complete issue - Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy

advertisement

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

R

UTGERS

J

OURNAL OF

L

AW

&

P

UBLIC

P

OLICY

V OLUME 9

Symposium Editor

A MANDA B OWERS

S PRING 2012

Editor-in-Chief

A NDREW D ODEMAIDE

Executive Editors

S HAWN E DWARDS

A USTIN E DWARDS

Managing Technology

Editor

M ICHAEL S CARDUZIO

I SSUE 3

Business Editor

W ALI R USHDAN

Managing Articles

Editors

J ULIE T ERSIGNI

J USTIN B ERNSTEIN

Managing Research

Editor

D IAA M USLEH

Managing Notes

Editors

E LENA F IKARIS

S AMUEL W ALTZER

Submissions Editors Managing Blog Editor

J OCELYN Y OUNG

N ATHAN E CHOLS

S TEPHEN T UCKER

Articles Editors

J

M

A VIO

OHN

ARK L

C

D

ROCE

ALVET

AZAROFF

W ILLIAM H ANNA

B RIAN H IGGINS

K ATIE M ANTON

K ELLY D OUGHERTY

A NDREA S CHLAFER

Blog Editors

R ACHEL F EUERHAMMER

M ARISSA H ERMANOVICH

C

C

J

J

HRISTINA

C

M

M

ARED

E

A

P

B

LEX

LLEN

ODENA

ERKOWITZ

C

RIYA

B

C

HARLES

ICHAEL

ICHAEL

M EGAN

AMBURN

D

HRISTINE

ROWN

ARBONE

C

D

D

E

F

HURI

G

ENNEN

ONGDON

ONNINI

DELMAN

ILOON

ARDNER

S AMANTHA G ROSS

Staff Editors

S TEVEN K AISER

C HRISTOPHER K ELLY

M ICHAEL K LAUDER

C ANDACE L ERARIO

K AITLIN M AC K ENZIE

J ENNIFER M ARTIN

S ALVATORE M ARTINO

D AVID M ILLER

M AX M ORGAN

M ARK N ATALE

W ILLIAM N EWELL

Faculty Advisors

P HILIP L.

H ARVEY

Marketing Editor

B RIAN Q UIGLEY

Notes Editors

T ERESA F INNEGAN

A LYSA C ASTRO

R OSS M AZER

S OHANA B AROT

M ARISA M C G ARVEY

E LIZABETH M ELAMED

S ARAH C RANSTON

D AWN N ICHOLSON

J EREMY R EICH

C HARLES R IFICI

E RIC R OSENBERG

N ICK S AVIO

J OSEPH S CHANNE

M ICHAEL S CHWART

K HUSHBOO S HAH

K RISTIAN S TOUT

T ZVI W EISZ

A DAM W ILSON

B EN Z IEMAN

S ARAH E.

R ICKS

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

About the Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy

The Rutgers Journal of Law and Public Policy (ISSN 1934-3736) is published three times per year by students of the Rutgers School of Law –

Camden, located at 217 North Fifth Street, Camden, NJ 08102. The views expressed in the Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy are those of the authors and not necessarily of the Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy or the Rutgers School of Law – Camden.

Form: Citations conform to The Bluebook: A Uniform System of Citation

(19 th ed. 2010). Please cite the Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy as 9

R UTGERS J.L.

& P UB .

P OL ’ Y (2012).

Copyright: All articles copyright © 2012 by the Rutgers Journal of Law &

Public Policy, except where otherwise expressly indicated. For all articles to which it holds copyright, the Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy permits copies to be made for classroom use, provided that (1) the author and the

Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy are identified, (2) the proper notice of copyright is affixed to each copy, (3) each copy is distributed at or below cost, and (4) the Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy is notified of the use.

For reprint permission for purposes other than classroom use, please submit request as specified at http://www.rutgerspolicyjournal.org/.

Manuscripts: The Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy seeks to publish articles making original contributions in the field of public policy. The

Journal accepts both articles and compelling essays for publication that are related to the expansive topic of public policy. Manuscripts must contain an abstract describing the article or essay which will be edited and used for publication on the website and in CD-ROM format. The Journal welcomes submissions from legal scholars, academics, policy makers, practitioners, lawyers, judges and social scientists.

Electronic submissions are encouraged. Submissions by email and attachment should be directed to submissions@rutgerspolicyjournal.org.

Paper or disk submissions should be directed to Rutgers Journal of Law &

Public Policy, Rutgers University School of Law – Camden, 217 North Fifth

Street, Camden, New Jersey 08102.

Subscriptions: Subscription requests should be mailed to Rutgers Journal

of Law & Public Policy, Rutgers University School of Law – Camden, 217

North Fifth Street, Camden, New Jersey 08102, or emailed to info@rutgerspolicyjournal.org.

Internet Address: The Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy website is located at http://www.rutgerspolicyjournal.org.

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

OFFICERS OF THE UNIVERSITY

R ICHARD L.

M C C ORMICK , B.A., Ph.D., President

W ENDELL P RITCHETT , B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Chancellor and Professor

LAW SCHOOL ADMINISTRATION

R AYMAN L.

S OLOMON , B.A., M.A., J.D., Ph.D., Dean and Professor of Law

C AMILLE S PINELLO A NDREWS , B.A., J.D., Associate Dean of Enrollment and Projects

A NGELA V.

B AKER , B.A., J.D., Associate Dean - Students & Career Planning

V ICTORIA C HASE , B.A., J.D., Associate Dean for Academic Affairs

J AYDEV C HOLERA , B.A., M.B.A., Director, Finance and Administration

A NNE V.

D ALESANDRO , A.B., M.L.S., J.D., Director of Law Library

E VE B ISKIND K LOTHEN , B.G.S., J.D., Assistant Dean for Pro Bono and Public Interest Programs

B ARBARA M AYLATH , B.A., Assistant Dean of Development

T HERESA M C C UEN , A.B., Ed.M, , Director of Alumni Relations

J OHN F.

K.

O BERDIEK , B.A., M.A., J.D., Ph.D., Director of Faculty Research

W ENDELL P RITCHETT , B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Chancellor and Professor

E D R ENTEZELAS , B.A., J.D., Assistant Dean

R UTH A NNE R OBBINS , B.A., J.D., Director of Lawyering Programs

S ANDRA S IMKINS , J.D., Chair for Clinical Programs

R EBEKAH V ERONA , B.S., J.D., Director of Career Planning

FACULTY

A ARON A RI A FILALO , A.B., J.D., LL.M.,

Professor of Law

D AVID E.

B ATISTA , A.B., J.D., M.S., Librarian

J OHN S.

B ECKERMAN , A.B., M.A., J.D., Ph.D.,

Visiting Professor

L INDA S.

B OSNIAK , A.B., J.D., M.A.,

Distinguished Professor of Law

H ON .

D ENNIS B RAITHWAITE , B.S., J.D., LL.M.,

Visiting Professor of Law

A.

H AYS B UTLER , B.A., J.D., M.S. (LIS),

Librarian II

M ICHAEL A.

C ARRIER , B.A., J.D., Professor of

Law

F RED C.

C HANDLER , Jr., B.A., LL.B., LL.M.,

Professor of Law Emeritus

E DWARD E.

C HASE , B.A., J.D., Professor of

Law Emeritus

V ICTORIA L.

C HASE , B.A., J.D., Clinical

Associate Professor of Law

R OGER S.

C LARK , B.A., LL.B., LL.M., J.S.D.,

LL.D., Board of Governors Professor

J ASON K.

C OHEN , B.A., J.D., Clinical Associate

Professor of Law

R USSELL M.

C OOMBS , B.A., J.D., Associate

Professor of Law

L UCY C OX , B.A., M.S., Ph.D., M.L.S.,

International and Foreign Law Librarian

P ERRY D ANE , B.A., J.D., Professor of Law

J OHN H.

D AVIES , B.S., LL.B., LL.M., Professor

of Law Emeritus

C HRISTINE D OUGHERTY , B.A., J.D., Visiting

Clinical Assistant Professor of Law

M ARC E DELMAN , B.S., J.D., Visiting Assistant

Professor

J AY M.

F EINMAN , B.A., J.D., Distinguished

Professor of Law

K IMBERLY D.

F ERZAN , B.S., J.D., Professor of

Law

K ATHRYN K OVACS , B.A., J.D., Assistant

B ARBARA A.

K ULZER , Professor of Law

A RTHUR B.

L ABY , B.A., J.D., Professor of Law

F.

G REGORY L ASTOWKA , B.A., J.D., Professor of

A RNO L IIVAK , B.A., M.L.S., J.D., Professor of

H ARRY L ITMAN , A.B., J.D.,Visiting Associate

M ICHAEL A.

L IVINGSTON , A.B., J.D., Professor

J OHN C.

L ORE , III, B.A., J.D., Clinical Professor

J ONATHAN M ALLAMUD , A.B., J.D., Professor of

E ARL M.

M ALTZ , B.A., J.D., Distinguished

A MAN M CLEOD , B.A., J.D., P H .D., Visiting

K IMBERLY M UTCHERSON , B.A., J.D., Associate

A LISON N ISSEN , B.A., J.D., Director, Academic

J OHN F.

K.

O BERDIEK , B.A., M.A., J.D., Ph.D.,

C RAIG N.

O REN , A.B., J.D., Professor of Law

T RACI O VERTON , B.A., J.D., Clinical Staff

D ENNIS M.

P ATTERSON , B.A., M.A., J.D., Ph.D.,

S

D

S

Professor of Law

Emeritus

Law

Law Emeritus

Professor of Law

of Law of Law

Law Emeritus

Professor of Law

Assistant Professor of Law

Professor of Law

Success Program

Professor of Law and Director of Faculty

Research

Attorney

Board of Governors Professor

TANISLAW

Distinguished Professor of Law

EBORAH

Emeritus-in-Residence

ARAH E.

P

R

P OMORSKI

ORITZ

ICKS

,

, LL.B., LL.M., J.S.D.,

B.A., J.D., Visiting Jurist

, B.A., J.D., Clinical Professor

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

D AVID M.

F RANKFORD , B.A., J.D., Professor of

Law

A NN E.

F REEDMAN , B.A., J.D., Associate

Professor of Law

S TEVEN F.

F RIEDELL , B.A., J.D., Professor of

Law

J ILL F RIEDMAN , B.A., J.D., Director of Pro

Bono & Public Interest Programs

S ANDRA G AVIN , B.A., J.D., Visiting Associate

Professor of Law

E RIC G ILSON , B.A., J.D., M.L.I.S., Student

Research and ILL

G EORGE G INSBURGS , Bacchalaureat Serie

Mathematiques, B.A., M.A., Ph.D.,

Distinguished Professor of Law Emeritus

S ALLY F.

G OLDFARB , B.A., J.D., Professor of

Law

E LLEN P.

G OODMAN , A.B., J.D., Professor of

Law

J OANNE G OTTESMAN , B.A., J.D., Clinical

Associate Professor of Law

P HILLIP L.

H ARVEY , B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Professor

of Law

S TACY H AWKINS , B.A., J.D., Visiting Assistant

Professor of Law

N ANCY H AWN , B.S., M.S., Co-Director

Mediation Center

N.E.H.

H ULL , B.A., Ph.D., J.D., Distinguished

Professor of Law

R ICHARD H YLAND , A.B., M.F.A., J.D., D.E.A.,

Distinguished Professor of Law

P AM J ENOFF , B.A., M.A., J.D., Clinical

Assistant Professor of Law

J OHN P.

J OERGENSEN , B.A., M.A., J.D.,M.S.

(LIS), Reference Librarian

D ONALD K.

J OSEPH , B.S., LL.B., Visiting

Associate Professor of Law

H ARRIET N.

K ATZ , B.A., J.D., Clinical Professor of Law

A.

K ODZO P AAKU K LUDZE , B.A., LL.B., LL.D.,

Ph.D., Distinguished Professor of Law

Emeritus

D ONALD K OROBKIN , B.A., A.M., J.D., Professor

of Law of Law and Co-Director, Pro Bono

Research Project

R UTH A NNE R OBBINS , B.A., J.D., Clinical

Professor and Director of Lawyering

Programs

S HEILA R ODRIGUEZ , B.A., M.A., J.D., Clinical

Associate Professor of Law

R AND E.

R OSENBLATT , B.A., M.S., J.D.,

Professor of Law

P ATRICK J.

R YAN , B.A., M.A., J.D., LL.M.,

J.S.D., Associate Professor of Law

A DAM S CALES , B.A., J.D., Professor of Law

M EREDITH L.

S HALICK , B.A., M.S., J.D.,

Visiting Clinical Asst. Professor of Law

S ANDRA S IMKINS , J.D., Clinical Associate

Professor of Law and Chair for Clinical

Programs

R ICHARD G.

S INGER , B.A., J.D., LL.M., J.S.D.,

Distinguished Professor of Law

S TANLEY P.

S TAHL , J.D., Visiting Professor of

Law

A LLAN R.

S TEIN , B.A., J.D., Professor of Law

B ETH S TEPHENS , B.A., J.D., Professor of Law

R ICK S WEDLOFF , B.A., J.D., Assistant Professor of Law

E.

H UNTER T AYLOR , Professor of Law

Emeritus

G ERARDO V ILDOSTEGUI , B.A., J.D., Assistant

Professor of Law

C ARL V INIAR , B.A., J.D., Co-Director

Mediation Center

A LEC W ALEN , B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Associate

Professor of Law

C AROL W ALLINGER , B.S., J.D., Clinical

Associate Professor of Law

R OBERT M.

W ASHBURN , A.B., J.D., LL.M.,

Professor of Law

R OBERT F.

W ILLIAMS , B.A., J.D., LL.M., LL.M.,

Distinguished Professor of Law

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Rutgers

Journal of Law & Public Policy

V OLUME 9 S PRING 2012 I SSUE 3

Current Issues in Public Policy

© 2012 by Rutgers University School of Law – Camden

ISSN 1934-3736

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Rutgers

Journal of Law & Public Policy

V OLUME 9 S PRING 2012 I SSUE 3

CONTENTS

P OST -R EFERENDUM S UDAN : T HE N ATION -B UILDING

P ORJECT AND ITS C HALLENGES .................................... 505

C HRISTOPHER Z AMBAKARI

T

HE

P

RICE OF

J

USTICE

: H

OW THE

C

APERTON

S

TANDARD

FOR

J

UDICIAL

R

ECUSAL

F

ELL

S

HORT

, B

UT

O

PENED

D ORR FOR R EFORM OF THE R ECUSAL S TANDARDS THE

A NYWAY ...................................................................... 545

M ARISA M C G ARVEY

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

POST-REFERENDUM SUDAN: THE NATION-

BUILDING PROJECT AND ITS CHALLENGES

1

Christopher Zambakari, B.S./MBA

2

Candidate for Law and Policy Doctorate (LP.D.)

College of Professional Studies

Northeastern University

Boston, Massachusetts

Zambakari.c@husky.neu.edu

INTRODUCTION

The Comprehensive Peace Agreement (“CPA”),

3

signed on

January 9, 2005, brought an end to the brutal civil war (1955-

1 The author would like to thank Divine Muragijimana (Brooklyn

College), Ana Afsharinasab (Arizona State University), Pamela Gutman

(University of Phoenix), and Andrew Dodemaide and members of the

Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy’s Editorial Board for their insightful comments and constructive feedback on the earlier draft of this article.

2 Christopher Zambakari is a candidate for a Law and Policy Doctorate

(LPD) at the College of Professional Studies, Northeastern University,

Boston, Mass.

3 Comprehensive Peace Agreement Between the Government of the

Republic of the Sudan and the Sudan People's Liberation Movement/Sudan

People's Liberation Army, Sudan-SPLM/A, at xi, Jan. 9, 2005, available at http://www.sudanarchive.net/cgi-

505

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

1972; 1983-2005)

4

that engulfed Sudan since its independence in 1956.

5

The CPA was the immediate culmination of the

negotiations that ended the hostility between the National

Congress Party (“NCP”) and the Sudan People’s Liberation

Movement/Army (“SPLM/A”).

6

It ultimately created a new

political dispensation and landscape in South Sudan. Over 2 million people have died and 4 million have been uprooted due to the civil war.

7

In fulfilling the mandate of the CPA, a referendum on self-determination

8

was conducted in January

2011, and 98.83 percent of South Sudanese effectively voted to secede from North Sudan.

9

The General Assembly of the United

Nations admitted the Republic of South Sudan into the community of nations as the 193rd member of the United

Nations on July 14, 2011.

10

The root causes of the war included disputes over resources, the role of religion in the state, self-determination, bin/pagessoa?a=pdf&d=Dl1d36.1.1&dl=1&sim=Screen2Image [hereinafter

Comprehensive Peace Agreement].

4 Background Note: Sudan, U.S.

D EP ’ T OF S TATE (Apr. 8, 2011), http://www.state.gov/r/pa/ei/bgn/5424.htm.

5 The World Fact Book: Sudan, U.S.

C ENT .

I NTELLIGENCE A GENCY , https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/geos/su.html

(last updated Nov. 10, 2011).

6 Background Note: Sudan, supra note 4.

7 Estimates for the Total Number of IDPs for all of Sudan (as of January

2011), I NTERNAL D ISPLACEMENT M ONITORING C ENTRE , http://www.internaldisplacement.org/8025708F004CE90B/%28httpCountries%29/F3D3CAA7

CBEBE276802570A7004B87E4?opendocument

(last visited Feb. 6, 2012);

The Background to Sudan's Comprehensive Peace Agreement, U.N. M ISSION

IN S UDAN , http://unmis.unmissions.org/Default.aspx?tabid=515 (last visited

Feb. 6, 2012).

8 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 1. This specific agreement was named the Machakos Protocol and was dated July 20, 2002.

9 SSRC Announces Final Referendum Results, S.

S UDAN R EFERENDUM

C OMM ’ N , http://www.ssrc.sd/SSRC2/ (last updated Feb. 8, 2011).

10 UN Welcomes South Sudan as 193rd Member State, U.N.

N EWS C TR .

(July 14, 2011), http://www.un.org/apps/news/story.asp?NewsID=39034.

506

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 the distribution of power,

11

and the institutional legacy of

colonialism.

12

The ensuing conflict devastated a significant part

of Africa's largest country and deprived southern, western, and eastern Sudan of stability, growth, and development.

13

Consistent with the mandate of the CPA,

14

in January 2011

South Sudan effectively voted to secede from north Sudan.

15

The

new nation in the south was inaugurated on July 9, 2011.

16

The

signing of the Comprehensive Peace Agreement in 2005 was the beginning of a long march to peace. Since the referendum on self-determination is in the past, it is necessary to think about the project of nation-building that lies ahead. This essay is divided into three sections: Sudanese colonial state, political

11 United Nations Information and Communications Technology

Division/DFS, The background to Sudan's Comprehensive Peace

Agreement, UNMIS (2009),

http://unmis.unmissions.org/Default.aspx?tabid=515; F RANCIS M ADING

D ENG , S ELF -D ETERMINATION AND N ATIONAL U NITY : A C HALLENGE FOR A FRICA

(Africa World Press 2010).

12 M AHMOOD M AMDANI , S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS : D ARFUR , P OLITICS , AND

THE W AR ON T ERROR 75-108, 109-45 (2009); A MIR H.

I DRIS , C ONFLICT AND

P OLITICS OF I DENTITY IN S UDAN 23-41 (2005); Christopher Zambakari, South

Sudan in the Post-CPA Era: Prospects and Challenges, P AMBAZUKA N EWS ,

Jun. 28, 2011, http://www.pambazuka.org/en/category/features/75248

[hereinafter Zambakari, Post-CPA Era]; D OUGLAS H. J OHNSON , T HE R OOT

C AUSES OF S UDAN ' S C IVIL W ARS 9-19 (2003).

13 Alex Cobham, Causes of Conflict in Sudan: Testing The Black Book, 17

E UR .

J.

D EV .

R ES ., 464-65 (2005).

14 Part A, Section 1.3 reads: “That the people of South Sudan have the right to self-determination, inter alia, through a referendum to determine their future status.” Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 2.

Part B, Section 2.5 states: “At the end of the six (6) year Interim Period there shall be an internationally monitored referendum, organized jointly by the

GOS and the SPLM/A, for the people of South Sudan to: confirm the unity of the Sudan by voting to adopt the system of government established under the

Peace Agreement; or to vote for secession.” Comprehensive Peace

Agreement, supra note 3, at 4.

15 South Sudan Profile: Overview, BBC N EWS A FR ., http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-africa-14069082 (last updated Feb. 11,

2012).

16 Id.

507

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 violence, and political reform. In the first section, the paper focuses on the institutional legacy of “Indirect Rule” in South

Sudan. In the second section, attention turns to issues driving political violence and grievances of the marginalized areas.

These issues will be illustrated by looking at the surge in political violence in the disputed regions

17

as reflective of the dilemma that faces both north and South Sudan in a post referendum era. In the last section of the paper, I argue that the way out of the current predicament in the disputed regions — building a more inclusive political community in the north and south that respects unity in diversity — is contained in the conceptual framework known as the New Sudan, as articulated by the SPLM/A. I will further argue that a successful nationbuilding project will depend on how the Government of South

Sudan (“GOSS”) and the GOS manage to build a more inclusive state, which addresses the citizenship question.

17 The Conflict Areas mentioned in the Comprehensive Peace Agreement for special status include Abyei Area, Southern Kordofan, and Blue Nile

States. Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at xi. The

Government of the Sudan (“GOS”) and the SPLM/A signed a separate protocol in Naivasha, Kenya on May 26, 2004 that was integrated into the

CPA, called The Resolution of the Abyei Conflict. Comprehensive Peace

Agreement, supra note 3, at 63. This resolution dealt specifically with the conflict over Abyei. Id. It was determined that unlike the other two regions, which were part of the north, Abyei’s future was to be determined through a referendum similar to the one in the south. Section 5.1 of this Resolution stated that “[t]here shall be established by the Presidency, Abyei Boundaries

Commission (ABC) to define and demarcate the area of the nine Ngok Dinka

Chiefdoms transferred to Kordofan in 1905, referred to herein as Abyei

Area.” Id. at 68. The result of the ABC was rejected by the government in

Khartoum. See Fresh Fighting Breaks Out in Sudan North-South Border

Region, S UDAN T RIBUNE (Mar. 21, 2008), http://www.sudantribune.com/Fresh-fighting-breaks-out-in-Sudan,26451.

The local administration of Abyei has been dissolved. Sudan: Abyei Seizure

by North “Act of War,” Says South, BBC N EWS A FR ., http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-africa-13491445 (last updated May 22,

2011). The referendum has not taken place. See Sudan: Thousands

Displaced by Abyei Violence "At Risk,” IRIN (Mar. 8, 2011), http://www.irinnews.org/Report.aspx?ReportID=92129.

508

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

SUDAN: AN OVERVIEW

Sudan, known as Bilad al-Sudan, or “the land of the blacks,”

18

is the largest country on the African continent — 2.5

million sq km or about 1 million square miles, approximately one-third of the size of the United States of America — almost equal in size to the United States east of the Mississippi River.

19

According to some estimates, the country has 500 different ethnic groups speaking 130 languages.

20

Peter Bechtold,

Chairman Emeritus of the Near East and North Africa Studies,

Foreign Service Institute, U.S. Department of State, reports a higher number consisting of 600 ethnic groups speaking 400 languages and dialects.

21

Sudan has a rich cultural heritage as a cradle of African civilization.

22

Historians call it “The Corridor to Africa.”

23

It shares a border with nine states: Egypt to the

north, the Libyan Arab Jamahiriya to the north-west, Chad and the Central African Republic to the west, the Democratic

Republic of the Congo to the south-west, Uganda to the south,

Kenya to the south-east, and Eritrea and Ethiopia to the east.

24

The region which became Sudan in 1821, after an invasion by

18 S HORT CUT TO D ECAY : T HE C ASE OF THE S UDAN 26 (Sharif Harir & Terje

Tvedt eds., 1994); M AMDANI , S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12, at 75.

19 Peter K. Bechtold, Darfur, the ICC and American Politics, M IDDLE E.

P OL ’ Y C OUNCIL , http://www.mepc.org/journal/middle-east-policyarchives/darfur-icc-and-american-politics (last visited Feb. 11, 2012);

Background Note: Sudan, supra note 4.

20 Garang’s Speech at the Signing Ceremony of S. Sudan Peace Deal,

S UDAN T RIBUNE (Jan. 9, 2005), http://www.sudantribune.com/TEXT-

Garang-s-speech-at-the,7476.

21 Bechtold, supra note 19.

22 Charles Bonnet, Excavations at the Nubian Royal Town of Kerma:

1975-91, 66 A NTIQUITY 611, 611-25 (1992); S HORT CUT TO D ECAY , supra note

18, at 21-22.

23 W ILLIAM Y.

A DAMS , N UBIA : C ORRIDOR TO A FRICA (1984).

24 The World Fact Book: Sudan, supra note 5; M OHAMED H.

F ADLALLA ,

S HORT H ISTORY OF S UDAN 1 (2007).

509

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Ottoman and British forces,

25

has a history that spans several

millennia.

26

The country was subdivided into kingdoms and sultanates that occasionally fought for supremacy at various periods.

27

After the British annexation of Egypt in 1882, the

British took over Sudan after three years of struggle between

1896 and 1899 and ruled it in conjunction with Egypt up until

1956.

28

Khartoum, the capital city of the Republic of Sudan,

29

is

located at the confluence of two rivers: the Blue Nile, carrying with it the residue and richness from Lake Tana as it passes through the highlands of Ethiopia, and the White Nile.

30

The

White Nile is a source of life for inhabitants along its path, flowing from Lake Victoria along the Kenya-Uganda and

Tanzania borders. Sudan is rich in mineral wealth with an abundance of crude oil and gold, and agricultural products such as cotton, livestock, gum Arabic, millet/sorghum, sesame, and wheat.

31

In addition, it also has large cattle ranches throughout

25 M AMDANI , S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12, at 76.

26 Id. at 77.

27 Julie Flint, Darfur, The Forgotten Sudanese War, W ORLD P RESS R EV .,

Mar. 2004, at 32, 32.

28 R. S. O'Fahey, Islam and Ethnicity in the Sudan, 26 J OURNAL OF

R ELIGION IN A FRICA 258, 260-62 (1996). This was the second conquest of the

Sudan in the nineteenth century. The first was the Turko-Egyptian conquest of 1821.

29 Sudan Profile: Facts, BBC N EWS A FR ., www.bbc.co.uk/news/worldafrica-14095114 (last updated Dec. 14, 2011). After July 9, 2011, Khartoum remains the capital city for Sudan while Juba is the capital city of the

Republic of South Sudan. South Sudan Profile: Facts, BBC N EWS A FR ., www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-africa-14069082 (last updated July 5, 2011).

There was an ongoing discussion about moving the capital city out of Juba, and on September 3, 2011, the Council of Ministers voted to move the capital of South Sudan to Ramciel. South Sudan Relocates its Capital from Juba to

Ramciel, S UDAN T RIBUNE (Sept. 3, 2011), www.sudantribune.com/South-

Sudan-relocates-its-capital,40027. As of the date of the writing of this paper,

Juba remains the physical capital in South Sudan.

30 The World Fact Book: Sudan, supra note 5.

31 United Nations Statistics Division, Sudan, UN DATA (2009), http://data.un.org/CountryProfile.aspx?crName=SUDAN; The World Fact

Book: Sudan, supra note 5.

510

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 the country and exports a surplus of cattle, sheep, and camels to the Arabian Gulf countries.

32

In 1956, Sudan became the first

country administered by Great Britain in Africa to become independent after World War Two.

33

“The Sudan’s Civil War,

also the first in postcolonial Africa, began with the Torit Mutiny, a few months before independence was attained on January 1,

1956.”

34

Since its independence, Sudan has been ruled by a

series of unstable parliamentary governments and military regimes.

35

Sudan came into existence in 1821, during the early part of the Condominium Rule, as a result of Turco-Egyptian occupation of the region south of Egypt.

36

This arrangement of

the joint British and Egyptian government ruled Sudan from

1899 to 1955.

37

Capturing the transition in Sudan from one political rule to the next is quite fascinating, yet challenging.

Much has been written in the past about the cultures of various ethnic groups, land, and history of the country, so time will not be spent on those subjects.

38

On January 9, 2011, South Sudan

exercised its right to self-determination as enshrined in the

32 O MAR H ASSAN EL D IRANI , M OHAMMAD A J ABBAR , B ABIKER I DRIS

B ABIKER , C ONSTRAINTS IN THE M ARKET C HAINS FOR E XPORT OF S UDANESE

S HEEP AND S HEEP M EAT TO THE M IDDLE E AST 8, available at http://mahider.ilri.org/bitstream/handle/10568/7/ResearchReport_No16.p

df?sequence=1.

33 D OUGLAS H.

J OHNSON , T HE R OOT C AUSES OF S UDAN ' S C IVIL W ARS 9-19

(2003)

34 Id.

35 See The World Fact Book: Sudan, supra note 5.

36 M AMDANI , S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12, at 76.

37 Francis M. Deng, War of Visions: Conflict of Identities in the Sudan 11

(1995).

38 A DAMS , supra note 23; T HE B RITISH IN THE S UDAN , 1898-1956: T HE

S WEETNESS AND THE S ORROW (R OBERT O.

C OLLINS & F ANCIS M.

D ENG EDS .,

1984); E.E.

E VANS -P RITCHARD , T HE A ZANDE : H ISTORY AND P OLITICAL

I NSTITUTIONS (1971); F ADLALLA , supra note 24.

511

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 provisions of the CPA, and voted overwhelmingly for secession from north Sudan.

39

The challenges facing the new state in the south are enormous. Among the pending issues that have yet to be resolved are the fate of Abyei,

40

Southern Kordofan,

41

and Blue

Nile.

42

Second, concern remains for many Sudanese living in the

Disputed Border Regions, as well as southerners in north Sudan and northerners based in South Sudan

.

43

The situation is explosive in

the disputed border regions.

44

This urgency prompted UN experts to warn that if the problem in Abyei is not brought under control, it “could derail the implementation of the peace agreement that ended the country’s civil war . . . .”

45

Third,

Sudan's giant north-south border— 2,010 km (1,250 miles) long— remains un-demarcated, with progress slow on fixing the boundaries.

46

Fourth, debt and legal treaties have not been settled.

Sudan's crippling debt, estimated at

US$36.8 billion, of which US$30.8

39 U.N. Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on the

Sudan, ¶ 2, U.N. Doc.

S/2011/239 (Apr.

12, 2011); SSRC Announces Final

Referendum Results, supra note 9.

40 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 63.

41 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 71.

42 Id.

43 U.N. Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on the

Sudan, ¶¶ 1-7, U.N. Doc. S/2011/314 (May 17, 2011); U.N. Secretary-General,

Report of the Secretary-General on the Sudan, ¶¶ 14, 17, 19, 21, U.N. Doc.

S/2010/681 (Dec. 31, 2010); U.N. Secretary-General, Report of the

Secretary-General on the Sudan, ¶¶ 17, 25, U.N. Doc.

S/2010/388 (July 19,

2010).

44 See, e.g., Sudan: Abyei Seizure by North “Act of War,” Says South,

supra note 17.

45 Abyei Conflict Could Derail Sudan’s North-South Peace Process, UN

Warns, UN N EWS C TR .

(Mar. 14, 2011), http://www.un.org/apps/news/story.asp?NewsID=37754&Cr1#.

46 D OUGLAS H.

J OHNSON , W HEN B OUNDARIES B ECOME B ORDERS : T HE

I MPACT OF B OUNDARY -M AKING IN S OUTHERN S UDAN ' S F RONTIER Z ONES 9, 28

(2010), available at http://riftvalley.net/?view=publications.

512

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 billion was in arrears at the end of 2010,

47 remains a major concern

in the north as well as in the south. The National Congress Party

(“NCP”) and the Sudan People’s Liberation Movement/Army

(“SPLM/A”) have not reach an agreement over Sudan’s staggering debt. The NCP want the debt to be divided between the two states.

Throughout the two decades of war, the NCP spent the money borrowed on military expenditure to wage a war with the South and neglected development in South Sudan.

48 The SPLM/A insist that

South Sudan should not shoulder the liability of repayment because it never benefited from the loans

.

49

Fifth, building a southern identity is a work in progress. Without a common northern enemy, many fear political fractures within the south.

50 Sixth, there is a failure to

integrate militia after a process of demilitarization, disarmament, and reintegration of former combatants.

51 Leaders in the south must work

to bring together often-disparate groups, including opposition forces and those outside the mainstream SPLA movement to form a truly inclusive political community.

52

47 Sudan: Country Brief, Context, T HE W ORLD B ANK , http://web.worldbank.org/WBSITE/EXTERNAL/COUNTRIES/AFRICAEX

T/SUDANEXTN/0,,menuPK:375432~pagePK:141132~piPK:141107~theSiteP

K:375422,00.html (last updated Apr. 2011).

48 Sudan: Birth of a Nation, 52 A FRICA C ONFIDENTIAL , no. 2, Jan. 21,

2011, at 3; Sudan: Khartoum's Debt Threat, 52 A FRICA C ONFIDENTIAL , no. 12,

June 10, 2011.

49 U.S. Official Says Cancelling Sudan’s Debt a Lengthy Process, S UDAN

T RIBUNE , Jan. 13, 2011, http://www.sudantribune.com/U-S-official-sayscancelling-Sudan,37598.

50 Analysis: Key Challenges for Southern Sudan After Split, IRIN,

available at http://www.irinnews.org/PrintReport.aspx?ReportID=91863.

51 U.N. Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on the

Sudan, ¶¶ 12-16, U.N. Doc. S/2010/314 (May 17, 2011); M AREIKE S CHOMERUS

& T IM A LLEN , S OUTHERN S UDAN AT O DDS W ITH I TSELF : D YNAMICS OF C ONFLICT

AND P REDICAMENTS OF P EACE 15, 62 (2010), available at http://www2.lse.ac.uk/businessAndConsultancy/LSEConsulting/recentRepo rts.aspx#Southern_Sudan.

52 S CHOMERUS & A LLEN , supra note 51, at 62.

513

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

CITIZENS WITHOUT A COUNTRY: THE PLIGHT OF

IDPS AND REFUGEES

The violence in Sudan has already cost the lives of millions, and there is no sign that the violence has ended. Instead, in the period shortly after the referendum, hundreds of people have been killed in clashes in the south and in the disputed regions.

Sudan Tribune, USA Today, and IRIN reported that in March

2011, more than 100 people were killed in two separate clashes involving the SPLA and “armed elements identified loyal to renegade groups operating in the two states of Greater Upper

Nile.”

53

The months of January and February were no less violent since the Geneva-based organization, Small Arms

Survey, reported that more than 200 people were killed when

Lt. Gen. George Athor, a dissident SPLA commander, took up arms after losing in the governorship election of Jonglei state.

54

The problem is exacerbated by two other matters, which complicate the situation in south Sudan further: Internally

Displaced Persons (“IDPs”) and refugees returning from neighboring countries or from outside of Africa altogether. A look at USAID statistics reveals the magnitude of the problem.

53 South Sudan Army Clashes With Rebel Group, Over 100 Dead, S UDAN

T RIBUNE (Mar. 8, 2011), http://www.sudantribune.com/South-Sudan-armyclashes-with,38227. See also More Than 100 Killed in Disputed Sudan

Region, USA T ODAY (Mar. 3, 2011), www.usatoday.com/news/world/2011-

03-03-Sudan_N.htm; Sudan: Thousands Displaced by Abyei Violence "At

Risk”, supra note 17.

54 George Athor’s Rebellion, Jonglei State, S MALL A RMS S URVEY , http://www.smallarmssurveysudan.org/pdfs/facts-figures/armedgroups/southern-sudan/emerging/HSBA-Armed-Groups-Athor.pdf updated Apr. 2011).

(last

514

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Table I: Numbers of IDPs and Refugees in Sudan

55

Number at a Glance

IDPs in Sudan

Source

In Darfur: 1.9 million

In S. Sudan: 29,021

In N. Sudan: 1.7 million

56

In E. Sudan: 68,000

Total: 3.7 million

U.N.-November 2010

OCHA

57

UNHCR

-February 2011

58

-December

2009

OCHA-October 2010

Sudanese Refugees

North-South & Three

Areas Returns

October 30, 2010 to

February 8, 2011

From Darfur: 275,000

From S. Sudan:

138,270

Total: 413,270

59

UNHCR-January 2010

UNHCR-February 2009

IDPs: 2 million

Refugees: 330, 000

January 2005 to

November 2010

UNHCR-November

2010

OCHA/RCSO

60

February

8, 2010

55 This table of statistics is duplicated from a report issued by USAID.

See USAID, S UDAN – C OMPLEX E MERGENCY : F ACT S HEET #2, F ISCAL Y EAR (FY)

2011 1-2 (Feb. 18, 2011), available at http://www.usaid.gov/our_work/humanitarian_assistance/disaster_assista nce/countries/sudan/template/fs_sr/fy2011/sudan_ce_fs02_02-18-

2011.pdf.

56 Figure includes approximately 400,000 IDPs living in four sites recognized by Sudanese authorities. Most IDPs in northern Sudan live in informal settlements in and around Khartoum. Id.

Id.

57 U.N. Office for the Coordination of Humanitarian Affairs (“OCHA”).

58 Office of the U.N. High Commissioner for Refugees (“UNHCR”). Id.

59 According to UNHCR, as of February 13, 248 Sudanese refugees had returned to Southern Sudan since October 30, 2010. Id.

60 U.N. Resident Coordinator’s Support Office (RCSO). Id.

515

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

The

South Sudan Relief and Rehabilitation Commission

(“SSRRC”) reported that 21,000 people are stranded in deplorable living conditions in IDP camps around Khartoum.

61 These people sold

property and businesses off when it was announced by the GOSS that they should return to the south. In the case of Abyei, the region that connects South Sudan to Sudan, violence has already cost hundreds of lives. The UN staffs in Abyei suggest that more than half the population has left town, with the number of displaced estimated to be around 100,000.

62

Lastly, the number of South Sudanese living in the north ranges from 1.5 million to 2 million, and a large number will not return to the south due to the difficult living conditions and current instability in the region.

63

These are the realities as they stand: proliferation of ethnic violence, a disputed border region pending consultation, millions of IDPs stranded throughout the country, and over half a million refugees yet to find a permanent home. In addition to the numerous challenges facing the south, the most pressing issue that it will have to resolve, should it decide to solve the issues fueling the ensuing violence, is the question of citizenship.

64

In order to

61 Sudan: Managing the Great Trek Southwards, IRIN, Mar. 10, 2011, http://www.irinnews.org/Report.aspx?Reportid=92150.

62 U.N.

O FFICE FOR THE C OORDINATION OF H UMANITARIAN A FFAIRS , S UDAN :

A BYEI C RISIS , S ITUATION R EPORT N O .

12 (Sept. 6, 2011), available at http://reliefweb.int/sites/reliefweb.int/files/resources/OCHA%20Situation

%20Report%20_12%20on%20Abyei%20Crisis%209%20June%202011.pdf.

See also USAID, supra note 55 (stating that there are 68,000 IDPs in Eastern

Sudan); Sudan: Managing the Great Trek Southwards, supra note 61;

Sudan: Thousands Displaced by Abyei Violence "At Risk”, supra note 17

(indicating that UN staff in Abyei suggest more than half the population has left town).

63 Marina Ottaway, Southern Sudanese Living in North Sudan, C

ARNEGIE

E NDOWMENT FOR I NT ’ L P EACE (Jan. 21, 2011), http://sudan.carnegieendowment.org/2011/01/21/southern-sudaneseliving-in-north-sudan; Briefing Paper on Southern Sudan: IDPs Return to

Face Slow Land Allocation, and No Shelter, Basic Services or Livelihoods,

I NTERNAL D ISPLACEMENT M ONITORING C TR .

(May 30, 2011), http://www.internal-displacement.org/briefing/south-sudan; Sudan:

Managing the Great Trek Southwards, supra note 61. See also Richard

Downie, Southern Sudan's Referendum, C TR .

FOR S TRATEGIC & I NT ’ L S TUDIES

(Jan. 5, 2011), http://csis.org/publication/southern-sudans-referendum.

64 A MIR H.

I DRIS , supra note 12, at 19-22; Ibrahim Abdullah, When Does an Indigene/Immigrant Become a Citizen? Reflections on the Nation-State in

Contemporary Africa, 7 A FR .

S OC .

R EV . 113, 113-17 (2003); Mahmood

516

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 conceptualize the violence occurring in Sudan, one must first and foremost understand the issues that led to the violence and continue to sustain the cycle of violence over time.

The main issues that link

Côte d’Ivoire, Nigeria, Liberia, Sierra Leone, Ethiopia, Somalia,

Burundi, Rwanda,

65

Democratic Republic of Congo,

66

Uganda,

Kenya, and South Africa, to the event that has led to the breakup of Africa’s biggest country, Sudan, are those of citizenship and nativity,

67

a question of who belongs and who does not belong.

68

Who is a native and indigenous to the homeland, and who is foreign, alien, or non-native in a tribal homeland? These questions center on the legitimacy to have a native authority to advocate for one’s right. They revolve around the issue of belonging, and the rights and entitlements that accompany civil citizenship. Most postcolonial African conflicts have revolved

Mamdani, Understanding the Crisis in Kivu: Report of the CODESRIA

Mission to the Democratic Republic of Congo September, 1997, C TR .

F OR

C IVIL S OC ’ Y (Nov. 20, 1998), http://ccs.ukzn.ac.za/files/mamdani.kivu.pdf

[hereinafter Mamdani, Understanding the Crisis in Kivu]; Zambakari, Post-

CPA Era, supra note 12.

65 For a good case study on Rwanda’s citizenship crisis, see M AHMOOD

M AMDANI , W HEN V ICTIMS B ECOME K ILLERS : C OLONIALISM , N ATIVISM , AND THE

G ENOCIDE IN R WANDA (2002).

66 For a good case study on the Democratic Republic of Congo (DRC)’s citizenship crisis, see Georges Nzongola-Ntalaja, Global Insights:

Citizenship, Political Violence, and Democratization in Africa, 10 G LOBAL

G OVERNANCE

403, 403-09 (2004); Mahmood Mamdani, The Invention of the

Indigène, L ONDON R EVIEW OF B OOKS (Jan. 20, 2011), http://www.lrb.co.uk/v33/n02/mahmood-mamdani/the-invention-of-theindigene [hereinafter Mamdani, The Invention of the Indigène]; Mamdani,

Understanding the Crisis in Kivu, supra note 64.

67 M OHAMED O MER B ESHIR , T HE S OUTHERN S UDAN : B ACKGROUND TO

C ONFLICT (1968); M OHAMED O MER B ESHIR , T HE S OUTHERN S UDAN : F ROM

C ONFLICT TO P EACE (1975); I DRIS , supra note 12, at 19-22; M AMDANI , S AVIORS

AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12; N EW S UDAN IN THE M AKING ?

E SSAYS ON A

N ATION IN P AINFUL S EARCH OF I TSELF (Francis M. Deng ed., 2010); S HORT CUT

TO D ECAY : T HE C ASE OF THE S UDAN , supra note 18; Francis M. Deng,

Ethnicity: An African Predicament, 15 Brookings Rev. 28, 28-31 (1997).

68 Identity, Security and the Renegotiation of National Belonging in

West Africa: Reflections on the Cote d’Ivoire Crises and its Repercussions on

the West Africa Region, CODESRIA (May 15-16, 2003), available at http://www.codesria.org/spip.php?article582&lang=fr.

517

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 around the question of citizenship.

69

Today Sudan is the

defining example of the failure to reform the colonial system and build an inclusive polity.

70

To illustrate the point and the difficulty in building a more equitable society that engages in a peaceful nation-building that is democratic, transparent, and inclusive of the diversity within the country, I will present the case of an Ethnic Administrative Division in South Sudan: the

One County-One Tribe Policy. In doing so, I hope to bring the study of South Sudan into the mainstream study of postcolonial

Africa, along with the challenges that most African countries face and the dilemma of unity in diversity.

71

PROBLEMS OF THE SUDAN: NORTH AND SOUTH

The 20th century was a period in human history replete with never-before-seen violence. One cannot help but ask: what is the reason behind the proliferation of violence in the postcolonial Sudan? Is it that violence is embedded in Sudanese cultures? If the kind of violence taking place after independence from the late 1950s is not revolutionary, counter-revolutionary, or even anti-colonial, how does one make sense of this new kind of violence?

72

Let us first explore the grievances that led to the signing of the CPA to frame the larger problem, and then turn to the specifics by looking at the politics of county creation in

South Sudan and how that is laying the groundwork for future conflicts.

On January 9, 2005, the SPLM/A and the GOS signed a peace agreement called the CPA, which ended the conflict in

South Sudan that had been going on since 1983. Between the

69 Zambakari, Post-CPA Era, supra note 12.

70 Id.

71 Francis M. Deng, Sudan: A Nation in Turbulent Search of Itself, 603

A NNALS A M .

A CAD .

P OL .

& S OC .

S CI .

155, 160 (2006).

72 Mahmood Mamdani, Columbia Univ., Making Sense of Non-

Revolutionary Violence: Some Lessons from the Rwandan Genocide, Text of the Franz Fanon Lecture 1 (Aug. 8, 2001), available at http://ccs.ukzn.ac.za/files/Mahmood%20Mamdani's%20Frantz%20Fanon%

20lecture.pdf [hereinafter Mamdani, Making Sense of Non-Revolutionary

Violence].

518

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

First Civil War and the SPLA/M uprising in 1983, there was another group, which referred to itself as Anyanya II.

73

The movement started shortly after the Addis Ababa Agreement and initiated military operations starting in 1978 in Eastern Upper

Nile on the Ethiopian border.

74

The CPA was the outcome of the so-called Machakos peace process, which began in July 2002. It was composed of six partial agreements that have been signed by the two parties

(NCP and SPLM/A).

75

The Agreement included important

stipulations for South Sudan to achieve the goal of selfdetermination for the people through a referendum organized in

2011.

76

The signatories to the CPA came to the realization that

South Sudan had been continuously dominated by North

Sudan.

77

Resources were not allocated equally between the

regions.

78

Power was highly centralized in the hands of a few in

Khartoum.

79

To cite one case, the process of Sudanization of the civil service, which took place shortly after the Juba Conference of 1947, resulted in only six out of 800 posts going to

73 John Young, John Garang's Legacy to the Peace Process, the SPLM/A

& the South, 32 R

EV .

A FR .

P OL .

E CON . 535, 538 (2005).

74 Id.

75 J OHAN B ROSCHÉ , S HARING P OWER –E NABLING P EACE ?

E VALUATING

S UDAN ’ S C OMPREHENSIVE P EACE A GREEMENT 2005 17-18 (2009), available at http://www.ucdp.uu.se/gpdatabase/info/Sud%203.pdf.

76 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 1. Part A, Section

1.3 reads: “That the people of South Sudan have the right to selfdetermination, inter alia, through a referendum to determine their future status.” Id. at 2. Part B, Section 2.5 states that “At the end of the six (6) year

Interim Period there shall be an internationally monitored referendum, organized jointly by the GOS and the SPLM/A, for the people of South Sudan to: confirm the unity of the Sudan by voting to adopt the system of government established under the Peace Agreement; or to vote for secession.” Id. at 4.

77 B ROSCHÉ , supra note 75, at 17-18.

78 Cobham, supra note 13, at 463.

79 S CHOMERUS & A LLEN , supra note 51, at 14.

519

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 southerners.

80

The history of South Sudan, along with other marginalized areas, is one of deliberate policies by each postcolonial government to marginalize socially, politically and economically peripheral regions in Sudan.

81

Thus, the CPA set out to correct the imbalances through power-sharing,

82

decentralization of authority, and equal allocation of revenue from oil between the north and the south.

83

More importantly, the CPA included the provision for a referendum on the selfdetermination of the south to be held at the end of the interim period.

84

The interim period has seen development in South

Sudan as a result of the wealth-sharing provision, which allocated 50 percent of the revenue from oil to the GOSS. In the area of reform of national and local institutions of governance, however, reform has been contradictory, as the London School of Economics’ report showed.

85

According to the CPA, too much centralization of power in Khartoum was part of the problem in

Sudan, so decentralization became a de facto solution.

86

In

southern Sudan the government experimented with decentralization only to return to a highly centralized system.

At the local level, the government policy was to enact legislation called the Local Government Act in 2009,

87

which was seen as a way to delegate power to the local institutions.

88

80 David S. Bassiouni, Keynote Address by Dr. David S. Bassiouni to

ESCA-USA 10th Annual Conference 4 (Sept. 4-5, 2010).

81 Christopher Zambakari, Old Sudan and New Sudan: Political Crisis

and the Search for Comprehensive Peace, P AMBAZUKA N EWS (Jan. 26, 2012), http://www.pambazuka.org/en/category/features/79401/print.

82 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 9. This agreement is known as the Protocol on Power Sharing.

83 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 45. This agreement is known as the Protocol on Wealth Sharing.

84 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 1.

85 S CHOMERUS & A LLEN , supra note 51, at 9, 15.

86 Id. at 38-39.

87 The Local Government Act, 2009 (2009) (S. Sudan), available at http://www.ldphs.org.za/resources/local-government-database/bycountry/sudan/sub-national-

520

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

However, this policy too is tainted by something familiar in

Sudanese history: the mode of rule adopted by British strategists to govern Sudan.

89

This was an administrative mechanism characterized by a duality in law, which translated into parallel structures, one governing those in the urban areas, and another system governing the peasants in rural areas.

90

It was a policy

that enabled British colonial administrators to divide up the majority of peasants into hundreds of smaller minorities and effectively deny them the political rights to mobilize or act as a majority.

91

The next section looks at the consequences of this

way of organizing the mass in the countryside.

ETHNIC ADMINISTRATIVE DIVISION-ONE

COUNTY-ONE TRIBE

Historically, south Sudan was composed of three provinces:

Bhar el Ghazal Region, Upper Nile, and Equatoria.

92

Today the south consists of ten states: Central Equatoria, Eastern

Equatoria, Jonglei, Lakes, Northern Bahr El Ghazal, Unity,

Upper Nile, Warrap, Western Bahr El Ghazal, and Western legislation/The%20Local%20Government%20Act%202009.pdf. This Act was made “[i]n accordance with the provisions of Article 59(2)(b) read together with Article 85(1) of the Interim Constitution of Southern Sudan,” which was enacted in 2005. Id. See also I NTERIM C ONST .

OF S.

S UDAN (2005), available at http://www.chr.up.ac.za/undp/domestic/docs/c_SouthernSudan.pdf.

88 The Local Government Act, 2009, supra note 87.

89 Zambakari, Post-CPA Era, supra note 12.

90 See generally, M AHMOOD M AMDANI , C ITIZEN AND S UBJECT :

C ONTEMPORARY A FRICA AND THE L EGACY OF L ATE C OLONIALISM , ch. 4 (1996)

[hereinafter M AMDANI , C ITIZEN AND S UBJECT ].

91 Christopher Zambakari, South Sudan and the Nation-Building Project:

Lessons and Challenges, 6 I NT ’ L J.

A FR .

R ENAISSANCE S TUD . 32, 39 (2011)

[hereinafter Zambakari, Nation-Building].

108.

92 See S HORT CUT TO D ECAY : T HE C ASE OF THE S UDAN , supra note 18, at

521

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Equatoria.

93

According to a report by the London School of

Economics on the dynamics of conflict in Sudan,

94

the best case

study that illustrates the tendency for a proliferation of states, counties, and homelands is seen with the Eastern Equatoria

State (“EES”), which until recently had two main districts: Torit and Kapoeta. Kapoeta was the first to then subdivide into three counties: north (Didinga), south (Buya), and eastern (Toposa and Nyangatom). Torit subdivided into three more counties:

Magwi (Acholi and Madi), Ikotos (Dongotona and Lago), and

Lafon/Lopa (Lopi and Pari).

95

Today, Eastern Equatoria has

eight counties, and this number is increasing.

96

The division is not arbitrary or accidental but reflects the reality on the ground, local and national politics above, and real grievances at the local level.

97

The capital of a county is located in the dominant tribe’s

homeland, which gives the tribe both political representation and access to resources.

98

The most important resource is land.

99

Government representatives are recruited from home

areas.

100

This method of ruling and organizing the mass of

peasantry is not unique to Sudan.

101

It is, in fact, one that is fairly common in Africa.

102

The creation of Ethnic Federalism, a constellation of tribes with corresponding local governments,

93 About South Sudan, Government, State Governments, E MBASSY OF THE

R EPUBLIC OF S.

S UDAN IN W ASH .

D.C., http://www.gossmission.org/goss/index.php?option=com_content&task=vi ew&id=351&Itemid=176.

94 S CHOMERUS & A LLEN , supra note 51, at 42.

95 Id.

96 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 43.

97 Id.

98 Id.

99 Id.

100 Id. at 42.

101 Id.

102 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 42.

522

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 can be seen in the case of Nigeria, which has a provision in its constitution called the Federal Character Commission,

103

or in

the Ethiopian constitution,

104

which mandates that each tribe

has a homeland or ‘One County-One Tribe Rule.’

105

Uganda has

an institution devoted to the management of the mass of peasantry in the rural areas called the Ministry of Local

Government.

106

Sudan has copied this mode of governance, and through the Local Government Act of 2009, created a hybrid system incorporating a Customary Law and Council into Local

Governance. This is an institutional legacy from the British mode of rule in Africa, indirect rule, which functioned on a dual system: one governing over the urban city dwellers and another over the peasants in the countryside.

107

Even when done with

103 C ONSTITUTION OF N IGERIA (1999), § 14(3).

“The composition of the

Government of the Federation or any of its agencies and the conduct of its affairs shall be carried out in such a manner as to reflect the federal character of Nigeria and the need to promote national unity, and also to command national loyalty, thereby ensuring that there shall be no predominance of persons from a few State or from a few ethnic or other sectional groups in that Government or in any of its agencies.” Id. §153(1)(c) establishes the

Federal Character Commission. The Third Schedule, Part 1, §7 states: “The

Federal Character Commission shall comprise the following members: (a) a

Chairman; and (b) one person to represent each of the states of the

Federation and the Federal Capital Territory, Abuja.” Id. The Third

Schedule, Part I, §8(1) empowers the Commission and states: “In giving effect to the provisions of section 14(3) and (4) of this Constitution, the

Commission shall have the power to: (a) work out an equitable formula subject to the approval of the National Assembly for the distribution of all cadres of posts in the public service of the Federation and of the States, the armed forces of the Federation, the Nigeria Police Force and other government security agencies, government owned companies and parastatals of the states.” Id.

104 Minasse Haile, The New Ethiopian Constitution: Its Impact Upon

Unity, Human Rights and Development, 20 S UFFOLK T RANSNAT ’ L L. R EV . 1,

19-20 (1996); Mahmood Mamdani, Columbia Univ., Political Identity,

Citizenship and Ethnicity in Post-Colonial Africa, Keynote Address at the

Arusha Conference: “New Frontiers of Social Policy” 16 (Dec. 12-15, 2005)

[hereinafter Mamdani, Keynote Address at the Arusha Conference].

105 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 42-43.

106 M AMDANI , C ITIZEN AND S UBJECT , supra note 90, at 60-61 (1996).

107 Id. at 16-22.

523

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 the intent of satisfying certain disenfranchised groups, this policy produces enormous violence and instability within a country. It preempts the creation of a truly inclusive state and focuses on a mode of governance, which produces many smaller

‘nation-states’ within the larger state.

The division is built on certain assumptions. It is argued by proponents of this continuous subdivision that the political map must follow the cultural map of a region at both the national level and the county level.

108

African countries that adhere to

this policy also rely on ethnic quotas to fill positions in government, federal institutions, universities, and the armed forces.

109

This raises a series of questions about qualification for

those positions and the unintended consequences of the policy itself. How does the state identify who can and cannot apply for jobs in state institutions? What are the criteria used in recruiting for these positions and how does the state achieve its objectives without turning citizenship into an ethnically-defined membership in a native homeland?

The real problem is that cultural and political boundaries should coincide and that the state should be a nation-state — such that the natural boundaries of a state are those of a common cultural community.

110

Mamdani has made this

observation in a number of places in regards to other African countries,

111

and the crisis that ensues as various groups seek to have representation by having a tribal homeland. Mamdani writes, “For no matter how much we redraw boundaries, the political crisis will remain incomprehensible until we address

108 Mamdani, Keynote Address at the Arusha Conference, supra note 104, at 4.

109 The case of Nigeria is illustrative of these tendencies. See

C ONSTITUTION OF N IGERIA , supra note 103, Third Schedule, Part 1, §8.

110 Mamdani, Keynote Address at the Arusha Conference, supra note 104, at 4.

111 Mahmood Mamdani, When Does a Settler Become a Native?

Reflections on the Colonial Roots of Citizenship in Equatorial and South

Africa, Inaugural Lecture (May 13, 1998); Mahmood Mamdani,

Understanding the Crisis in Kivu, supra note 64; Mamdani, Keynote

Address at the Arusha Conference, supra note 104; Mahmood Mamdani, The

Invention of the Indigène, supra note 66.

524

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 the institutional – political – legacy of colonial rule.”

112

As this paper is being written, the Lopit and the Pari have filed for new counties, claiming that they can no longer coexist with each other.

113

Today, there are demands in South Sudan to create counties based on ethnicities, and each ethnicity should be entitled to its

114

With a country as diverse as Sudan, one must ask: homeland.

where does this process of continuous political fragmentation end? There is one problem that is a direct outcome of this particular mode of organizing a population: political violence.

What happens when IDPs and refugees return to South Sudan?

Where will they live? Should they be confined to already demarcated states with respective counties, or should they also fight to have their own counties? How about immigrants? What happens to immigrants who do not have a county? If right to land and political representation follows an ethnic system whereby everyone has a homeland, what happens to immigrants who have neither a homeland in Sudan, nor a representation in the form of a native authority? The answer lies in a particular form of the state that has emerged in Africa after independence.

115

The reality of the postcolonial state in Africa can be summarized as follows: in an increasingly integrated global economy, people move to wherever they have the chance for a better life. A dynamic economy moves people, mostly labor migrants, outside their ‘tribally defined homeland’ and forces them to cross over different boundaries. However, the colonial state especially penalizes those that are most dynamic, those who respond to favorable economic conditions across political

112 Mamdani, Keynote Address at the Arusha Conference, supra note 104, at 4-5.

113 S CHOMERUS & A LLEN , supra note 51, at 43.

114 See M AREIKE S CHOMERUS AND T IM A LLEN , S OUTHERN S UDAN AT O DDS

W ITH I TSELF : D YNAMICS OF C ONFLICT AND P REDICAMENTS OF P EACE 40-42

(2010), http://www2.lse.ac.uk/businessAndConsultancy/LSEConsulting/pdf/southe rnSudan.pdf.

115 Abdullah, supra note 64, at 113; M AMDANI , C ITIZEN AND SUBJECT , supra note 90, at 52-90.

525

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 boundaries, those who go in search of employment and better living conditions outside of their countries. It brands them as aliens, non-indigenous, or foreigners.

116

The cases of the

Banyarwanda in Uganda and in Eastern Congo, the Ghanaians in Nigeria, and the Burkinabe in Ivory Coast, are illustrative of these tendencies in the postcolonial period.

117

In each of the

mentioned cases, violence has been the outcome as those defined as natives and indigenous confront those branded as non-natives and non-indigenous.

In the next section, I will discuss the colonial state in Africa and the relevance of its study as it applies to South Sudan. In doing so, I hope to show that the development in Sudan is not unique to Sudan, but is a problem that affects all African countries. Last, I will look at the reform of that state and draw relevant lessons from a country where a successful reform has been undertaken, war brought to an end, and the example that inspired the signing of the CPA. The same lesson has applied where mass violence has been stopped, such as in Mozambique.

The Mozambican National Resistance (“RENAMO”) was involved in some of the most heinous crimes in Mozambique: cutting off hands, maiming, burning villages, deliberately targeting civilians, and kidnapping children and forcing them into carrying out brutalities against their own parents and friends.

118

The U.S. State Department estimates that one million

Mozambicans perished during the civil war.

119

In Mozambique,

116 Mahmood Mamdani, Social Movements and Constitutionalism in the

African Context (Ctr. for Basic Research, Working Paper No. 2, 1989);

Mamdani, Understanding the Crisis in Kivu, supra note 64; Mamdani,

Keynote Address at the Arusha Conference, supra note 104, at 4; Nzongola-

Ntalaja, Global Insights, supra note 66.

117 Abdullah, supra note 64; Mahmood Mamdani, The Social Basis of

Constitutionalism in Africa, 28 J. M OD . A FR . S TUD . 359, 367 (1990).

118 Glenda Morgan, Violence in Mozambique: Towards an Understanding of Renamo, 28 J. M OD . A FR . S TUD . 603, 607-09 (1990); Mahmood Mamdani,

Good Muslim, Bad Muslim: A Political Perspective on Culture and Terrorism,

104 A M .

A NTHROPOLOGIST 766, 769 (2002); Thandika Mkandawire, The

Terrible Toll of Post-Colonial ‘Rebel Movements’ in Africa: Towards an

Explanation of the Violence Against the Peasantry, 40 J.

M OD .

A FR .

S TUD . 181,

206-7 (2002).

119 Background Note: Mozambique, U.S.

D EPT .

OF S TATE (Nov. 4, 2011), http://www.state.gov/r/pa/ei/bgn/7035.htm.

526

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 like in South Africa, violence was brought to an end through political reform. Today, RENAMO sits in Parliament and not in prison.

120

The peace agreement signed in 2005 between the

SPLA/M and the GOS was also modeled on a similar understanding, whereby there was no military victory but a stalemate between the adversaries.

121

Both parties agreed with the signing of the CPA that no one was to be held accountable for the atrocities committed in Sudan during the civil war.

122

The key in every case has been political reform of the state, and prioritizing political reform over criminalizing opponents. At the core of the political reform is the recognition that we must not see all public violence as criminal. It was only when the

South Africans decriminalized political adversaries, expanding the realm of political membership, that there was an opening for dialogue that resulted in the transformation ushered in during a post-apartheid South Africa. That same political imagination was at work in the dialogue that delivered the CPA in Sudan, and the violence came to an end. The African example of how to resolve the citizenship question, manage diversity within unity, and reform the colonial state can be seen within South Africa’s transition from apartheid to a democratic system. This, more than the lessons of the European nation-state, is relevant for containing non-revolutionary violence based on political exclusion in South Sudan.

MAKING SENSE OF NON-REVOLUTIONARY

VIOLENCE IN AFRICA

In light of the recent developments around Africa, Bret

Stephens, a Deputy Editor for the Wall Street Journal, called for a new kind of colonialism in Africa to help solve Africa’s problems. He wrote recently in his column:

120 M AMDANI , S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12, at 285-86.

121 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3.

122 Mahmood Mamdani, The New Humanitarian Order, 287 T HE N ATION

17, 22 (Sept. 29, 2008).

527

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

It means that colonialism, for which the West has spent the past five decades in nonstop atonement, was far from the worst thing to befall much of the colonized world. It means, also, that some new version of colonialism may be the best thing that could happen to at least some countries in the postcolonial world.

123

What Stephens failed to come to terms with was the devastating legacy of colonialism in Africa, from which Africa has yet to fully recover five decades later. Instead of contextualizing the violence and its corresponding twin on the continent, underdevelopment, Stephens saw the problem as internal and prescribed the solution to be a ‘new version of colonialism’ to be externally imposed. Implicit in his analysis is that colonial power brought law and order to the colonies. The departure of colonial powers led to chaos and lack of development. This also shows the failure to understand the nature of postcolonial violence in Africa. Stephens is not saying anything new that has not been said before. His western-centric view, which denies that African agencies are capable of producing progressive movements and leading social transformation, has its roots in European racist scholarship.

124

It is neither original, nor supported by historical fact. Rather, it is a viewpoint created politically. Any policy designed to bring lasting peace in former colonies must begin with the question of citizenship, which is what most of the violence revolves around.

125

At the heart of the colonial system of governance was

dualities in how the colonized were organized, and how those deemed civilized were governed.

126

It was a project enforced by

law, whereas the urban civilized were governed under common

123 Bret Stephens, Haiti, Sudan, Cote d’Ivoire: Who Cares?, Wall St. J.,

Jan. 11, 2011, at A15.

124 G EORG W ILHELM F RIEDRICH H EGEL , T HE P HI l OSOPHY OF H ISTORY 91-92

(J. Sibree trans. 1956).

125 Zambakari, Post-CPA Era, supra note 12.

126 Id.

528

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 law, natives were governed under customary law.

127

Customary law, in turn, discriminated based on membership in an ethnic homeland.

128

It was a system that privileged those considered

natives and discriminated against those considered aliens, foreigners, and non-natives.

129

To move forward requires that

we rethink the institutional legacy of colonialism and the legacy of the postcolonial state in Africa. It demands political imagination in thinking of a different future, one based on moving forward, and not one based on the wrongs of the past.

Those who study violence distinguish between two dominant forms: violence that makes sense, and violence that does not make sense. In an attempt to come to terms with the consequences of a bloody and violent century,

130

which still continues into the 21 st century, scholars group revolutionary violence, anti-colonial struggles during the decolonization phase, and counter-revolutionary violence, as meaningful and humane. This kind of violence is said to be progressive.

131

The

second kind of violence is said to be reactionary and regressive; thus, it is counter-productive. This latter kind is meaningless violence that seems to defy reason, and therefore lies outside the scope of understanding. It is devoid of meaning.

132

The former is a legacy from the European Enlightenment, which viewed politically organized violence as a necessary component of progress. The latter is linked to the process of state formation in

Africa.

133

It is an outcome of the mode of rule used to colonize

Africa in the 19 th century.

127 Id.

128 Id.

129 M AMDANI , C ITIZEN AND S UBJECT , supra note 90.

130 Peter Wallensteen, War and Peace: Lessons from the 20th Century:

The Hoirup Inaugural Lecture, 89 S CANDINAVIAN R EV . 5, 6 (2001).

131 Mamdani, Making Sense of Non-Revolutionary Violence, supra note

72, at 8.

132 Id.

133 I DRIS , supra note 12, at 2-3.

529

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Columbia University’s leading scholar on African Politics,

Mahmood Mamdani, has called the latter type of violence that is devoid of meaning, “non-revolutionary violence.”

134

Progressive violence or ‘good violence’ is also associated with the legacy of

Karl Marx, who famously professed “revolution is the midwife of history.”

135

This tradition finds its genesis in the French

Revolution.

136

Since the French Revolution, violence has been

understood as essential to progress.

137

On the other hand,

Marxist paradigm failed to account for non-revolutionary violence – violence that does not remain class specific, but transcends both class and ethnicity.

138

“Its failure was in its inability to understand the kind of violence that pits the impoverished and disempowered against each other.”

139

With

non-revolutionary violence, the lines of battle are not drawn by wealth and poverty, but by differences not economic in nature.

140

In Africa, we see a significant reduction in interstate conflict,

141

but a proliferation of ethnic conflicts within states with an increasing death toll for civilian population, including both direct and indirect conflict deaths.

142

This development can be

134 Mamdani, Making Sense of Non-Revolutionary Violence, supra note

72, at 1.

135 Mahmood Mamdani, Culture Talk: Six Debates That Shape Discourse

on "Good" Muslims, 22 A

M .

J.

I SLAMIC S OC .

S CI . 95, 101 (2005).

136 Id.

137 Id.

138 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 37.

139 Id. at 37-38.

140 Mamdani, Making Sense of Non-Revolutionary Violence, supra note

72, at 1.

141 Lotta Themnér & Peter Wallensteen, Armed Conflict, 1946-2010 ,

J.

P EACE R ES . 525, 525-26 (2011), available at http://jpr.sagepub.com/content/48/4/525.

142 G ENEVA D ECLARATION S ECRETARIAT , G LOBAL B URDEN OF A RMED

V IOLENCE 2-3 (2008), available at http://www.genevadeclaration.org/fileadmin/docs/Global-Burden-of-

Armed-Violence-full-report.pdf; Thandika Mkandawire, The Terrible Toll of

530

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 seen in Sudan. Whereas the CPA brought the war between the north and south to an end, the south has been plagued by mass interethnic violence. The Border States,

143

eastern and western regions, Abyei, and Southern Kordofan, all have been engulfed in a series of violence.

144

This kind of violence is nonrevolutionary. The outcome of non-revolutionary violence easily leads to ethnic and racial cleansing.

POLITICAL VIOLENCE AND ETHNIC CLEANSING

Most violence in Africa is related to access to resources and participation in the political process. The most important of resources is access to land. A good place to start is to study how land was treated under colonial rule. For the British, the lessons learned in India led to the removal of land from the market and handed over to the native authority,

145

who effectively governed

its allocation to those designated as natives, and deprived those considered non-natives. According to leading British colonial administrator, Lord Lugard: “the native authority is thus de

facto and de jure ruler over his own people . . . . He exercises the power of allocation of lands, and with the aid of the native courts, of adjudication in land disputes and expropriation for offences against the community.”

146

In this sense, a non-native could rent but not own land. Land belonged to the collective membership and was accessed as a customary right. Given that the rich, whether native or non-native could purchase land

Post-Colonial ‘Rebel Movements’ in Africa: Towards an Explanation of the

Violence Against the Peasantry, J.

M OD .

A FR .

S TUD . 181, 181-83 (2002).

143 The Border States mentioned in the Comprehensive Peace Agreement for special status include Abyei, Southern Kordofan, and Blue Nile. See

Comprehensive Peace Agreement, supra note 3, at 65, 73.

144 Christopher Zambakari, In Search for Durable Peace: The

Comprehensive Peace Agreement and Power Sharing in Sudan, I NT ’ L J.

H UM .

R TS .

*14 (forthcoming Fall 2012).

145 S IR H ENRY S UMNER M AINE , L ECTURES ON THE E ARLY H ISTORY OF

I NSTITUTIONS 81-82 (7 TH ED .

1914); H ON .

S IR F.

D.

L UGARD , T HE D UAL

M ANDATE IN B RITISH T ROPICAL A FRICA 286 (4th ed. 1929).

146 L UGARD , supra note 145, at 203.

531

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 anywhere, what then was the reality of the poor peasant? If “you could not afford to buy land in the first place, you could still claim land ‘customarily’, in your ‘home’ area, from your

‘customary’ chief, as a ‘customary’ right, under ‘customary’ law.”

147

The outcome was a strong sense of ethnic belonging. All

this led to a heightened sense and drive to belong to a tribe, whose land will be accessed exclusively as a customary right from the native authority by those considered natives of the land.

From the 1930’s through the 1940’s, the British colonial policy in the south gained momentum. Besides the conscious effort to shape the identity of the subjects in both the north and south, a far more brutal outcome of the British Southern Policy was reflected in the forceful displacement of people from one region, where they were considered non-indigenous, to another, where they were considered indigenous. It involved the purification of all the ethnic groups considered foreign to the region.

148

Contacts between the two regions were restricted.

Historically, Sudan was also home to immigrants from East and

West Africa, who moved to wherever the living conditions were suitable for settling, and to those making their way to the Mecca.

Tribes such as Banda, Dongo, Kreish, Feruge, Nyangulgule, and

Togoyo, who adopted Islamic and Arabic cultures and maintained constant contacts with Arab tribes in Central and

Western Sudan (Darfur and Khordofan), were forcefully removed from their regions and resettled in other areas away from the influence of their northern Arab neighbors.

149

The policy adopted and implemented throughout southern Sudan resembled a similar project in apartheid South Africa with the administration of a Pass System.

150

Characteristic of this project

was the re-tribalization of the population, where the ethnic

147 Mahmood Mamdani, Columbia Univ., When Does a Settler Become a

Native? : Reflections of the Colonial Roots of Citizenship in Equatorial and

South Africa 2 (May 13, 1998).

148 B ESHIR , T HE S OUTHERN S UDAN : B ACKGROUND TO C ONFLICT , supra note

67, at 51.

149 Id.

150 G ENERAL J.C.

S MUTS , A FRICA AND S OME W ORLD P ROBLEMS 73-103

(1930).

532

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 groups were fragmented and restricted from moving outside the tribal homeland. This was a political project focused on ethnic cleansing and racial purification so as to create a homogenous group throughout Sudan. Mohamed Beshir captured the outcome of the Southern Policy as it was being implemented throughout South Sudan:

In pursuance of this policy, all natives of Darfur and Khordofan were prevented from entering Bahr al Ghazal. No natives of the latter were allowed to go to Khordofan or Darfur. The traditional contact between the Dinka and Arabs which took place annually at the common grazing grounds of Bahr al Arab was reduced to the minimum. The Dinka settled in the north were asked to return so that “a more complete separation could be enforced.” A

Pass System, similar to that applied in South

Africa, was applied, in order to control the contact between north and south. In a meeting held at

Kafia Kingi on 14 February, 1940, between District

Commissioner, Western District, Bahr al Ghazal, and his counterpart in Darfur, it was agreed that only those Northerners who had passes signed by the District Commissioner would be allowed to enter Raga District.

151

The British colonial project shaped and changed the very nature of the organization of resistance through the mechanism of law. This included the Closed District Ordinances, an administrative division of Darfur into tribal homelands, and the imposition of a dual system of governance, one in the north and a different one in the south.

152

This project defined individuals

and grouped them into categories and enforced the distinction in law.

153

The policy laid by the British in the early 20th century

in Sudan also explains the cycle of violence in Darfur in the west

151 B ESHIR , T HE S OUTHERN S UDAN : B ACKGROUND TO C ONFLICT , supra note

67, at 51.

152 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 40

153 M AMDANI , S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12, at 152-63.

533

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 of the country and the deadlock over the disputed regions, with

Abyei being the most contested area.

154

So explosive is the

dispute over Abyei that it is instructive to compare it to yet another explosive and unresolved dispute between India and

Pakistan over Kashmir.

155

Abyei has already proved to be a

destabilizing force for North and South Sudan. Without reaching a region-wide consensus, which will settle the underlying issues over political participation and access to pasture and land, Abyei may end up turning into Sudan’s

‘Kashmir’.

156

The problem in Abyei between the Ngok, Dinka

and the Misseriya, and the conflict between the Camel Nomads of the north in Darfur and the agriculturalists in Southern

Darfur, is that the demand for tribal homeland in South Sudan revolves around the same issues: political representation, access to pasture for cattle, and claims to a tribal homeland being advocated for on behalf of the tribe.

157

Without resolving the

underlying issues, the violence will not subside. Instead, the frequency and intensity of the new waves of violence will be far more deadly, given that the region is heavily armed, and because the central governments in North and South Sudan do not have a monopoly over arms as demonstrated by the outstanding rebellions currently underway in western Sudan (Justice and

Equality Movement, or “JEM”, SLM/A, and the several armed militias in the Republic of South Sudan).

158

The regions have not been thoroughly demilitarized. Militias have not been completely disarmed and reintegrated into the armed forces or society.

159

The central governments in Khartoum and Juba have

154 Id.

155 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 46.

156 Id.

157 Flint, supra note 27, at 32.

158 Southern Dissident Militias, S MALL A RMS S URVEY S UDAN .

ORG , http://www.smallarmssurveysudan.org/facts-figures-armed-groupssouthern-sudan-emerging.php (last updated July 2011); Southern Dissident

Militias, T HE S UDAN H UMAN S ECURITY B ASELINE A SSESSMENT P ROJECT , http://www.smallarmssurveysudan.org/facts-figures-armed-groupssouthern-sudan-emerging.php (last updated July 2011).

534

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 not acquired total monopoly or control over arms and traffic of weapons into the region.

Land has always been an asset in Africa. It is the source for livelihood for the mass of the peasantry. With British indirect rule, access to land, and participation and representation in local governance, was assigned to native authorities who administered land and settled local disputes.

160

Violence in the postcolonial period cannot be understood as revolutionary or counter-revolutionary.

161

This violence does not fit into existing

paradigms because it is not based on non-market distinctions.

162

It is not animated by class distinction.

163

It is rather the outcome of a distinction made by the state and inscribed in law.

164

It

must be understood as a result of a particular mode of organizing the colonized. It is the outcome of the process of state formation.

165

Furthermore, the kind of violence that is

ethnic in character, whereby the battle lines are not drawn by wealth or poverty,

166

cannot be solved by a top-down approach,

foreign aid, development assistance, or military intervention.

167

This is because, to use the words of Frantz Fanon, postcolonial violence pits the “Wretched of the Earth” against each other, the

159 L YDIA S TONE , F AILURES AND O PPORTUNITIES : R ETHINKING DDR IN

S OUTH S UDAN 1-3 (May 2011), available at http://www.smallarmssurveysudan.org/pdfs/HSBA-SIB-17-Rethinking-

DDR-in-South-Sudan.pdf.

160 L UGARD , supra note 145, at 203.

161 M AMDANI , C ITIZEN AND S UBJECT , supra note 90, at 1-2.

162 Mamdani, Making Sense of Non-Revolutionary Violence, supra note

72, at 2.

163 Id.

164 Id.

165 See I DRIS , supra note 12, at 23-41.

166 Mamdani, Making Sense of Non-Revolutionary Violence, supra note

72, at 1.

167 See F RANTZ F ANON , T HE W RETCHED OF THE E ARTH (C. Farrington trans., 1963).

535

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 poor against the poor, and the disempowered against the disenfranchised.

168

Wealth and poverty are not the determining factors, but rather non-economic factors are the driving force fueling and sustaining what Mamdani has called “nonrevolutionary violence.”

169

The base of this violence was laid in

the colonial period. Its legacy and institutions were inherited at independence by nationalists.

170

Rather than reform the institutions inherited at independence, African states have struggled over the past five decades to fix what colonialism left behind. Some countries have demonstrated the will to move forward after the tragedy of colonial administration.

171

In the

last section, I want to return to the conceptual framework of the

New Sudan, pioneered by the late Dr. John Garang, as an alternative nation-building project.

172

I will argue that this

alternative offers the best solution to the problems of the Sudan in the north, the south, and in the disputed border regions. I will contextualize the discussion by drawing on the experience in

South Africa, where violence was brought to an end without resorting to criminal justice. In this light, the CPA can be seen first and foremost as a political settlement, which brought 21 years of war to an end without anyone standing trial.

NEW SUDAN: A WAY FORWARD

The current study of Sudan suffers from an epistemological weakness, lack of familiarity with the history of the country, and too much emphasis on political systems rather than critically

168 Id.

169 Mamdani, Making Sense of Non-Revolutionary Violence, supra note

72, at 1.

170 See id. at 16-17.

171 In East Africa, the best case that illustrates a successful reform of the colonial state is that of Tanzania under the leadership of President Nyerere.

In his keynote address to the East African Legislative Assembly Symposium in June 2011, Mamdani observed that it is the only country in the region where a group has not been persecuted collectively on a racial or ethnic base.

172 J OHN G ARANG , T HE C ALL FOR D EMOCRACY IN S UDAN 118-42 (Mansour

Khalid, ed., 2nd ed. 1992).

536

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 analyzing the foundation upon which the postcolonial institutions are built.

173

The notion that the conflict in Sudan is

one between Arabs and Africans, Muslims and Christians, north and south,

174

can be partially explained by historicizing the legacy of the late colonialism in shaping the very landscape in which debate takes place. No one understood this problem better than Dr. John Garang, who pioneered the vision and concept known as the New Sudan. In redefining the problem in

Sudan from the problem of the south, Garang effectively included all marginalized regions in the struggle for liberation and reform of power at the center.

175

The national identity crisis of whether Sudan is African or Arab is a contested issue today.

In the North, the emphasis has been placed on the Arab/Islamic character of the state.

176

With the secession of the south, the

tendency in the north has been to consolidate the Arab identity while silencing all marginal identities within the north.

177

The opposite phenomenon is taking place in the south where the

173 I DRIS , supra note 12, at 3.

174 Framing the conflict in Sudan as one between “Arabs and Africans,”

“Muslim and Christians,” and “north and south” is misleading. Garang attempted to shift this paradigm by contextualizing the conflict and providing an alternative history and causes of the conflict by linking the cause to a particular form of the state and demanding that power be fundamentally restructured. One of the successes of the SPLM/A under Garang was to redefine the problem in national rather than regional terms. Other scholars have also challenged the radicalized history, which has been dominant in the colonial and postcolonial period. For alternative explanations, see M AMDANI ,

S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12; I DRIS , supra note 12; G ARANG , T HE

C ALL FOR D EMOCRACY IN S UDAN , supra note 172; D ENG , W AR OF V ISIONS , supra note 37; G.

N ORMAN A NDERSON , S UDAN IN C RISIS : T HE F AILURE OF D EMOCRACY

(1999).

175 G ARANG , T HE C ALL FOR DEMOCRACY IN S UDAN , supra note 172, at 118-42.

176 I DRIS , supra note 12.

177 The current crisis in the disputed border regions and the violence in

Darfur are illustrative of the tendency to consolidate an Arab identity while silencing other ethnicities in the north. South Kordofan and Darfur have some of the most diverse, multiethnic, pluralistic communities in the north and west of Sudan. The government in Khartoum has been trying to group these diverse nationalities under one umbrella, Arabs.

537

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 elites have moved quickly to shape the identity of the country as

African, secular and black. It has been noted that this struggle for national identity has been one of the contributing factors to the violence in Sudan.

178

He wrote: “This multiple denial of a

Sudan which is uniquely Sudanese and not an appendage to

Arabism, Islamicism or Africanism lies at the root of the political problems of the ‘Sudan.’"

179

Most scholars dismiss the

easy and simplified answer, which is characteristic of the way the problems in Sudan have been reported in the media.

180

Norman Anderson rightly dismissed the notion that the problem is ‘Arabs’ against ‘Africans’ and claimed that the relationship between the ‘Arab’ and the ‘African’, north and south, is complex.

181

Sudan has a historical relationship with the outside

world, including the Mediterranean and Arabia, predating recorded history. During the Islamic era, Muslim Arabs chose to intermarry and assimilate rather than rely on conquest and force.

182

Garang took this vision a bit further in his analysis of

what constituted the problems of Sudan and offered a model of nation-building rooted in the concepts of unity in diversity, respect for human rights and rule of law, equitable distribution of national resources, devolution of power from the center to historically marginalized regions, and value of multiple identities. Sudan is a melting pot of nationalities, religions, and languages.

183

There will be no peace if some groups feel

marginalized, intimidated, and territorially besieged. The

178 S HORT -C UT TO D ECAY , supra note 18, at 14.

179 Id.

180 See, generally, Peter K. Bechtold, Darfur, the ICC and American

Politics, 16 M IDDLE E.

P OL ’ Y 149 (2009); Ammina Kothari, The Framing of

the Darfur Conflict in The New York TImes: 2003-2006, 11 J OURNALISM

S TUD . 209 (2010).

181 A NDERSON , supra note 174.

182 M AMDANI , S AVIORS AND S URVIVORS , supra note 12, at 200;

C HRISTOPHER Z AMBAKARI , South Sudan and the nation-building project:

Lessons and challenges, International Journal of African Renaissance

Studies - Multi-, Inter- and Transdisciplinarity (Forthcoming April 16, 2012),

8 (2012).

183 G ARANG , T HE C ALL FOR D EMOCRACY IN S UDAN , supra note 172, at 127.

538

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 problem can be seen in regions that have people with multiple identities: Abyei, Kordofan, Nuba Mountains and Blue Nile. Dr.

Amir Idris, Associate Professor of African Studies and Associate

Chair of the Department of African and African American

Studies at Fordham University, captured this dilemma recently in the Sudan Tribune. He wrote:

I was born and raised in the north by two parents who came from two different worlds. My father came from southern Sudan and my mother was born and raised in the north. I married a woman who is a southern Sudanese. Our two children are proud to define themselves as

Canadian.

184

Despite the independence of the south, South Sudan is still linked to the north socially and economically.

185

Oil makes up

98% percent of government income in South Sudan.

186

Though

the oil fields are located in the south, the port and refineries are located in the north.

187

The south is so inextricably linked to the north that it can be argued that the south cannot find peace if the north is unstable, and the opposite can be seen as true for the north. The difficulty can be seen in the attempt to solve the problem in Abyei. The referendum on self-determination did not undo relationships forged historically over thousands of

184 Amir Idris, I Hate to Choose: Personal Reflections on the

Referendum, S UDAN T RIBUNE , Nov. 21, 2010, available at http://www.sudantribune.com/I-hate-to-Choose-Personal,37003.

185 The CPA mandated that oil revenue be shared equally between the two parties to the agreement during the interim period. G LOBAL W ITNESS ,

F UELLING M ISTRUST : T HE N EED FOR T RANSPARENCY IN S UDAN ’ S O IL I NDUSTRY 4

(Sept. 2009), available at http://www.globalwitness.org/library/fuellingmistrust-need-transparency-sudans-oil-industry. Agreements over the distribution of oil revenue in post-CPA era have not been finalized. The government in South Sudan depends heavily on revenue from oil, which accounts for 98% of its income. Id. at 7, 17.

186 Id.

187 Id. at 5.

539

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 years, and it did not change the social and cultural fabric of the country.

188

Rather than to prematurely de-link all relationships between the north and south, Sudan can learn a lesson from the South

African experience where violence was effectively brought to an end, and an inclusive political community, which accounts for the diversity within South Africa, was created and inaugurated with the first election in 1994. South Africa, like Sudan, had the option to perpetuate an endless war or reach a political settlement. It opted for the latter. The terms of the settlement are instructive in settling the crisis in the disputed regions and all marginalized areas in Sudan. The solution in north and

South Sudan demands a similar political imagination like the one in South Africa. A research specialist in South Africa notes this imagination:

“ it was the fact that the contending political forces imagined the future of what South African citizenship might look like after apartheid, and that this imagination was shaped by the historical particularity of state formation in South

Africa, by both its limits and its possibilities.”

189

This political imagination, crucial in propelling South Africa forward, was summarized in South Africa’s Freedom Charter of

1955. The Charter presented a vision of South Africa that is similar to what Garang envisioned for Sudan, and declared:

“that South Africa belongs to all who live in it, black and white, and that no government can justly claim authority unless it is based on the will of all the people.”

190

In 1994, Mandela

reiterated the concept and premise of the new South Africa. He identified what appears to be the Achilles heel of the nationbuilding project throughout Africa in noting that the challenge today for political leaders was “to build a nation in which all people - irrespective of race, colour, creed, religion or sex - can assert fully their human worth; after apartheid, our people

188 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 48.

189 Suren Pillay, The Political Imagination of State Reform: Reflections on the Making of Political Community after Apartheid in South Africa,

CODESRIA B ULL ., no. 1 & 2, 2010, at 35, available at http://www.codesria.org/spip.php?article1209&lang=en.

190 The Freedom Charter, A FR .

N AT ’ L C ONG .,

http://www.anc.org.za/show.php?id=28 (last visited Feb. 16, 2012).

540

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 deserve nothing less than the right to life, liberty and pursuit of happiness.”

191

Mandela also warned that failure to properly manage diversity within an inclusive framework was a recipe for disaster, which destroys the human capital and the potentials of citizens. The New Sudan vision as presented at the Koka Dam

Conference on March 20, 1986, was a conceptual framework for a country that was inclusive of all its multiple ethnic groups, and embracing all nationalities, races, creeds, religions, and genders.

192

It was a country in which all Sudanese were equal stakeholders.

193

Specifically, the New Sudan, as initiated by the signing of the CPA, was a country voluntarily united in justice, honor and dignity for all its citizens, regardless of their race, religion, or gender.

194

To turn the vision into reality required a

shift of historical significance, not only in Sudan, but also in

Africa. Given the legacy discussed in this paper, most countries in Africa have failed to fully reform and move beyond the colonial state and its institutional apparatus, reforming both the center and the sphere of customary authority, which has remained mostly intact since independence. The proposed

Second Republic is a move away from defining the problem in ethnic or regional terms, and defining it in national terms, hence

Garang’s insistence that there was no southern problem, but rather a national problem in Sudan.

195

This national problem will remain in both the north and the south as long as the institutions at the national and local level of governance remain unreformed.

In South Africa, the African National Congress realized that victory was not possible. It also acknowledged that apartheid

South Africa was a racially exclusive state. The solution was not in re-racializing the post-apartheid state through a demand for a black majority, but rather, de-racializing and reforming the

191 Nelson Mandela, The Future of South Africa, A FR .

N AT ’ L C ONG . (Mar.

1, 1994), http://www.anc.org.za/show.php?id=3652.

192 G ARANG , T HE C ALL FOR D EMOCRACY IN S UDAN , supra note 172, at 118.

193 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 49.

194 G ARANG , supra note 172, at 118.

195 Id. at 125-28.

541

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 state.

196

The limit of the South African transition from apartheid

to a post-apartheid democratic system is that it managed to deracialize the civil services and the state at the center, but it continues to uphold the customary sphere without reforming it in the name of tradition. Such is the limit in South Africa, but that is a problem that it is working out as it moves forward. The lesson of South Africa is “[i]t recognized that all belonged and that the creation of a single political community was the goal.

Race, ethnicity and history defined the answer in the past, but will not define it in the future.”

197

“For north and South Sudan, those who will pay allegiance to the national flag, those who choose to have a common future not bound by the past, those

Sudanese who chose to live side by side as friends and neighbors, will have to put the past aside and work for a peaceful common future.”

198

That the living must be prioritized

over the dead is the lesson of South Africa.

199

South Africa

belongs to “belongs to all who live in it.”

200

North and South

Sudan belong to the North and South Sudanese.

CONCLUSION

This paper started by demonstrating the successes of the

CPA, which established the Interim Constitution of Southern

Sudan, and effectively ended the war between the north (NCP) and South Sudan (SPLA/M). The CPA, enacted in 2005, formed the semi-autonomous GOSS in the southern part of the Republic of Sudan, and effectively ended the violence that has devastated

Sudan since 1955. A brief history of Sudan was offered to provide a background to the rest of the paper. Next, the plight

196 Pillay, supra note 189, at 37.

197 Id.

198 Zambakari, Nation-Building, supra note 91, at 50.

199 Mahmood Mamdani, Columbia Univ., Lessons of Nuremberg and

Codesa: Where Do We Go From Here? (July 14, 2010), available at http://humanities.ufs.ac.za/dl/userfiles/Documents/00000/98_eng.pdf.

200 A FRICAN N ATIONAL C ONGRESS , T HE F REEDOM C HARTER (1955),

available at http://www.anc.org.za/show.php?id=72.

542

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 of IDPs and refugees was presented, illustrating the daunting task of managing the inflow of displaced people in the various parts of Sudan.

The number of South Sudanese living in the north ranges from 1.5 million to 2 million, and a large number of them will not return to the south due to the difficult living conditions and current instability in the region. Among the key issues that affect both the

GOSS and the GOS are the proliferation of ethnic violence, a disputed border region pending consultation, millions of IDPs stranded throughout the country, and over half a million refugees yet to find a permanent home. A case study was presented to illustrate the tendency for the proliferation of counties in South Sudan. It was argued that this mode of organizing the mass of peasantry preempts the creation of a truly inclusive state, and focuses on a mode of governance that produces many smaller ‘nation-states’ within the larger states in South Sudan. The division is built on the assumptions that the political map must follow the cultural map of a region at the national level and at the county level. The real problem with this logic is that no matter how many counties are created and how much the map of the country and region is redrawn, the political crisis will remain. This political crisis always leads to political violence.

The proliferation of ethnic violence in Sudan is best understood as an indispensable component of the process of state formation and colonial governmentality, deployed to colonize African colonies in the late 19th century. To move forward and pre-empt future violence requires political imagination to rethink an alternative future based on a common future, rather than a common past and descent. The solution for both governments in north and South Sudan is found in

Garang’s conceptual framework of the New Sudan,

201

which is consistent with the other successful case in the African context,

South Africa’s transition from apartheid to a democracy. The lesson of South Africa is the creation of a single political community inclusive of the diversity within the country. The

New Sudan vision is the most progressive attempt at reforming the state in Sudan. It theorizes a political reform of the colonial state in Sudan, the building of an inclusive community where citizens will not be discriminated against based on race, color, creed, religion, ethnicity or sex. Race, ethnicity and history

201 G ARANG , supra note 172, at 118-42.

543

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 defined the solutions in the past, but race and ethnicity will not define solutions in the future. The solutions to Sudan’s problems cannot be imposed by force; they cannot be externally imposed upon the Sudanese from outside. Any forceful and externally enforced solution has not worked in the past and will not work in the future.

544

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

THE PRICE OF JUSTICE:

HOW THE CAPERTON STANDARD FOR

JUDICIAL RECUSAL FELL SHORT, BUT

OPENED THE DOOR FOR REFORM OF THE

RECUSAL STANDARDS ANYWAY

Student Note

Marisa McGarvey

“It appears that justice is indeed for sale.” -- Hugh

M. Caperton

1

“Just as no man is allowed to be a judge in his own cause, similar fears of bias can arise when – without the consent of the other parties – a man

chooses the judge in his own cause.”

2

1 Hugh M. Caperton, Address at the National Judicial College’s “Electing

Nevada’s Judges: Protecting Impartiality and Ensuring Accountability (Oct.

18, 2010), in 48 D UQ .

L.

R EV .

727, 732 (2010). Mr. Caperton further stated, “I am a citizen that has experienced firsthand the devastation and destruction that big money campaign donations are causing in judicial elections and ultimately in our courts.” Id.

2 Caperton v. Massey Coal Co., 129 S. Ct. 2252, 2265 (2009) (emphasis added).

545

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

PART I: THE FACTS – JUDICIAL ELECTIONS IN

THE PAST, PRESENT, AND CAPERTON

A.

A B RIEF H ISTORY OF J UDICIAL E LECTIONS IN THE

U NITED S TATES

B.

T

HE

C

URRENT

S

TATE OF THE

N

ATION

C.

T

HE

C APERTON D

ECISION

PART II: THE LAW – THE VARYING STANDARDS

FOR JUDICIAL RECUSAL

A.

T HE P AST : T HE A CTUAL B IAS S TANDARD

B.

T HE P RESENT : T HE

C

APERTON S TANDARD

C.

T

HE

F

UTURE

: T

HE

A

PPEARANCE OF

B

IAS

S

TANDARD

INTRODUCTION

The role of a judge and his or her resulting discretion over a given case form a powerful and central feature of the legal system in the United States. While it is true that a case is

“decided” by a jury, the judge who hears the matter still wields a substantial degree of control over the proceedings, including often having the final say over sentencing.

3 Therefore, the mode

in which a judge comes to exercise this type of influence is similarly important. In fact, “the question of how we choose our

3 Matthew J. Streb, The Study of Judicial Elections, in R

UNNING FOR

J UDGE

: T HE R ISING P OLITICAL , F INANCIAL , AND L EGAL S TAKES OF J UDICIAL

E LECTIONS 3-4 (Matthew J. Streb ed., 2009), available at http://www.nyupress.org/webchapters/0814740340chapt1.pdf.

546

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 judges, whom we entrust to uphold and interpret our laws, speaks to foundational principles of our judicial branch . . . and our nation as a whole.”

4

In “the vast majority of states,” the preferred mode of selection for at least some judgeships is by way of judicial elections.

5

However, the common law rule only dictated that a judge’s recusal from a matter be mandatory when said judge had a direct, personal, and/or pecuniary interest in the matter

before him.

6 It may be that the common law at the time did not

contemplate an era when corporations would be permitted to contribute staggering amounts of money toward judicial elections, and thereafter be called to appear in court before a judge who is aware of the “debt of gratitude”

7 he now owes to

the corporation for facilitating his elevation to the bench.

The reader may wonder how it is that the Constitution could tolerate such an appearance of bias, whether the bias be real or not, and the Supreme Court ultimately addressed the issue in

2009, in Caperton v. Massey Coal Co.

8 While said decision did

not explicitly overrule any precedent, it also clearly represented a shift in the law with respect to when recusal becomes mandatory, rather than merely discretionary. This shift is twofold, as the Court both expanded the factual reach of the due process requirement for recusal and clarified this recusal standard as being objective, rather than subjective as under the common law. These two developments now permit constitutional law to address certain circumstances where the

“interest” of the judge at issue cannot be directly tied to the case at hand, in order to reach situations where there is a substantial

4 Justice Sandra Day O’Connor, Keynote Address at the Seattle University

School of Law Symposium, State Judicial Independence – A National

Concern (Sept. 14, 2009), in 33 S EATTLE U.

L.

R EV . 559, 561 (2010).

5 See Streb, supra note 3, at 7. In fact, “[a]lmost 90 percent of all state judges must face voters” at some point in order to remain seated on the bench. Id.

6 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2255.

7 See id. at 2262.

8 Id. at 2252.

547

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 probability that a reasonable person would in fact be biased,

“directness” of the connection with the case notwithstanding.

The following note shall attempt to analyze and clarify the various standards for recusal, including the constitutional minimum standard when a litigant has contributed financially to the campaign of the judge assigned to the contributor’s case, as set forth by the Court in Caperton.

9 In Part I, this note will

briefly detail the history of judicial elections in this country, provide an overview of some current practices in this area, and then relate a more detailed description of the facts in the

Caperton case itself. In Part II, this note shall examine and evaluate the proposed and actual standards that have been used in order to regulate judicial recusal in the past and present, to wit: the old “actual bias” standard; the somewhat confusing

“probability of bias” standard enacted via Caperton; and the

“mere appearance of bias” standard used by many states and recommended by the American Bar Association, among others.

Lastly, in Part III, this note will look at certain proposed solutions that may function to better protect against corruption than judicial election methods as presently employed.

PART I: THE FACTS – JUDICIAL ELECTIONS IN

THE PAST, PRESENT, AND CAPERTON

A.

A B RIEF H ISTORY OF J UDICIAL E LECTIONS IN THE

U NITED S TATES

Criticism of judicial elections is not a new phenomenon.

Alexander Hamilton clearly vocalized the concern of many of the

Founding Fathers that such a system of selection plainly jeopardized the judiciary’s ability to remain independent and impartial.

10 This risk was highlighted by what America had

learned from the example of England and the contentious interplay between an independent judiciary and a royal sovereign.

11

Such concern, evidently still relevant today, formed

9 Id.

10 Streb, supra note 3, at 8.

11 Id.

548

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 the basis of the Founders’ implementation of the federal system of executive appointment of judges, subject to legislative confirmation, for lifetime terms.

12 In addition, all thirteen

original colonies also adopted systems of judicial appointment rather than election.

13

During the mid-1800s, however, the country experienced a relatively rapid shift in the years leading up to the Civil War, and more and more states chose to switch to an election process to select the judiciary.

14

In fact, by the time of the Civil War, out of thirty-four states in the Union, twenty-four states had made the switch and turned away from judicial appointment.

15

There have been a myriad of reasons offered by scholars for this dramatic shift in the political process, but most of the explanations offered are rooted in the general attitude of the

American people. This was a time now known by the advent of

Jacksonian democracy, an era that was marked by a surge in support for popular participation in government, which included expansion of the voting pool to include more of the public.

16 This increase in public participation was at least in

part based upon popular resentment for the land-owning class,

12 Id.

13 Id. Seven of the original thirteen states utilized legislative appointment, while five adopted gubernatorial appointments, subject to approval by special legislative committees. Id. at 8-9. Lastly, Delaware copied the federal model, gubernatorial appointment with legislative confirmation. Streb, supra note 3, at 9.

14 Id. at 9. Mississippi was the first such state, amending the state constitution in 1832 to reflect the new requirement of popular election as to all state judges. Id. New York was the second state to do so in 1846, and thereafter the floodgates opened, such that by 1850, seven states had switched to judicial elections in that year alone. Id. In stark contrast to the states that joined the Union pre-1830, the remainder of states who were admitted to the Union from 1846 until Alaska in 1959, all provided for judicial elections at least in some respects. Id.

15 Id.

16 Streb, supra note 3, at 9.

549

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 who were thought to be in control of the judiciary, and a corresponding rise in efforts to end class-based privileges.

17

The early 1900s brought a new wave of criticism of judicial selection methods, specifically as to popular elections, from new political groups such as the Progressives, joined by the American

Bar Association, still aimed at eliminating corruption on the

18

The subsequent outcry led to the introduction of nonbench.

partisan elections in certain states, where ballots only contained candidates’ names and did not list his or her associated political party.

19

This was seen as a compromise between attempts to eliminate the rampant corruption present in most big-city politics at the time, while still maintaining judicial accountability directly to the voting public.

20 In 1927, non-

partisan elections were being utilized for judicial selection in twelve of the forty-eight states.

21 However, these states were to

quickly learn by example that this did not provide the muchneeded panacea for political malfeasance on the bench.

Non-partisan elections did not appear to be the solution, as demonstrated by the three states that adopted and then quickly abandoned the process in 1927 in favor of switching back to partisan elections.

22

A main concern that led to this switch was

17 Larry C. Berkson, Judicial Selection in the United States:

A Special Report, A M .

J UDICATURE S OC ’ Y , http://www.judicialselection.us/uploads/documents/

Berkson_1196091951709.pdf (last visited Mar. 21, 2012)

(updated by Rachel Caufield and Malia Reddick).

18 Id. Such criticism of the popular election method was voiced as early as 1853 at the Massachusetts Constitutional Convention, where delegates deemed the method a failure as implemented in New York, and refused to adopt the same. Id.

19 Streb, supra note 3, at 10. It is worth noting that the first nonpartisan judicial election was held in 1873, in Cook County, Illinois. Id.

20 Id.

21 Id.

22 Id. The three states that had abandoned judicial elections by 1927 were: Iowa, Kansas, and Pennsylvania (note that they are not included as part of the twelve states who were using judicial elections by 1927). Berkson,

supra note 17, at 2.

550

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 the lack of an informed electorate, as political party leaders still controlled the selection of candidates, who were “thrust upon an unknowledgeable electorate, which, without the guidance of party labels, was not able to make reasoned choices.”

23 In

response, the American Judicature Society proposed a new process: the retention election.

24

Exactly what it sounds like, a retention election simply posed to the voting public the issue of whether or not a certain judge should remain on the bench after his or her first allotted term had run.

25

Retention elections were to take place after a probationary period, with the judiciary initially being chosen via a merit selection plan, which openly acknowledged that the judicial candidate pool would be expanded so as to preclude consideration of “inappropriate partisan factors such as an individual’s party affiliation, party service, or friendship with an appointing executive.”

26

The advent of retention elections still represented efforts to balance the goal of having an independent judiciary while preserving judicial accountability to the people.

27

This system was first utilized in Missouri in 1940 and is the most common method used in the United States today although, of course, there are many variations thereof.

28

However, most modern retention election systems do have certain features in common, such as a non-partisan committee that recruits and screens potential candidates and thereafter submits to the appointing executive a short list, usually three to five candidates, from

23 Berkson, supra note 17, at 2.

24 Streb, supra note 3, at 10.

25 Id. at 10-11.

26 Berkson, supra note 17, at 2.

27 Streb, supra note 3, at 10-11.

28 Id. at 11. California was actually the first to utilize a merit selection plan in 1934; however, Missouri was the first to use this method as it is now known today in 1940, leading to its popular nickname, the “Missouri Plan.”

Id. It is still the mostly commonly used method, although there are differences that vary from state to state. Id.

551

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 which to choose, followed by an unopposed retention election a year or two after appointment.

29

B.

T HE C URRENT S TATE OF THE N ATION

In the United States, the only country in the world that elects judges, there are at least thirty-six states that utilize at least some form of judicial elections in their court systems.

30 This is

obviously more than a majority, and therefore, deserves some measure of scrutiny at least equal to that which is applied toward any potential for bias in legislative or executive branch elections. The commonality of the practice is much more troubling in light of the growing involvement of corporate money with respect to judicial elections in particular. Corporate entities have become more free to exercise their “First

Amendment rights” pursuant to recent Supreme Court decisions such as Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission

31 and

have seized upon their newfound opportunity in order to influence American politics in another, more hidden manner than the customary lobbying efforts directed toward legislatures.

32 In fact, the amount of contributions made toward

judicial campaigns in the past ten years is estimated to be in excess of $206 million, as compared with the mere $83 million in contributions raised during the 1990s.

33 Moreover, these

29 Berkson, supra note 17, at 2.

30 Id. “Eight states elect all of their judges in partisan elections, and seven states use partisan elections to elect some of their judges. Thirteen states use nonpartisan elections to select all of their judges . . . [and] eight states use nonpartisan elections to select some of their judges.” Id.

31 130 S. Ct. 876 (2010).

32 “Politics makes strange bedfellows and is often a seedy, if not downright ugly, process.” Keith R. Fisher, Selva Oscura: Judicial Campaign

Contributions, Disqualification, and Due Process, 48 D UQ .

L.

R EV . 767, 812

(2010).

33 David L. Baker, Foreword, 58 D RAKE L.

R EV .

657, 658 (2010) (citing

Matthew Mosk, Study Shows Money Flooding into Campaigns for State

Judgeships, ABC N EWS state-judgeships/story?id=10120048).

(Mar. 17, 2010), http://abcnews.go.com/Blotter/study-shows-money-flooding-campaigns-

552

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 figures appear to only represent so-called direct campaign contributions and do not take into account the independent expenditures made by corporate CEOs and the like.

34

Looking at such extreme numbers begs the question, how can the American people ensure that their judicial system is functioning properly as an independent branch of government, governed solely by the federal and state constitutions, statutes, and common law? How can the public be assured that judges are not falling into the common trap laid for legislators, that of being swung by money and special interest groups far away from the truth, at the price of justice itself?

35

It seems almost too obvious that “[t]he advent of more money presents more potential for [judicial] recusals and an even greater need for standards for ensuring judicial independence, impartiality, and integrity.”

36

However, it is common for states to provide for subjective levels of inquiry to determine whether a judge will choose to recuse himself, historically making it “largely a personal decision for judges.”

37

An example of one such subjective standard is the pre-Caperton standard for West Virginia courts, wherein recusal was mandated whenever a judge determined that his impartiality

“might reasonably be questioned.”

38

While this standard sounded strict in theory, one was left to wonder what it actually looked like in practice, as generally only the judge himself was left to make and review the decision as to whether or not to recuse himself, based upon his own ability to be impartial. This

34 James Sample, Court Reform Enters the Post-Caperton Era, 58 D RAKE

L.

R EV .

787, 791-92 (2010).

35 To continue on with the theme of rhetorical questions, as one author so eloquently phrased the struggle that the Caperton Court faced, “in the face of well-documented public mistrust of judges continuing to sit and hear cases in such circumstances, as part of more widespread public concerns about the fairness and impartiality of our courts, would applying due process limitations allay those concerns or exacerbate them?” Fisher, supra note 32, at 790-91.

36 Baker, supra note 33, at 658.

37 Id.

38 W. Va. Code of Judicial Conduct Canon 3E(1) (1993).

553

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 circular logic has been accused of rendering “useless the ability of the court to act in any way that resemble[s] a fair tribunal.”

39

How have standards, such as the foregoing, fared insofar as their effectiveness in achieving recusal is concerned, in cases where a potential for bias arises? One example of this type of standard in play occurred in Wisconsin in 2007, where a judicial run-off resulted in the election of Annette Ziegler. Ziegler received in excess of two million dollars from the lobbying group

Wisconsin Manufacturers & Commerce (“WMC”), which by itself was greater than the sum total of her official campaign monies.

40

WMC then expended their corporate funds on financing an appeal for, and writing an amicus brief in support of, a tax refund case worth $350 million, in which Ziegler subsequently wrote the 4-3 decision, cast in favor of WMC’s position.

41 The only surprise in this case was that Ziegler was

previously disciplined while serving as a lower court judge, for failing to recuse herself on eleven different cases that concerned a bank where her husband happened to be a director.

42

Apparently, this prior impropriety did not prove to be an impediment to her later election to the high court. In the words of the now-famous plaintiff Hugh Caperton, “so much for due process.”

43

If only the 2007 Wisconsin election was the exception instead of the rule; however, developments in other areas of the country undermine that naïve hope. By way of example, in a

2004 election in Illinois, Lloyd Karmeier went on to win the socalled ‘tort wars’ after receiving over a million dollars in contributions stemming from connections to State Farm

Insurance Company, in a heated race between the US Chamber of Commerce-backed Karmeier, and Gordon Maag, supported

39 Caperton, supra note 1, at 731.

40 Sample, supra note 34, at 795.

41 Id. at 796.

42 Id. at 795-96.

43 Caperton, supra note 1, at 731.

554

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 by trial lawyer groups.

44

Approximately ten million dollars were spent overall between the two candidates.

45

Upon his win,

Karmeier thereafter cast the deciding vote in State Farm’s appeal of a $450 million damage award, saving the company roughly half of a billion dollars, which some presume to have constituted the quid pro quo between them.

46

An enlightened Alabama rule now acknowledges the reality of the seeming inability of states to maintain a judicial election system that somehow addresses the very real danger of campaigns and the corresponding necessary funding, which can easily overcome the impartiality of the judiciary. The Alabama law requires, by way of motion, the automatic recusal of its circuit court judges in any case in which a party or his counsel contributed greater than $2,000 to the judge’s campaign.

47 This

rule certainly seems to make sense and likely contributes to upholding public confidence in that state’s courts. This is so because, even as to those judges who were not improperly influenced by their campaign contributors, the appearance of impropriety may still be conveyed to the public in many instances. A large part of the populace already cynically views our present day government as being controlled by “big money,” and in recent years this criticism has reached the judicial system as well.

48

Without the full confidence of the public at large, our legal system lacks any meaningful ability to enforce the law,

49

44 Adam Skaggs, Judging for Dollars, T HE N EW R EPUBLIC (April 3, 2010,

12:00 AM), http://www.tnr.com/article/politics/judging-dollars.

45 Streb, supra note 3, at 1.

46 Skaggs, supra note 44.

47 William E. Raftery, “The Legislature Must Save the Court from

Itself”?: Recusal, Separation of Powers, and the Post-Caperton World, 58

D RAKE L.

R EV .

765, 768 (2010).

48 See, e.g. Baker, supra note 33, at 660; Fisher, supra note 32, at 778

(discussing the “already widespread public perception that justice is for sale and that only the wealthy can expect to receive it.”); and Bert Brandenburg,

Big Money and Impartial Justice: Can They Live Together?, 52 Ariz. L. Rev.

207, 207 (2010) (discussing his concern that “[m]any Americans believe that justice is for sale.”).

555

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 and according to the plaintiff in Caperton, “[o]ur citizens have lost faith in our courts.”

50

The state of the nation’s judicial electoral systems has become such a concern that many members of the judiciary have voiced their aversion to the widely-felt and significant influence of corporate money. The Chief Justice of the Oregon Supreme

Court, Paul J. De Muniz, has stated that the reforms currently being proposed are not adequate to stem what he predicts to be the coming tide of “ugliness,” as he refers to “big money, partisanship, attack ads, etc.”

51 These were his remarks at a

conference that was celebrating that particular court’s 150th anniversary; hence, it is clearly a matter of great importance to him. In fact, the advice he gave “for the Oregon judiciary of the future” is to “add merit selection of judges to the discussion,” adding that this is a “public discussion that needs to begin now.”

52

49 This holds true regardless of the legitimacy and/or legal accuracy of a specific ruling or case. With respect to Caperton, one scholar noted, “[N]o matter whether the decision on the merits was right on the mark, nothing would shake the public perception that justice in West Virginia was for sale.”

Fisher, supra note 32, at 815. As to the topic generally, he went on to state that:

“[e]ven a biased judge can render a correct decision. Doing so, however, diminishes public confidence not only in the correctness of that particular decision but in the legitimacy of judicial decisionmaking in general. . . With so many fine legal minds misunderstanding the overriding importance of public perceptions of fairness and impartiality to the legitimacy of the judiciary itself, it is small wonder that recusal and disqualification law is in such disarray.”

Id. at 815-16.

50 Caperton, supra note 1, at 731. In other words, “[m]oney is money, and it’s all about the appearance.” Fisher, supra note 32, at 814.

51 Paul J. De Muniz, Chief Justice, Oregon Supreme Court, Past is

Prologue: The Future of the Oregon Supreme Court (Oct. 9, 2009), in 46

W ILLAMETTE L.

R EV .

415, 441 (2010).

52 Id. at 442.

556

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

C.

T HE

C

APERTON D ECISION

Perhaps the aforesaid elections were surprising because they took place in the United States of America, and not in some remote and isolated country where rampant corruption in the courtroom might unfortunately be expected. After all, our

Constitution guarantees due process to all, not to “some citizens, or citizens with lots of money, or citizens who support special interest groups that are spending millions on judicial elections; it says every citizen.”

53

In June of 2009, the Supreme Court agreed to hear a noteworthy case relating to judicial elections, in order to finally set some sort of national standard. Whether that standard will actually be efficient in halting the type of implicit bias resulting from large special-interest donations in support of judicial election campaigns is a question that will be addressed in Part II. As to the “extraordinary situation where the

Constitution require[d] recusal”

54 that mandated this

intervention by the highest Court in the land, the story begins at the Upper Big Branch Mine in West Virginia.

This mine set the scene for a verdict of liability for fraudulent misrepresentation, concealment, and tortious interference with existing contractual relations against the A.T. Massey Coal

Company and affiliates (collectively, “Massey”), who had, according to the jury findings, intentionally driven another company out of business.

55

This finding was rendered in 2002 by a West Virginia jury that awarded $50 million in compensatory and punitive damages against Massey. All of defendant’s post-trial motions disputing the verdict and the monetary award were denied by the trial court, which found that

Massey had acted intentionally and with “utter disregard” for the rights of plaintiffs.

56

Conveniently, subsequent to this disastrous verdict for

Massey, but prior to the lapsing of the permissible time for an appeal, the 2004 elections for the West Virginia Supreme Court

53 Caperton, supra note 1, at 727.

54 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2265.

55 Id. at 2257.

56 Id.

557

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 of Appeals occurred.

57

This is, of course, the same court in front of which Massey’s appeal ultimately landed. In hindsight, one can see how Massey’s chairman/CEO/president, Don

Blankenship, decided that the most efficient course of action was to support the campaign of Brent Benjamin, who was running against the incumbent Justice McGraw.

58

Naturally,

Blankenship did not stop with his $1,000 donation to

Benjamin’s campaign committee, an amount which is equal to the maximum allowable donation by statute. He additionally contributed approximately two and a half million dollars to a lobbying organization entitled “And For the Sake Of the Kids.”

Notwithstanding the nature of such a benign name being given to what could be termed a morally ambiguous cause, what can be proven by the facts is that Blankenship alone contributed more than two-thirds of the total monies raised by this group.

59

Lastly, Blankenship also spent in excess of half of a million dollars relative to independent expenditures such as direct mailings, television advertisements, etc.

60

Benjamin went on to win the election with 53.3% of the vote, and one can only assume at least in part due to the roughly three million dollars spent by Blankenship alone, which was “more than the total amount spent by all other Benjamin supporters and three times the amount spent by Benjamin’s own committee.”

61 Despite any negative implications the public may

have drawn from these excessive donations, Justice Benjamin denied plaintiffs’ motion to disqualify himself based on the alleged conflict in April of 2006.

62 Thereafter, in December

2006, Massey filed a petition to appeal the jury verdict, and the case was granted review by Supreme Court of Appeals.

63

In light

57 Id.

58 Id.

59 Id.

60 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2257.

61 Id.

62 Id.

63 Id. at 2258.

558

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 of the surrounding circumstances, it is perhaps not a surprise to learn that in November of 2007 the fifty million dollar verdict was reversed. It was a surprise to the plaintiff, Hugh Caperton, though, who has stated, “after nine years of delays, motions, pretrial hearings, depositions, and a trial that lasted over seven weeks . . . you are now finally sitting in front of the West Virginia

Supreme Court of Appeals hoping, that after all these years, justice will finally be served.”

64 Alas, there would be no justice

for Mr. Caperton, who alleged that his business had been completely destroyed by defendant Massey, and said that his feeling about the case “can only be described in one word -- sickening.”

65

The state Supreme Court’s reversal was accompanied by an opinion (joined by Justice Benjamin) that openly admitted that the defendants’ actions had “warranted the type of judgment rendered”

66

by the jury. Yet regardless of such an admission, the West Virginia Court still reversed the damage award, based upon certain vague procedural niceties, such as a contractual forum selection clause.

67 Notwithstanding any legal validity the

majority may have seen, “[i]t was the first time in the 147 year history of West Virginia that a jury award had been overturned on the grounds of forum selection,”

68

and therefore it was clearly an extraordinary decision. The dissent blatantly accused the majority’s opinion of being “morally and legally wrong.”

69

After the stunning reversal, plaintiffs again looked to disqualify certain justices hearing the matter, and one such

64 Caperton, supra note 1, at 728.

65 Id. at 727-29. Mr. Caperton’s actual remarks with respect to the collapse of his business were as follows: “[I]magine all of your hard work being destroyed by one of the nation’s largest coal companies, who coveted the business that you had worked so hard to build, not by using ethical competitive business practices, but by engaging in an illegal and fraudulent scheme that they had planned for years.” Id. at 727-28.

66 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2258.

67 Id.

68 Caperton, supra note 1, at 729-30.

69 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2258.

559

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 application was granted. Justice Maynard recused himself after photographs of his vacation taken with none other than Don

Blankenship were made public, a vacation which took place on the French Riviera, during the pendency of the case.

70

Similarly, on the other side, Justice Starcher recused himself pursuant to the defendants’ request, which was apparently based upon

Starcher’s “public criticism of Blankenship’s role in the 2004 elections.”

71 In fact, Justice Starcher even went so far in his

recusal memorandum as to urge Justice Benjamin to disqualify himself as well, but his colleague’s suggestion went unheeded.

72

Thus, it came to be that Justice Benjamin was then acting as the

Chief Justice with respect to the rehearing that the case was granted.

In his capacity as such, Justice Benjamin denied plaintiffs’ third motion for his disqualification, which was this time accompanied by a popular poll showing that over sixty-seven percent of West Virginia citizens doubted his ability to remain fair and impartial.

73 He then once again presided over a divided

court that reversed the damages award. This time the dissent went even further, calling the majority opinion “fundamentally unfair” and acknowledging that Justice Benjamin’s failure to recuse himself had led to “genuine due process implications arising under federal law.”

74 This in conjunction with the

accusation that “justice was neither honored nor served,”

75 may

perhaps have influenced the Supreme Court’s decision to grant

certiorari in this matter, which they later characterized as a set of “extreme facts” leading to a situation where the “probability of bias…[rose] to an unconstitutional level.”

76

Such a characterization constitutes a euphemism for what a

70 Id.

71 Id.

72 Id.

73 Id.

74 Id. at 2258-59.

75 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2258.

76 Id. at 2265.

560

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

“reasonable” citizen might have called this situation, and what the plaintiff in the case did call it – “a black eye on the judicial system.”

77

PART II: THE LAW – THE VARYING STANDARDS

FOR JUDICIAL RECUSAL

A.

T HE P AST : T HE A CTUAL B IAS S TANDARD

According to the Caperton Court, precedent with respect to judicial recusal mandated judicial recusal based on the notion of the “traditional common law prohibition on direct pecuniary interest . . . [and] a more general concept of interests that tempt adjudicators to disregard neutrality.”

78 Prior to Caperton, a

seminal case on this issue was Tumey v. Ohio,

79

where the Court held that due process only requires recusal in those instances where the common law rule - “a direct, personal, substantial, pecuniary interest”

80 - was triggered. Such was the case in

Tumey, where a mayor, who doubled as a judge, received supplemental compensation for convicting and prosecuting any violations of the state liquor trafficking prohibition.

81 The Court

stated that the general rule provided for disqualification was “an interest in the controversy,” but noted that the law was uncertain relative to “what the degree or nature of the interest must be.”

82 However, the mayor’s “direct personal pecuniary

interest in convicting the defendant who came before him for

77 Caperton, supra note 1, at 731.

78 Id. at 2260.

79 273 U.S. 510 (1927).

80 Id. at 523.

81 Id. at 518. The municipal regulation provided for this by permitting the mayor, deputy marshal, and certain others involved in the prosecution, to retain the amount of fees and costs that were to be paid by the defendant. Id.

Therefore, if the defendant was not convicted and ordered to pay, there were no funds from which to additionally compensate the mayor et al.

82 Id. at 522.

561

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 trial, in the $12 of costs imposed in his behalf” was found to be sufficient as a violation of the constitutional guarantee of due process.

83

Unfortunately, the Court did not provide future litigators with much specificity as to that requisite degree or nature of the interest; however, they did distinguish a situation where the “[i]nterest is so remote, trifling, and insignificant that it may fairly be supposed to be incapable of affecting the judgment of . . . an individual.”

84 Beyond these remote

interests, it was held to deprive a criminal defendant of due process “to subject his liberty or property to the judgment of a court, the judge of which has a direct, personal, substantial pecuniary interest in reaching a conclusion against him.”

85 The

linchpin of the analysis was that the interest be “direct.”

Otherwise, ruled the Tumey Court, mandatory judicial recusal was left solely up to the discretion of state legislatures relative to

“mere” issues such as “kinship, personal bias, state policy, [and] remoteness of interest.”

86

In the same vein, mere personal bias or prejudice were consistently deemed to be insufficient so as to require recusal as a matter of due process, inasmuch as “the traditional commonlaw rule was that disqualification for bias or prejudice was not permitted,” based upon a circular legal presumption that judges

87

In fact, were impartial due to their sworn oath to be impartial.

those types of cases were stated as being exclusively within the purview of state legislative discretion.

88

By way of example, in

Lavoie, a state justice was required to recuse himself due to his standing as a lead plaintiff in a lawsuit pending before the trial court where the facts were substantially the same as those in the

83 Id. at 523.

84 Tumey, 273 U.S. at 523 (quoting Thomas M. Cooley & Victor H. Lane,

A T REATISE ON THE C ONSTITUTIONAL L IMITATIONS , 594 (7th ed. 1903)).

85 Id.

86 Id.

87 Aetna Life Ins. Co. v. Lavoie, 475 U.S. 813, 820 (1986).

88 Id. at 821 (citing Patterson v. New York, 432 U.S. 197, 201-02 (1977)).

562

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 appellate matter in which he cast the deciding vote.

89

Conversely, in addressing appellant’s other claim, the Court did not require recusal with regard to the other justices in that case, who were presumed to have “a slight pecuniary interest” in the case, as potential litigants in a class-action suit that could have resulted from the case at issue.

90

However, the Court distinguished the hypothetical instance as not mandating recusal because that interest was “too remote and insubstantial to violate the constitutional constraints.”

91

Lavoie is noteworthy as an intermediary case between

Tumey and Caperton because a careful reading of the matter shows the seeds out of which Caperton will grow. Although the

Lavoie Court states that the decision does not address “whether allegations of bias or prejudice by a judge . . . would ever be sufficient under the Due Process Clause to force recusal,” in the next breath it is acknowledged that in “the most extreme of cases” presenting an issue of bias, disqualification would in fact be constitutionally required.

92 Of course, the Lavoie Court

quickly went on to note that the case at hand fell “well below that level” and held that the basis of the decision was not “mere

89 Id. at 813-14. The defendant insurance company was sued for a bad faith refusal to pay a claim, and the verdict of three and a half million dollars in punitive damages awarded against them (the largest such punitive award ever in Alabama) was affirmed on appeal in an opinion authored by the justice at issue in Lavoie. Id. at 813. The company later learned, while the case had been pending, that the justice had filed two suits of his own against insurance companies for bad faith refusals to pay claims, also seeking punitive damages. Id. Therefore, the Supreme Court held that his affirmance in the underlying Lavoie matter “had the clear and immediate effect of enhancing both the legal status and the settlement value of his own case.” Id. at 814.

90 Lavoie, 475 U.S. at 814. The other justices were seen as potential litigants in a class-action suit filed by the later-disqualified justice inasmuch as the action was on behalf of all state employees insured under the group insurance plan. However, the Supreme Court deemed this to be “highly speculative and contingent” because the court hearing the class action suit had not yet even certified a class, “let alone awarded any class relief of a pecuniary nature.” Id.

91 Id. at 825-26.

92 Id. at 821.

563

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 allegations of bias and prejudice,” but rather, the Justice’s “more direct stake in the outcome.”

93 Still, the door was certainly left

open for future cases where the allegations of bias and prejudice could be held sufficient to establish a violation of due process.

In sum, to use the oft-quoted language by which the twentieth-century Supreme Court tested whether recusal is required, recusal was required in any situation that would “offer a possible temptation to the average man as a judge to forget the burden of proof . . . or which might lead him not to hold the balance nice, clear and true . . . .”

94 Yet, it is still a frequent

practice to permit the judge who has been asked to recuse himself to exercise total discretion over whether this standard has been triggered. Twenty-four states either explicitly permit a trial judge to hear his own recusal motion or are silent on the subject and therefore implicitly permit it.

95 Only fifteen states

require another judge to hear the matter either initially or at least in the event that the hearing judge declines to recuse himself.

96 The law is even more lenient for appellate judges, and

at least seven states do not overtly apply the trial court recusal rules to their appellate courts.

97 Thus one may conclude that

while in the past the Supreme Court used strong language to

93 Id. It may be of interest to the reader that prior to the Supreme Court’s hearing of this case, the Alabama justice at issue “retired from the court for health reasons.” Id. at 823 n.2.

94 Tumey, 273 U.S. at 532.

95 Raftery, supra note 47, at 767-68. Missouri and Oklahoma expressly permit the practice, while the laws of Alabama, Arizona, Connecticut,

Georgia, Hawaii, Indiana, Iowa, Kentucky, Minnesota, Mississippi, Nebraska,

New Hampshire, New York, Pennsylvania, Rhode Island, South Carolina,

Tennessee, Utah, Vermont, West Virginia, Wisconsin, and Wyoming are all silent on this issue. Id. at nn.5-6.

96 Id. at 768. The states that require another judge to hear the matter

(either initially or upon the hearing judge’s declining to recuse himself) are

Alaska, Arkansas, California, Colorado, Florida, Illinois, Louisiana, Montana,

Nevada, North Dakota, Oregon, South Dakota, Texas, Virginia, and

Washington. Id. at n.7.

97 Id. at 768. The following states have laws that do not expressly state that trial judge recusal rules also apply to appellate judges: Illinois, Kansas,

Nevada, North Carolina, Ohio, South Dakota, and Washington. Id. at n.16.

564

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 discuss the issue of judicial recusal, the actual standards that were set forth, for the most part, lacked the teeth for effective enforcement.

B.

T

HE

P

RESENT

: T

HE

C APERTON S

TANDARD

The Court achieved a subtle shift in the way one can interpret precedent for mandatory recusal through the holding of Caperton. While the standard enacted therein is still objective, and the Court effected this shift without the outright overruling of any cases, Caperton noted that the Court has identified since Tumey “additional instances, which, as an objective matter, require recusal.”

98

The shift in the standard is termed subtle because whereas prior to this decision, language was employed to imply the requirement of actual bias, as under the common law, the Caperton court re-framed the inquiry, to examine whether under the circumstances, “experience teaches that the probability of actual bias on the part of the judge or decisionmaker is too high to be constitutionally tolerable.”

99

Seemingly for the first time, the Court boldly held that under its objective standard, recusal may still be constitutionally required in some instances “whether or not actual bias exists or can be proved.”

100

Some have posited that the novelty of the decision stems partly from the Court’s allowance of solely the past connection between Justices Benjamin and Blankenship “to serve to create an assumption of bias” despite the fact that there was “no present or future effect on the judge.”

101

The Caperton Court further went on to specifically point out that even though Justice Benjamin of West Virginia “did undertake an extensive search for actual bias,” the inquiry did not stop there.

102 While still treading lightly, the Court did at

98 Caperton v. Massey Coal Co., 129 S. Ct. 2252, 2259 (2009).

99 Id. (citing Withrow v. Larkin, 421 U.S. 35, 47 (1975)) (emphasis added).

100 Id. at 2265.

101 Gerard J. Clark, Caperton’s New Right to Independence in Judges, 58

D RAKE L.

R EV .

661, 704-05 (2010).

102 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2265.

565

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 least acknowledge the complexity of a system that essentially relies on self-policing. “The difficulties of inquiring into actual bias, and the fact that the inquiry is often a private one, simply underscore the need for objective rules.”

103

This so-called private inquiry, reasoned the Court, was so difficult partially because it was possible for a judge who did not recuse himself to have “conducted a probing search into his actual motives and inclinations,” without finding anything to be improper,” although the Due Process Clause may have mandated otherwise.

104

The Caperton Court was careful to point out that there had been no claim of any overt quid pro quo arrangement, but in the same breath, they also recognized Blankenship had made “extraordinary” donations to a judicial campaign while having “a vested stake” in a case pending before the same judiciary.

105

Therefore, in the eyes of some commentators, the case was “purely circumstantial, relying on inference and supposition,”

106

but to others, such as this author, and perhaps the Court, the inference of bias was the only logical conclusion to be drawn from the facts.

An important detail in the Caperton decision was the Court’s holding regarding what was not relevant to recusal, i.e. “whether

Blankenship’s campaign contributions were a necessary and sufficient cause of Benjamin’s victory.”

107

Taking this to its logical conclusion, it seems as though in the future it will not be incumbent upon the party seeking recusal to have to prove any actual connection between the judicial win in the election and the financial contributions from an adverse party. This is another way in which the Court seems to speak in more relaxed language regarding the circumstances where judicial recusal must be required, by easing the burden of proof to that of a realistic level, inasmuch as the aforesaid connection between the victory and the money would likely be extremely difficult to demonstrate.

103 Id. at 2263.

104 Id.

105 Id. at 2265.

106 Clark, supra note 101, at 705.

107 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2264.

566

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Moreover, the Caperton court provided a list of factors for assistance in evaluating the new standard, and such factors are as follows: “the contribution’s relative size in comparison to the total amount of money contributed to the campaign, the total amount spent in the election, and the apparent effect such contribution had on the outcome of the election.”

108

Again, this is a subtle but distinct shift away from the previous decisions, which spoke harshly of needing to prove an actual pecuniary interest of the judge was involved before he would be forced to recuse himself. In Caperton, by contrast, the Court highlights certain aspects that make the case ripe for recusal, which will surely provide guidance to future litigators and the judiciary themselves. “The temporal relationship between the campaign contributions, the justice’s election, and the pendency of the case is also critical,” said the Court, emphasizing the reasonable foreseeability that the Caperton appeal would land in front of the new justice, which existed at the time the contributions were being made.

109

Of course, the Caperton Court also addressed concerns that had been raised over the potential flood of litigation involving judicial recusal that could have resulted from the decision.

Several times it was noted how rare the circumstances that had presented themselves in Caperton really were: “[n]ot every campaign contribution by a litigant or attorney creates a probability of bias that requires a judge’s recusal, but this is an exceptional case.”

110 An attempt was made to create a definite

bright-line around constitutionally-required recusal, as opposed to recusal which may be called for merely by the standards of professional ethics, by citing to precedent indicating that such constitutionally-required recusal was only mandated in those extremely atypical cases where “the probability of actual bias is too high to be constitutionally tolerable.”

111

108 Id.

109 Id. at 2264-65.

110 Id. at 2263.

111 Id. at 2257 (quoting Withrow v. Larkin, 421 U.S. 35, 47 (1975)).

567

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3

Nevertheless, despite the limitations that were placed around its holding, Caperton was a significant case because, as the

Court itself stated, for the first time they were looking at the framework previously set up specifically in the “context of judicial elections” and not necessarily as presented “in the precedents we have reviewed and discussed.”

112 In addition, for

the first time something other than “a direct pecuniary interest” was held to be sufficiently influential so as to require a judge to recuse himself pursuant to the federal Constitution, and not merely vis-à-vis a state’s judiciary code or rules of professional responsibility. “Though not a bribe or criminal influence,

Justice Benjamin would nevertheless feel a debt of gratitude to

Blankenship for his extraordinary efforts to get him elected.”

113

This phrase will surely be used in future litigation as symbolic of the many indirect ways in which a judge can be biased toward a case besides having a “direct” monetary stake in the case’s outcome.

In sum, while previously the Court had spoken of “an objective standard,” it was not until Caperton that the commonlaw burden of needing to show actual bias on the part of the judge was eliminated. The Caperton court clarified that from now on, the reviewing court must not look into the subjective existence of bias, but rather the objective likelihood of bias in that particular situation or whether there is an unconstitutional

“potential for bias.”

114

In particular, when the issue arises with respect to campaign contributions by a party, the court must look to see if there is a “serious risk of actual bias . . . when a person with a personal stake in a particular case had a significant and disproportionate influence in placing the judge on the case by raising funds or directing the judge’s election campaign when the case was pending or imminent.”

115

Despite the progress that was made in Caperton, it is still the law that the Constitution only requires judicial recusal under an

112 Id. at 2262.

113 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2262.

114 Id.

115 Id. at 2263-64.

568

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 extraordinary factual scenario, begging the question “what good a precedent on an extreme case does for the more run-of-themill cases with unjust results springing from judicial bias.”

116

Yet the very same opinion also urges state governments to enact broader rules, requiring recusal in many more situations. The

Caperton court explicitly advised states to do so based upon their vital state interest in maintaining public confidence in courts, and the importance of the same is demonstrated by way of a June 2010 poll done by the organization Justice at Stake, which revealed that eighty-one percent of Americans felt that a judge must not hear the case of anyone who contributed more than $10,000 to his campaign.

117

If this is the case, some commentators have wondered why the Supreme Court only went so far as to set this constitutional floor, expecting states to do the rest, instead of making the federal Constitution demand more as part of the guarantee of due process. Perhaps it is because “Caperton points out, in stark relief, the incompatibility of elected judges and the ideal of an independent judiciary,” and it may even be said more dramatically that “Caperton is at war with judicial elections.”

118

It may be that the Supreme Court, sensing this inevitability that

“[j]udges concerned about their reelection will not be independent . . . [and] will sacrifice justice and the rule of law to public opinion,”

119

was hesitant to go any further in essentially condemning what is the preferred practice for judicial selection in a majority of states.

C.

T HE F UTURE : T HE A PPEARANCE OF B IAS S TANDARD

Despite the Supreme Court’s failure to expressly implement the mere appearance of bias as the constitutional standard for judicial recusal, the Caperton decision certainly paves the way for such a standard in the future. The Court acknowledged in the decision that almost every state, including West Virginia, has

116 Clark, supra note 101, at 706.

117 Caperton, supra note 1, at 734.

118 Clark, supra note 101, at 705-06.

119 Id. at 706.

569

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 adopted the American Bar Association’s objective standard for recusal, and they urge the states to go further than the constitutional floor set in Caperton, presumably by strictly applying the ABA standard.

120

That standard is contained in the

Model Code of Judicial Conduct, and states that “[a] judge shall avoid impropriety and the appearance of impropriety.”

121

The comment to the 1990 Code further sets forth a test, “whether the conduct would create in reasonable minds a perception that the judge’s ability to carry out judicial responsibilities with integrity, impartiality and competence is impaired.”

122

While in theory this standard sounds as though it should be more than sufficient to redress concerns over an elected judiciary’s impartiality, apparently in practice it has not served this function, based upon instances such as those discussed in

Part I. Perhaps this is because the language of this standard, similar to other recusal standards, is highly vague. After all,

“[q]uestions about ‘impartiality’ or ‘public perception’ or ‘the average man as judge’ lack precision. The Supreme Court calls these standards ‘objective,’ but they are not. Imprecise standards provide uncertain guidance and invite disputes.”

123

This formed part of the concern for the Caperton dissent who argued that the majority decision was likely to lead to a flood of litigation. The dissent pointed out many seemingly benign situations that, according to them, might constitute a probability of bias under the Caperton standard. Clearly positing a slippery slope argument, the dissent stated that the following “could give rise to a ‘probability’ . . . of bias: friendship with a party or lawyer, prior employment experience, membership in clubs or associations, prior speeches and writings, religious affiliation, and countless other considerations.”

124

The dissenting opinion, written by Chief

Justice Roberts, also came up with forty difficult and complex

120 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2266.

121 M ODEL C ODE OF J UDICIAL C ONDUCT Canon 1 (2011) (emphasis added).

122 M ODEL C ODE OF J UDICIAL C ONDUCT Canon 2A cmt. (1990).

123 Clark, supra note 101, at 702.

124 Caperton, 129 S. Ct. at 2268 (Roberts, J., dissenting).

570

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 questions, regarding the meaning and scope of the majority decision’s language, that courts will now be forced to consider

“[w]ith little help from the majority.”

125

Of course, it is likely that a similar list of questions concerning the specifics of the rule could be formulated for almost any important Supreme

Court decision; however, this irony is lost on the Caperton dissent. Furthermore, courts engage in complicated analyses to decide cases on a regular basis, and there is no reason why they should not have to do so relative to the extremely important issue of judicial recusal. The issue is so important because it has the potential to undermine the fundamental basis of our legal system: that of free and fair access to the courts by any citizen.

While the dissent may have legitimate concerns and while the majority may have only imposed the absolute bare minimum as a constitutional standard, there is still hope for the future. In

125 Id. at 2269-72. By way of example, question number nine asks:

What if the case involves a social or ideological issue rather than a financial one? Must a judge recuse from cases involving, say, abortion rights if he has received

‘disproportionate’ support from individuals who feel strongly about either side of that issue? If the support wants to help elect judges who are ‘tough on crime,’ must the judge recuse in all criminal cases?

Id. at 2269.

Question number thirty-three queries:

What procedures must be followed to challenge a state judge’s failure to recuse? May Caperton claims only be raised on direct review? Or may such claims also be brought in federal district court under 42 U.S.C. § 1983, which allows a person deprived of a federal right by a state official to sue for damages? If § 1983 claims are available, who are the proper defendants? The judge? The whole court? The clerk of court?

Id. at 2271.

The remaining thirty-eight questions are similarly cumbersome. In fact, one scholar even inquired as to “whether some makeweight questions were included in order to yield the magic total of forty?” Fisher, supra note 32, at

817.

571

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 light of Caperton, courts and scholars across the country are reviewing and discussing both the federal constitutional floor and the standards of individual states. The renewed interest in the topic has already generated feedback and public commentary on both sides of the issue, and same can certainly be viewed as a step in the right direction. The ABA’s Standing

Committee on Judicial Independence, as part of its Judicial

Disqualification Project launched in 2007, has taken initiative and issued a new set of recommendations in the summer of

2009 in response to the Caperton decision.

126

Such recommendations provide much of the necessary detail and clarity in how to evaluate the “mere appearance of bias” standard by setting forth specific procedures and rules that need to be adopted as well as suggesting specific data that should be gathered in order to help judges make better decisions relative to recusal.

127

Some of the ABA recommendations include:

“assigning contested disqualification motions to a different judge,” “adopting a de novo standard of appellate review in matters in which judges’ decisions not to disqualify themselves are challenged,” “establishing procedures for review of

[decisions by appellate court judges to deny recusal motions] by the remainder of the court, by a specially constituted court, or by an advisory board,” “adopting judicial substitution or peremptory challenge procedures for trial judges,”

“disseminating data about judicial disqualification within their jurisdictions,” “encouraging judges to explain the reasons for their judicial disqualification decisions,” and “providing more systematic guidance to the judiciary about when a

126 Joan C. Rogers, Draft ABA Report Reviews Rules and Processes for

Judicial Recusal, Recommends Improvements, 77 U.S.L.W.

1782 (2009),

available at http://www.americanbar.org/content/dam/aba/images/ judicial_independence/lawweek_case_focus.pdf.

127 Id.

572

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 judge's impartiality might reasonably be questioned.”

128

Moreover, the ABA also provided special guidance for states that utilize judicial elections, by setting forth a list of factors to be considered when a judge’s impartiality has been, or may reasonably be, questioned due to campaign contributions.

These factors are as follows:

“[t]he level of support,” “any distinction between the direct contributions or independent expenditures,” “[t]he timing of the support in relation to the case for which disqualification is sought,” and “the relationship, if any, between the supporter and (i) any of the litigants, (ii) the issue before the court, (iii) the judicial candidate, and

(iv) the total support received by the judicial candidate and the total support received by all candidates for that judgeship.”

129

Thus, despite the Supreme Court’s reluctance to crack down on mandatory judicial recusal, the fact that they addressed the issue at all has already led to some noticeable effects. For those champions of the Constitution who agree with the Court that recusal can be mandated by the guarantee of due process, these effects are both beneficial and welcome changes. More than half of the states have been revising their judicial conduct codes based upon the 2007 ABA Model Code, and a few have already

130

adopted a new code.

Arizona changed its code to now reflect the ABA’s revisions, including a new rule that makes recusal mandatory when a judge is made aware that a party and/or his counsel have contributed a sum total within the prior four years

Even Hugh Caperton, while

that exceeds a certain amount.

131

128 Clark, supra note 101, at 699 (quoting Standing Comm. on Judicial

Independence, ABA, R EPORT TO THE H OUSE OF D ELEGATES 2-3 (2009)).

129 Id. at 700 (quoting Standing Comm. on Judicial Independence, ABA,

R EPORT TO THE H OUSE OF D ELEGATES 3 (2009)).

130 Rogers, supra note 126, at 4.

131 Id.

573

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 acknowledging that the Supreme Court’s decision ultimately did not change the result in his situation, recognized the case’s

“tremendous impact on our judicial system,” insofar as it gave

“judges a standard in which to follow with respect to their recusal from cases involving large contributors.”

132 While the

opinion by itself only provided a vague framework for judicial recusal in atypical cases, by expanding the reach of the federal

Constitution at least beyond the common law, it left the door wide open for states to reform their own standards, and sparked much-needed discussion on the issue. This dialogue is the hidden treasure of the opinion, and the true legacy of Caperton.

PART III: SOLUTIONS

Former Supreme Court Justice Sandra Day O’Connor has tirelessly worked since her retirement from the Court to educate and reform the negative public perceptions that have come to be associated with judicial elections and the supposed unfairness of the legal system.

133 The current system being utilized in

Arizona, her home state, is offered as an example of how to mitigate the dangers associated with traditional political elections, in order to preserve the appearance of an independent judiciary. Arizona maintains nonpartisan judicial nominating committees, made up of both attorneys and non-attorneys, that are tasked with reviewing all applications for a vacant seat on

132 Caperton, supra note 1, at 733.

133 Fisher, supra note 32, at 791. Fisher wrote:

[T]he selfless and nonpartisan labor of many people, including retired Justice Sandra Day O’Connor and countless others for whom the health, and indeed the survival, of an independent judiciary – the bulwark erected by the Founders against self-aggrandizement and abuse of power by the political branches – is of paramount importance to the welfare of our democracy. That health, and that survival, are being challenged by a significant diminution in public trust and confidence in the judiciary, particularly at the state level.

Id. at 791-92.

574

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 both the superior and appellate level courts.

134 Upon

completing said review, the committee then submits a list of the three most qualified candidates, of which no more than two may be from the same political party, to the governor for a final

135 The committee has a set of

appointment decision.

qualifications to be considered in their review, for the most part based upon the candidate’s meritorious qualities, as well as the geographic diversity of the jurisdiction.

136 The judge then serves

for a term certain, and thereafter in an uncontested retention election, the public can vote yes or no in order to keep or remove the judge.

137 If so removed, the committee begins the process

again to fill the vacancy, while the electorate is benefitted by virtue of another commission tasked with rendering judicial performance reviews, which are made publically available.

138

Justice O’Connor herself has stated when speaking in the context of Arizona’s system, “I would love it if more states would move toward some kind of a selection system with appointments recommended by a commission and retention elections.”

139

Beyond any drastic changes in a state’s overall method, she also offers more minor suggestions that could be easily implemented.

Longer judicial terms once elected is one such suggestion.

140

She further recommends increasing public awareness by way of disseminating “voter guides” that contain “performance

134 Rebecca White Berch, A History of the Arizona Courts, 3 P HOENIX L.

R EV . 11, 32 (2010). Note that in counties with populations of less than

250,000, the superior court judges may be chosen via the merit selection committees, or via nonpartisan elections, at the discretion of each such county. Streb, supra note 3, at 8; Berch, supra note 134, at 33-34.

135 Berch, supra note 134, at 32.

136 Id. at 33-34.

137 Id. at 32-33. As to the length of the term, superior court judges remain on the bench for four-year intervals. Appellate judges are initially appointed for two years, then face a retention election, and thereafter remain for six-year intervals. Id. at 32.

138 Id. at 34.

139 O’Connor, supra note 4, at 565.

140 Id.

575

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 evaluations” of the incumbent judges in order to foster moreeducated voting decisions.

141

Finally, she also advises that our governments reconsider laws surrounding judicial recusal and election funding,

142

two issues that are obviously closely intertwined.

With respect to other ways in which the judicial selection process can be improved in those states that utilize elections in some form or another, there is a quite simple solution that may negate some of the perceived injustice. All states should amend their judicial conduct codes to include a provision requiring that any denial of a motion to disqualify must be accompanied by an explanation in writing, on the record.

143

Along the same lines, some scholars have recommended that states should also implement a requirement of a sworn affidavit executed by counsel for the party requesting disqualification, stating the exact facts that necessitate the recusal.

144

The judge would then be required to accept as true all facts that were stated therein.

145

This would eliminate prolonged and contested disputes between the party and the judge over the veracity of such facts. That is so because even if the judge is forced to recuse himself when he does not believe the facts contained in the affidavit are true, he will still have a remedy by way of a complaint to the bar association relative to the attorney who swore to those facts.

146

States also need to reconsider current disclosure requirements with respect to judicial campaigning; however,

141 Id. at 565-66.

142 Id. at 566.

143 Fisher, supra note 32, at 837. Having an explanation of the denial of the recusal motion in writing would certainly assist the parties themselves in proceeding with their dispute, but in addition, “[s]uch written explanations would not only enrich the law of judicial disqualification, but, more importantly, would over time provide firmer guidance to judges who have to apply disqualification rules to novel factual settings,” thereby creating a set of precedents for judicial recusal to clarify the standards that have been accused of being vague. Id.

144 Id. at 836.

145 Id.

146 Id. at 836-37.

576

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 disclosure is an issue that needs to be explored and revamped on both sides of the coin. That means that the public is entitled to more stringent rules regarding both better access to campaign financing and donation information, and the obligation of judges to disclose on the record “information that the judge believes the parties or their lawyers might reasonably consider relevant to a possible motion for disqualification, even if the judge believes there is no basis for disqualification.”

147

The author makes reference to the “coin” inasmuch as the judiciary will also need better access to information and more disclosure in order to properly assess their own impartiality or lack thereof.

Due in large part to the Citizens United decision, it may be difficult presently for a judge to ascertain the exact source from which his campaign funding may have come. Therefore, the judiciary must be well apprised as to these sources in order to make an appropriate decision regarding recusal. Some examples of disclosures that should be made available to judges are subjects such as “corporate affiliations, support for filing of briefs amicus curiae, etc.”

148

Another important area ripe for reform is the review process that is applied to denied motions for disqualification. The law is somewhat complicated on the issue presently, inasmuch as it not only varies from state to state, but also varies from court to court, depending on whether the recusal is requested at the trial court or appellate level. All states should work toward improving such processes by specifying (or clarifying, if such a procedure already purports to be in place), the procedure by which an interlocutory appeal of a refusal to recuse can be

149

Of course, as noted above, such an obtained quickly yet fairly.

appellate decision, either affirming or reversing the trial judge’s decision, should be accompanied by a full statement of reasons, made available in writing.

Moreover, relative to appellate judges in particular, states must work toward revision of the rules in order to eliminate from “the subject justice . . . [the] sole authority to decide such

147 Id. at 830.

148 Fisher, supra note 32, at 833.

149 Id. at 831.

577

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 motions.”

150

These issues are not as salient with regard to trial court judges, inasmuch as a refusal to recuse at that level is usually subject to some sort of appellate review; however,

“where the recusal decision is vouchsafed to the sole discretion of a state high court judge . . . due process concerns are heightened.”

151

Michigan has come up with a solution to this conundrum, by permitting a denial of a recusal motion by the judge in question to be reviewed by the balance of the court.

152

Another proposed solution is to empanel a special committee of retired members of the judiciary to review such denials.

153

This author does caution that any of the foregoing solutions alone will certainly not be sufficient to stem the tide of perceived injustice in the eyes of the public. Furthermore, any such revisions to state judicial codes must be accompanied by a stated standard for recusal on “the mere appearance of impropriety.”

This standard as written must also be strictly applied in order to both reassure the public and develop a body of case law that interprets the aforementioned objective standard. Such a standard, and strict application and enforcement thereof, must be used in conjunction with a modified selection process such as the above-noted appointment and retention election procedure in Arizona. The duality of this burden thrust upon states to review and revise the rules of judicial conduct is imperative in order to safeguard the public’s constitutional right to an impartial judiciary, because “the spectacle of large expenditures to support judicial election campaigns creates a spectre of partiality and impropriety that is profoundly injurious to public perception of the judiciary.”

154

150 Id. at 811.

151 Id.

152 Id.

153 Id.

154 Fisher, supra note 32, at 799.

578

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy

CONCLUSION

Vol 9:3

The functions and responsibilities of the judicial system in this country are a fundamental basis underlying much of our legal system, and thereby this role as viewed by the public serves to give to the system its legitimacy, or lack thereof, in the eyes of its citizenry. However, the rules in place that govern judges stemming from the common law are inadequate to address this issue in light of the initial advent of an elected judiciary in the majority of the several States, and the more recent introduction of corporate money and special interest groups into the mix. As has happened in many other instances involving public policy issues in the past, the law has been slow to catch up with the real world. Therein lies the importance of Caperton v. Massey Coal

Co. Inc.

In Caperton, the Supreme Court actually took a giant step away from the common law rule that a judge’s recusal from a matter was only mandatory when said judge had a direct, personal, and/or pecuniary interest in the matter at hand. As discussed in detail above, while Caperton did not purport to outright overrule any prior law, it also clearly represented a transformation in the way in which attorneys, judges, and citizens will approach the subject of judicial recusal in the future. Such a transformation was achieved firstly by factually going beyond the common law to recognize that “mere” bias or prejudice can also lead to a constitutionally-mandated recusal, rather than forcing a litigant to show a “direct interest” in his particular matter. Secondly, the Court also made clear that this recusal standard is objective and to be examined in light of what a reasonable person would think constitutes a probability of bias, helping to eliminate the subjective type of soul-searching for “actual bias” done by individuals such as Justice Benjamin in

Caperton, which was previously deemed to be sufficient.

In sum, in Part I, this note looked at the history of judicial elections in United States and how they came to resemble what they do today, looked at some specific examples of disputed and arguably corrupt judicial elections and corresponding results, and went through the facts of Caperton in greater detail. Part II dealt with the varying standards for judicial recusal, both those currently in use and some proposed standards, including in relevant part: the “actual bias” standard; the “probability of bias” standard resulting from Caperton; and the “mere

579

Spring 2012 Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy Vol 9:3 appearance of bias” standard. Finally, Part III was a brief and woefully inadequate attempt to suggest certain reforms to state judiciary codes in order for the legal system to help regain the support and trust of the American people.

While the preceding statement may sound dramatic, a reform of the ways in which judges are selected and disqualified from hearing cases is absolutely essential to the health of our nation.

155 Big money and politics have no place in an

individual’s matter that has come before a court. The very essence of an independent judiciary excludes the notion that a citizen would not be allowed redress when he has legitimate concerns over the alleged bias of the judge in his case. To summarize this lack of redress in the words of Mr. Caperton himself, “[i]t is a feeling that no citizen should ever have to endure in any court in this country.”

156

155 “A substantial majority of the public – often 80% or higher – believes that monetary campaign support influences judicial decisions, according to a variety of surveys conducted at both the national and state levels.” Fisher,

supra note 32, at 767 n.106.

156 Caperton, supra note 1, at 729.

580

Download