The Idea Theory The Conformal Theory Aristotle • Lived in Greece 384-322 BCE • Student of Plato at the Academy • Taught Alexander the Great • Started his own school, the Lyceum • Towering figure in Western philosophy and Christianity • According to Aristotle, substances are composed of matter + form. Hylomorphism Greek words ‘hule’ (matter) + ‘morphe’ (form) The doctrine is sometimes called Aristotle’s matter-formism. Introduced to understand some issues with identity over time. What’s the Same? What’s Different? Essential vs. Inessential Form Aristotle’s Psychology The soul is the form of the body. Asking whether the soul = the body is like asking whether the bronze statue = its shape. Maybe, maybe not, but it’s not of deep philosophical importance. The Heirarchy of Ensouled Beings Intellectual Soul Perceptual Soul Nutritive Soul The Conformal Theory When an animal perceives a thing, “it is made like it and is such as that thing is” (De Anima ii 5, 418a3–6). Aristotle also holds a similar view, identifying the form of the knower and the thing known. This is an obscure doctrine. Conformal Theory: Literal Interpretation Perceives Conformal Theory: Literal Interpretation Perceives Linguistic Representation Aristotle thought that spoken language was an outward sign of the state of one’s soul. So the (spoken) word ‘house’ was a sign of my soul having the form of a house. Linguistic Representation So we can say that ‘house’ represents houses, because it is a sign of a state of my soul that represents houses (by identity of form with them). Some Problems • [First let students talk.] • If my eyes have the same form as a house when I see a house, how come people looking at my eyes don’t see houses? • If my eyes have the same form as a house when I see a house, and having-the-same-form is representing/ perceiving, then how come the house doesn’t represent/ perceive me. • If I’m looking at your eyes and you’re looking at my eyes, what form do our eyes have? Aquinas and the Conformal Theory • St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274 CE) • Doctor of the Church, Catholic Church’s greatest theologian and philosopher. • Tried to synthesize Aristotle with Christianity. • Tried to elaborate the conformal theory and deal with some of the problems. Aquinas and the Conformal Theory Elaboration of the theory: The house-form was not “really” present in my eyes, it was only “spiritually” present. Spiritually present forms represent really present ones, but not vice versa. Conformal Theory: Aquinas’ Interpretation Spiritual Form Real Form Perceives Does That Solve The Problems? • If my eyes have the same form as a house when I see a house, how come people looking at my eyes don’t see houses? • If my eyes have the same form as a house when I see a house, and having-the-same-form is representing/ perceiving, then how come the house doesn’t represent/ perceive me. • If I’m looking at your eyes and you’re looking at my eyes, what form do our eyes have? New Science, New Problems The 17th Century saw the rise of corpuscularianism. It was a lot like Greek atomism, except whereas atoms are essentially indivisible, corpuscles could theoretically be divided. Notable corpuscularians were… Robert Boyle, 1627-1691 Isaac Newton, 1643-1727 Thomas Hobbes, 1588-1679 John Locke, 1632-1704 John Locke • Father of Classical Liberalism (civil liberties, economic freedom, limited government) • Along with Descartes, most important 17th Century Western philosopher. • Worked in Boyle’s lab. Corpuscularianism The view was that everything is made out of corpuscles– microscopic little bits that had a certain shape, size, and momentum. Corpuscularianism However, the corpuscles did not have color, taste, smell, sound, or warmth. These other qualities were explained as the effects of the corpuscles on our sensory organs. For example, heat is just the motion of corpuscles, but this motion causes us to experience the sensation of warmth. The Unreality of Tastes, Colors, etc. “I think that tastes, odors, colors, and so on are no more than mere names so far as the object in which we place them is concerned, and that they reside only in the consciousness. Hence if the living creature were removed, all these qualities would be wiped away and annihilated” (Galileo, The Assayer). Galileo, The Assayer “I think that tastes, odors, colors, and so on are no more than mere names so far as the object in which we place them is concerned, and that they reside only in the consciousness. Hence if the living creature were removed, all these qualities would be wiped away and annihilated” Problems for the Conformal Theory But if colors, for example, exist only in the mind, then it cannot be true that when I represent a white horse, my soul has the same form as a white horse. There are no white horses. There are horses that cause me to experience whiteness when light bounces off of them. But the whiteness itself depends on me, the observer. Whiteness exists only in minds. The Idea Theory Macbeth, Act I, scene i Is this a dagger which I see before me, The handle toward my hand? Come, let me clutch thee. I have thee not, and yet I see thee still. Art thou not, fatal vision, sensible To feeling as to sight? or art thou but A dagger of the mind, a false creation, Proceeding from the heat-oppressed brain? Hallucinations Normally we talk as though we see physical things, out there in the world. “I see a dagger”– a dagger is obviously not mental. But what do I see when I hallucinate a dagger? Ideas A popular view among 17th and 18th Century Western philosophers was that what you really saw was ideas– mental things. On this view, ideas were something like little colored pictures in the mind. Idea Theory Mind Idea of a Dagger Dagger Hallucination Mind Idea of a Dagger No Dagger Indirect Realism Views of this general form are called “indirect realism.” What you directly see are mental entities (for example, ideas). You only indirectly see the real things that the ideas represent. Indirect realism allows us to maintain that there’s an appearance-gap between what we see (ideas) and the things that the ideas represent. Resemblance Theory According to the resemblance theory of representation, ideas represent things by resembling them– sort of like how painting works. Painting The Nature of Ideas According to Locke, ideas are “the pictures drawn in our minds” (Essay, II.x.5). The Nature of Ideas An idea of a horse, then, is very much like a picture, image, or painting of a horse. Compare Hume: “By ideas I mean the faint images of [perceptions] in thinking and reasoning” (Treatise, I.i.1). Resembles Sees Mind Idea of a Dagger Dagger Resemblance This means that even though what you see are ideas, the ideas are close copies of the real things, the way a realistic painting is a close copy of a scene. Corpuscularianism Revisited So how do we handle the fact that the world isn’t colored? Partly Resembles Sees Mind Idea of a Dog Dog Note This was already really part of the original resemblance theory… nobody thinks your idea of a dog smells like a dog! Terminology Locke called properties like shape, size, and motion– properties that both ideas and real things could have– primary qualities. Other properties that only ideas had were called secondary qualities. Locke on Language “Words are sensible signs, necessary for communication of ideas. Man, though he have great variety of thoughts, and such from which others as well as himself might receive profit and delight…” Locke on Language “yet they are all within his own breast, invisible and hidden from others, nor can of themselves be made to appear…” Locke on Language “The comfort and advantage of society not being to be had without communication of thoughts, it was necessary that man should find out some external sensible signs, whereof those invisible ideas, which his thoughts are made up of, might be made known to others.” Problems #1: Abstract Ideas George Berkeley (1685-1753) Locke on General Terms “It is not enough for the perfection of language, that sounds can be made signs of ideas, unless those signs can be so made use of as to comprehend several particular things…” Locke on General Terms “…for the multiplication of words would have perplexed their use, had every particular thing need of a distinct name to be signified by…” Locke on General Terms “To remedy this inconvenience, language had yet a further improvement in the use of general terms, whereby one word was made to mark a multitude of particular existences.” Particular Terms Locke General Terms Dog Abstract Ideas If we accept the idea theory, then, we have to accept that there are “abstract ideas”– not mental pictures of a particular person, but mental pictures that resemble equally a group of things. These abstract ideas are the meanings of general terms. Berkeley vs. Abstract Ideas Berkeley, however, argues that abstract ideas are impossible. The abstract idea of a man is supposed to apply equally to a tall man and a short man; a black man and a white man; a skinny man and a fat man; well-dressed man and a pauper, etc. But no picture resembles equally all such men, as any picture of a man depicts him as either skinny or fat, but not both and not neither. Problem #2: The Determinacy of Thought Wittgenstein’s Man on the Hill “A picture which corresponds to a man walking up a hill forward corresponds equally, and in the same way, to a man sliding down the hill backward.” -- Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein’s Man on the Hill “Perhaps a Martian would describe the picture [as the man sliding down]. I do not need to explain why we do not describe it so.” Representation can be more determinate than resemblance. Seeing vs. Seeing-as What the Necker cube example suggests is a more general problem. You can look at the Fischer cow and not see that it is a cow. When you see the picture as a cow, your perception changes. But if your idea of the picture is just a copy of that picture in your head, what about it changes such that once it was just squiggles and then it’s a cow? Problem #3: Error Representation and Error On the Idea Theorist’s view, I can only represent a thing if I have a mental image that sufficiently resembles it. But there seem to be lots of things that we can think about, while being massively in error about. Advertisements vs. Reality Problem #4: The Structure of Resemblance Equivalence Relations Resemblance as an Equivalence Relation Resemblance, like identity, is an equivalence relation, meaning it’s reflexive, symmetric, and transitive: • Reflexive: for all X, X resembles X. (Everything resembles itself.) • Symmetric: for all X and Y, if X resembles Y, then Y resembles X. • Transitive: for all X, Y, and Z, if X resembles Y and Y resembles Z, then X resembles Z. Problem for the idea theory: resemblance is an equivalence relation, but representation is not. Therefore representation ≠ resemblance. 1. Representation is Not Reflexive You can have a representation that represents itself (for example, a map that includes the map’s location), but most representations don’t represent themselves. You can have a painting of a horse, that is not a painting of a painting of a horse (not a painting of itself). 2. Representation is Not Symmetric Most of what gets represented is not representational. My thoughts represent lakes and rivers and trees, but lakes and rivers and trees don’t represent my thoughts. And even when I do represent representations (when I think about a painting, say), usually they don’t represent me or my thoughts. 3. Representation is not Transitive The directory at the museum might represent the location of a certain Picasso painting. That painting could represent a horse. But the directory doesn’t represent any horses, it only represents paintings. Problem #5: Truth-Evaluability Concepts Concepts are representations of things or qualities: so I can have a concept of Obama, or a concept of red, or a concept of a horse, or a concept of a concept. Importantly, concepts are not truth-evaluable. My concept of red isn’t true, and it isn’t false either. It might be more or less accurate. Propositions We can say that when I think of a thing, or think about a thing, then I am entertaining a concept. However, when I think that such-and-such, I am entertaining a proposition. Propositions For example, I can think that Obama is the US president, or think that grass is red, or think that the concept of a horse is not a concept. Propositions are truth-evaluable: when I think that grass is red, my thought is false. (Not so when I just think of red.) The idea theory seems to have trouble distinguishing concepts and propositions. According to the idea theory, thought is having ideas, and ideas are like mental pictures. Are mental pictures truth-evaluable? If they are, then concepts aren’t ideas. If they aren’t, then propositions aren’t ideas.