Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Uncertainty, Politics, and Barbarism Mevrouw de Rector Magnificus, Mijnheer de Decaan Dear Esteemed Colleagues and Friends, Introduction. Recently, while writing in the Washington Post, Oxford University’s White Professor of Moral philosophy, Jeff McMahan, called for a ‘humanitarian’ proxy war against the “barbarians” of ISIS in Syria by the “West.”i In response, I noted that “the West” is not a proper contrast to “barbarian;” a barbarian (think of the action-figure, Conan) is traditionally opposed to a ‘civilized’ or ‘humane’ person. After all, “the West” is not incompatible with barbarism in its midst.ii For example, in 1672 a mob lynched and cannibalized the Brothers De Witt in plain daylight at the Gevangenispoort in the Hague. Spinoza reacted with horror;iii his land-lady restrained him from putting a placard at the murder site. It is supposed to have read: "Ultimi barbarorum," that is, “ultimate barbarians.”iv At the time, the Dutch Republic was the wealthiest, most cultivated, and literate society of Europe.v The anecdote about the placard is often used to suggest that Spinoza was a supporter of De Witt.vi Before I get to Spinoza’s real attitude toward De witt, I provide you a roadmap of what follows. First, I first briefly re-introduce De Witt. For, inspired by Spinoza and Hume, I treat De Witt as a would-be-modern-philosopher-king equipped with the latest science. I do so in order to explore the nature of politics and the limitations of science. In the second, third, and fourth parts of this lecture, I explore Spinoza’s and David Hume’s analyses of the downfall of De Witt in order to argue, first, that politics is characterized by activity under uncertainty;vii second, that the political is about securing unity in the context of conflicting 1 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com interests and values. I claim that this understanding of politics is central to the Liberal tradition prior to the middle of the twentieth century. The fifth part is a brief interlude about an unknown episode that involves De Witt’s contemporaries, Christiaan Huygens, and Johannes Hudde. In the sixth part, I describe how twentieth century Liberal thought tried to do without uncertainty and sketch some of the contours of my future research; I wish to contribute to reviving the Liberal tradition in a way that is realist and utopian, although today I focus more on the realist strain.viii I end with a brief conclusion. One disclaimer: I have introduced some terms, ‘Liberal,’ ‘uncertainty,’ ‘politics,’ and ‘barbarism’ without definition. I characterize these more precisely in what follows. 1. De Witt, Hudde, and Huygens In this section, I briefly introduce De Witt. Johan de Witt (1625-1672) was part of a talented group of students of the Cartesian (Leiden) mathematician Van Schooten. Van Schooten translated Descartes’s La Géometrié into Latin (1649), and wrote an important commentary on it (1661).ix This commentary included an appendix by De Witt.x Van Schooten also published a translation of Christiaan Huygens’s work on probability (1657).xi Building on Huygens’s treatise, Huygens, De Witt, and, yet another student first published by Van Schooten, Johannes Hudde,xii explored foundations of probability and life insurance in subsequent decades.xiii All three (Huygens, Hudde, and De Witt) were independent minded, Cartesians and figure in my narrative today. De Witt, as Raadspensionaris of the State of Holland, was the most powerful politician in the Dutch Republic until he got massacred in 1672--the year when Dutch forces were overrun by a French army and facing English attack at sea.xiv In what follows, I treat De Witt as an exemplar of the limitations of a certain style of scientific politics. 2 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com 2. Spinoza and De Witt’s Fall In this section, I discuss Spinoza’s criticisms of De Witt in order to call attention to two themes: first, the role of knowledge in politics; second, to argue that domestic strife is a symptom of bad leadership and badly functioning institutions. Spinoza outlived De Witt by five years, and during that period he worked on the posthumously published Political Treatise. This book reveals that Spinoza was not a defender of the Dutch oligarchy under De Witt. In fact, he thought it inherently unstable. In chapter 8, Spinoza describes the collapse of the Dutch Republic. He asserts that within an oligarchy, daily political rule is devolved to a bright upstart.xv In 1672 it turned out that De Witt was dispensable. Spinoza was right to predict that the Dutch would never recover their former glory.xvi De Witt was probably the most capable person to lead the Dutch confederacy. This is the meritocratic element of an aristocracy. But by becoming dependent on the judgment of one, political decision-making also becomes more fragile. This connects to Spinoza’s defense of democratic decision-making in the (earlier, 1670) Theological Political Treatise, where he argued for the epistemic benefits of a multiplicity of public voices in decision-making. Spinoza did not expect infallibility from democratic decision-making, but he did expect fewer disastrous mistakes and more stability.xvii In the Political Treatise, there is no trace of nostalgia for oligarchy; Spinoza resists the urge to turn De Witt into a martyr. Rather, Spinoza explicitly treats De Witt's fall as evidence for the bad institutional design of the Dutch republic. In fact, De Witt’s fall is an instance of a more general claim by Spinoza. Throughout the Political Treatise, Spinoza treats war, internal strife, lawlessness, criminality, etc. as de facto evidence of bad institutional design. I made two Spinozistic moves in this section: first, the significance of epistemology, that is, the role of the nature and scope of knowledge, to political 3 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com theory. Second, domestic strife is, in fact, a sign of bad leadership and badly functioning institutions. I elaborate on both moves before long. 3. Magnanimous De Witt In this section I discuss David Hume’s analysis of the Fall of De Witt in order to argue for three claims: first, a politician must inspire unity among the citizenry. Second, politicians act under conditions of genuine uncertainty. Third, scientific politics risks expert overconfidence. The eighteenth century Scottish philosopher, David Hume, is now best known for his Treatise. But in his own lifetime Hume grew rich and famous with his History of England.xviii In his narrative Hume introduces Johan De Witt with superlative qualifications: De Witt is “equally eminent for greatness of mind, for capacity, and for integrity.”xix Later, when Hume describes the meeting of Sir William Temple, the English ambassador in The Hague, and De Witt, he again evokes De Witt’s magnanimity.xx De Witt sacrifices “all private considerations to the public service.” Of all the exemplary political characters treated by Hume only the quasi-mythical Alfred the Great, and the ruthless King Edward 1st, receive a more generous evaluation from Hume in his seventeen hundred year narrative.xxi Hume emphasizes that De Wit is willing to negotiate to prevent war; De Witt’s greatness is not of the conquering kind.xxii But while De Witt prefers to avoid war, he will not yield on matters of principle (“reason”) or justice (“equity”). For according to the foreign policy doctrine attributed to De Witt, concessions will not prevent war, but only lead to new demands that will eventually lead to war (or full surrender). De Witt’s maxim is not a universal one; it is not appropriate to weak powers or - as the Netherlands are today --, protectorates. Hume intimates that to stand on principle or justice when one is not capable of or unwilling to sacrifice for independence is, while noble, an act of foolishness. This entails that De Witt is 4 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com taken to accept that international politics is a kind of Hobbesian state of nature. Only a great state can enforce equity. Such justice is also a matter of selfinterest because, as I have shown in joint work with the economist Spencer Pack, by Hume's lights there is little difference between justice/equity and property.xxiii Among qualities praised by Hume, is De Witt’s ability to preserve, even promote, a spirit of unity in a confederation that was notoriously incapable of such unity: recall the execution of De Witt’s predecessor, the pensionary of the State of Holland Van Oldebarneveldt and the civil war unleashed by the stadtholder William II of Orange. To generate and maintain unity, guided and constrained by reason and equity, is the political act as such. The unity is not metaphysical, but dispositional.xxiv That is, a politician or a society must be able to generate, or facilitate, opinions and habits of thought that allow individual citizens or constitutive orders of a polity to maintain a latent or actualized commitment to some unity.xxv For Hume, good political leadership involves ensuring that unity is maintained through external threat and the forces of internal dissolution. Now, De Witt is as close to a philosopher-king we have seen in the modern age; De Witt is the expert that rules experts; Hume makes the point explicitly with an allusion to Plato’s Republic 488e–489d, while describing De Witt as follows: “The genius of this man was of the most extensive nature. He quickly became as much master of naval affairs, as if he had from his infancy been educated in them; and he even made improvements in some parts of pilotage and sailing, beyond what men expert in those arts had ever been able to attain.”xxvi Hume’s account is surprising in two ways. To recognize these surprises, I first need to remind you that Hume is known to be a defender of the impartial even stable rule of law--a core commitment of all strands of Liberalism.xxvii In fact, in this tradition ‘barbarism’ and the ‘rule of law’ are antonyms; the one excludes the other.xxviii 5 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Yet, when there is a threat to the security or survival of the state, Hume’s position is more flexible. For, he notes and approves of De Witt's willingness to break Dutch law, in order to ratify rapidly a treaty (The Triple League) deemed necessary for the public interests: “de Wit [sic] had the courage, for the public good, to break through the laws in so fundamental an article…Though they acknowledged, that, if that measure should displease their constituents, they risqued [sic] their heads...”xxix The second surprise is that while law is rule-bound, a politician’s craft is not. A politician has to act under conditions of genuine uncertainty and while there are maxims that can be followed, there are circumstances when she is in uncharted waters. For the “public good” one may even break the law with all the unintended consequences that may entail. One might think, then, that political wisdom consists in a willingness to make decisions. This view is now often associated with Nietzsche and Carl Schmitt. But this is not Hume’s position. For Hume bring the state of emergency under the rule of law in his one Utopian work, his short enigmatic essay, “Idea Of a Perfect Commonwealth.” It is rarely studied—even Jonathan Israel overlooks it in his massive works on the Enlightenment.xxx I’ll spare you all the details of Hume’s utopian blueprint. But, it turns out, that during “extraordinary emergencies,” Hume allows a junta with dictatorial power for “six months.”xxxi For Hume the emergencies arise, if they do, only in foreign affairs, especially in the context of war and conquest. So, even in "the most perfect of all" possible states we need to prepare for unexpected and unpleasant surprises. Hume's proposal might appear as a nod to Livy's famous account of the dictatorship of Cincinnatus in Republican Rome.xxxii But Hume is explicit that his commonwealth is an improvement of ancient republics because he considers these "oppressive." He has little fondness for the Ancient embrace of slavery. 6 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com A better way to understand Hume's treatment is to take him at his word, and note the "resemblance that [the blueprint of a perfect commonwealth] bears to the commonwealth of the United Provinces, a wise and renowned government."xxxiii Hume's perfect commonwealth is not a confederation, but a federation that can act as a true unity in foreign affairs even during an emergency. That is, while foreshadowing the American Presidency, Hume designs his own ideal state to make space for a future De Witt, who, in cases of emergency, can make public spirited decisions in foreign affairs without too much constraint but within a legal framework. But rather than trusting a single person with emergency powers, he assigns such authority to a small group.xxxiv It is an open question if Hume's approach does not lead to the "oppression" he dreads. States of emergency within a liberal framework are not a mere historical curiosity. As I speak, France has been operating under emergency powers for a few months already. In my judgment this is a mistake because France’s survival is not at stake and the seeds for future division and hatred are being sown on a daily basis.xxxv Let me return to Hume’s analysis of De Witt’s Fall in his History. There he argues that courageous decision-ism can be taken too far. xxxvi In particular, politicians often must act under conditions of uncertainty; a wise politician legislates ends and acts on fallible causal social knowledge that she learns from the social scientist. xxxvii For, on Hume’s view, where there are stable social or national institutions we can discover robust patterns of behavior. Hume thinks this is true in modern states, but not in the international arena.xxxviii Hume points to multiple causes for De Witt’s fall; the most spectacular is De Witt’s misjudgment of the international situation.xxxix De Witt’s response to the threat posed by England and France is treated as an instance of expert overconfidence. De Witt treats his country's potential enemies as rational, calculating agents--ones that understand their own self-interests properly and that will act accordingly. In the grip of his (proto-)rational choice model of 7 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com reality, De Witt treats something as “impossible” that he ought to prepare for.xl De Witt is turned into an anti-exemplar of an intellectual that mistakes his own rational view of the world for reality. In particular, Hume does not deny that De Witt understands the true interest of King Charles II as well as the King, but his Cartesian science has not prepared De Witt for the true political art.xli As Spinoza had also concluded, Cartesian science does not provide guidance for applying one’s knowledge in political life. For, Descartes takes political power as given; the first maxim of Descartes’s Discourse on Method is “to obey the laws and customs of my country.”xlii Modern natural science may originate in the desire to conquer nature, but by Spinoza’s and Hume’s lights it fails at the art of ruling and statebuilding. Recall from the section on Spinoza, first, the significance of epistemology in political theory. Second, the fact that domestic strife is a signal of bad leadership and badly functioning institutions. In this section I have developed both points. So, we are in a good position to understand three Humean lessons: first, when possible guided and constrained by reason and equity, a politician must be able to generate, or facilitate, opinions and habits of thought that allow citizens to maintain commitment to some unity. Second, while a politician should draw on the best available science, there are going to be occasions where she has to act under conditions of genuine uncertainty and while there are maxims that can be followed, there are (absent world government), by necessity, circumstances when she is in uncharted waters. Third, even the smartest rulers run the risk of expert over-confidence. The points developed here link up to my scholarly work on the role of uncertainty and expert overconfidence, and I say a bit more about them before long. But first I want to draw out one more feature from the Spinozistic and Humean reflection on De Witt’s Fall. 8 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com 4. Hume’s neo Spinozism In this section, I complete my Humean-Spinozist analysis of De Witt’s fall by claiming that we have to reflect on exceptional exemplars of success and failure in order to grasp the art of ruling. According to Hume, De Witt's failure of scientific imagination is exacerbated by the fact that “by a continued and successful application to commerce, the [Dutch] were become unwarlike, and confided entirely for their defence in that mercenary army, which they maintained.” xliii Here Hume echoes Machiavelli's injunction against reliance on mercenaries.xliv But the more fundamental problem that Hume diagnoses, and this brings him unexpectedly close to, and deepens, Spinoza's analysis, is that the Dutch were not a true unity and so, because of lack of mutual trust had fired the experienced officer corps of the Dutch army thought to be too loyal to the Orangist faction. In addition, while De Witt had been careful to prevent corruption in naval affairs, he had allowed a form of crony-ism seep into military affairs. Hume implies that better political leadership by De Witt could have saved the Dutch.xlv So, while Hume recognizes the limits of a political science that treats the world as populated with rational agents acting in their own best interests, he thinks there is a true art of ruling.xlvi In part, Hume signs up to Spinoza’s approach, that is, to develop democratic institutions that promote epistemic resources. Hume has a lot to say about institutional design; but it seems he also thought – echoing Spinoza (and Machiavelli) -- that one could teach the art of ruling by historical reflection on examples of success and failure. Thus, Hume combines the modern social scientific focus on institutional design and incentives with ongoing reflection on positive and negative exemplars of political rule. My historical case study has aimed at presenting the following six points: first, the significance of epistemology in political theory. Second, the fact that domestic strife is a signal of bad leadership and badly functioning institutions. 9 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Third, guided and partially constrained by justice, a politician must be able to generate, or facilitate, opinions and habits of thought that allow individual citizens to maintain commitment to minimal unity. Fourth, while a politician should draw on the best available science, she has to act under conditions of genuine uncertainty. Fifth, expert over-confidence is always a danger. Sixth, we have to reflect on exceptional exemplars of success and failure in order to learn the art of ruling. Before I close with my own research agenda in light of these six points, I make a brief detour. 5. A brief interlude: Huygens and Hudde About two decades ago, the philosopher-engineer Professor George E Smith, my teacher at Tufts, enlisted me in a translation project and scholarly research on a key episode in the history of physics that involved two issues: the great debate between Huygens and Newton over universal gravity and the search for longitude with Huygens’s pendulum clocks which was arguably the most important technological issue for a country dependent on commerce by sea. The two episodes are linked because Huygens appealed to the evidence provided by his clocks on Thomas Helder’s expedition to the Cape of Good Hope aboard the VOC ship, Alcmaer, to argue against Newton and for his own theory of gravity.xlvii As it happens the recipient of Huygens’s 1688 report was Johannes Hudde part of the talented generation of Leiden, Cartesian mathematicians; by 1688 Hudde had also invented first-rate firehose-pumps, was the leading director of the VOC, and among Holland’s most powerful politicians—as one of the Mayors of Amsterdam, he basically arranged the means for Stadtholder William III of Orange to invade England. (Amsterdam remembers him with a small street near the Amstel-hotel.) He also had maintained a secretive correspondence with Spinoza over God’s nature and existence.xlviii 10 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Hudde was thus in an excellent position to support and evaluate Huygens’s efforts to build a working pendulum clock that could find longitude at sea. In my original paper with Smith, we note that in his 1688 report Huygens’ recommends to the Directors of the Dutch East India Company that major efforts be undertaken to determine longitudes for numerous locations.xlix The VOC never followed up on this big-science-grant proposal. By contrast, the French were already engaged in such a project. After Huygens died in 1695 the Hudde-led VOC basically dropped further research into using clocks to find longitude. This despite the fact that Huygens had built up a twenty year technological lead over any competition. Next time you hear a Dutch politician extoll the ‘VOC mentality,’ you may wish to remind him not just of the immoral activities of the Company and its monopolistic rent-seeking, but also insist that Dutch decline set in, in part, because of Hudde’s failure to develop and maintain a strategic, scientific infrastructure that would engage in foundational research. The lack of strategic thought exemplifies the Cartesian a-political approach to science which takes politics for granted. I mention this explicitly because the department of political science of the University of Amsterdam was founded in 1947 to cure the Dutch political elite, and I quote the historian, Jan Romein, from its “political naivety and social ignorance.”l 6. Uncertainty and Politics In this section I articulate some of my research plans and some of my core commitments. I treat politics as activity under conditions of uncertainty. By ‘uncertainty’ I mean circumstances in which we have no grounds to assign probabilities to expectations and outcomes; these circumstances occur when we lack access to underlying distributions.li The existence of uncertainty can be an obstacle to scientific consensus. If we have scientific answers, and one can 11 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com assume agreement over ends, then an issue or a problem can be depoliticized and left to experts or technocracy.lii Not all activity in the face of uncertainty is political. Rather than offer you a definition of ‘the political,’ I echo Spinoza and Hume, and I’ll treat politics as the task, when possible guided by science and justice, of generating or facilitating, opinions and habits of thought that allow citizens to maintain commitment to some unity despite the existence of competing values and interests. It follows from this task that it’s not just politicians that engage in the political, but that paradigmatic activities associated with the media, educators, clergy, civic religion, bureaucracy, and parenting also intersect with the political. One controversial consequence of my approach is that I reject the idea that ethics always trumps politics. I do so for two reasons: first, some such unity is a pre-condition for moral lives with others. Second, morality is, in fact, better served if we try to have it do less work for us.liii During the last decade, I have studied the role of uncertainty in mathematical economics and political philosophy since World War II. It turns out that the disciplinary split between both fields was, in part, constituted by efforts at developing decision procedures that could ignore uncertainty and generate consensus for the chosen area of study.liv In political philosophy, this project is associated with the great Liberal programs of Rawls and Habermas. I do not need to remind a Dutch audience that when we leave the clouds of theory and find steady ground in our fertile landfills, we are familiar with our own brands of consensus-searching Liberalism: we call it ‘polderen’ or ‘paars.’ Technologies of consensus production can also be found in mathematical economics, where they are, most notably, associated with Arrow’s elimination of uncertainty from general equilibrium theory and in finance theory where they are associated with the use of mathematical techniques of randomness to assume away uncertainty. An example is the rational asset-pricing formula associated 12 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com with names like Black, Scholes, and Merton. These programs have adherents that continue to add sophisticated bells and whistles. I apologize for using names as short-hand. I note that these are all men; I return to this issue shortly. The prestige of consensus was reinforced, during the last six decades, by Thomas Kuhn’s and Kuhnian views of science – in which science is conceived as an authoritative, de-politicized field with a high degree of consensus and most activity is oriented toward problem-solving which, in turn, ordinarily generates more consensus. This, too, presupposes given ends. Once one accepts these moves one can work with representative agent models in economics and philosophy. Moreover, to reject consensus as a ruling norm could then be characterized as a form of irrationality.lv In his inaugural address, my predecessor, Jos De Beus, in observing these trends in Dutch political life decried the culture of consensus, which favors the privileged and masks an extensive inner 'rot' (his words).lvi The financial crisis since 2007 has re-introduced a more widespread interest into the existence and nature of uncertainty inside and outside of political economy.lvii At the start of the crisis the CFO of Goldman Sachs, which had the most admired risk models, was reported as saying, “We were seeing things that were 25 standard deviation moves, several days in a row.”lviii That is to say, Goldman Sachs really had no clue about underlying distributions—they thought they inhabited a world of probable risk, bit it turned out that it is really uncertain.lix Goldman was not alone in failing to grasp the nature of uncertainty. For example, I have studied the Dutch planning agency; on the day Lehman Brothers filed for bankruptcy, its forecasting model still predicted considerable growth for the Dutch economy the following year.lx In reality the Dutch economy contracted by four percent. We have to learn to treat mathematical models of human behavior as useful policy tools that have costs and benefits associated with them, but that should be mistrusted if they are treated as consensus building devices that are the only 13 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com model of reality. We need a better understanding of the politics presupposed and suppressed by such models; we also need better institutions and practices. I feel fortunate that I have joined a department with Jeffrey Underhill, Daniel Mugge, and Jonathan Zaitlin—all of whom study these issues with great sophistication; I have already been inspired by our tentative collaborations. But I am getting ahead of myself. On my approach, nearly all political problems have been encountered before despite changes in technology, population growth, and conceptual and religious transformations. I offer a modest example: in his original 1688 report to the Dutch east India Company in which Huygens defended his pendulum clock, Huygens noted that the "crew" of the Alcmaer had "taunted" and "laughed at" the researchers with Huygens’s pendulum clock on board the ship. Huygens here echoes the description found in Plato's Republic, Book VI, 488b-d. The way I understand it, for much of the Liberal tradition, roughly from the seventeenth century through the 1930s, uncertainty was associated with disease, death, war, and theological dogmas, which would inflame the passions that, in turn, would generate more political instability and uncertainty. In addition to representative government and freedom of thought, one of the core ideas of the Liberal tradition is to redirect people’s passions to commerce, family, sports, and leisure so that uncertainty could be channeled to less dangerous ends. The role of the (welfare) state, then, is to create institutions that through the rule of law and public health reduce uncertainty. On this approach there is no expectation that uncertainty can be eliminated fully. For it is understood that markets and new technologies create their own species of uncertainty. In fact, given that financial markets allow states to expand the scope of war-making, itself a source of greatest uncertainty, Liberalism does not promise to eliminate uncertainty. That is, I have just sketched the germ of a large research project that can take me through retirement. My new colleague, Marieke de Goede, has written two 14 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com wonderful books that inform my analysis. Marieke has already cured me of my naïve faith in precautionary principles; her work has demonstrated that in the face of great uncertainty precautionary principles will be abused to justify ‘barbaric’ actions by purportedly Liberal states (including the Netherlands): think of Guantanamo Bay, forced rendition, torturous interrogation, treat warrefugees as prisoners, and massive spying on citizens, etc. My big-picture project is informed by two more ‘local’ projects. First, in order to avoid staying trapped in the same series of concepts, I work on the history of political thought because Liberalism cannot be renewed only from within. Here I mention my interest in feminism. For, female and male feminism is a persistent strain of criticism of the Liberal tradition and one of its main sources of renewal.lxi I collaborate with Sandrine Berges to bring the ideas of Sophie de Grouchy to the world, and I collaborate with Marietje van der Schaar on generating interest in the role of women in early analytical philosophy. I am looking forward to develop this line of research with my new colleagues, especially Luara Ferracioli, Annelien de Dijn, and Saskia Bonjour. Second, together with Manja Bomhoff, I have been awarded a grant to study the new Dutch Act on long-term care and its impact, especially, on home care for the elderly. In preparing the grant we have been aided greatly by my new colleagues, Imrat Verhoeven and John Grin. While I remain fond of abstract ideas, I have come to recognize that responsible theorizing also requires engaging with the lived experiences of those not well represented in the seminar room or the corridors of political power and public opinion. 7. Conclusion Today I spoke to you of my conception of politics and its relationship to uncertainty. Along the way, I drew on fine-grained historical detail, the history of political theory and the history of the sciences. I also intimated quite a large 15 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com number of research projects. Some of you may have the suspicion that while I pretend to be a hedgehog focused on uncertainty, I am really a fox who cannot stick to a single line of thought. There is truth to the suspicion, but I want to dispel it. So, I close with my methodological stance and remind you of my core insight. First, in all of my research I am a methodological analytical egalitarian. This is an approach revived by my friends, David Levy and Sandra Peart, two creative economists.lxii That is, I posit motivational homogeneity in order to allow research into the social and institutional causes of observed variety. One consequence of this stance is that an expert cannot assume herself to be outside the system or society she models.lxiii Obviously, not everybody is equal, but people take themselves to be equal when their interests or ways of life are at stake. So, beliefs matter, and ultimately we should not treat the agents of social and political life as thoughtless atoms.lxiv The Levy-Peart stance comes with a norm of responsible speech: one cannot promote policies in which the downside risks of implementation are wholly placed on less powerful others. This norm motivates, for example, my response to those that advocate proxy war in foreign lands. Finally, I promised you my core idea. This idea draws on a strand of thought that is now associated with Hayek. Hayek and I agree that there is no human vantage point from which full knowledge of political affairs is possible, that is, there is fundamental uncertainty. He used that insight to argue against socialist planning and scientific politics in favor of markets. But markets presuppose political and legal institutions and are influenced by surprising technological and scientific developments. Meanwhile the financial crisis has reminded us that markets are also a source of uncertainty and, thereby, generate ongoing need for politics. So, because there is uncertainty, including market uncertainty that can generate massive dislocations and social transformations, there remains a need for politics.lxv That is, by embracing an “epistemic turn” – I owe the term to 16 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Martin Van Hees -- in political philosophy, I thereby embrace the centrality, even primacy of politics. In reading the inaugural lectures of my predecessors, I discovered that, in so doing, I continue the tradition of this Chair. I close with a thought borrowed from Al-Farabi, the Islamic philosopher, who figures in my seminar this week. He notes that democracy is compatible “with the most good and most evil.”lxvi After the experience of the twentieth century, I would not recommend aiming for the most good, but we should minimize the evils. Acknowledgments I would like to follow tradition and use this opportunity to acknowledge publically some of the supererogatory assistance I received during my career. First, I thank the College van Bestuur, the Dean of faculty, and Wouter Van der Brug and his search committee for hiring me and for granting me this honor. I am thrilled by the welcome I have received from the department, and I am especially grateful to our Chair, Floris Vermeulen, for easing my transition to the University of Amsterdam and a whole new discipline. Second, I single out some of my teachers. At the Vossius, Anneke Luger kept my life on track; I also thank, Rob Brouwer, Jan Stronk, who was the first to suggest I leave town, and the late, wonderful Hans de Klonia. My professors at Tufts continue to be generous; not just George Smith, but also Dan Dennett, Jody Azzouni, and Drussila Brown. In addition, the late Michael Fixler suggested I go to Chicago. There I was mentored by Bill Wimsatt, Howard Stein, Martha Nussbaum, Charles Larmore, and the late Ian Mueller. It turns out that my wonderful supervisor, Dan Garber, is right about something: many of the most important mentors are colleagues on the job. Before returning home to Amsterdam, I have worked at five fantastic institutions with wonderful colleagues; I single out for gratitude, Red Watson, Pauline Kleingeld, and Jose Bernadette. 17 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Third, my best scholarly work has been co-authored with some very fine scholars. I cannot list them all, and I have already mentioned George Smith, Spencer Pack, and Sandrine Berges; here I note, especially, Chris Smeenk, Merel Lefevere, Rogier de Langhe, and my new colleagues, Brian Burgoon, Marieke de Goede, and Marlies Glasius. In addition Mary Domski and Ryan Hanley have, as editors, published very fine papers under my name. Fourth, my understanding of what philosophy could be was transformed by my co-bloggers at NewAPPS. They taught me that excellence and relevance can be mutually supporting. Bij Nader Inzien has made a strong start, and I look forward to our joint development. Fifth, I thank my fantastic PhD students, Marij, Johan, Barnaby, Jo, Laura, Sylvia, Stijn, and Lea. They put up with a lot of (I use a technical term) meshuggas, while I get to learn from them. Sixth, David Levy and M.A. Khan, started out as ‘informants’ about contemporary economics, but they have become exemplars of academic integrity and intellectual fraternity. Seventh, I thank my parents and sister for unstinting encouragement and support. Finally, Avi and Sarit for teaching me love and happiness I never expected. Dixi, Ik heb gezegd. Eric Schliesser, February 5, 20161 i Jeff McMahan "Syria is a Modern Holocaust," The Washington Post. https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/in-theory/wp/2015/11/30/syria-is-a-modern-day-holocaust-we-must-act/ ii http://digressionsnimpressions.typepad.com/digressionsimpressions/2015/12/when-an-ethicists-calls-forproxy-war.html iii Spinoza broadly agreed with Hobbes’ account of the state of nature, but improved upon it by insisting in his Theological Political Treatise (1670) that the state of nature was always a real possibility. Spinoza’s position was vindicated by the barbarism at the Gevangenispoort. iv Dee Michael Della Rocca (2008) Spinoza, London: Routledge, 27. Rowen 1978?, who is quite skeptical of most tales surrounding Spinoza’s and De Witt’s relationship, allows that this story “has the stamp of truth” (because young Leibniz is ultimate source). For a searching exploration of the episode see Stan Verdult http://spinoza.blogse.nl/log/de-leuze-ultimi-barbarorum-is-een-van-de-werken-van-spinoza-zijn-kortste.html 1 I thank Anneke Luger, Luara Ferracioli, David Teira, and, especially, Rene Brouwer, for very useful comments on an earlier draft. 18 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Even a century later Adam Smith insisted that “Dutch” and “trustworthy” were near synonyms and thought it the height of civilization. By ‘civilization’ Smith and his contemporaries meant ‘governed by the rule of law.’ vi Gilles Deleuze (1988) Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. Translated by R. Hurley, San Francisco: City Light Books, 13. This is not a surprising inference because the Theological Political Treatise, which he published a few years before the massacre, says nice things about the city of Amsterdam and has a broadly anti-clerical orientation. During the 1670s to be anti-clerical often entailed support for the oligarchic regime of De Witt. Rowen op. cit., 391-399, notes, correctly, that De Witt’s own political philosophy is not Spinozistic. He also points out (411) that there is no evidence that Spinoza and De Witt ever met nor that De Witt was interested in Spinoza. vii See Alfonso Vergaray (2014) "Rethinking Uncertainty: Spinoza and Hume on Shaping Uncertain Secular Futures" dissertation defended at Virginia Tech University. See also Bell, J. (2008). Deleuze's Hume: philosophy, culture and the Scottish Enlightenment. Oxford University Press. viii I proceed under the assumption that Liberalism is not seen as a worthy option by four non-trivial groups of fellow citizens: first, a-generation of Jihadists, whom remind all us of our society’s painful failure to offer a compelling, inclusive good to all of our young; second, the populists who insist that they alone know what’s good for the nation and, thereby, deny reasonable disagreement; third, the plutocrats and their technocratic intellectuals who mistrust the electorate and encourage disenfranchisement, expert rule, or lotteries. Fourth, the noble souls who have come to the conclusion that Liberal values only serve the interest of the ruling classes. For the utopian strain, see See Schliesser, E. (2013). “Philosophic prophecy.” in Philosophy and Its History: Aims and Methods in the Study of Early Modern Philosophy, edited by M. Laerke, et. al., Oxford: Oxford University Press. ix Isaac Newton taught himself Cartesian mathematics from this book. x Elements of Linear Curves; Easton, J. B. (1963). Johan de Witt's kinematical constructions of the conics. The Mathematics Teacher, 632-635. xi Hald, A. (2003). A history of probability and statistics and their applications before 1750 (Vol. 501). John Wiley & Sons, 68, xii For an account of Hudde’s contribution, see Pedersen, K. M. (1980). Techniques of the calculus, 1630-1660. From the calculus to set theory, 1630-1910. xiii Ciecka, J. E. (2008). The First Mathematically Correct Life Annuity Valuation Formula. Journal of Legal Economics, 15(1), 59. Hald op. cit., especially pp. 122-142 xiv On De Witt’s life, including his own political philosophy, see the biography of Rowen, H. H. (1978). John de Witt, grand pensionary of Holland, 1625-1672. Princeton University Press. After the transition of power in 1672, Hudde became one of the mayors of Amsterdam and a leading figure in the Dutch East India Company. xv "In every council the secretaries and other officials of this kind, as they have not the right of voting, should be chosen from the commons. But as these, by their long practice of business, are the most conversant with the affairs to be transacted, it often arises that more deference than right is shown to their advice, and that the state of the whole dominion depends chiefly on their guidance: which thing has been fatal to the Dutch." (8.44) The context describes the malfunctioning of aristocracy. xvi See Klever, W. (1993). A new document on De Witt's attitude towards Spinoza. Studia Spinozana: An International and Interdisciplinary Series 9:370-388. Admittedly, De Witt's family background was more patrician than Spinoza would allow, but De Witt's rise to power was indeed a consequence of richer patricians scheming on his behalf. xvii The quoted passage of Political Treatise 8.44 is, thus, an auxiliary to Spinoza’s argument for the epistemic advantages of democracy. (He explicitly notes the lack of a right to vote for the commons.) Steinberg, J. (2010). Benedict Spinoza: Epistemic Democrat. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 145-164. xviii David Hume (1776) “My own Life” http://davidhume.org/texts/mol.html. For my analysis, see Schliesser, E. (2003). The Obituary of a Vain Philosopher. Hume studies, 29(2), 327-362. xix David Hume, The History of England from the Invasion of Julius Caesar to the Revolution in 1688, Foreword by William B. Todd, 6 vols. (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund 1983). Vol. 6, 195-6. http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/793#Hume_0011-06_440 xx “Sir William Temple…This man whom philosophy had taught to despise the world, without rendering him unfit for it, was frank, open, sincere, superior to the little tricks of vulgar politicians: And meeting in de Wit with a man of the same generous and enlarged sentiments, he immediately opened his master’s intentions, and pressed a speedy conclusion.” David Hume, The History of England, op. cit. Vol. 6; 221-220, http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/793#Hume_0011-06_499 xxi I have been unable to find a serious discussion of Hume’s treatment of De Witt’s fall. xxii See Alexander the Great at Treatise 3.3.2.12. xxiii Pack, S. J., & Schliesser, E. (2006). Smith's Humean criticism of Hume's account of the origin of justice. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 44(1), 47-63. xxiv ‘spirit’ v 19 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com Hume’s position is a non-trivial improvement over Hobbes’s approach in which such unity is a natural and even inevitable by-product of the coming into being of the Leviathan. It is natural to think that because Hume is a critic of the social contract tradition, that he rejects all of Hobbes’ account. But at a crucial juncture in his account of the origin of justice, Hume echo one of the more striking moments in Hume when he asserts that justice is the sense that “all the members of the society express to one another, and which induces them to regulate their conduct by certain rules.” (Treatise 3.2.2.10) For, in Leviathan, the commonwealth is, when not founded through conquest, instituted by a covenant “of every man with every man . . . as if every man should say to every man, I Authorise and give up my Right of Governing my selfe, to this Man, or to this Assembly of men,” (II.17). It is this covenant that generates “a real unity.” (See also Hobbes’s De Corpore Politico, 1.6.7. in The Moral and Political Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury: 1750, London, p. 52) In Hobbes this unity is lodged “in one and the same Person.” (To avoid confusion: a Hobbesian person can involve more than one human being.)For both Hobbes and Hume the rules of justice, and thereby political unity, should be understood, or conceptualized, as originating at a particular moment in time when all the potential members of a society say something to all the other members about their wish to be ruled by law. Hume denies, of course, that this is a historical fact. xxvi David Hume, The History of England, op. cit. Vol. 6; 197; http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/793#Hume_001106_443 Throughout his treatment of De Witt, Hume reminds the reader of his strength of mind under duress. xxvii For a very careful treatment see McArthur, Neil. David Hume's Political Theory: Law, Commerce, and the Constitution of Government. University of Toronto Press, 2007. xxviii In Hume, the adherence to rule of law fits a larger, conservative commitment to the value of tradition. But that is not true of Liberalism as such. xxix David Hume, The History of England, op. cit. Vol. 6, 321; http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/793#Hume_001106_502 xxx For more thorough criticism of Israel, see De Dijn, Annelien. 2012. The Politics of Enlightenment: From Peter Gay to Jonathan Israel. The Historical Journal, 55: 785-805. Schliesser, E. (2014). Jonathan Israel, Democratic Enlightenment: Philosophy, Revolution, and Human Rights, 1750-1790. Œconomia. History, Methodology, Philosophy, (4-4), 651-657. In Hume's plan for a perfect commonwealth foreign policy is insulated from democratic control. He lodges it in the "council of state" which includes only three members. xxxi The junta consists of eight members. xxxii Livy, Ab Urbe Condita, iii. 26–29 translated by John Henry Freese, Alfred John Church, and William Jackson Brodribb http://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/10828/pg10828-images.html. xxxiii One of his improvements over the constitution of the Dutch Republic is the removal of the veto power, "which every province and town has upon the whole body of the DUTCH republic, with regard to alliances, peace and war, and the imposition of taxes, is here removed." http://www.econlib.org/library/LFBooks/Hume/hmMPL39.html xxxiv He requires the senate's judgment that there is, indeed, a state of emergency. xxxv Another example of emergency power is the European Central Bank, which has been operating very close to the edge of its legal mandate for over half a decade now. xxxvi Hume makes the point by drawing a contrast between vulgar and refined politicians. When Hume describes the meeting of Temple and De Witt, he writes about Temple that “This man, whom philosophy had taught to despise the world, without rendering him unfit for it, was frank, open, sincere, superior to the little tricks of vulgar politicians.” Temple has contempt for the “vulgar politician.” The implied contrast here is with his attitude toward the refined politician. Hume agrees with Temple’s criticism of the ‘vulgar politician.’ For according to Hume, the vulgar politicians “are apt... to have recourse to more hasty and more dangerous remedies.” David Hume, The History of England, op. cit. Vol. 6, 322; http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/793#Hume_0011-06_702. xxxvii Hume reports Temple as claiming” (correctly) that “to remove things from their center, or proper element, required force and labour; but that of themselves they easily returned to it.” That is, Temple’s position presupposes knowledge of social causes (i.e., knowledge of what is 'natural' or 'proper' in social life.) xxxviii See Hume “That Politics May be Reduced to a Science.” xxxix Though de Wit’s intelligence in foreign courts was not equal to the vigilance of his domestic administration, he had, long before, received many surmises of this fatal confederacy; but he prepared not for defence, so early or with such industry, as the danger required. A union of England with France was evidently, he saw, destructive to the interests of the former kingdom; and therefore, overlooking or ignorant of the humours and secret views of Charles, he concluded it impossible, that such pernicious projects could ever really be carried into execution. Secure in this fallacious reasoning, he allowed the republic to remain too long in that defenceless situation, into which many concurring accidents had conspired to throw her. David Hume, The History of England, op. cit. Vol. 6, 257-8; http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/793#Hume_0011-06_576 xl Hume is aware that De Witt had political reasons for allowing the army to be weakened (see below). xxv 20 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com This is not the place to articulate Hume’s positive views of the role of the emotions in foreign affairs; but he is quite clear that these are governed not only by rational considerations. Here’s a nice example of Hume’s criticism of British foreign policy: “In the first place, we seem to have been more possessed with the ancient GREEK spirit of jealous emulation, than actuated by the prudent views of modern politics…Here then we see, that above half of our wars with FRANCE, and all our public debts, are owing more to our own imprudent vehemence, than to the ambition of our neighbours.” (“Of the Balance of Power.”) Rotwein is still an indispensable guide to the role of passions in Hume’s account of social life. See his lengthy introduction to Hume, David. "Writings on Economics, edited and introduction by Eugene Rotwein." (1955): Madison: University of Wisconsin Press xlii AT VI 22/CSM I 122. One might have thought that Cartesians would be well placed to have knowledge of human nature. Descartes’s Passions of the Soul is a careful analysis of causes of human affairs. xliii While it is unclear if De Witt should have allowed the Orangist army to remain a mortal threat to his regime, it is pretty clear that Hume thinks that military affairs should be closely guarded against corruption. “these new officers, relying on the credit of their friends and family, neglected their military duty; and some of them, it is said, were even allowed to serve by deputies, to whom they assigned a small part of their pay.” David Hume, The History of England, Vol. 6, 258; http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/793#Hume_0011-06_577 xliv And taken out of context, one might also assume that Hume agrees with those Republican authors of his day that declaimed against the vices of luxury and commerce (for Hume's considered views, see "Of Commerce" and "Of Refinement in the Arts.") For excellent discussion, see Hont, I. (2005). Jealousy of trade: international competition and the nation-state in historical perspective. Harvard University Press. xlv Hume here deviates from Spinoza's (briefer) analysis which explicitly treats De Witt's power, and subsequent fall, as evidence for the bad institutional design of the Dutch (oligarchic) aristocracy of his age. (Hume is not against such explanations, as his treatment of the natural experiment involving Genoa very nicely exhibits in his essay, "That Politics May be Reduced to a Science.") xlvi This is not the place to explore Hume’s account of political rule. See José A. Benardete (2013). Greatness of Soul in Hume, Aristotle, and Hobbes as Shadowed by Milton's Satan. Cambridge Scholars Publishing. xlvii Newton’s Principia appeared during this period. xlviii Klever, W. N. A. (1997). Mannen rond Spinoza, 1650-1700: presentatie van een emanciperende generatie. Uitgeverij Verloren. xlix "And although these errors will be improved upon before long through the use of the clocks, it would still be very helpful if one investigated the true longitude at some important places with regard to the Meridian of Texel or Amsterdam, by observing the satelites of Jupiter, of which there was mention before." Translated by G.E. Smith & Eric Schliesser see Huygens, OCCH, Vol. 9, p. 290f. l Philip van Praag & Herman de Liagre Böhl (2015) “Tussen Wetenschap en Engagement: De Roerige Geschiedenis van de Amsterdamse Politicologie, in Politicologie in Nederland: Van Politisering naar Professionalisering, red. Rudy B. Andeweg & Barbara Vis. Oudewater: NKWP, o. 20 li The Locus Classicus is Knight, F. H. (1921) Risk, uncertainty and profit. Boston: Houghton Mifflin; see also Keynes, J. M. (1921). A treatise on probability. London: Macmillan. In economics, conditions of uncertainty are operationalized if no long-run profitable insurance is possible; see Malinvaud, Edmond. "The allocation of individual risks in large markets." Journal of economic theory 4.2 (1972): 312-328. lii Harman, Graham. "Bruno Latour: Reassembling the Political." (2014). liii Both claims require further defense. I have discussed the first claim, en passant, in two papers: Schliesser, Eric. "Articulating practices as reasons." Adam Smith Review 2 (2006): 69-97 & Schliesser, E. (2013). “Philosophic prophecy.” Op. cit. liv Eric Schliesser "The Separation of Economics from Virtue: a Historical Conceptual Introduction," in Baker, J. A., & White, M. D. (Eds.). (2015). Economics and the Virtues: Building a New Moral Foundation. Oxford University Press. lv For an example see G.J. Stigler lvi jos de bos (2001) "Een primaat van politiek" Vossiuspers, Amsterdam, p. 8. lvii Here’s some evidence for it. Knight, F. H. (1921) Risk, uncertainty and profit. New York: [publisher]. In December 2015 it had amassed 22224 citations according to scholar.google of which 8993 since 2010 and circa 12500 since 2007. That is to say, since the financial crisis broke it amassed more citations than in the first eighty-five years since it was published. Presumably many of the new citations are totemic. Scholar.google numbers should be treated with caution, but they give good evidence of the size of the effect that I am describing. lviii David Viniar in The Financial Times On 13 August 2007. lix It is very misleading to conceive of such occurrences as fat tails. lx Schliesser, Eric. "Four Species of Reflexivity and History of Economics in Economic Policy Science*." Journal of the Philosophy of History 5.3 (2011): 425-445. xli 21 Politics, Barbarism, and Uncertainty. Draft 4. Do not quote w/o permission. Nescio2@yahoo.com lxi I have started researching and teaching two traditions of thought that are not intrinsically Liberal, but also not anti-Liberal as such: nineteenth century Zionism and medieval Islamic political thought. Nineteenth-century Zionism was born from a profound diagnosis of the failure of the Liberal project to deliver the promised fruits of Jewish Emancipation. Second, the golden age of Islamic political theory was developed in the context of multiethnic empires in which there were competing sources of intellectual authority: revelation, law, tradition, and science; the tradition is also essential background to Thomist and Spinozist philosophy. As the Argentinian story-teller, Borges, reminds us, this tradition is a living present in ‘Western’ thought long before some of our young turned to Jihad.A few years ago I was giving a lecture on Spinoza at the Rotary club in Zeist. During Q&A I was asked why the Islamic world had not developed its own Spinoza. Before I answered that Spinoza was deeply indebted to Islamic thought, I asked the audience to indulge me in a personal question to them. How many of them had parents or grandparents with roots in the Dutch-Indies. To my amazement about two-thirds of the hands went up; I then asked how many knew anything about the brand of Islam practiced there. All the hands stayed down. After that evening, I reflected on my Bildung. I had read Multatuli, Nijhoff, Du Perron, Van Dis, etc. But I was basically as ignorant as my audience about the history of Dutch experience with Islam. lxii Levy, D. M., & Peart, S. (2008). The street porter and the philosopher: conversations on analytical egalitarianism. University of Michigan Press. Levy, D. M., & Peart, S. J. (2008). Thinking about analytical egalitarianism. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 67(3), 473-479. lxiii Cf. How for Rawls, “the moral theorist” can be thought of “as an observer, so to speak, who seeks to set out the structure of other people’s moral conceptions and attitudes…We may also include ourselves, since we are ready to hand for detailed self-examination. But in studying oneself, one must separate one’s role as a moral theorist from one’s role as someone who has a particular conception.” Rawls, John. "The independence of moral theory." Proceedings and addresses of the American philosophical association. Vol. 48. American Philosophical Association, 1974: 7. lxiv That is, models of social reality should not be purely extensional, but have to be intentional (with all the concerns about opacity, lack of substitution, etc.). lxv Markets, technology, and science all generate social transformations of the sort discussed and modelled by L.A. Paul in individuals. Paul, L. A. (2014). Transformative experience. Oxford University Press. lxvi Al-Farabi Political Regime, in The Political Writings, Volume II Cornell University Press (2015) p. 87 (section 115) Obviously, what he means by the institutional structure of ‘democracy’ and what moderns may mean by ‘democracy’ is different. 22