Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 13, No. 8, 2004, pp. 129–146. COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS To Aurelio Carboni on his 60th birthday STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE Abstract. We show, for a monad T, that coalgebra structures on a T-algebra can be described in terms of “braidings”, provided that the monad is equipped with an invertible distributive law satisfying the Yang-Baxter equation. 1. Introduction The aim of this note is to provide an equivalent description of T∗ -coalgebra structures on a T-algebra, for T a monad — equipped with a special kind of distributive law — on a category C, and T∗ the comonad induced by the adjunction Co LT / Alg(T) RT LT R T Our interest for such coalgebras is motivated mainly by classical descent theory: let f : R → S be a morphism of commutative unital rings, and consider the induced functor f ! : R-mod → S-mod defined by f !(N ) = N ⊗R S (where S is seen as an R-module by restriction of scalars). The descent problem for f consists in recognizing when an S-module is of the form f !(N ) for some R-module N. A classical theorem [6, 2, 7], which establishes a deep link between descent theory and the theory of (co)monads, asserts that, if f is faithfully flat, then an S-module is of the form f !(N ) if and only if it is equipped with a T∗ -coalgebra structure, where T∗ is the comonad on S-mod induced by the adjunction R-mod o f! f∗ / S-mod f! f∗ and f ∗ is the restriction of scalars functor. (For this reason, a T∗ -coalgebra structure on an S-module M is sometimes called a descent datum for M.) It is also well-known that, for Second author supported by the Australian Research Council; third author by FNRS grant 1.5.116.01. Received by the editors 2003-12-11 and, in revised form, 2004-10-01. Published on 2004-12-05. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification: 18C15, 18C20, 18D10, 16B50. Key words and phrases: Descent data, monads, distributive laws, Yang-Baxter equation. c Stefano Kasangian, Stephen Lack, and Enrico M. Vitale, 2004. Permission to copy for private use granted. 129 130 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE any morphism f : R → S of commutative unital rings, there are several equivalent ways of describing what a T∗ -coalgebra structure for an S-module is, and a natural problem is to lift to a categorical level these other descriptions of T∗ -coalgebra structures. In a recent paper [11], Menini and Stefan, extending results by Nuss [12] on noncommutative rings, replace the situation R-mod o f! / f∗ S-mod f! f∗ Alg(T) LT R T by Co LT RT / where T is a monad on an arbitrary category C (indeed, even in the non-commutative situation, f ∗ : S-mod → R-mod is a monadic functor, so that S-mod is equivalent to the category of algebras for the monad on R-mod induced by the adjunction f ! f ∗ ). In this context, they prove that, if the monad T is equipped with a “compatible flip” K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 , then to give a T∗ -coalgebra structure on a T-algebra X is equivalent to giving a “symmetry” on X, that is an involution T X → T X satisfying some suitable conditions. Unfortunately, the following natural example, which is a direct generalization of the classical case of commutative rings, does not fit into their general context: let C be a braided monoidal category and let S be a monoid in C, then the braiding cS,S : S ⊗ S → S ⊗ S induces a natural isomorphism K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 on the monad T = − ⊗ S : C → C, but this natural isomorphism is not a flip unless the braiding is a symmetry and the monoid is commutative. In this note we adapt the notions of “compatible flip” and “symmetry” to encompass the previous example, as well as another example coming from the theory of bialgebras. In Section 2 we introduce the notion of BD-law on a monad T as a special case of distributive law in the sense of Beck [1]. Using a BD-law K, we can define K-braidings on a T-algebra, and we want to show that K-braidings correspond bijectively to T∗ -coalgebra structures. There are two different methods: in Section 3 we use K-braidings to define a category Brd(T, K) equipped with a forgetful functor V : Brd(T, K) → Alg(T). We show, using the Beck criterion [10], that V is comonadic; and that the corresponding comonad is T∗ , so that Brd(T, K) is isomorphic to Coalg(T∗ ). In Section 4 we give a different proof based as far as possible on general facts about monads and distributive laws. This second proof is quite long, but it seems to us of some interest, since it shows that the bijection between K-braidings and T∗ -coalgebra structures is the natural bijection induced by a pair of adjoint functors. The description of K-braidings we obtain in this way is slightly different, but in fact equivalent, to that used in Section 3. 131 COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS 2. BD-laws on a monad To begin, we fix notation. A monad T on a category C is a triple T = (T : C → C, m : T 2 ⇒ T, e : IdC ⇒ T ) consisting of a functor T , and natural transformations m and e making the diagrams eT Te +3 T 2 ks T MMM qT MMM (1) qqq (2) q MMM q q m qqq T MMM M "* t| qqq T T T3 mT Tm (3) T2 m +3 T 2 m +3 T commute. A T-algebra is a pair (X, x : T X → X) in C such that the diagrams eX / TX X OOO OOO (4) OOO x OOO 1 OO' X T 2X mX TX Tx / TX (5) x x /X commute. Given two monads T and S on the same category C, a distributive law of T over S is a natural transformation K : T S ⇒ ST such that the diagrams Te +3 T S yy y y BBBB y BBB (6) yyyyyyy y eT BBB% x yyy K T BBB B eS +3 T S yy BBB y y y BBBB (7) yyyy BB yyyy Se BB% x yyy K S BBB ST T S2 Tm TS KS +3 ST S SK +3 S 2 T (8) K mT +3 ST ST T 2S mS TS TK +3 T ST KT 3+ ST 2 (9) K Sm +3 ST commute. We refer to [1, 3] for more details on monads and distributive laws. When the natural transformation K is an isomorphism, the definition of distributive law can be simplified, as in the following lemma: 2.1. Lemma. Consider two monads T and S on a category C, and a natural isomorphism K : T S ⇒ ST. Then (8) implies (6) and (9) implies (7). Moreover, K satisfies (8) and (9) iff K −1 does. 132 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE Proof. We prove that (9) implies (7); the proof of the other implication is similar, and the rest of the statement is obvious. The proof is contained in the following diagram, in which unlabelled regions commute by naturality: eS S FFFFF FFFFeS FFFF FFFF F Se ' +3 ST 7? KS w w w Smwwww w w ww wwwww (2) K TS T Se K +3 T S +3 ST ST e +3 ST 2 KS KT K T K −1 T K +3 +3 2 (9) kk 19 T S SSSSS T ST k k k S k S S SSS kkk K −1 (1) kkk mS SSSSSS kkkkk eT S %-3+ TS T S. TS ST eST +3 T ST 2.2. Definition. Let T be a monad on a category C. A BD-law on T is a natural 2 transformation K : T ⇒ T 2 such that (B) K satisfies the Yang-Baxter equation: T3 TK KT (10) T3 +3 T 3 T K 3+ T 3 KT +3 T 3 TK KT +3 T 3 (D) K is a distributive law (that is, it satisfies equations (6–9)). A BCD-law on T is a BD-law such that (C) the monad T is K-commutative: K +3 T 2 } AAAA } } AAA (11) }}}}} m AAAA }}} m $ z }}} T 2 AAA T A BD-law or BCD-law is said to be invertible if the natural transformation K is so. 2.3. Remark. Once again, as stated in Lemma 2.1 for the distributivity conditions, a natural isomorphism K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 satisfies conditions (B) or (C) iff K −1 does. 2.4. Remark. If C is an arbitrary monoidal category, and T is a monoid in C, one can define a BD-law or BCD-law on T as above. A monoid equipped with an invertible BCD-law has been called a quasi-commutative monoid by Davydov [5], since the BCD-law provides a kind of “local braiding” with respect to which the monoid is commutative. 133 COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS 2.5. Remark. If K is involutive — that is, K 2 = 1 — each of the conditions (8) and (9) implies the other. This fact, together with Lemma 2.1, means that compatible flips in the sense of Menini and Stefan [11] are precisely the involutive BCD-laws. 2.6. Example. Let C = (C, ⊗, I, . . .) be a monoidal category and S = (S, mS , eS ) a monoid in C. The monoid S induces a monad T on C in the following way: • T = − ⊗ S: C → C • mX = 1 ⊗ mS : X ⊗ S ⊗ S → X ⊗ S • eX = 1 ⊗ eS : X X ⊗ I → X ⊗ S 2.6.1 If C is braided, with braiding c = {cX,Y : X ⊗ Y → Y ⊗ X}, then there is an invertible BD-law K on T defined by KX = 1 ⊗ cS,S : X ⊗ S ⊗ S → X ⊗ S ⊗ S. In this case, condition (B) is precisely the Yang-Baxter equation; by naturality of the braiding, conditions (8) and (9) reduce to the following equations, which hold in any braided monoidal category: •777 • 7 •=== • • == == === == == === = • • • = • 77 77 7 • •777 • 77 7 777 • • • •... •... • .. .. .. . .. ... .. .. .. .. .. .. • • • • = •777 • 7 77 77 7 •777 • • 77 7 777 • • • This BD-law is a BCD-law precisely when the monoid S is commutative; it is involutive if and only if cS,S is so, in particular if the braiding c is a symmetry. 2.6.2 Let K be a field and take as C the category of K-vector spaces. Let H be a cobraided bialgebra with universal form r : H ⊗ H → I; there is a natural isomorphism of H-comodules crV,W : V ⊗ W → W ⊗ V defined by V ⊗W τ / W ⊗ V ∆⊗∆ / H ⊗ W ⊗ H ⊗ V 1⊗τ ⊗1/ H ⊗ H ⊗ W ⊗ V r⊗1⊗1/ W ⊗ V where ∆ is the coaction and τ is the standard twist: see [9]. If S is any H-comodule algebra (in particular, one can take S = H), then we have an invertible BD-law K on T defined by KX = 1 ⊗ crS,S : X ⊗ S ⊗ S → X ⊗ S ⊗ S. Indeed, conditions (8-10) follow from [9, Proposition VIII.5.2], using the fact that the multiplication mS : S ⊗ S → S is a homomorphism of H-comodules. 2.7. Example. If f : R → S is a morphism of unital rings, with R commutative, we can specialize Example 2.6.1 by taking C = R-mod, so that K is defined by the standard twist S ⊗ S → S ⊗ S. This is possible also if R is not commutative, provided its image lies in the centre of S : taking now C = R-R-bimod, the standard twist on S can be defined and gives once again an invertible BD-law on T. If we drop the centrality condition the standard twist can no longer be defined, but one can use the additivity 134 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE of the category of bimodules to define a different BD-law. In fact, if C is an additive category and T is any monad on C, then there is an involutive BCD-law K on T defined by K = (eT + T e) · m − T 2 ; see [11]. This case generalizes results on non-commutative rings established in [4, 12]. 3. Coalgebras and braidings For the reader’s convenience, let us recall how the definition of coalgebra for a comonad specializes when the comonad is of the form T∗ . 3.1. Definition. Let T = (T, m, e) be a monad on a category C and consider the ∗ comonad T on Alg(T) induced by the adjunction LT Co RT / LT R T Alg(T) A T∗ -coalgebra structure on a T-algebra (X, x : T X → X) is a morphism r : X → T X such that Tr / 2 r r / / TX X OOO TX TX X T X x (12) X r OOO (13) OOO x OOO 1 OO' mX / TX r X TX (14) T eX Tr / T 2X We denote by T∗ -coalg(X, x) the set of T∗ -coalgebra structures on a T-algebra (X, x). 3.2. Remark. For all X ∈ C, the morphism T eX : T X → T 2 X is a T∗ -coalgebra structure on the free T-algebra LT X = (T X, mX). This is the (object part of the) canonical comparison functor C → Coalg(T∗ ). 3.3. Definition. Let T = (T, m, e) be a monad on a category C and let K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 be a BD-law. A K-braiding on a T-algebra (X, x : T X → X) is a morphism c : T X → T X such that TX O eX X c (15) 1 / TX x /X T 2X Tc KX Tc (16) T 2X / T 2X KX / T 2X / T 2X Tc KX / T 2X T 2X Tx TX KX / T 2X (17) c Tc / T 2X mX / TX We denote by K-Brd(X, x) the set of K-braidings on a T-algebra (X, x). 3.4. Remark. If K is invertible, condition (17) means that c is a morphism c : T (X, x) → T ∗ (X, x) in Alg(T), where T is the lifting of T on Alg(T) induced by the distributive law K −1 . COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS 135 3.5. Remark. We shall see in Proposition 3.9 that if K is invertible or involutive then the same is true of any K-braiding, whence by Corollary 3.11 it will follow that if K is an involutive BCD-law, then K-braidings are precisely symmetries in the sense of Menini and Stefan [11]. 3.6. Remark. If K is a BD-law on T, then KX is a K-braiding on LT X, for all X ∈ C. Indeed, conditions (16) and (17) correspond respectively to conditions (10) and (9), while condition (15) is the pasting of (1) and (6). In the bijection stated in Corollary 3.8, KX corresponds to the T∗ -coalgebra structure T eX of Remark 3.2. If T is a monad on a category C and K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 is a BD-law, we write Brd(T, K) for the category having pairs (X, x) ∈ Alg(T), c ∈ K-Brd(X, x) as objects. An arrow f : (X, x), c → (X , x ), c in Brd(T, K) is an arrow between the underlying T-algebras such that the diagram Tf TX c / T X TX Tf c / T X commutes. We are ready to state our main result. 3.7. Theorem. Let T = (T, m, e) be a monad on a category C and let K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 be a BD-law on T. The forgetful functor V : Brd(T, K) → Alg(T) is comonadic, and the corresponding comonad on Alg(T) is the comonad T∗ induced by the adjunction LT RT between C and Alg(T). Proof. We show that V has a left adjoint and then apply Beck’s theorem. The free T algebra functor LT : C → Alg(T) factorizes as LT = V J, where J : C → Brd(T, K) is the functor sending an object X of C to the algebra (T X, mX) equipped with the K-braiding KX : T 2 X → T 2 X. The counit : LT RT → 1 may be seen as a natural transformation V JRT = LT RT → 1. For an object (X, x, c) of Brd(T, K), write β : X → T X for the composite eX X and observe that, by commutativity of / TX T eX TX x eT X Tx X / T 2X eX / TX KX c / TX * / T 2X (17) c Tc / T 2X mX / TX 136 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE and T eX TX c * / T 2X / T 2X eT X KX Tc TX eT X Tc (16) KX / T 2X / T 2X 4 / T 2X KX Tc / T 2X T eX this makes β a map in Brd(T, K) from (X, x, c) to (T X, mX, KX). This gives the component at (X, x, c) of a natural transformation β : 1 → JRT V . The triangle equation V.V β = 1 is precisely equation (15), while the other triangle equation JRT .βJRT = 1 follows easily from the definitions of BD-law and of T-algebra. Thus there is an adjunction V JRT , which clearly induces the same comonad as LT R T . It remains to verify the Beck condition. Let f, g : (X, x, c) → (Z, z, c ) be morphisms in Brd(T, K), and let (W, w) i i u f / (X, x) \ g / / (Z, z) v be a split equalizer diagram in Alg(T), with ui = 1, iu = gv, and f v = 1. Since T i is (split) monic, the only possibility for a K-braiding c : T W → T W on (W, w) compatible with i is given by TW Ti / TX c / TX Tu / TW and we need only check that this does indeed give a braiding; the fact that the resulting diagram is an equalizer in Brd(T, K) is then obvious. Thus we must check equations (15,16,17); instead, we allow the reader to contemplate the following diagrams at his or her leisure: TW O Ti eW W / TX O c eX i /X 1 1 / TX Tu x /X u / TW w /3 W COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS T 2u T 2 XHH v; / T 2 W KW / T 2 W HH T 2 g v HH vv HH vv v H# v v / 2 2 T 2i T O X T 2 g T O Z T c / T 2O Z HH HH HH T 2f T 2f T 2i H T 2 v HH$ 2i T / / / T 2X T 2W T 2X T 2X Tc 1 Tc KW T 2W T 2i T 2i / T 2X KX KX Tc / T 2X 137 / T 2 X KX / T 2 X Tc T 2u T 2W T 2u KW / T 2W T 2i / T 2X HH v; HH T c v v KW vv KX vv HH v v HH v v v v H# vv vv T 2u / 2 / 2 2 T W T 2i T X T 2X T W T 2W v: Tw Tx TW Ti / TX mX / TX Tc Tu mW / T W. 3.8. Corollary. Let T = (T, m, e) be a monad on a category C and let K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 be a BD-law on T. For (X, x) a T-algebra, consider the map Ψ(X,x) : K-Brd(X, x) → T∗ -coalg(X, x) (c : T X → T X) → (r : X eX / TX c / TX ) and the functor Ψ : Brd(T, K) → Coalg(T∗ ) (X, x), c f / (X , x ), c → (X, x, Ψ(c)) f / (X , x , Ψ(c )) 1. The functor Ψ is an isomorphism of categories; 2. The map Ψ(X,x) is bijective. Proof. Since the forgetful functor V : Brd(T, K) → Alg(T) is comonadic, the induced comparison functor Ψ : Brd(T, K) → Coalg(T∗ ) is an isomorphism of categories and so it induces a bijection on objects. 138 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE 3.9. Proposition. For a BD-law K : T 2 → T 2 we have the following facts about a K-braiding c : T X → T X on an algebra (X, x): 1. The diagrams Tc T 2X mX / T 2 X KX / T 2 X (18) TX T 3X Tx T 2x / TX c T KX / T 2X mX T 2c T 3X TX c T mX T 2X (19) / T 3X / TX o Tx KX T 2X commute; 2. If K is invertible then so is c; 3. If K is involutive then so is c; 4. If K is a BCD-law then the diagram c / TX DD zz DD (20) zzz z x x DD }zz ! T XDD X commutes. Proof. In each case the proof goes as follows. Modify the definition of K-braiding so that the extra condition is assumed part of the structure, then check that the modified category Brd(T, K) is still comonadic via the same comonad. This involves (i) proving that the cofree objects (T X, mX, KX) have the required property, and (ii) proving that in the split equalizer diagram in the proof of Theorem 3.7, the induced morphism c = T u.c.T i : T W → T W satisfies the condition if c : T X → T X does so. In each case (i) is entirely straightforward: for example, the fact that the cofree objects satisfy (18) is precisely (9). We therefore check only (ii). 1. If c satisfies (18), then so does c by commutativity of the diagram v vv vv v vv Tc T 2W mW T 2i TW / T 2X mX Ti T 2u Tx / TX T 2u / T 2W HH HH KX HH KW HH HH HH HH H$ H$ / 2 T X T 2W T 2 XHH v; c / TX Tu Tw / TW COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS 139 while (19) is obtained by pasting together (17) and (18). 2 and 3. If c is invertible, then a straightforward calculation shows that T u.c−1 .T i is inverse to T u.c.T i. 4. If xc = x then the diagram c / TX T ; XDD GG w z D GGT u w z D T i ww z D GG z DD w zx GG w z x D ww # }zz ! T WGG X T W DD = DD u GG ww zz w i z DD G w z DD ww w zz w GGG zz # ! {ww /W W 1 commutes and so wc = w. 3.10. Remark. If K is a distributive law, condition (18) means that c is a morphism c : T ∗ (X, x) → T(X, x) is the lifting of T to Alg(T) induced by the distributive law K. in Alg(T), where T In fact we can use the Proposition to give two alternative formulations of the definition. One of them will be used in the following section, the other to make the connection with the “symmetries” of [11]. 3.11. Corollary. In the definition of K-braiding, condition (17) can be replaced by (19), while if K is a BCD-law then (15) can be replaced by (20). Proof. We have seen that for a K-braiding (19) always holds; conversely (17) follows easily from (19) by composing with eT X : T X → T 2 X. Similarly, if K is a BCDlaw then (20) holds for any K-braiding, while (15) follows from (20) by composing with eX : X → T X. If K is an involutive BCD-law on a monad T, then a symmetry on a T-algebra (X, x), was defined in [11] to be an involution c : T X → T X satisfying (16, 17, 20); combining the proposition and the corollary one now sees as promised that this is precisely a K-braiding. 4. Another proof We proved our main theorem in the previous section; here we provide an alternative proof, which may be of interest to some readers. It exhibits the bijection which is the object part of the isomorphism Φ of Corollary 3.8 as being part of the natural bijection (between hom-sets) of an adjunction. To do this, we use the definition of K-braiding involving (19) rather than (17); see Corollary 3.11. 140 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE 4.1. Proposition. Let T = (T, m, e) be a monad on a category C and let K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 be an invertible BD-law on T. For (X, x) a T-algebra, we have a bijection K-Brd(X, x) ∼ = T∗ -coalg(X, x) given by Ψ(X,x) : K-Brd(X, x) → T∗ -coalg(X, x) (c : T X → T X) → (r : X eX c / TX / TX ) ∗ Ψ−1 (X,x) : T -coalg(X, x) → K-Brd(X, x) (r : X → T X) → (c : T X Tr / T 2 X KX / T 2 X T x / T X ) As explained above, the proposition can be deduced from Corollary 3.8; our alternative proof occupies the remainder of the paper. Let T and S be monads on a category C. A morphism of monads is a natural transformation ϕ : S ⇒ T such that ϕ2 S2 m (21) S e +3 S NNN (22) NN ϕ NN e NN NN "* +3 T 2 IdC NN m +3 T ϕ T Following [1], such a morphism ϕ induces a functor ϕ∗ : Alg(T) → Alg(S) defined by ϕ∗ (X, x : T X → X) = (X, ϕX · x : SX → T X → X). Moreover, ϕ∗ has a left adjoint ϕ! : Alg(S) → Alg(T) sending an S-algebra (Y, y) to the object ϕ!(Y, y) in the coequalizer T SYGG Ty GG GG G T ϕY GG # T 2Y / TY < y yy y y yy yy mY q / ϕ!(Y, y) in Alg(T), provided that such a coequalizer exists. Indeed, if f : (Y, y) → ϕ∗ (X, x) is a morphism of S-algebras, then x.T f : T Y → X coequalizes T y and mY.T ϕY . Conversely, from g : ϕ!(Y, y) → (X, x), we get g.q.eY : (Y, y) → ϕ∗ (X, x). If K : T S ⇒ ST is a distributive law of T over S, we can consider the composite monad ST on C. Explicitly, ST = (ST : C → C, ST ST SKT +3 S 2 T 2 mm +3 ST , Id C Moreover, there are two morphisms of monads as in S 1 =Se +3 ST ks 2 =eT T. ee +3 ST ) COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS 141 Now, for any T-algebra (X, x : T X → X) and S-algebra (Y, y : SY → Y ), the adjunction 2 ! ∗2 gives a natural bijection Ψ : Alg(ST)[2 !(X, x), 1 !(Y, y)] / Alg(T)[(X, x), ∗ 1 !(Y, y)] 2 The bijection of Proposition 4.1 will turn out to be a particular case of this natural bijection. To see this, we give an explicit description of Ψ and of the hom-sets involved. First of all, let us recall from [1] that the coequalizer defining 2 !(X, x) always exists. In fact, it is given by the solid part of the following diagram in Alg(ST) SeT X } ST T X ST x SmX SeX / ST X / Sx / SX with action on SX given by ST SX SKX / S 2T X S2x / S 2 X mX / SX Indeed, one easily verifies that the dotted arrows satisfy the equations for a split coequalizer [2]. Recall also that if f is a morphism of ST-algebras coequalizing ST x and SmX, then the induced ST-algebra map out of SX is f.SeX. Unfortunately, the existence of the coequalizer defining 1 !(Y, y) is not automatic. We need the following lemma, which makes sense because of Lemma 2.1: 4.2. Lemma. Consider two monads S and T on a category C, and let K : T S ⇒ ST be an invertible distributive law of T over S. Consider the composite monad ST induced by K and the composite monad TS induced by K −1 . Then K : TS ⇒ ST is a morphism of monads, and it satisfies the following equations TS\d AA }}:B AAAA η1 } } } AAAA }}} } AAAA } } } }} K S AAAA T }} } AAAA } } }}} AA }}} 1 AAAA $ z }}} 2 η2 ST where η1 = T e and η2 = eS. Proof. The equations 1 = Kη2 and 2 = Kη1 are conditions (6) and (7), and they imply condition (22). As far as condition (21) is concerned, let us give the idea of the proof, instead of the complete calculation. (This could be formalized using the string calculus of [8].) Think of K as a braiding between T and S. Then condition (21) amounts 142 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE to the following equation •NNNN p• p• •NNNN NNN ppppp NNN ppppp pN pN N N pp NNN pp NNN NN= NN ppp ppp p p p p • •== • • == == ==? ? •?? •?? • • ?? ?? ?? ?? ?? ?? • •=== • • • = == === = •== •== • • == == == == == == T • TTTTT jj• j j j TTTT jjj Tj jjj TTTTTTT j j j TT j •jj • = • which can be proved using the distributivity equations three times. Indeed, the distributivity admits the following graphical representation (this is condition (8)) • •VVVVVVV •=== • == == == q• •MMMM MMM qqqq q MM qqq MMMMM q q q • p• q• VVVpVpp qqq q q V p VVVV qqq pp VVVV ppp VVVV p p qqq V• q •=p== • == == == • • = • As a consequence of the previous lemma, 1 ! : Alg(S) → Alg(ST) can be obtained as η2 ! Alg(S) / Alg(TS) (K −1 )∗ / Alg(ST) and then 1 !(Y, y) can be described by the following coequalizer in Alg(ST) T eSY w (K −1 )∗ (LTS (SY )) T Sy T mY T eY z / (K −1 )∗ (LTS (Y )) / KSY Ty / TY KY LST (SY ) ST y mT Y.SKY / LST (Y ) / with action on T Y given by ST 2 Y SmY −1 / ST Y K Y / T SY Ty / T Y. We are now ready to describe the bijection Ψ. 4.3. Lemma. Consider two monads S and T on a category C, and let K : T S ⇒ ST be an invertible distributive law of T over S. For any T-algebra (X, x) and S-algebra (Y, y) : 143 COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS (i) The hom-set Alg(S)[(Y, y), ∗1 (2 !(X, x))] is the set of morphisms r : Y → SX such that Sr / 2 SY S X y (12) Y mX / SX r commutes. (ii) The hom-set Alg(ST)[1 !(Y, y), 2 !(X, x)] is the set of morphisms c : T Y → SX such that T KY / T Sc / T ST Y T SSX T 2 SY T 2y T 2Y mY (19) TY T SX / SX o c T mX Sx KX ST X commutes. (iii) The natural bijection Ψ : Alg(ST)[1 !(Y, y), 2 !(X, x)] / Alg(S)[(Y, y), ∗ (2 !(X, x))] 1 induced by the adjunction 1 ! ∗1 is given by Ψ(c) : Y eY c / TY / SX Ψ−1 (r) : T Y Tr / T SX KX / ST X Sx / SX. Proof. Following the description of ϕ! ϕ∗ given at the beginning of this section, we have Ψ(c) and Ψ−1 (r) given respectively by Y TY eY / TY eT Y eT Y / ST Y ST r / K −1 / ST Y ST SX SKX / / T SY SST X Ty nT X / TY Sr SeSX / S 2X / ST SX y Y r / SX o mX S 2X o S2x / SX / ST X Sx / SX which are easily seen to reduce to formulas given in (iii). For r : Y → SX, to be a morphism of S-algebras means that SY c SKX S 2T X commutes, which immediately reduces to (12) by (6) and (4). 144 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE For c : T Y → SX, to be a morphism of ST-algebras means commutativity of ST 2 Y SmY ST c / ST SX SKX / SST X SSx / SSX ST Y K −1 Y / T SY Ty / TY c mX / SX which, by (8) and (9), reduces to (19). This is the best we can do working at this level of generality. ¿From now on, we assume S = T and (X, x) = (Y, y). We now combine the next two lemmas with the previous one to complete the proof of Proposition 4.1. 4.4. Lemma. Let T be a monad on a category C, and let K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 be an invertible distributive law on T. Fix a T-algebra (X, x). In the bijection of Lemma 4.3, the map r : X → T X satisfies condition (13) iff c = Ψ−1 (r) : T X → T X satisfies condition (15). Proof. Condition (15) says precisely that Ψ(c) satisfies (13). 4.5. Lemma. Let T be a monad on a category C, and let K : T 2 ⇒ T 2 be an invertible BD-law on T. Fix a T-algebra (X, x). In the bijection of Lemma 4.3, the map r : X → T X satisfies condition (14) iff c = Ψ−1 (r) : T X → T X satisfies condition (16). Proof. (14) ⇒ (16) : T 2r KX / T 2X / 3 T 2 X PP hhh4 T X h h PPP 2 h KT Xhhhhh PTPPr PPP hhhh h h h h P' hhhh T KX (14) T KX T 2r T 3 X PP T 3X T KX T 3X T 2x T 2X KX 2 T X PPP PTPKX PPP PP' T 3r / T 4X 3 T 3 X T X nn } T 3 eXnnnn }} } n T KT X T 2x n } n nn }} n w 3 } T r / T 4 X (1) }} T 2X }} 1 } } (12) } KX T 2 mX }} } } ~ 2 T r / T 3X (10) T 3 XHH T 2O X HH HH KT X T 2x H KT X HH# / T 3X / T 3X T 3 eX T 2r T (KX) COALGEBRAS, BRAIDINGS, AND DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS 145 (16) ⇒ (14) : n X SSSSS SSSS nnn SeX SSSS n n n SSSS n n S) wnn T eX eT X / T 2X o T X PP TX HH PPP (7) HH T c PPP H c KX HHH P eT X PPP H# ' eT X c TX T 2X T 2 X5 o 55 55 Tc 55 (6) 55 eT X / 2 (16) T eX 55 T X PP T X KX PPP (6) 55 PPP 55 KX P 5 T eX PPP ' o 2 T X T 2X eX nnn Tc The proof of Proposition 4.1 is now complete. References [1] J. Beck, Distributive laws, in Seminar on Triples and Categorical Homology Theory (Lecture Notes in Mathematics 80), pp. 119–140, Springer, Berlin, 1969. [2] F. Borceux, Handbook of categorical algebra I, Cambridge University Press, 1994. [3] F. Borceux, Handbook of categorical algebra II, Cambridge University Press, 1994. [4] M. Cipolla, Discesa fedelmente piatta dei moduli, Rend. Circ. Mat. Palermo 25:43– 46, 1976. [5] A. Davydov, Quasicommutative monoids, Lecture at Australian Category Seminar, 21 January 2004. [6] A. Grothendieck, Technique de descente et théorèmes d’existence en géométrie algébrique, I : Généralités, descente par morphismes fidèlements plats, Séminaire Bourbaki 190 (1959-1960). [7] G. Janelidze and W. Tholen, Facets of descent III: monadic descent for rings and algebras, preprint, 2004. [8] A. Joyal and R. Street, Geometry of tensor calculus I, Adv. Math. 88:55–112, 1991. [9] C. Kassel, Quantum groups (Graduate Texts in Mathematics 155) Springer-Verlag, New York, 1995. [10] S. Mac Lane, Categories for the working mathematician (Graduate Texts in Mathematics 5), Springer, New York-Berlin, 1971. 146 STEFANO KASANGIAN, STEPHEN LACK, AND ENRICO M. VITALE [11] C. Menini and D. Stefan, Descent theory and Amitsur cohomology of triples, J. Algebra 266:261–304, 2003. [12] P. Nuss, Noncommutative descent and non-abelian cohomology, K-Theory 12:23–74, 1997. Dipartimento di Matematica Università di Milano Via Saldini 50 I 20133 Milano, Italia School of Quantitative Methods and Mathematical Sciences University of Western Sydney Locked Bag 1797 Penrith South DC NSW 1797 Australia Département de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées Université catholique de Louvain Chemin du Cyclotron 2 B 1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgique Email: Stefano.Kasangian@mat.unimi.it, s.lack@uws.edu.au, vitale@math.ucl.ac.be This article may be accessed via WWW at http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/ or by anonymous ftp at ftp://ftp.tac.mta.ca/pub/tac/html/volumes/13/8/13-08.{dvi,ps} THEORY AND APPLICATIONS OF CATEGORIES (ISSN 1201-561X) will disseminate articles that significantly advance the study of categorical algebra or methods, or that make significant new contributions to mathematical science using categorical methods. The scope of the journal includes: all areas of pure category theory, including higher dimensional categories; applications of category theory to algebra, geometry and topology and other areas of mathematics; applications of category theory to computer science, physics and other mathematical sciences; contributions to scientific knowledge that make use of categorical methods. Articles appearing in the journal have been carefully and critically refereed under the responsibility of members of the Editorial Board. Only papers judged to be both significant and excellent are accepted for publication. The method of distribution of the journal is via the Internet tools WWW/ftp. The journal is archived electronically and in printed paper format. Subscription information. Individual subscribers receive (by e-mail) abstracts of articles as they are published. Full text of published articles is available in .dvi, Postscript and PDF. Details will be e-mailed to new subscribers. To subscribe, send e-mail to tac@mta.ca including a full name and postal address. For institutional subscription, send enquiries to the Managing Editor, Robert Rosebrugh, rrosebrugh@mta.ca. The typesetting language of the journal is TEX, and LATEX2e is the preferred flavour. TEX source of articles for publication should be submitted by e-mail directly to an appropriate Editor. They are listed below. Please obtain detailed information on submission format and style files from the journal’s WWW server at http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/. You may also write to tac@mta.ca to receive details by e-mail. Information for authors. Editorial board. Michael Barr, McGill University: barr@barrs.org, Associate Managing Editor Lawrence Breen, Université Paris 13: breen@math.univ-paris13.fr Ronald Brown, University of Wales Bangor: r.brown@bangor.ac.uk Jean-Luc Brylinski, Pennsylvania State University: jlb@math.psu.edu Aurelio Carboni, Università dell Insubria: aurelio.carboni@uninsubria.it Valeria de Paiva, Palo Alto Research Center: paiva@parc.xerox.com Martin Hyland, University of Cambridge: M.Hyland@dpmms.cam.ac.uk P. T. Johnstone, University of Cambridge: ptj@dpmms.cam.ac.uk G. Max Kelly, University of Sydney: maxk@maths.usyd.edu.au Anders Kock, University of Aarhus: kock@imf.au.dk Stephen Lack, University of Western Sydney: s.lack@uws.edu.au F. William Lawvere, State University of New York at Buffalo: wlawvere@buffalo.edu Jean-Louis Loday, Université de Strasbourg: loday@math.u-strasbg.fr Ieke Moerdijk, University of Utrecht: moerdijk@math.uu.nl Susan Niefield, Union College: niefiels@union.edu Robert Paré, Dalhousie University: pare@mathstat.dal.ca Robert Rosebrugh, Mount Allison University: rrosebrugh@mta.ca, Managing Editor Jiri Rosicky, Masaryk University: rosicky@math.muni.cz James Stasheff, University of North Carolina: jds@math.unc.edu Ross Street, Macquarie University: street@math.mq.edu.au Walter Tholen, York University: tholen@mathstat.yorku.ca Myles Tierney, Rutgers University: tierney@math.rutgers.edu Robert F. C. Walters, University of Insubria: robert.walters@uninsubria.it R. J. Wood, Dalhousie University: rjwood@mathstat.dal.ca