THE SOCRATIC PARADOXES THE SOCRATIC PARADOXES In the early dialogues Plato depicts Socrates as claiming not to know anything worthwhile. At the same time Plato portrays Socrates as sympathetic with some counterintuitive theses: 1. No one errs willingly. 2. Virtue is just a kind of knowledge. 3. The virtues are inseparable from one another. 4. Virtue is suf ficient for happiness . Etymologically speaking, something ‘paradoxical’ goes against opinion. Why are these theses paradoxical in this sense? THE STRUCTURE OF PLATO’S PROTAGORAS The Protagoras illustrates major themes of Socratic moral thinking. The following topics are discussed in the following order: 1. Is virtue teachable? 2. Is virtue divisible into distinct, separable parts? Or are all virtues identical with one thing? 3. Is pleasure the good? 4. Do we ever intentionally do what we know to be bad? 5. How do cowardly and courageous individuals dif fer from one another? 6. Is virtue identical with knowledge? 7. Is virtue teachable? THE HEDONIST THESIS The question: Is pleasure the good? By “the good” Socrates does not mean the only good thing. What else is good, on the view Socrates is defending? What might Socrates mean by “pleasure is the good”? THE HEDONIST THESIS The question: Is pleasure the good? By “the good” Socrates does not mean the only good thing. What else is good, on the view Socrates is defending? What might Socrates mean by “pleasure is the good”? Roughly, pleasure is the source of all goodness. Or, perhaps better: pleasure is the criterion of goodness. HEDONISM DEFENDED Bad pleasures and good pains generate doubts about hedonism. Far from making trouble for hedonism, Socrates thinks bad pleasures and good pains actually provide confirmation for the view. What’s his argument? HEDONISM DEFENDED Bad pleasures and good pains generate doubts about hedonism. Far from making trouble for hedonism, Socrates thinks bad pleasures and good pains actually provide confirmation for the view. What’s his argument? In calling some pleasures bad and some pains good, pleasure is our criterion. And we are unable to identify any further criterion at work. SOCRATES, PLATO, AND HEDONISM Plato’s considered viewpoint, explicit in later dialogues, is that hedonism is false. Is the hedonism of the Protagoras something Plato gets from Socrates? Or is it just part of an ad hominem argument against the many? This is a matter of dispute. WEAKNESS Incontinence/Weakness of Will/ Akrasia: S is able to do what S believes to be (all things considered) the best available option, but intentionally does something less good instead. Illustrations? Socrates denies that incontinence is psychologically possible. BETWEEN RECKLESSNESS AND ILLNESS Suppose Todd steals a copy of the Republic from the public library. In everyday thinking we distinguish three ways of thinking about Todd’s act: 1. Reckless Todd. He might ’ve played it safe. But he thought it worth the risk, so he went for it. 2. Weak Todd. His better judgment told him not to do it, but he failed to exert self -control. He went ahead and took the thing. 3. Klepto Todd. He thought it wrong to take it and would have preferred all things considered not to take it, but he couldn’t help himself. His impulse to steal was irresistible . SOCRATES’ THESIS Reckless Todd and Klepto Todd are both doing the less good thing unintentionally. So how do they dif fer? Socrates wants to show that so -called Weak Todd is also acting unintentionally. No one intentionally does less than the best. He challenges the common view that weakness is a distinct category by rejecting the idea that so-called Weak Todd has a correct judgment about what is best. Weak Todd is really no dif ferent from Reckless Todd. SOCRATES’ ARGUMENT We have no good explanation of why anyone would act incontinently. The explanation of the many: S does less than the best because S is overcome by pleasure. But: pleasure = the good. So the many are saying: S does less than the best because S is overcome by goodness. Consider two options: Action A amount of goodness: 10 Action B 4 Why would anyone, knowing the difference in value, choose B over A? Clearly its goodness cannot account for the choice of B! Perhaps the goodness of A could explain the choice of A over B, but it cannot account for the choice of B over A . A FURTHER CONSIDERATION Plausible assumptions about human nature seem to rule out the possibility of incontinence. Suppose S is choosing between X and Y. A . If S believes it would be better all things considered to do X than Y, then S wants to do X more than Y. (358d) B. If S wants to do X more than Y, then S will choose to do X rather than Y. THE PROBLEM RESTATED Our folk-psychological reason explanations account for actions by showing how they make sense from the subject ’s point of view: the agent has reason to perform the action, given her desires and her beliefs about the world. (next slide) In cases of weakness it seems that the agent is not doing what makes sense from her own point of view—she is not doing what she has reason to do. The upshot is that our folk -psychological framework for explaining behavior is unable to make such behavior intelligible. REASON EXPLANATIONS (ILLUSTRATION) Why did Bob go to the refrigerator and take out a beer? A reason explanation might take the following form: While watching football, Bob came to desire a beer. Bob believed that the best available means to acquiring a beer was to go to the refrigerator and take out a beer. CONCLUSION/ACTION: Bob went to the refrigerator and took out a beer. Note that reason explanations presuppose that agents are able to reason. They are able to infer a course of action from premises/assumptions. TOPIC FOR DISCUSSION Is Socrates underestimating our folk psychology? Does commonsense have the resources to make weakness of will intelligible? SELF-CONTROL Suppose S judges action A to be better than B. At the same time doing A will be harder and require discipline or self control. Perhaps S might fail to do A either because (i) S lacks the selfcontrol required or because (ii) S has the self -control required but chooses not to exert self -control. Do these seem like promising ways of making sense of weakness within our folk -psychological framework? How might Socrates best respond? SELF-CONTROL (i) S lacks the self-control required or (ii) S has the self -control required but chooses not to exert self-control. Socrates would reject both of these ways of making sense of weakness: (i) If S does not have the self -control abilities required, then S is unable to do otherwise. But weakness requires the ability to do otherwise. (ii) We still have no good explanation of why someone would choose what they judge to be worse. Talk of “self-control” suggests that the self is tempted by something judged to be less good. But if you judge it to be less good, don’t you want it less? So why would you be tempted? APPARENT INCONTINENCE Socrates does not deny that people sometimes seem to act weakly. So what is actually going on in such cases? His answer: ignorance. He realizes this answer is opaque. We will work up to it in stages. TWO CLAIMS DISTINGUISHED In his statement of what the many think at 352e, Socrates defines weakness as failure to what is best even though one knows what is best and is able to do it. Distinguish the following two claims. K. Knowledge incontinence is psychologically impossible: no one ever acts contrary to what one knows to be the best option. B. Belief incontinence is psychologically impossible: no one ever acts contrary to what one believes to be the best option. Is Socrates committed only to K and not B? Not likely. It is widely agreed that Socrates is committed to B as well as K. His endorsement of B comes out in claims like: “No one errs willingly.” (358d) Why does this passage suggest that Socrates accepts B as well as K? “NO ONE ERRS WILLINGLY” Restated, Socrates is saying: no one willingly or intentionally chooses the less good option (errs). This is a general point about intentional behavior, whether it is guided by knowledge or belief. No one intentionally does what they know or believe to be less good. FURTHER REFINEMENTS B. Belief incontinence is psychologically impossible: no one ever acts contrary to what one believes to be the best available option. Socrates’ understanding of B is subtle. He accepts both of the following: Synchronic belief incontinence IS NOT psychologically possible: no one ever acts contrary to what one, at the moment of action, believes to be best. Diachronic belief incontinence IS psychologically possible: sometimes one acts contrary to one’s belief about what is best because belief is unstable. THE INSTABILIT Y OF BELIEF “To acquire an untied work of Daedalus is not worth much, like acquiring a runaway slave, for it does not remain, but it is worth much if tied down, for his works are very beautiful. What am I thinking of when I say this? True opinions. For true opinions, as long as they remain, are a fine thing and all they do is good, but they are not willing to remain long, and they escape from a man’s mind, so that they are not worth much until one ties them down by giving an account of the reason why… After they are tied down, in the first place they become knowledge, and they remain in place. That is why knowledge is prized higher than correct opinion, and knowledge dif fers from correct opinion in being tied down .” (Meno 97e-98a) THE STABILIT Y OF KNOWLEDGE Because knowing what is best involves grasping why it is best, one who knows will not be deceived, e.g., by temporal illusions . Diachronic knowledge incontinence is psychologically impossible: no one ever acts contrary to what one knows to be the best available option. The science of measurement ensures that the knower will not be duped by temporary changes in perspective. We are now able to grasp the sense in which so -called weak acts are due to ignorance: they are due to lack of knowledge about what is best. VALUE ILLUSIONS? Can you think of any examples of value illusions (temporal or otherwise)? How might a science of measurement help to avoid error in these cases? VALUE ILLUSION IN NATURE There is some (less than decisive) evidence that male fiddler crabs (Uca mjoebergi) exploit susceptibility to size illusion when displaying for females. WHERE WE ARE NOW Protagoras 351b-362a (summary) 1. Is pleasure the good? 2. Do we ever intentionally do what we know to be bad? 3. How do cowardly and courageous individuals dif fer from one another? 4. Is virtue identical with knowledge? 5. Is virtue teachable? WHAT’S WRONG WITH THE COWARD? From the point of view of the many, the coward has a problem with fear. What’s the problem, exactly? COWARDICE & FEAR From the point of view of the many, cowards can miss the mark principally in two ways: 1. The coward can go wrong by fearing things more than he should. E.g., he might be overly concerned about personal comfort or avoiding injury. 2. Even when the coward recognizes what the correct response to the circumstances is, he can go wrong by allowing himself to be driven by fear, thus failing to exert self -control. COURAGE AS WISE ENDURANCE From these points we might infer: Courage = d f In the face of future evils, ( i) knowing which among available options are genuinely worse (more to be feared) and to what extent, and (ii) having the will to act in accord with that knowledge. Note that this is likely what Laches has in mind when he defines courage as wise endurance. ILLUSTRATION Take the soldier who courageously sticks to his post even though his safety is threatened. The soldier knows that in the circumstances at hand it is worse to flee one’s post. It is worse, say, because of how shameful fleeing in those circumstances is. And because it is worse, fleeing is actually more to be feared! The soldier not only knows what the right thing to do is; he has the will to endure in the face of fears concerning his own safety. Does this account adequately capture our commonsense notion of courage, or do we need to add that the courageous person will not need to exert significant ef fort towards self control? (Some regard straining to do the right thing in the face of fears as a sign of cowardice .) SOCRATES ON COURAGE Part (ii) of the definition above seems to be an important addition because we think it is possible that someone might know what is right but fail to do it because he fails to exert self control (or because he failed to develop normal capacities of self-control). Since Socrates denies that it makes sense to speak of self control in this context, he will want to modify the account of courage above. What account will Socrates prefer? SOCRATES ON COURAGE Courage = d f In the face of future evils, knowing which among available options are genuinely worse (more to be feared) and to what extent. FEAR VS KNOWLEDGE Socrates: knowledge is in control. The many respond: virtue requires more than knowledge because fear is a powerful force. 1. Pathological fear. One has fear without an expectation of future evil. (E.g. upon seeing a harmless pet mouse.) 2. Exaggerated fear. One’s degree of fear is not proportional to one’s judgment about the potential for harm. The danger is real but admittedly not so bad. (E.g. in fearing public speaking, one’s fear of embarrassment might be out of step with one’s judgment about how bad embarrassment really is.) 3. Foolish fear. One’s fear is entirely a product of a mistaken judgment about potential danger —mistaken either in whether there is something to be feared or in how serious the threat is. (E.g. someone falsely judges that to embarrass oneself really is the worst thing that can happen .) WHAT WOULD SOCRATES SAY? 1. Pathological fear. One has fear without an expectation of future evil. 2. Exaggerated fear. One’s degree of fear is not proportional to one's judgment about the potential for harm. The danger is real but admittedly not so bad. 3. Foolish fear. One’s fear is entirely a product of a mistaken judgment about potential danger —mistaken either in whether there is something to be feared or in how serious the threat is. Given Socrates’ definition of courage, the courageous person will not have foolish fear. How might he address the possibility of being overcome by pathological or exaggerated fear? WHAT WOULD SOCRATES SAY? 1. Pathological fear. One has fear without an expectation of future evil. 2. Exaggerated fear. One’s degree of fear is not proportional to one's judgment about the potential for harm. The danger is real but admittedly not so bad. How might Socrates address the possibility that one might be overcome by pathological or exaggerated fear ? Socrates: Fear = d f Expectation of future evil (Protagoras 358d) How does this definition rule out the possibility of pathological & exaggerated fear? WHAT WOULD SOCRATES SAY? 1. Pathological fear. One has fear without an expectation of future evil. 2. Exaggerated fear. One’s degree of fear is not proportional to one's judgment about the potential for harm. The danger is real but admittedly not so bad. Socrates: Fear = d f Expectation of future evil (Protagoras 358d, Laches 198b) Fear cannot come apart from one’s expectations/judgments about future evil. The extent to which S fears E is just a function of how bad (& how likely) S judges E to be . So pathological & exaggerated fear are not possible! FEAR AS EXPECTATION OF FUTURE EVIL Any worries about Socrates ’ definition of fear? SOCRATES UNDER ATTACK In the Laches the following view of courage is attributed to Socrates: Courage = d f knowledge of what is and is not to be feared. Let’s call this the Socrates-Nicias account of courage. Socrates and Nicias entertain three objections to this account. We will consider each in turn. LACHES’ OBJECTION Doesn’t the Socrates-Nicias account of courage have the consequence that the courageous will be those who can predict future events, say, prophets or scientists? Why does this objection miss the mark? LACHES’ OBJECTION Doesn’t the Socrates-Nicias account of courage have the consequence that the courageous will be those who can predict future events, say, prophets or scientists? Why does this objection miss the mark? Nicias wants us to draw a distinction between two kinds of knowledge: 1. Knowledge of what states of af fairs will occur. 2. Knowledge of what states of af fairs are good/bad. An expert can be better at predicting what will occur without knowing the value of those outcomes. The courageous person knows about value. A LINGERING WORRY Won’t the courageous person need to know more than just how to rank various outcomes in terms of value? Won ’t the courageous person know how to bring about the best outcomes? And this is more than just knowledge of good & evil. SOCRATES’ FIRST OBJECTION Aren’t wild beasts sometimes courageous ? The Socrates-Nicias account of courage seems to be too narrow in failing to accommodate courage in wild beasts. Why does the Socrates-Nicias account seem ill -suited to include such cases of courage? How does Nicias respond to this objection? SOCRATES’ FIRST OBJECTION Aren’t wild beasts sometimes courageous ? The Socrates-Nicias account of courage seems to be too narrow in failing to accommodate courage in wild beasts. Why does the Socrates-Nicias account seem ill -suited to include such cases of courage? How does Nicias respond to this objection? Nicias wants us to draw the following distinction: 1. Animals, children, and foolish adults can be rash (or even mad). 2. Only the one who knows what is & isn ’t to be feared is courageous. A LINGERING WORRY Are Socrates & Nicias “over -intellectualizing” what it is to be courageous? Perhaps being courageous is more about being conditioned/trained in ways that produces certain habits. Perhaps our behavior is more continuous with animals than Socrates & Nicias are acknowledging. SOCRATES’ SECOND OBJECTION Socrates’ second objection is a reductio ad absurdum argument. What’s that? REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM Illustration: 1 . Sam stole the goat. 2. If Sam stole the goat, Sam’s shoes are muddy. 3. Sam’s shoes are muddy. (by modus ponens) 4. Sam’s shoes are not muddy. 5. Sam didn’t steal the goat. P (target of the reductio) P→Q Q (by modus ponens: next slide) -Q -P MODUS PONENS P→Q P Q SOCRATES’ SECOND OBJECTION (A REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM) 1. Courage is the science (knowledge) of what ought to be an object of fear & what ought not. 2. Fear = expectation of future evil. Hence, 3. Courage is the science of future evils and non-evils (goods). 4. The same science has understanding of the same things, whether future, present, or past. E.g., mineralogy, the study of properties of minerals, articulates laws that are context sensitive but not time-indexed. Accordingly, 5. Courage is the science of all goods & evils. So, 6. Courage is the whole of virtue. But, 7. Courage is just one part of virtue. Hence, 8. Courage is not knowledge of what is & isn’t to be feared. RESPONSE TO SOCRATES’ SECOND OBJECTION How does Socrates in the Protagoras implicitly respond to his objection in the Laches? THE UNIT Y OF VIRTUE Protagoras endorses the commonsense idea that one might be courageous and yet lack other virtues like wisdom. Socrates has shown that courage just is knowledge of good and evil, so one cannot be courageous without being wise . Is Protagoras’ view really our commonsense view ? Isn’t the courageous person someone who is dependable in matters of danger? Someone who is unjust, intemperate, and unwise does not seem to be the sort of person we can count on to do the right thing in dangerous contexts . Presumably a courageous person must be sensitive to the demands of justice; someone who lacked such sensitivity might be better labeled as rash. VIRTUE AS TEACHABLE How does Socrates’ thesis that the virtues are identical with one thing relate to the overarching question in the Protagoras of whether virtue is teachable? VIRTUE AS TEACHABLE How does Socrates’ thesis that the virtues are identical with one thing relate to the overarching question in the Protagoras of whether virtue is teachable ? If virtue amounts to knowledge of good & evil, presumably it is teachable! THE SOCRATIC PARADOXES 1. 2. 3. 4. No one errs willingly. Virtue is just a kind of knowledge. The virtues are inseparable from one another. Virtue is suf ficient for happiness. We have already discussed 1 , 2, & 3. Why think Socrates is committed to 4? APOLOGY 30CD “Neither Meletus nor Anytus can harm me in any way; he could not harm me, for I do not think it is permitted that a better man be harmed by a worse; certainly he might kill me, or perhaps banish or disfranchise me, which he and maybe others think to be great harm, but I do not think so . I think he is doing himself much greater harm doing what he is doing now, attempting to have a man executed unjustly.” What assumptions about harm might Socrates be making here? A PLAUSIBLE SUGGESTION 1. If S is virtuous, then S is happy. 2. Something is a harm to S only if it adversely af fects S ’s happiness. Hence, 3. The only way to harm a virtuous person is to deprive that person of her virtue. Otherwise, she will continue to be happy and so will not be harmed. But, 4. Killing, banishing, disenfranchising will not remove S ’s virtue. Hence, 5. Killing, banishing, disenfranchising will not harm S. GORGIAS 473A “Doing injustice is worse than suf fering it.” How might this thesis presuppose the idea that virtue is all you need for happiness? GORGIAS 473A “Doing injustice is worse than suf fering it. ” How might this thesis presuppose the idea that virtue is all you need for happiness? Doing injustice makes you an unjust person. Being unjust prevents you from a sure path to happiness (provided being virtuous is suf ficient for happiness). Meanwhile, suf fering injustice needn ’t have any impact on your well-being (if being virtuous is suf ficient for happiness). A LINGERING WORRY Socrates does not of fer a working theory of what human happiness/well-being consists in. Until this issue is settled, it is hard to see how we can determine whether having a certain character is by itself enough to yield happiness. In the early dialogues we do not find Socrates arguing for the claim that virtue is suf ficient for happiness. In the Republic we finally get an argument, though it is for the comparative claim that the virtuous person is happier than the vicious one.