SERIE RESEARCH mEmORMIDII !<l$j p.

advertisement
p.
ET
05348
!<l$j
SERIE RESEARCH mEmORMIDII
RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS AND NEW CLASSICAL MACROECONOMICS
H. Visser
Research Memorandum 1989-8
J a n u a r i 1989
VRIJE UNIVERSITEIT
FACULTEIT DER ECONOMISCHE WETENSCHAPPEN
EN ECONOMETRIE
AMSTE
RDAM
Onderzoekgroep Financiële instellingen en markten
1
RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS AND NEW CLASSICAL MACROECONOMICS
1. Introduction: The Phillips-Curve
The Keynesian-Hicksian IS-LM model of macroeconomics has some trouble finding an
explanation for wage and price movements. The relationship between unemployment
and wage or price changes known as the Phillips curve seemed to provide the
missing equation in the Standard macroeconomic model (cf Phillips 1958). One
implication was that a trade-off between employment and price stability was
possible, that more employment could be 'bought' at the price of more inflation.
However, Milton Friedman (1969) and E.S. Phelps (1971) soon put a damper on those
propagating active macroeconomic policies. Friedman introduced the concept of the
Natural Rate of Unemployment (NRU), as an analogue to Knut Wicksell's natural
rate of interest. At NRU, a kind of Walrasian equilibrium prevails, which allows
for unemployment of the structural and frictional varieties, but excludes
Keynesian unemployment following from deficiënt demand. For all practical
purposes, NRU means full employment. Starting from NRU, unemployment can indeed
be reduced in Friedman's view by expansive macro-economie (monetary and/or
fiscal) policies, but only for a comparatively short time (a few quarters).
Higher aggregate demand drives prices up. Employers perceive better market
conditions and hire more labour. Workers interpret rising wage offers as relative
wage increases and supply more labour. After a time people understand that
nominal wage and price increases do not mean real wage or relative price
increases, and employment and GNP return to their NRU values, though at a higher
rate of inflation. People take account of expected inflation. The wage equation
representing the Phillips-curve:
W
= a0 + aa/U
(1)
was extended by an argument representing expected price increases:
W = a0 + al /U + a2P*
(2)
with W = wage rate, U = rate of unemployment, P = price level; a dot denotes
rates of change and an asterisk denotes expected values.
In Friedman's view, economie agents do not suffer from money illusion, i.e., they
will not, if full information is available, confuse nominal
with real movements. Thus, P* will converge to W (abstracting all the time from
productivity increases) and a2 = 1. NRU, i.e., the equilibrium value of U,
therefore is
NRU = - a 0 / ai
(3)
Demand-management measures induce a movement along a short-term Phillips-curve
which is foliowed by a move of_ the short-term Phillips-curve. That move occurs
when expectations adjust. The short-term curves all cut the long-term Phillipscurve, which runs vertical at NRU.
Phelps's reasoning differs only slightly from Friedman's. In Phelps's
island parable workers may accept work at a certain wage rate on their own
island, but may also row to other islands in order to collect information on
wages prevailing there. They weigh up the income foregone if they spend time on
collecting information and the additional future earnings that may be the fruit
of their search activities. Unlike Friedman's workers, who increase their labour
supply if (perceived) real wages rise, Phelps's workers simply seek the highest
wages at which they can work a given number of hours a week. Like Friedman's
2
workers, they will first mistake increased nominal wage offers following from an
expansionary impulse for better relative wage offers (in Friedman's case: better
real wage offers) and cut short their search activities. When the higher nominal
wage turns out to be a lower relative wage, they (or rather some of them) start
rowing again and unemployment returns to NRU.
In the Friedman-Phelps story, unemployment is voluntary, it is search
unemployment or frictional unemployment (barring structural unemployment of
workers whose marginal productivity is too low to ever find work). It would be
suboptimal, from a welfare-theoretic point of view, to try to reduce unemployment
below NRU. A reduction can only be brought about by deceiving workers. It is
another thing to reduce NRU itself, by removing frictions on the labour market,
such as incomplete job information, minimum wage laws and housing controls (which
impede regional mobility).
Restrictive macro-economie policies should in principle work out in the same
way: a temporary reduction of employment and real production, foliowed by a
return to NRU at a lower rate of inflation. Similarly, random shocks should not
set in motion deviation-amplifying mechanisms. This implies that markets work
satisfactorily. If not, there is a possibility that a positive shock works as
explained by Friedman and Phelps, whilst a negative shock may lead to protracted
unemployment, which in this case is of the involuntary variety. Even so, the
lasting contribution by Friedman and Phelps is that expectations receive a
systematic treatment in economie theory. Their emphasis on adaptive expectations
can be seen as one manifestation of a more general rule that says that any
empirically established economie relationship (in this case the short-term
Phillips-curve) breaks down when policy makers try to exploit it (Goodhart's
law).
2. Rational expectations and New Classical Macroeconomics
The logie of Friedman's adapative expectations implies that unemployment can be
held below NRU at the cost of ever-increasing inflation, because with adaptive
expectations, i.e., a weighted average of past and current inflation rates,
expected wage or price rises lag actual increases and people continue to
overestimate their relative or real income:
Et Pt+ 1 - E ^
Pt = b(Pt - E t . a P t )
0 < b < 1
(4)
E is the expectational operator, subscripts denote periods.
But rational economie agents will notice that their forecasts are
systematically wrong. They will take account of the ever-increasing inflation and
not stick with adaptive expectations once they understand how the economy really
works (cf Friedman 1976 pp. 230-'31). This idea of rationality builds on a 1961
article by Muth, who proposed that expectations are "essentially the same as the
predictions of the relevant economie theory" (Muth 1961 p. 315). His hypothesis
was, more precisely, that "expectations of firms (or, more generally, the subjective probability distribution of outcomes) tend to be distributed, for the same
information set, about the prediction of the theory (or the 'objective'
probability distribution of outcomes)" (Muth 1961 p. 316). Predictions may be
wide off the mark, but they are not systematically wrong. In other words, errors
are not serially correlated.
Muth applied the concept of Rational Expectations (henceforth RE) to
speculative behaviour and to the cobweb cycle. It has since with more or less
success been applied to single markets, such as the foreign exchange market (see
the chapter on Exchange Rate Determination, below). Lucas (1972) introduced the
idea into macroeconomics. In a macroeconomic setting, the Phillips-curve has been
reinterpreted as a supply function - which was sorely missing in the IS-LM
3
framework - and RE plus this supply function coupled to the idea of continuous
market clearing gave New Classical Macroeconomics (NCME). NCME (a misnomer,
according to Niehans, 1987, because classical economics was quite something else)
was first used to outdo Friedman and other monetarists in their stand against
policy activism. Though governments would be wise, in the monetarist view, not to
exploit the short-term Phillips-curve trade-off between inflation and employment,
because they would as likely as not intensify cyclical movements instead of
counteracting them, it is in principle not impossible for them to affect real
variables, such as employment and production. NCME went one better and denied
that governments could systematically affect real variables. Tobin therefore
coined the term 'Monetarism, Mark II' for NCME (Tobin 1980 p. xiii).
3. PolicY-ineffectiveness
3.1
Monetary
policy
NCME started out emphasising the ineffectiveness of stabilisation policies,
first of all of monetary policy. It has later been argued by NCME proponents that
this neutrality proposition had been overemphasised and that they never intended
to take it seriously but meant to show that monetary policy measures may have
quite different effects than one would expect under non-rational expectations
(Sargent in Klamer 1984 p. 70, Minford 1986 p. 327). A common point of departure
is the so-called Lucas supply function (here in a form that Minford and Peel 1981
call the Sargent-Wallace aggregate supply function)s
? % = yn
+ a
i(Pt - Et_i P t ) + u 1 > t
a1>0
(5)
where yst denotes real output at time t, yn the natural rate of output,
corresponding with NRU, Pt the price level at time t and Uj t is a serially
uncorrelated random disturbance with mean zero. All magnitudes are expressed in
logs.
Essentially, equation (5) is a reformulation of the Phillips curve. If actual
prices equal expected prices, unemployment is at NRU and production is at its
'natural' level, apart from random disturbances. The economy is on the long-term,
vertical Phillips curve. When price surprises occur, i.e., actual prices differ
from expected prices, output differs from its natural level, as in Friedman and
Phelps's microeconomic approaches.
The supply function is complemented by an aggregate demand function:
ydt = Mt - Pt + u 2 > t
(6)
where yd denotes the log of aggregate real demand.
If goods markets clear, yst = ydt and Pt can be solved from equations (5)
and (6):
Pt = (Mt + a, E t . I Pt - yn)/(l + a,)
(7)
We now introducé rational expectations. First assume that the money supply is
known to be held constant or to follow a fixed rule, such that E t . 1 Mt = Mt .
Given that E t _ 1 ux t = 0 and E t _ t u2 t = 0 , the rational expectation of Pt in
period t - 1 is
Et.i
pt -
<Mt
+
»i
E
t-i
PC - y » > / u
+
»i)
Combining equations (7) and (8), we find that
<8>
4
P t - E,.! P t - (u 2 > t - u 1 > t )/(l + a x )
(.9)
or, in words, that deviations of actual prices from expected prices are
completely random; and so are deviations of output from its 'natural' level, as
shown by equation (5).
We now assume that the monetary authorities resort to an activist monetary
policy. They decide to follow a proportional feedback rule, increasing the money
supply when output falls short of the natural level and decreasing it when output
exceeds the natural level:
Mt - M, + a 2 (y t .l - y n ) + u 3 f t
(10)
M n is the trend value of the money supply. An error term is added because the
authorities are assumed not to be able to completely control the money supply.
With rational expectations, economie actors will lose little time in finding out
what rule the authorities are following. At the end of period t - 1 they will
form a rational expectation of the money supply in period t:
M
K-l
t = M n + a 2<y t -l " 7n>
<U>
Substituting equation (11) in equation (6) and taking expectations, we find that
Et-i
p t = £Mn +
a
2
(yt-i
- yn)
+
a
i
E
t-i pt - y
n
] / d+
a
i>
<12>
and
Pt
" *t-l
P
t
= (-«l,t
+
U
2,t
+
U3,t)/d
+
a
l >
<
1 3
>
Because economie actors take account of the monetary policy rule, prices do not
systematically deviate from expected prices and monetary policy does not
systematically affect real variables. The monetary authorities can only influence
real output and employment by engineering surprise shocks in money growth. The
more frequently they change their policy rule, the less easily the public is
moved to revise its decisions. There may exist a short-term Phillips-curve after
all, but it tends to disappear if the authorities try to exploit it. The more
often the authorities change the money supply rule, the less easily will the
public be fooled and the more vertical will the short-term Phillips-curve run
(see Lucas 1973).
Strictly speaking, there is little sense in monetary policy as depicted
above, because disturbances are not serially correlated. Measures taken to
correct an output shock in one period only take effect in the next one.
Nevertheless, the example serves to show that monetary policy cannot bring
unemployment systematically below NRU. This is as well, because NRU represents a
kind of macro-equilibrium and a systematically lower rate of unemployment
requires economie agents to be deceived, which can hardly be optimal. It is
another thing if policy can help to reduce fluctuations.
3.2. Policy
effectiveness
under
NCME
NCME does not rule out a positive contribution of monetary policy to economie
stabilisation. First of all, the authorities may have prior knowledge of economie
disturbances. The measures they take will then have real effects. But an
informational advantage really makes a weak case for active policy making. Either
the information will be available to the public without much delay (Grossman 1980
p. 13, Wagner 1981 p. 5) or the authorities could make the information freely
5
available (McCallum 1980a p. 43).
It has been shown that slight modifications to the model discussed above may
suffice to give the authorities the opportunity to reduce output fluctuations, at
the cost of an increase in price fluctuations. Asako (1982), e.g., developed a
model where current prices and expected future prices are mutually dependent,
while expected future prices also depend on the money-supply rule. Current supply
and demand depend upon the difference between current prices and expected future
prices. Different money supply rules then result in different values for the
variance of output. In non-linear models, the authorities can even influence the
average value of output and employment: if they are able to manipulate the
variance of the difference between actual and expected prices, and output depends
in a non-linear way upon this difference, average output is affected by the money
supply rule (cf Shiller 1978 p. 10, Snower 1984).
In an open economy with fixed exchange rates macroeconomic policies are
bound to be non-neutral, even if they were expected by the public. This is
because at least one price, the price of tradeables, is not free to move with the
domestic price level. For a small country, this price is even fixed. An expected
increase in the money supply will increase the nominal demand for both tradeables
and nontradeables, driving up the price of nontradeables in the process.
Production of nontradeables will increase and production of tradeables will fall
as producers of nontradeables draw workers away from the tradeables industries.
Nominal wages will rise in terms of tradeables and fall in terms of nontradeables
(otherwise equilibrium on the labour market could not be maintained). When the
aggregate price level is not very sensitive to the price of nontradeables, and
nominal wage demands therefore do not rise to a great extent when nontradeables
prices increase, aggregate employment may rise, provided labour demand in the
nontradeables sector reacts relatively strongly to a fall in the product wage
(nominal wage level relative to the price of the product of the industry) and
labour demand in the tradeables sector is relatively insensitive to an increase
in the product wage (cf Montiel 1987).
3.3. Fiscal
policv
The discussion on the effectiveness of macro-economie stabilisation policies has
tended to concentrate on monetary policy. After all, fiscal policies can hardly
be neutral, as they affect on the one side government expenditure and therefore
the system's demand functions, and on the other side tax rates and therefore
labour supply and savings or the supply of loanable funds. For another thing,
automatic stabilisers work automatically and are not dependent for their
effectiveness on an informational advantage on the part of the authorities. Tax
receipts, e.g., react automatically to variations in sales. Consequently, by
varying the characteristics of the built-in stabilisers the authorities can
influence output variability.
3.4. Superneutralitv
Even if macroeconomic stabilisation measures were ineffective, policy measures
might bear on the long-term growth path of the economy. A change in the rate of
money growth and the concomitant change in the rate of inflation may affect
investment by virtue of the Tobin or Mundell-Tobin effect (cf Tobin 1965, Mundell
1963, Mundell 1971 Ch. 2). Higher inflation, e.g., makes holding real capital
more attractive relative to holding money. Investment is stimulated and per
capita production increases. This effect can be included in rational expectations models by making the demand for capital an increasing function not only of
the expected real return on capital but also of the expected rate of inflation
(cf Fischer 1979). Alternatively, a real-balance effect can be introduced in the
6
consumption function. Higher inflation will induce people to reduce their real
balances, which in turn affects consumption and in its wake the desired capital
stock and therefore investment (McCallum 1980b pp. 727-'27, Begg 1982 pp. 147'49). In case the long-term growth is not affected, there is superneutrality.
Superneutrality is even less probable with fiscal policy, for the reasons
mentioned.
4. Non-clearing markets and policy effectiveness
If markets are not assumed to clear continuously, i.e., if NCME is not
maintained, policy effectiveness need not at all be impaired by RE. Some form of
price stickiness is called for. One way of achieving this is to introducé
contracts that fix prices or wages for a period during which the monetary
authorities can react to new information. The public can then perfectly well
forecast what policies the authorities will follow but, being bound by contracts,
is not able to react to these policies.
A case in point is a model developed by Fischer (1977) in which at the end
of each period new wage contracts are drawn up for one half of the work force for
the next two periods. There is some serial correlation in disturbances, which
means that policy measures that take effect only next period still make sense.
The variability of output and employment can be reduced in this way. In a linear
model mean levels of real variables cannot be reduced, as that would still imply
that workers would be fooled, which they will only accept for the duration of
the contracts. Repeated attempts to fooi them would be answered by a revision of
the contracts.
In another model, developed by Phelps and Taylor (1977), prices and wages
are fixed before the money supply is decided upon. Inventories carry disturbances
from one period to the next. Monetary policy thus is both possible and useful. In
cases such as these, it is not true that a fixed money supply rule is optimal
when the expectations of the public are rational, nor is it true that monetary
policy which follows a feed-back rule is only optimal when the public's
expectations are not rational (see for such a proposition Korteweg 1976 p. 500).
Admittedly models have been built where stabilisation policy is
ineffective, even without instantaneous market clearing (McCallum 1977,
McCafferty 1982). This can be seen as a testimony of the ingenuity of model
builders, but not much more. Of more importance is the question why agents should
conclude such contracts in the first place. This problem is tackled in section 7
below.
In a model with asset holdings monetary policy will generally be non-neutral,
even with continuous clearing of all markets. Unforeseen price movements change
the real value of nominally denominated government assets, provided they are
considered to be net wealth (Minford 1986 p. 231). As for private debt,
distribution effects may occur, i.e., creditors and debtors may react
asymmetrically to changes in the real value of debt consequent upon unexpected
price level changes.
5. Business cycles
A remarkable feat of NCME has been the construction of models that purport to
explain business cycles within the framework of continuously clearing markets. If
markets clear continually, business cycle movements imply cyclical movements of
equilibrium output and employment. One might try to explain these movements by
introducing exogenous shocks, such as technological changes (which make marginal
productivity curves and labour demand move) and changing preferences as to
consumption and leisure (which makes labour supply move). Butj as Tobin (1980 p.
37, 1981 p. 37) notes, there is no reason why such moves should be auto-
F- T I
g
>
Tl
M
F(D
CL
i
FO
(D
«^^.
o
t-< B
m c
FCL
M
<D
H
O
CT
Fp
co
T)
FH H 00 I— O
O (D 3 vo O
C C H B
00 §
M P
H
H
|
1
M
rt
3
P
^
(0 rt co
O o"
3 H - • T J P ro
^
ü^ ro
>
Fd i—
rt T ) co ro
CT H r t w
F- H •
( D O M •O (D P H
d
3
3
$ 3
F- O
rt rt
p" (D
CL
>
d
F-
co 3
F- O
H H i
FO* O
H P
F- T l
d F-
ID
O FH i r t4
p
O (D
o H
(B
cr M
d
CO 00
F- O
3 O
(D CL
»
a
CO
t i P co
co T l F- rt
<D T l 3 CT
H (D P
O O CO rt
O P co
3 O
rt
Hi f f n
y
H- >• V ] (D
g
O
co
rt d
P
rt
H I J
F- P
pi CO
3 CO
F-
cr 3
d oo
o co
3
tJ |D
tfHH
CL
d ro
O
r t co
<D
M O
3 " H- r t ^3
vj
ro o
3
3 w
o d
CL 3
ro f j
ro
3
co
ro
M
<
3
ro
co
co
o
cr d
ro F o
M
H
vi
M r t (D *"3 <-*
CO M- CO O O
- O
M Hl
3 r t (D
P
o
T J oo
p 0 FH O 3
r t CL r t
co
H ) •. H
H
ro
O
B
a
rt
cr
ro
Hl
p
O
rt
H-
cr
H
Fd
3
co r 1 cr
d d
P
H
(D
ro
O
P
fi
O CO
P Fco 3
ro
H CO
vo co
vj
rt ro
«i Tvi
o
I X
1
P
O. •
O
M
rt cr ro ro
ro *<J. w
CO
8
co 3
o
rt
p T i rt CL
p d •
(D
CL l-l
M
F- t— co
cr
p
rt o u i
cr d cr
rt
(D
co
vj
rt
H,
P
<!
ro
S
o
o
0^
-rt
p
M
M
O
1-1
*
p
•<!
•ti
rt
1
s~\
ö
d
II
Hl
f»
M
M
*"~V
VO
-J
VO
*d
rt
II
FH)
a
i—•
Vi
rt
O
M
rt
0
Ü
l
t—
p
rt
CO
1
Tl
w
•
rt
i
i—
N>
*»
*•
*TJ
rt
^^
+
M
ro
^
F-
II
» 3
•—
cr
i—•
VO
M-
oo
u>
Vi
Tl
•
^**
rt
f
H-
M
1
oo
Ui
>*•
•
0«**
-rt
i
H-
»*^
+
d
rt
rt
H.
ro
3
1—'
O
X
TJ
CL
F-
%-*
+
II
" 3
M
cr
•*
^
rt
i
P-
+
d
rt
B
.
(D
• 00
.
F-
cr cr p
ro ro d
3 ro F-1
M <D
d
ti
3
lrt
F- CL P
cr F- M w d
p
3
CL H
co
P
3
o s!
p
p
MTI
M
p
ro
P O
M
P F- O FO (D r t
F- F-
H-1
iH-
cr
P
co
ro oo ro 3 s o «! M
o o o cr 3 o ro
o o H F- M n FCL 3
?r co
cr
ro d
co o
cr H n
8 Vcr
p (D co ro
F- j oo
f O M P ro r t F d
P F- >< o 3
«! i? OP roH ocr 3 TJM CO O
F- P co p d 3 s» cr rt
MT)
M H ro F- F- cr
M F- O FH I ro
rt c r r t co 3p 3 r t H
CL
ro
p
H 3 co M
Vj
Hi H-
ro
^co
ro
X rt
co <i Tl
co
ro P vo p P H- r t ro cr
CL 00 o
rt v i o o
3 o
rt
3
d
a cr
Ti ro P d T ) romp
CL <J 1-1 p H
o ro ro H F- r t H C L '
F- 0 ro ro r t rt
H
FF- 1
3
3 3 co
P
O O o
O f- 1
3 rt O
rt
P P H I ro cr > P rt
F3
Mi P
3 (B
H
CL 3
M
P CL 3
F - d co C L cr
<! O M C0
CL F- O 3 CL CL d ro
(D
M ro
ro ro T)
H3
T
)
rt
3
cr
3
•n
DO FVJ CL
Tl rt F- o 3
>i
co
3
rt
ro
P
H- o <
P ro 3 rt
M CT 3 M ro
CL
i
CT O < - F- P
co d ro 3
F- P
oo
ï!
ro
CL H- 3 F- H ro o
CL H
<
O r t 3 oo F d co £ Hro rt P
d co p rt cr
p
C T T ) rt ro 3 .
3
P cr
1
3 cr ro rt 3
o
3
co
d
r t Fro d
u. Hr t <!
d
oo
o ro
n P dM P" O ^ 3
co
>i rt
ro ^
cr ro
3 3 H ro ?r
P cr 3 ro
ro
P
H
l
co oo
ro 3
Tl
co ro P ro
cr 3
rt
• FVO FM o 3
P .
P ro
O Tl
F00 M
c r co o . P i-t
3 n
3
ro H M- co ro
P O f l CL Frt ro o o
H0Q
3 H- P ro C L r t FH
CLVj
p
O
3
3
CT
cr
ro
ro
<
r
t
F.
a
H
CJ.
a a <J CL
3
ro rt
< F- cr H I
os
ro
H co ro d P
P ro
TT
d
ro
ro
P
C
O
i-t
co ro co 3
P cr
ro
co ro p
» ö ü O »
oo ro
rt 3
d cr d
rt
co T J
r t rt O p
oo
P H- c r H I
rt P F- H O cr cr r i CO
p oo
F - N P ro ro ro rt F'
M
ro cr
H r t (D T l H
O CL co ^ M ro c r co
ro
F- cr co ro ro
H ro
ro ro Foo
cr co ro
p 3 ro
o ro co H CO ^e« H
co p rt
co
P
< vi
rt P T)
F d.
H Fo
ro
F8 H O M H S rt o ro <!
M d o
3
o o CL r t (D < O H l
H
rt rt
ro
O
ro
cr cr
CL M CO
co CO H '
ro
T l H.
rt 3
o P 3 cr T) ro T )
co r t F- ro ro
ro
d o ro
n
oo
H
i
r
t
n
ro
p
ti
M
»
ro P
ro ro
T l o CL
H
F- 3 <
FM H
{J CO
Tl ?f
rt F
F- < r t (D
o
< vj
F- 3
- a rt
0) CL ro C L
^
cr
F- o
3 ro co
co p
F- Fo
rt
oo
ro M
P vi
F- M 3
- cr
ro
CL
M
O Tl
F- O 3
Hl 3
3
3
M
(D
o
co co rt
dJ C L Fo
o
M
ro
T
l
rt rt
P (0 00 ^ N
rt
3
H
3
3
co t l T )
cr cr <j p
O
rt
ro co ro
1
F- O
ro
cr co O t i
cr
o
H
rt
Tl <
Hi Tl o
M ro
.. co F- 3
P
O
ro
pö
Mi-i ro
n rt
P
o 8
3 ro
ro
ro T I
CL
O
ro
f
o
o
00
T
l
M
3 F3
3
d
F- r t
rt co d C L T ) cr 8 ro 3 ro
ro ti
oo d
o
rt O
ro F- o d >i- p
o
rt H
ro 3
rt
HCL 3 p O F- 3
co 3
«! i H
CL
3
cr
O F- H
F- co ro o oo ro 3 rt
3 cr M F- O
ti
00
rt ro P P
ro
M
H ro ro 3 ro 3^ (D P
3
d ro
cr co F- rt P M CO
p
3 <
P
co ro
rt n p
3
.fj
ro
3
P
n
vo
rt
rt
T
l
•
ro
M
co
ro d
CL
rt
H P ro
o croo
«! ro
Fcrt-j.
co P p
(0 H
r t C L O ro P 8
F- H
si H
TJ
n
Ort
CO o.
3 H
H i cr d 3 co H M ro
F- ro cr P ro
3
C
L
co
co
ro
o
oo
ro
o
ro o
cr ro
co
o rt
d
rt
P
t voi CL
d w
H
T)
ro 00 rt
P
co ro cr
M ti
M P rt rt
H
cr
a rt
?r
F- rt H O Frt a ro FP O >i
ro
to o P
ro
3 co 00
T) M 3 8
o
oo
p
*
ro
3 o
oo d CL T l
cr M F- <! P CL
• ro H P
rt
w M d H Tl
P rt
ro co
ro o ro ro
3
P
o
cr
— CL
rt
P
O
CL<) co
M CL H
H I ro
O
P
<
d
ro rt
o Fcr M d rt
P O
F3
rt
o.
3
ro
3
ro
3 ro c r
£2 w V ! O P
ro
3
si
rt
ro
rt
p
o <!
CL
ro
F- co
n
O rt
^ ro
CL
O
ro
ro
P
. 3
M
MT)
F- 00 << F3 P
d
y*
S °-
5
•v*
8
involuntary unemployment is denied, is that they do generate positive serial
correlation in consumption and production, as happens in real-world cycles, but
that they fail to generate positive serial correlation in investment (Dotsey and
King 1988 p. 5). Another very serious problem for empirical testing of the NCME
hypothesis is that with lagged income in the aggregate supply function it tends
to become observationally equivalent with Keynesian models.
6. Empirical implications of NCME
In equilibrium business cycle models, fluctuations in employment are not
deviations from NRU, but movements of. NRU, apart from random disturbances. Darby
(1976) for the US and Benjamin and Kochin (1979 a, b, 1982) for the UK did not
hesitate to draw the conclusion that the unemployment of the 1930s was nothing to
worry about. Darby rested his case on a post-war finding that the government
spending multiplier was very small over a period of two or three years. In other
words, the five to seven per cent of the labour force employed in public
construction work in the US between 1934 to 1940 and officially counted as
unemployed, would in his view have been employed by private enterprise had the
government not taken them on. But of course the real government spending
multiplier can hardly be anything else than near-zero in a near-full-employment
economy as existed for large periods in the post-war era. This finding is totally
irrelevant for the 1930s. Moreover, even not counting those on public
construction work, unemployment was abnormally high (never lower than 9.2 per
cent, reached in 1937, as against 14.3 per cent including those on relief work,
using the same data as Darby).
Benjamin and Kochin argue that, had the British unemployment insurance
system in the interbellum been no more generous than it was in 1913, official
unemployment would have averaged seven per cent instead of fourteen. Without
denying that unemployment benefits may have played a role, it must be said that
Benjamin and Kochin seem to neglect the severity of the qualifications for
receiving benefits and to over-estimate the attractiveness of being on the dole
(cf Metcalf, Nickell and Floros 1982 pp. 387-393) whilst, moreover, their results
were not very robust (Ormerod and Worswick 1982, Collins 1982). What is more,
Benjamin and Kochin do not allow for demand effects in their research strategy,
though those effects seem to explain British unemployment in the interbellum
quite satisfactory (Broadberry 1983, Hatton 1983).
It is impossible to review the literature on empirical testing of RE and
NCME here. We will just give an idea of what is involved in such tests. For
expectations to be rational they must be both efficiënt and consistent.
Expectations are efficiënt if one-period forecasts and realisations share a
common autoregressive pattern:
n
x
t
-
s
a
ixt-i
+
u
i,t
i-1
n
E
t-1
X
t
=
b
2
iXt-i
+
U
2,t
i-1
Efficiency requires that &t - b± for all i, which means that expectations should
be generated by the same process that generates the variable to be forecast.
Otherwise, expectations are biased. Forecasts are consistent if the multiperiod
forecasts are obtained recursively, with the rational forecasts being substituted
for the as yet unobserved realisation of the series. On top of that, rationality
requires orthogonalitv. i.e., absence of serial correlation of forecast errors u
9
with known past errors. Using inflation expectations data from surveys held over
a long period by J. Livingston, Pesando (1975) found that the information used in
the six-month forecasts was not applied consistently to generate twelve-month
forecasts. It was also found, not only by Pesando but by others researchers as
well, that agents made systematic forecast errors (see Carlson and Parkin 1975,
Sheffrin 1983 pp. 17-23; an update of Carlson and Parkin by Batchelor and Orr
1988, however, was inconclusive). The outcome on orthogonality was mixed
(Batchelor and Orr 1988). Similar results have been found for interest-rate forecasts (B.M. Friedman 1980).
Rational expectations have been very extensively applied in models of
financial markets. The idea is that markets are efficiënt, which means that
expectations are rational and arbitrage is quick. In other words, frictions are
minimal and all available information is rapidly reflected in prices. See on this
the chapter on exchange rates.
One upshot of RE and NCME is that expected changes in money growth affect
the rate of inflation, whilst unexpected changes first of all affect real
variables. Tests based on this idea have been reasonably positive for NCME, see
Wogin (1980) for Canada 1927-'72, Attfield, Demery and Duck (1981) for the UK
1963-'78, Barro (1977, 1978) for the US 1941-'73, Bomhoff (1979 Ch. 4) for the
Netherlands 1953-'76. Less positive results, however, have been reported by Barro
and Rush (1980) for the US 1941-1980 and negative results by Driscoll, Ford,
Mullineux and Sen (1983) for the UK over the post-war period through 1979 and
Paleologos (1986) for post-war Greece. In such tests much depends of course on
the way expectations are modelled. Apart from that, there is the problem of
observational equivalence, i.e., the fact that the time series are compatible
with several rival theories (cf Sargent 1976, see for an especially lucid
discussion of the econometrie issues involved Attfield, Demery and Duck 1985).
If anticipated changes in money growth only affect the rate of inflation, it
should be possible to reduce inflation by means of a restrictive monetary policy
without serious side-effects in the form of unemployment. Eckstein (1981)
concluded from simulations with the 800-equation DRI-model (from Data Resources,
Ine) for the US that there is great resistance of factor prices to demand
management, including monetary policy. It appeared that changes in long-term
expectations take time (Eckstein 1981 pp. 60-62, 79). Gradual price adjustment
was also reported by Gordon (1982) for the US, 1890-1980. This might explain why
disinflation policies in the US starting in 1979 (cf Mankiw 1986 p. 218), in
Britain under Mrs Thatcher, also starting in 1979 (cf Attfield, Demery and Duck
1985 pp. 195-'97), and in Chile under Pinochet after 1973 (cf Corbo and de Melo
1987) initially caused a sharp rise in unemployment. The public possibly first
sits back to see if the government's policy is credible, i.e., will not be
reversed.
7. NCME and market clearing
NCME imposes not only RE but also continuously clearing markets. We have seen
above that initially policy ineffectiveness was postulated but that it was later
admitted that this idea was oversold. Shocks may cause multi-period deviations
from trend output and employment. This could, however, be explained without
abandoning the continuous-clearing postulate. Continuous market clearing seems
hard to defend, though. We have already cited evidence of gradual price
adjustment. It has been emphasised that some degree of price stickiness may be
preferable for both sellers and buyers. Okun stressed the fact that continuous
market clearing implies the universality of organised auction markets, resembling Walras's model. Such markets can only exist for products that are
standardised and can be viewed as homogeneous by a prospective buyer who places
orders through a broker. Markets for other products, heterogerieous goods, are
search or customer markets. Sellers in these markets are price makers and,
10
therefore, quantity takers. A demand shock will intially alter quantities and
leave prices unchanged. Sellers have an incentive not to change prices too
frequently. They have a kind of implicit contract with their customers. Shopping
is costly. If customers can be sure of the prices advertised by their suppliers,
they will return for repeat buys. With frequent price adjustments, customers will
spend more time shopping around, so it is in the interest of both seller and
buyer to enter into an implicit contract (Okun 1981 Ch. 4).
Nominal wage rigidities can be explained by the costs of changing nominal
wages or of indexation (Corden 1987 p. 173, Minford 1986 p. 321). Nonetheless, if
inflation is high and variable, indexation clauses are likely to be included in
wage contracts and contracts will have a shorter duration. Imperfect information
may be more important in practice, as emphasised by New Kevnesian economists (cf
Greenwald and Stiglitz 1987 pp. 123-'5), who follow in Okun's steps (Okun 1981
Ch. III). They point to such facts as the imperfect information that employers
have about employees and the costs of taking on new personnel. It may be preferable from the point of view of maximising profits to boost the morale of the work
force that is employed by the firm by keeping wages high rather than taking on
people who are willing to supply labour at a lower wage. The cost of selection
procedures and also that of training of new personnel is far from negligible. For
employees, searching for other jobs may be costly (see, apart from Okun, also
Hahn 1980 p. 288).
Empirical evidence of sticky prices, apart from the study by Gordon
mentioned above, was found by Silberston (1973) and Rotemberg (1982). Sticky
wages and prices were found by Gordon (1983) for post-war USA, but not for postwar Britain and Japan. Carlton (1986) studied individual transactions price data
collected by G. Stigler and J. Kindahl and found that prices can be quite rigid,
prices to individual buyers in some industries remaining constant for several
years. Price rigidity was positively correlated with the degree of concentration
in the industry concerned.
The above implies that that unemployed workers may offer their labour
services below the going wage rate and still be refused employment. Employers may
quite rationally prefer to hire at a fixed wage and ration the posts offered. In
other words, there are quantity constraints and the system does not function like
a Walrasian general-equilibrium system where all agents are price takers and the
auctioneer makes sure that an optimum is found. Nor would it do to introducé nonmarket-clearing and retain the other aspects of the Walrasian model (Lucas 1987
Ch. 5). That model does not admit of involuntary unemployed remaining unemployed
even though they offer their labour services at a rate below the going market
rate. It only determines hours of employment and wages, neglecting quits and
fires.
In the goods markets there are quantity constraints as well. In the real
world firms are price setters who set output targets on the basis of expected
sales. Deviations of output from trend result from faulty sales forecasts, not
from incorrect price expectations, as in NCME models (cf Forman 1980 p. 38).
Furthermore, in the real world communication and coordination between markets is
time-consuming and costly (Gordon 1981 p. 526). Decisions made in one market
during one period may only affect other markets during the next period, and
economie agents in any one market are constrained by conditions prevailing in
other markets which lack the flexibility of Walrasian markets. Firms may be
unable to lower their selling prices at short notice after a negative demand
shock, for instance, because their suppliers will only after a lapse of time be
willing to adjust the prices of inputs. A demand shock therefore first affects
quantities and only after a period of time will prices react. In such a non-NCME
world stabilisation policies may be quite effective. Rational expectations are
not precluded and may even strenghten the effectiveness of stabilisation measures. Agents may, e.g., hold that with a higher money stock the demand for goods
will be higher. Higher expected demand for the next period may improve employment
expectations for the next period, depress savings for the current period and in
11
that way increase demand and employment for the current period. There is in that
case not a unique RE equilibrium (cf Hahn 1982, Tobin 1980 p. 45; see Begg 1982
section 6.4 and Neary and Stiglitz 1983 for models in this vein).
Arguably real monetary economies are characterised by the very properties
that NCME leaves out, such as transaction costs, apart from information costs to
some degree, and economies of scale that preclude perfect competition.
Essentially, NCME models, often one-good models, describe a world where money is
inessential. They have to rely on quite improbable suppositions to explain
economie fluctuations. Neither firms nor workers are likely to confuse price
level and relative price movements for other than restricted periods or small
changes. The Friedman-Phelps approach and the Lucas supply function are not wellfounded.
8. Rational expectations; positive contributions and problems
The RE hypothesis has a lot going for it. RE as such do not imply policy ineffectiveness (as we have seen, not even NCME precludes policy effectiveness). RE
have, though, brought home the fact that expectations concerning policy measures
affect the outcome of those measures. This led Lucas (1976) to make short shrift
of econometrie model simulations of economie policy measures. He argued that, as
agents take account of the government's policy, the structural parameters of the
model cannot be assumed to be stable. The logic of this Lucas critique seems
unassailable. More generally, RE have made us aware that models where economie
agents make systematic mistakes offer unexploited opportunities for profit
making. This runs counter to economie insights and intuition.
Still, the applicability of RE seems restricted. RE presuppose a 'true'
probability distribution of outcomes which is known by agents. This means that it
only fits situations characterised by Knightian risk, not uncertainty, i.e.,
recurring stochastic processes (Lucas 1977 p. 15). One might try to 'rescue' RE
by introducing subjective or Bayesian probability, but different people may hold
widely diverging beliefs about the future, whilst RE models usually postulate
identical beliefs about probability distributions of future events (Bray 1985 p.
167). This does, however, not seriously handicap RE in comparison with other
suppositions. It is a universal problem. There is no way to get rid of Keynes's
'dark forces of time and ignorance' (Keynes 1936 p. 161).
If, because of unforeseen shocks, the structural parameters of the system
change, it seems reasonable to expect a learning period during which agents
assemble information about the new structure. In that case we are back with a
kind of adaptive expectations (B.M. Friedman 1979 p. 36, Sijben 1980 p. 92). It
is not of the naive adaptive kind, though, where agents make systematic errors
of the kind described by Milton Friedman in his attack on the idea of a long-term
Phillips-type trade-off between inflation and employment. An obvious case is when
a new government announces that it will reverse the pernicious policies of its
predecessor. Especially when similar policy intentions in the past only paved the
way to heil, as so often happens with good intentions, agents will tend to adopt
a wait-and-see attitude first. Only after it has become clear that a new regime,
e.g. a liberalised foreign-trade regime, is there to stay, investors will change
their behaviour accordingly and, in this case, move from import-competing
industries to export industries.
In the course of a learning process, economie agents take decisions based on
incomplete information, i.e., a false model of the system, and in that way make
the system itself change. Convergence to a RE equilibrium requires agents to
improve their forecasts faster than the model changes (Runde and Torr 1985).
There are some obstacles standing in the way of the implied feedback. It often
takes considerable time before the outcome of a decision is known and then it may
be difficult to attribute it to a particular action, and there is often no
information about what would have happened had other decisions been taken
12
(Tversky and Kahneman 1986 p. S274). Another thing is that some models admit of
multiple equilibria, as noted earlier (section 3,2, above). Optimism and
pessimism may be self-fulfilling (Fischer 1988 p. 325), which opens the way for
government policies. This is the case when the values of today's endogenous
variables depend on today's expectations of tomorrow's exogenous variables (see
for such a model the chapter on exchange rates). Again, this is not peculiar to
RE models, but an inescapable feature of dynamic models with expectations as to
the future. To complicate matters, agents may quite rationally expect other
agents not to base their decisions on so-called market fundamentals, such as real
growth, money growth and interest rates, and base their own decisions on those
expected decisions by others. This opens up the possibility of rational
speculative bubbles, a subject more pursued in the litterature on RE in financial
markets than in RE macromodels. We will return to it in the chapter on exchange
rates. Finally, there is disturbing evidence from psychological tests that people
judge the likelihood of a future event by its similarity to current events,
ignoring both prior information and the quality of current evidence (e.g., sample
size) and underestimating uncertainties (A. Tversky and D. Kahneman, cited by
Arrow 1982 p. 5). Also, it was found that alternative descriptions of a problem
often influence decisions (Tversky and Kahnemann 1986 p. S251).
It seems fair to conclude that NCME neglects some of the basic features of a
monetary economy, but that RE have a useful, though limited role to play, e.g.,
in providing a research strategy for some kinds of markets.
13
This chapter is a rewritten version of Visser 1984.
Bibliographv
K.J. Arrow, Risk Perception in Psychology and Economics, Economie Inquiry. vol.
20 no. 1, 1982.
K. Asako, Rational Expectations and the Effectiveness of Monetary Policy with
Special Reference to the Barro-Fischer Model, Journal of Monetarv Economics, vol.
9 no. 1, 1982.
C.L.F. Attfield, D. Demery and N.W. Duck, A Quarterly Model of Unanticipated
Monetary Growth, Output and the Price Level in the U.K. 1963-1978, Journal of
Monetarv Economics. vol. 8 no. 3, 1981.
C.L.F. Attfield, D. Demery and N.W. Duck, Rational Expectations in
Macroeconomics. Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1985.
R.J. Barro, Unanticipated Money Growth and Unemployment in the United States,
American Economie Review, vol. 67 no. 2, 1977. Reprinted in R.E. Lucas, Jr and
Th.J. Sargent (eds), 1981.
R.J. Barro, Unanticipated Money, Output, and the Price Level in the United
States, Journal of Political Economv. vol. 86 no. 4, 1978. Reprinted in R.E.
Lucas, Jr and Th.J. Sargent (eds), 1981.
R.J. Barro and M. Rush, Unanticipated Money and Economie Activity, in S. Fischer
(ed.), Rational Expectations and Economie Activity. University of Chicago Press,
Chicago 1980.
R.A. Batchelor and A.B. Orr, Inflation Expectations Revisited, Economica. vol. 55
no. 219, 1988.
D.K.H. Begg, The Rational Expectations Revolution in Macroeconomics, Philip
Allan, Deddington 1982.
D.K. Benjamin and L.A. Kochin, Voluntary Unemployment in Interwar Britain, The
Banker. vol. 129 no. 636, 1979(a).
D.K. Benjamin and L.A. Kochin, Searching for an Explanation of Unemployment in
Interwar Britain, Journal of Political Economv. vol. 87 no. 3, 1979(b).
D.K. Benjamin and L.A. Kochin, Unemployment and Unemployment Benefits in
Twentieth-Century Britain: A Reply to Our Critics, Journal of Political Economv,
vol. 90 no. 2, 1982.
A.S. Blinder and S. Fischer, Inventories, Rational Expectations, and the Business
Cycle, Journal of Monetarv Economics. vol. 8 no. 3, 1981.
E.J. Bomhoff, Inflation. the Quantitv Theorv and Rational Expectations. North
Holland, Amsterdam 1980.
M. Bray, Rational Expectations, Information and Asset Markets: An Introduction,
Oxford Economie Papers, vol. 37 no. 2, 1985.
S.N. Broadberry, Unemployment in Interwar Britain: A Disequilibrium Approach,
Oxford Economie Papers, vol. 35 no. 3, 1983.
14
K. Brunner, A. Cukierman and A.H. Meltzer, Money and Economie Activity,
Inventories and Business Cycles, Journal of Monetarv Economies, vol. 11 no. 3,
1983.
J.A. Carlson and M. Parkin, Inflation Expectations, Economica, vol. 42 no. 166,
1975.
D.W. Carlton, The Rigidity of Prices, American Economie Review, vol. 76 no. 4,
1986.
M. Collins, Unemployment in Interwar Britain: Still Searching for an
Explanation, Journal of Political Economy. vol. 90 no. 2, 1982.
V. Corbo and J. de Melo, Lessons from the Southern Cone Policy Reforms, World
Bank Research Observer. vol. 2 no. 2, 1987.
M.W. Corden, The Relevance for Developing Countries of Recent Developments in
Macroeconomic Theory, World Bank Research Observer. vol. 2 no. 2, 1987.
M.R. Darby, Three-and-a-Half Million U.S. Employees Have Been Mislaid; Or, an
Explanation of Unemployment, 1934-1941, Journal of Political Economy. vol. 84 no.
1, 1976.
M. Dotsey and R.G. King, Rational Expectations Business Cycle Models: A Survey,
Economie Review. Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond, vol. 74 no. 2, 1988.
M.J. Driscoll, J.L. Ford, A.W. Mullineux and S. Sen, Money, Output, Rational
Expectations and Neutrality: Some Econometrie Results for the UK, Economica. vol.
50 no. 199, 1983.
0. Eckstein, Core Inflation. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs 1981.
S. Fischer, Long-Term Contracts, Rational Expectations, and the Optimal Money
Supply Rule, Journal of Political Economy. vol. 85 no. 1, 1977.
S. Fischer, Anticipations and the Nonneutrality of Money, Journal of Political
Economy. vol. 87 no. 2, 1979.
S. Fischer, Recent Developments in Macroeconomics, Economie Journal, vol. 98 no.
391, 1988.
S. Fischer (ed.), Rational Expectations and Economie Policy. University of
Chicago Press, Chicago 1980.
L. Forman, Rational Expectations and the Real World, Challenge. vol. 23 no. 5,
1980.
B.M. Friedman, Optimal expectations and the extreme information assumption of
'rational expectations' macromodels, Journal of Monetarv Economies. vol. 5 no. 1,
1979.
B.M. Friedman, Survey Evidence on the 'Rationality' of Interest Rate
Expectations, Journal of Monetary Economies. vol. 6 no. 4, 1980.
15
M. Friedman, The Role of Monetary Policy, in The Optimum Quantity of Money and
Other Essays. Macmillan, London 1969. Presidential address to the American
Economie Association, first published in American Economie Review, vol. 58 no. 1,
1968.
M. Friedman, Price Theory. Aldine, Chicago 1976.
R.J. Gordon, Output Fluctuations and Gradual Price Adjustment, Journal of
Economie Literature. vol. 19 no. 2, 1981.
R.J. Gordon, Price Inertia and Policy Ineffectiveness in the United States, 18901980, Journal of Political Economy. vol. 90 no. 6, 1982.
R.J. Gordon, A Century of Evidence on Wage and Price Stickiness in the United
States, the United Kingdom, and Japan, in J. Tobin (ed.), Macroeconomics. Prices,
and Quantities: Essays in Memory of Arthur M. Okun. Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1983.
B. Greenwald and J.E. Stiglitz, Keynesian, New Keynesian and New Classical
Economics, Oxford Economie Papers, vol. 39, 1987.
H.I. Grossman, Rationa! Expectations, Business Cycles, and Government Behavior,
in S. Fischer (ed.), o.e. 1980.
F.H. Halm, Unemployment from a Theoretical Viewpoint, Economica. vol. 47 no. 187,
1980.
F.H. Hahn, Money and Inflation. Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1982.
T.J. Hatton, Unemployment Benefits and the Macroeconomics of the Interwar Labour
Market: A Further Analysis, Oxford Economie Papers, vol. 35 no. 3, 1983.
J.M. Keynes, The General Theory of Emplovment. Interest and Money. Macmillan,
London 1936.
A. Klamer, The New Classical Macroeconomics. Wheatsheaf, Brighton 1984.
P. Korteweg, Activisme of automatie in de monetaire politiek?, Economisch
Statistische Berichten, vol. 61 no. 3054, 1976.
D. Laidler, Monetarism: An Interpretation and an Assessment, Economie Journal.
vol. 81 no. 361, 1981.
R.E. Lucas, Jr, Expectations and the Neutrality of Money, Journal of Economie
Theory. vol. 4 no. 2, 1972.
R.E. Lucas, Jr, Some International Evidence on Output-Inflation Tradeoffs,
American Economie Review, vol. 63 no. 3, 1973.
R.E. Lucas, Jr, An Equilibrium Model of the Business Cycle, Journal of Political
Economy. vol. 83 no. 6, 1975.
R.E. Lucas, Jr, Econometrie Policy Evaluation: A Critique, in. K. Brunner and A.H.
Meltzer (eds), The Phillips Curve and Labor Markets. Carnegie-Rochester
Conference Series on Public Policy, vol. 1, 1976.
R.E. Lucas, Jr, Understanding Business Cycles, in K. Brunner and A.H. Meltzer
(eds), Stabilization of the Domestic and International Economy, CarnegieRochester Conference Series on Public Policy, vol. 5, 1977.
16
R.E. Lucas, Jr, Models of Business Cycles. Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1987.
R.E. Lucas. Jr and Th.J. Sargent (eds), Rational Expectations and Econometrie
Practice, George Allen & Unwin, London 1981.
N.G. Mankiw, Issues in Keynesian Macroeconomics, Journal of Monetary Economics,
vol. 18, 1986.
S. McCafferty, Rational Expectations, Disequilibrium Quantities, and Policy
Effectiveness in a Non-Market-Clearing Framework, Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv.
vol. 118 no. 3, 1982.
B.T. McCallum, Price-Level Stickiness and the Feasibility of Monetary
Stabilization Policy with Rational Expectations, Journal of Political Economy.
vol. 85 no. 3, 1977.
B.T. McCallum, The Current State of the Policy-Ineffectiveness Debate, American
Economie Review, vol. 69 no. 2, 1979.
B.T. McCallum, The Significance of Rational Expectations Theory, Challenge. vol.
22 no. 6, 1980(a).
B.T. McCallum, Rational Expectations and Macroeconomic Stabilization Policy,
Journal of Money. Credit, and Banking, vol. 12 no. 4 part II, 1980(b).
D. Metcalf, S.J. Nickell and N. Floros, Still Searching for an Explanation of
Unemployment in Interwar Britain, Journal of Political Economy. vol. 90 no. 2,
1982.
P. Minford, Rational Expectations and Monetary Policy, Scottish Journal of
Political Economy. vol. 33 no. 4, 1986.
P. Minford and D. Peel, The Role of Monetary Stabilization Policy under Rational
Expectations, Manchester School, vol. 49 no. 1, 1981.
P.J. Montiel, Output and Unanticipated Money in the Dependent Economy Model, IMF
Staff Papers, vol. 34 no. 2, 1987.
R.A. Mundell, Inflation and Real Interest, Journal of Political Economy. vol. 71
no. 3, 1963.
R.A. Mundell, Monetary Theory. Goodyear, Pacific Palisades 1971.
J.F. Muth, Rational Expectations and the Theory of Price Movements, Economiea.
vol. 29 no. 3, 1961.
J.P. Neary and J.E. Stiglitz, Toward a Reconstruction of Keynesian Economics:
Expectations and Constrained Equilibria, Quarterlv Journal of Economics. vol. 98
Supplement, 1983.
J. Niehans, Classical Monetary Theory, New and Old, Journal of Money. Credit, and
Banking. vol. 19 no. 4, 1987.
A.M. Okun, Prices and Quantities: A Macroeconomic Approach. Basil Blackwell,
Oxford 1981.
P.A. Ormerod and G.D.N. Worswick, Unemployment in Interwar Britain, Journal of
17
Political Economv. vol. 90 no. 2, 1982.
L.T. Oxley, Rational Expectations and Macroeconomic Policy: A Review Article,
Scottish Journal of Political Economv. vol. 30 no. 2, 1983.
J. Paleologos, Unanticipated Money, Output, and Inflation in Greece, Public
Finance, vol. 41 no. 3, 1986.
J.E. Pesando, A Note on the Rationality of the Livingston Price Expectations,
Journal of Political Economv. vol. 83 no. 4, 1975.
E.S. Phelps, Introduction, in E.S. Phelps a.o., Microeconomic Foundations of
Emplovment and Inflation Theorv. Macmillan, London 1971.
E.S. Phelps and J.B. Taylor, Stabilizing Powers of Monetary Policy under Rational
Expectations, Journal of Political Economv. vol. 85 no. 1, 1977.
A.W. Phillips, The Relationship between Unemployment and the Rate of Change of
Money Wage Rates in the United Kingdom, 1861-1957, Economica. n.s. vol. 25, 1958.
Reprinted as Unemployment and Wage Rates in R.J. Ball and P. Doyle (eds),
Inflation. Penguin, Harmondsworth 1969.
J.J. Rotemberg, Sticky Prices in the United States, Journal of Political Economv.
vol. 90 no. 6, 1982.
J. Runde and C. Torr, Divergent Expectations and Rational Expectations, South
African Journal of Economics. vol. 53 no. 3, 1985.
Th. J. Sargent, Testing for Neutrality and Rationality, in A Preseription for
Monetary Policy; Proceedings from a Seminar Series. Federal Reserve Bank of
Minneapolis, Minneapolis 1976.
Th. J. Sargent and N. Wallace, 'Rational' Expectations, the Optimal Monetary
Instrument, and the Optimal Money Supply Rule, Journal of Political Economv. vol.
83 no. 2, 1975.
S.M. Sheffrin, Rational Expectations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1983.
R.J. Shiller, Rational Expectations and the Dynamic Structure of Macroeconomic
Models, Journal of Monetary Economics. vol. 4 no. 1, 1978.
A. Silberston, Price Behaviour of Firms, in Survevs of Applied Economics. vol. I.
Macmillan, London 1973. First published in Economie Journal, vol. 80, 1970.
D.J. Snower, Rational Expectations, Nonlinearities, and the Effectiveness of
Monetary Policy, Oxford Economie Papers, vol. 36 no. 2, 1984.
J.J. Sijben, Rational expectations and monetary policy. Sijthoff & Noordhoff,
Alphen aan den Rijn 1980.
J. Tobin, Money and Economie Growth, Econometrica. vol. 33 no. 4, 1965.
J. Tobin, Asset Accumulation and Economie Activitv. Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1980.
J. Tobin, The Monetarist Counter-Revolution Today - an Appraisal, Economie
Journal, vol. 91 no. 361, 1981.
A. Tversky and D. Kahneman, Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions, Journal
18
of Business, vol. 59 no. 4 pt 2, 1986.
H. Visser, New Classical Macroeconomics as Seen bv an Impressed Non-believer or,
Keynes and the Classics All Over Again. SUERF, Tilburg 1984.
H. Wagner, Wirtschaftspolitik im Lichte rationaler Erwartungen, Koniunkturpolitik. vol. 27 no. 1, 1981.
G. Wogin, Unemployment and Monetary Policy under Rational Expectations, Journal
of Monetary Economics. vol. 6 no. 1, 1980.
Download