (X,,) satisfies (woc) Q Q and Considering only the nonobvious case, we can assume that there @ such that $ x C and N C. We can also assume there is 9 @ such that $ (b, a) Let I. C. 5, is (x,y) where C and O C qc(a) Then qC(x) qc[a) @0-I and (b,y) -1. (woc)l Thus (x,a), (a,b), (b,y) are all in @-i, which implies (x,y) -I. Thus @ N -I, and again by (x,y) (woc)l we conclude q(x) qC(y). Consequently, 0 implying 0 C and so (woc)2 is established. qC(x) qC(y), To prove (woc)3, let x Q 9. If x 9 6 then q (x) q (y), and (x,y) qC(x). qc(b) Likewise, qC(y ). By (a,x) , follows by (woc) x and C, a 9 q(y) I. Otherwise there are elements a, b in X such that (a,b) But this implies q (a) C. I] qc(b), so that (y,b) -I @ q (x), so that (x,a) and I, [i Thus (x,a), (a,b), (b,y) are all in @ and so (x,y) @. Next, we consider weak compatibility for convergence spaces. preordered set, and let q be a convergence structure on X. weakly preordered convergence, (X, C) is a w.p.c.s, and q , , If (X, space if there is a Cauchy structure , q) is a on X such that qc. q) is a weakly preordered convergence space, then it is an immediate consequence of Theorem 2.5 that every Cauchy sructure C compatible with q has the (X, @, C) is a w.p.c.s.; in particular (X, @, property that Let (X,) be a The triple (X, q) has this property. Thus we obtain For a preordered set (X, COROLLARY 2.6. with convergence structure q, the following statements are equivalent. (X, @ q) is a weakly preordered convergence space. (X, @, q) is a w.p.c.s. (a) (b) (c) is a Cauchy structure on X such that q If qc then (X, ,C) is a w.p.c.s. One final characterization of weakly preordered convergence space which makes no reference to the notion of Cauchy structure is given in the next theorem. The triple (X, @ THEOREM 2.7. q) is a weakly preordered convergence space iff the following conditions are satisfied: -i (a) (x,y) q(y) implies q(x) (b) @-i (x,y) @ PROOF. If (X, implies q(x) q(y)= ,q . is a weakly preordered convergence space, then (a) follows immediately from Corollary 2.6, and (b) follows from Corollary 2.6 and the fact that q q c for some Cauchy structure C q) Conversely, assume the two conditions; it suffices to show that (X, satisfies condition (woc) I. From (a) and (b), we see that for any x, y q X, q(x) and q(y) are either equal or disjoint; thus C is a Cauchy structure. Also (a) gives "half" of condition (woc)l, and the other "half" comes from (b), since q(x) q(y) implies q(x) In case q(y) # , and so (x,y) -i. is a partial order, it is appropriate to speak of a weakly ordered Cauchy space or a weakly ordered conve.rg.ence space in the case of weak order compatibility. (X, ,C In this case the compatibility is indeed "weak", since any triple where (X, ) is any poset and C any T Cauchy a weakly ordered Cauchy space, and likewise if q is any T structure will constitute 2 convergence space then D.C. EENT and R. AINIO 216 , q) will be a weakly ordered convergence space. It is well known that, in (X, C) general, every T 1Cauchy space has a variety of T completions. Thus if (X, is any weakly ordered Cauchy space and (X’, C’) is any T 1 completion of (X,C), then can be defined on X’ in many ways so as to make (X’, ’, ’) a a partial order , ’ weakly ordered Cauchy completion of (X, , treatment of this topic may be found in [2]. C). In the case of strong compatibility the completion theory is much more complicated. Not all ordered Cauchy spaces have ordered Cauchy completions. A detailed REFERENCES i. GHLER, W. Gr,,.dqtrr,,-- der Ana3ysi. Bsnd und Stuttgart 1977. 2. KENT, D. C. and VANIO, R. Sci. 8 (1985), 483-496. 3. NACHBIN, L. 1965. ! Birh,,=r Vrag, Basel Ordered Cauchy Spaces, Internat. J. Math. and Math. Topo.logy and Order, Van Nostrand Studies, No. 4, Princeton, N.