INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM - Cambridge Center for Behavioral

advertisement
Behavior and Philosophy, 35, 1-55 (2007). © 2007 Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
Gordon R. Foxall
Cardiff University
ABSTRACT: Two of the leading contenders to explain behavior are radical behaviorism
and intentionality: an account that seeks to confine itself to descriptions of response–
environment correlations and one that employs the language of beliefs and desires to
explicate its subject matter. While each claims an exclusive right to undertake this task, this
paper argues that neither can be eliminated from a complete explanatory account of human
behavior. The behavior analysis derived from radical behaviorism is generally sufficient for
the prediction and control of behavior in the laboratory and its applications, but it fails to
provide an explanation of behavior since it cannot deal with the personal level of
explanation, the continuity of behavior, and the delimitation of behaviorist interpretations.
Only the inclusion of intentional terms can achieve these ends. An intentional account
cannot succeed, however, without the incorporation of a behavioral criterion for the
ascription of intentional content based on the analysis of systematic environment–behavior
relationships. This paper proposes an overarching philosophical framework for the analysis
and interpretation of behavior that incorporates both radical behaviorism and intentional
psychology in a model, “intentional behaviorism,” that additionally links the explanation of
behavior to neuroscience and evolutionary psychology. Finally, the paper proposes a link
between the philosophical framework of intentional behaviorism and the world of
empirical science by describing a tentative model of research, “super-personal cognitive
psychology,” that shows how the disparate elements previously discussed impinge upon
psychological investigation.
Key words: radical behaviorism, intentional psychology, philosophy of science,
explanation, Dennett, Skinner
[O]ne cannot expect the question as to the scientific status of psychology to be
settled by empirical research in psychology itself. To achieve this is rather an
undertaking in epistemology. (Hempel, 1980, p. 16)1
AUTHOR’S NOTE: This paper is part of a series of publications concerned with the
philosophy of economic psychology. For the sake of continuity, it draws to a limited degree
on portions of Foxall, 2004 and 2007a, by kind permission of the publisher, while Foxall
(2007b) builds on the analysis presented here and applies it to the analysis of economic
behavior. I am grateful, as ever, to Jean Foxall. Please address all correspondence to
Gordon Foxall, Cardiff University, Aberconway Building, Colum Drive, Cardiff,
CF10 3EU, Wales, UK. Tel: +44 (0)29 2087 4275; E-mail: foxallg@cf.ac.uk.
1
Hempel’s paper was originally published in H. Feigl & W. Sellars (Eds.) (1949).
Readings in Philosophical Analysis (pp. 373-384). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Reference here is given to its republication in 1980 since this source contains revisions by
the author and a brief account of how his thought changed since the initial publication.
1
FOXALL
Introduction
The more I see of behavior analysts’ struggling to accommodate the thinking
of other psychologists, usually cognitive in orientation, to the vocabulary of
behavior theory, and thereby missing much of the point, including much of what is
relevant to behaviorism, the more I wonder why we are not open to a broader
philosophical framework that can cope with both kinds of utterance. The work of
the famed behaviorist philosopher Quine (1960) should be sufficient to alert us to
the impossibility of such translation. Moreover, numerous other philosophers such
as Chisholm (1957), Dennett (1969), and Searle (1983) at least suggest to us the
explanatory riches of a linguistic system that includes intentional idioms such as
desires and beliefs, and a range of empirical analyses of behavior—among others,
those of Bolles (1972), Bindra (1978), Toates (1986), and Dickinson (1997)—
make clear the advantages of a psychological theory that recognizes the two. Some
behavior analysts readily employ the language of intentionality, apparently
oblivious of the extra-behaviorist avenues of explanation into which this
necessarily leads them. But most of us seem to prefer a vocabulary that is limited
to the descriptive level of the three-term contingency and thereby restricted in
terms of the range of explanation open to us and the contribution that we, as
behavior analysts, can make to the development of both empirical and theoretical
psychology. I should like to explore a framework of conceptualization and
analysis, “intentional behaviorism,” that embraces the terminology of radical
behaviorism and intentional psychology, not because such a synthesis is desirable
on its own merits, but because each of the systems of explanation represented by
these linguistic modes is necessary to the completion of the program of the other.
Intentional psychology, in which beliefs and desires assume a central
explanatory role, provides the foundation of cognitive psychology and much of its
social, organizational, educational, and economic applications. Its explanatory
stance is exactly opposite to that of behaviorism, which has traditionally striven at
all costs to avoid intentional terms like “believes” and “desires.” However, despite
the fact that neither program can succeed wholly without the other, there is much
that the proponents of each of these approaches have misunderstood in the other’s
arguments.
Finding a resolution thus requires a thorough and critical examination of both
intentionality as a means of explaining behavior and of radical behaviorism as a
particular philosophy of psychology. Hence, this paper draws upon the
contributions of two leading exponents of these respective systems: Daniel Dennett
in the case of intentionality and Frederic Skinner for radical behaviorism. This is
necessary in order to understand how their systems contrast with alternative
approaches to intentionality and behaviorism, respectively, as well as to build a
coherent, overarching framework for understanding behavior.
Dennett’s program, since the appearance of his first book, Content and
Consciousness, in 1969, has been concerned with the place of intentional idioms in
the explanation of behavior and the neurological basis of consciousness—in other
words, in the biological and philosophical underpinnings of cognitive psychology.
2
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
Central to both enterprises has been the distinction between a sub-personal and a
personal level of analysis. This distinction has informed his work on the legitimate
ascription of content to intentional systems and the delineation of human
consciousness. There is, nevertheless, controversy among philosophers over the
significance of Dennett’s distinction between personal and sub-personal levels of
explanation and the uses to which it may be put. The disagreement is occasioned in
some degree by the different emphases Dennett himself has accorded the meanings
and usages of these levels since he introduced the distinction and by the different
criteria he has emphasized over the years as appropriate to justify the ascription of
content. Difficulties include the number of intentional explanations suggested by
Dennett’s successive analyses, the relationships among them, and the legitimacy of
ascribing content at more than one level. While Dennett’s initial distinction
apparently precluded the ascription of content at the sub-personal level, which was
identified with neuroscientific theory and research, his later tendency casts the
personal/sub-personal distinction as that between the whole and its parts, with the
result that the personal level as a source of explanation in its own right has been
relatively ignored. The later thinking that permitted the ascription of content to
sub-personal components via the pragmatic use of the intentional stance helped
blur the original distinction between explanatory levels.
The intentional stance is the philosophical position that any entity the
behavior of which can be predicted by attributing to it beliefs and desires is an
intentional system, and this lays open the possibility of ascribing intentional
content not only at the personal level but at any level that facilitates prediction
(Dennett, 1983, 1987). The intentional stance is better understood when contrasted
with the two other stances Dennett introduced at the same time. The design stance
is used to “make predictions solely from knowledge or assumptions about the
system’s functional design, irrespective of the physical constitution or condition of
the innards of the particular object” (Dennett, 1978, p. 4). The information
provided by this stance leads us to define what an object will do, what its function
must minimally be, regardless of its form. From the physical stance we make
predictions on the basis of the physical state or conditions of the system; it depends
on knowledge we have in the form of laws of nature. Predicting that when the
bough breaks the baby will fall involves using the physical stance, as does
forecasting that the atmospheric conditions that are about to bring rain will also
bring on my lumbago. Through the recognition that the best chess-playing
computers now defy prediction by either of these stances, Dennett arrives at the
third stance: the intentional stance. In using it, “. . .[O]ne assumes not only (1) that
the machine will function as designed, but (2) that the design is optimal as well,
that the computer will ‘choose’ the most rational move” (Dennett, 1978, p. 5).
Note that rationality here means optimal design relative to a goal, and that
prediction is relative to the nature and extent of the information the system has
about the field of endeavor. “One predicts behavior. . .by ascribing to the system
the possession of certain information and supposing it to be directed by certain
goals, and then by working out the most reasonable or appropriate action on the
basis of these ascriptions and suppositions. It is a small step to calling the
3
FOXALL
information possessed the computer’s beliefs, its goals and subgoals its desires”
(Dennett, 1978, p. 6).
Dennett’s associated attempt to formulate the philosophical basis of “subpersonal cognitive psychology” in contradistinction to the intentional systems
theory that inhered in the personal level of explanation has enabled his system of
explanation to become increasingly elaborate, but it has also increased confusion.
The issue is clearly of direct concern to the quest for the philosophical
foundations of social cognitive psychology inasmuch as processing accounts
necessarily rest upon some construal of the nature of intentional ascription, upon
the specification of cognitive performance by an underlying competence theory of
intentionality and behavior (Bechtel, 1988). I shall argue, however, that the
distinction is just as important an element in the foundations of behavioral
psychology, for the personal/sub-personal distinction suggests a personal/superpersonal distinction that involves behavioral science in a more complete
psychological science.
In contrast to Dennett’s intentional psychology, Skinner’s radical behaviorism
avoids reference to cognitive events and processes in its explanations of behavior,
repudiating cognitivism as the “creationism of psychology” and proposing that
whatever believing and desiring may also be, they are behaviors to be
characterized and explained like any other behaviors, invisibility to third parties
notwithstanding (Skinner, 1974). Behavior is a function of its environmental
consequences, which reinforce (make it more probable in similar circumstances in
the future) or punish (make behavior less probable). I argue that, while such
contingencies may be valuable for the prediction and control of behavior, they are
inadequate for an explanation of behavior that seeks to account for its continuity
and its representation at the personal level, and that is constrained by the credible
consequences of the action. Only intentionality can provide the theoretical
structures required to accomplish an adequate explanation of behavior. I
nevertheless propose that the intentional program itself cannot be completed
without a formal and systematic understanding of the role of the environmental
determinants of behavior as reflected in behavior analysis.
Although the admission of private events (thoughts and feelings) into the
ontology of radical behaviorism (Skinner, 1945) is usually taken to demarcate it
from other neo-behaviorisms such as those of Tolman and Hull, it is in fact the
determination of radical behaviorists to avoid intentional language in their
statements of behavioral causation that is the defining characteristic of radical
behaviorism. Yet, despite radical behaviorism’s effectiveness as a means of
predicting behavior, the question arises as to whether it can provide a satisfactory
explanation thereof without resort to intentional idioms.
Intentional and Extensional
Some words seem to “reach out” to things other than themselves. They “refer”
to or are about something else. In using the word “desire,” it is necessary to
specify what it is that is desired; in speaking of “belief,” it is similarly impossible
4
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
to proceed without alluding to what is believed. Belief and desire are known by
philosophers as “attitudes,” and their sense is completed by stating a proposition
about what is believed or desired. Such propositions usually begin with “that.” I do
not simply desire: I desire that something or other be the case. I do not just believe:
I believe that such and such is the case. Not all words are of this kind. We do not
speak of “breathing that” or “bathing that.” The first kind of expression is called
intentional (from the Latin intendere). While intentionality’s special properties
were known to the scholastic philosophers of the Middle Ages, it came to
prominence with Brentano’s nineteenth-century insistence that intentionality must
be the mark of the mental. Mental events were to be distinguished from physical
things by virtue of the way they were spoken of. In addition to the “aboutness” of
such locutions, Brentano drew attention to two linguistic characteristics that
separated them from other words.
First, it may not be truthful to substitute two words or phrases that are
equivalent one for the other in intentional sentences. “John believes that Satan
roams the earth like a devouring lion” is an intentional sentence that may be true,
but it might not be accurate to say “John believes that the Devil roams the earth
like a devouring lion” since John may not be aware that, at least in the context of
fairly orthodox Christian belief, Satan and the Devil are one and the same.
Sentences of this kind are said to be referentially opaque by dint of the incapacity
of the speaker to substitute codesignative terms and yet be sure of retaining the
truth value of his or her words. This contrasts with the extensional language of
science, in which the substitution of codesignatives leads to perfectly accurate
statements (which are, accordingly, known as referentially transparent). One can
alternate between “There is the Prime Minister of Great Britain” and “There is the
First Lord of the Treasury” without losing the truth value of what one is
maintaining. The Prime Minister and the First Lord are one and the same person;
hence, the sentences have the same extension.
Second is what Brentano called “intentional inexistence”: the things referred
to in an intentional sentence do not necessarily exist. When I say “I believe that
there are Hobbits at the bottom of my garden” I speak of imaginary creatures that
have no existence other than fictional—but when I say “I am going to drive my car
to Scotland,” there has to be a car which I shall drive.
The modern emphasis among some philosophers of psychology is that
intentionality is not the mark of the mental in any sense that would suggest a sharp
ontological dichotomy, but a means of distinguishing alternative ways of speaking
of or explaining the world: a source of alternative modes of explanation:
alternative and quite distinct, because it is not possible to translate intentional
sentences into extensional ones that carry precisely the same meaning.
Philosophers from Chisholm (1957) and Dennett (1969), for instance, who are
sympathetic to the idea of incorporating intentionality in behavioral explanations,
to the behaviorist Quine (1960), who is not, agree on this. The everyday, matter-offact observation “She said that the train would be late” cannot be rendered with
certainty as “She said ‘The train will be late’” since, by specifying a form of words
that she uttered, this adds information that the intentional sentence does not
5
FOXALL
contain. For the same reason, “She said ‘The train has been delayed’” or “She said
‘The train’s engine needs to be replaced’” or “She said ‘The driver is drunk again’”
are not equivalent to the intentionally-expressed sentence. Each kind of statement
belongs to a distinct mode of explanation: one leads irrevocably to cognitive
psychology; the other, to behaviorism.
Radical Behaviorism
Radical behaviorism as a philosophy of psychology is strictly extensional: it
strives to account for its subject matter, behavior, in sentences that are referentially
transparent, in which codesignatives are substitutable because they have the same
extension. It is thus distinguished from cognitivism by its rigorous avoidance of
intentional language, and from both cognitivism and other neo-behaviorisms by its
inclusion of thinking and feeling (“private events”) as phenomena that require
explanation on the same terms as public responding. Its focus is the prediction and
control of behavior by reference to its environmental consequences and the
antecedent stimuli that set the scene for reinforcement or punishment. In its
adherence to Machian positivism, it holds that when the environmental stimuli that
control behavior have been identified, the behavior has been explained. The truth
criterion it applies to this endeavor is pragmatism rather than realism. The
scientific arm of this philosophy, behavior analysis, seeks the prediction and
control of behavior in the environmental–behavioral contingencies which, in their
familiar “three-term” construal, propose that SD: R → SR where SD is a cue or
discriminative stimulus, R is an operant class, and SR is a reinforcing stimulus. The
discriminative stimulus (SD) sets the occasion ( : ) for (but does not elicit as does
the unconditioned stimulus of classical conditioning) an operant class (R) which
produces (Æ) a reinforcing consequence (SR), which, via feedback, makes the
future enactment of this operant class in similar circumstances more probable
(Moore, 1999; see also Staddon & Cerutti, 2003). The behavior in question is
operant behavior, which, by operating on the environment, brings about
consequences that control its future rate of emission.
Each element of the three-term (or, in general, n-term) contingency is
described in extensional language: its operation is not dependent upon wants or
beliefs, desires or intentions (Smith, 1994). It describes both contingency-shaped
and rule-governed behaviors in terms of “a system of functional relationships
between the organism and the environment” (Smith, 1994, pp. 127-128). Hence, an
operant response “is not simply a response that the organism thinks will have a
certain effect, it does have that effect.” Further, a reinforcer “is not simply a
stimulus that the organism desires to occur. It is a stimulus that will alter the rate of
behavior upon which its occurrence is contingent.” And a discriminative stimulus
“is not simply a stimulus that has been correlated with a certain contingency in the
organism’s experience. It is one that successfully alters the organism’s operant
behavior with respect to that contingency.” Descriptions of contingent behavior do
not take propositions as their object; rather, their object is relationships between an
organism’s behavior, its environmental consequences, and the elements that set the
6
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
occasion for those contingent consequences. So behavior analysis does not
attribute propositional content to any of the elements of the three-term
contingency. “Instead of accepting a proposition as its object, the concept of
reinforcement accepts an event or a state of affairs—such as access to pellets—as
its object” (Smith, 1994, p. 128). Mentalistic description: “The animal desires that
a pellet should become available.” The behavior analytic description is not “The
animal’s lever presses are reinforced that a pellet becomes available”; it is “The
animal’s lever presses are reinforced by access to pellets.” A discriminative
stimulus would not be described as a signal that something will happen, but simply
that a contingency exists. “It attributes an effect to the stimulus, but not a content.”
Whereas the substitutability of identicals fails in mentalistic statements (such
statements are said to be logically opaque), behavioral categories are logically
transparent, suggesting that “behavioral categories are not a subspecies of
mentalistic categories” (Smith, 1994, p. 129).
Neither is the proposition that “reinforcer” merely denotes “desire” feasible;
desires are not equivalent to reinforcers, or reinforcers to desires. Common-sense
notions imply that if a stimulus is (positively) reinforcing it is desired, and if it is
desired it is because it is a (positive) reinforcer—but in fact neither notion holds.
Objects of desire may not be attainable (e.g., the fountain of youth, perpetual
motion) and so cannot be (linked to) reinforcers. Nor are reinforcers necessarily
desired: given appropriate histories, responding under fixed and variable-interval
schedules can be maintained by the delivery of electric shock, at least with
monkeys and cats (see, e.g., Morse & Kelleher, 1977). The shocks are avoidable
simply by not responding, but are not avoided. Noxious shocks (which otherwise
can serve as negative reinforcers) cannot be “desired,” yet under certain conditions
they can maintain behavior as positive reinforcers.
Nor do functional units of the speaker’s verbal behavior, such as mands and
tacts (Skinner, 1957), have propositional content. They are simply statements of
contingencies that account for an individual’s behavior in the absence of his or her
direct exposure to those contingencies. A mand is “a verbal response that specifies
its reinforcer” (Catania, 1992, p. 382): for example, “Give me a drink” plus the
unspoken, “You owe me a favor” or “Else I shall ignore your requests in future.”
Even if this is expressed as “I desire that you give me a drink. . .”, it is actually no
more than a description of contingencies. A tact is “a verbal discriminative
response. . .in the presence of or shortly after a stimulus” (Catania, 1992 p. 399):
“Here is the bank.” Even if this were expressed as, “I want you to see the bank,” its
function would be confined to establishing the stimulus control of the word
“bank,” as when the listener replies, “Oh, yes, the bank.” More technically, the
mand denotes the consequences contingent upon following the instructions of the
speaker or of imitating his or her example. Much advertising consists of mands—
“Buy three and get one free!” “Don’t forget the fruit gums, mum”—which indicate
contingencies under the control of the speaker. Tacts present a contact with part of
the environment and, depending on learning history, a potential for behavior on the
part of the recipient. A trademark or logo may be followed by making a purchase
or entering a store. The definitive source is Skinner’s Verbal Behavior (1957).
7
FOXALL
The functional units of the listener’s verbal behavior, as proposed by Zettle &
Hayes (1982), similarly describe contingencies rather than express propositional
content. Pliance, for instance, is the behavior of the listener who complies with a
verbal request or instruction: hence, “Pliance is rule-governed behavior under the
control of apparent socially mediated consequences for a correspondence between
the rule and relevant behavior” (Hayes, Zettle, & Rosenfarb, 1989, p. 201). Pliance
is thus simply the behavior involved in responding positively to a mand. Tracking
is “rule-governed behavior under the control of the apparent correspondence
between the rule and the way the world is arranged” (Hayes et. al., 1989, p. 206). It
involves tracking the physical environment, as when following instructions on how
to get to the supermarket. Once again, its form—for example, “Turn left at the
traffic light” plus the unspoken “and you’ll get to Sainsbury’s”—is a basic
description of contingencies rather than an expression of propositional attitudes.
Precisely as Smith has concluded with respect to contingency-shaped behavior, we
may conclude with respect to rule-governance that “beliefs and desires have
propositional content. . . .Designations of discriminative stimuli and reinforcing
stimuli, by contrast, do not accept that-clauses” (Smith, 1994, p, 128). A third
functional unit of listener behavior has no corresponding unit for the speaker: the
augmental (Zettle & Hayes, 1982) is a highly motivating rule that states
emphatically how a particular behavior will be reinforced or avoid punishment:
“Just one more box top and I can claim my free watch!”
The private events that distinguish radical behaviorism are not “cognitive” or
“mental” rather than material or physical. They are essentially private, collateral
responses under the influence of the same environmental stimuli that control
overt—or, better, public—responding. As such, their ontological status is fixed by
their place in the three-term contingency; they are responses in need of operant
explanation by means of an account that causally links them with antecedent and
reinforcing stimuli occurring in the extra-personal environment rather than
discriminative or reinforcing stimuli, which are capable of determining the
frequency of a response. They are dependent variables.
Radical behaviorism explains verbal behavior in similar terms to nonverbal
behavior: that of the speaker as a series of functionally defined speech (and quasispeech) units—tacts, mands, autoclitics, echoics, intraverbals; that of the listener as
a series of functionally defined verbal units that prescribe the consequences of
rule-following—tracks, plys, augmentals.
Behavior analysis seeks to proceed extensionally, that is, in verbal behavior
that avoids propositional content, describing its observation in language that is
referentially transparent. It has three components or modes: (1) the experimental
analysis of behavior, which is a laboratory-based investigation, (2) applied
behavior analysis devoted to interventions to treat behavior dysfunctions,
instructional design and execution, organizational behavior management, etc., and
(3) radical behaviorist interpretation using the principles of behavior gained in
basic and applied analysis to provide an account in operant-contingency terms of
the complex behaviors that are not amenable to direct experimental examination.
Radical behaviorist interpretation frequently involves the use of mediating events,
8
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
something ostensibly ruled out by Skinner’s avoidance of “theoretical terms” but
which appears necessary at this level of explanation. However, these mediating
events are not intentionalistic; they remain part of an extensional account whose
explanatory terms are extrapolated, for example, from the experimental to the nonexperimental sphere.
Radical behaviorist explanation thus proceeds on the basis of the contextual
stance (Foxall, 1999), which states that behavior is predictable insofar as it is
assumed to be environmentally determined; specifically, insofar as it is under the
control of a learning history that represents the reinforcing and punishing
consequences of similar behavior previously enacted in settings similar to that
currently encountered. The contextual stance thus portrays behavior as taking place
at the temporal and spatial intersection defined by learning history and behavior
setting. It is this intersection that defines the situation.
Three Imperatives of Intentionality
While there is no doubting the capacity of behavior analysis within the
framework of radical behaviorism to predict and control behavior, in the operant
laboratory (as well as in successful applications) there is a need for further
conceptualization if we wish to account more fully for certain aspects of behavior.
Explanation of the extensional kind is optional for behavior analysts, who may
wish to remain within the philosophy of science set by Machian positivism as, did
Skinner (Mach, 1896/1959, 1905/1976; Smith, 1986)—but there is no compelling
reason to confine inquiry to this extensional level of analysis. In seeking to extend
the conceptual framework here, I am concerned with methodology—with instances
in which it is impossible to proceed with inquiry in the absence of intentional
language—rather than with ontological questions. I should like to pursue three
areas in which I believe explanation that goes beyond the n-term contingency can
yield answers to questions that would be asked as a matter of course in most
scientific endeavors but which have not usually found a place within radical
behaviorism. These areas concern the treatment of the personal level of analysis,
accounting for the continuity of behavior, and delimiting behavioral interpretations
of behavior by delineating the scope of behavioral consequences that can be called
upon to provide a causal explanation thereof.
The Personal Level
The personal level of analysis is central to Dennett’s earliest work on
intentionality. The personal level of explanation is that of “people and their
sensations and activities” rather than that of “brains and events in the nervous
system” (Dennett, 1969, p. 93). The latter belong to the sub-personal level, at
which an extensional science such as physiology (neuroscience) operates, its
mechanistic explanations inappropriate to so-called mental entities such as pain
which occur and can be understood only at the personal level. The personal level is
that at which the organism as a whole can be said to act. As Ryle and Wittgenstein
9
FOXALL
have pointed out, it is a stage of explanation that is quickly exhausted because so
little can be said at this level. Of his pain, the bearer can say little more than that it
hurts. In Dennett’s system, as we shall see, this is the level at which beliefs,
desires, and other intentional idioms are ascribed, but for now we are concerned
only with the personal level as an analytical tool in extensional behavioral science
and its implications for the explanation of behavior.
The personal level has two aspects: a first-personal perspective (that from
which I actually feel my pain as an inner-body experience) and a third-personal
viewpoint (that in which I attribute pain to another person who is sobbing and
holding her head as well as using the word “migraine” a lot). The acceptance of
these “subjective” and “objective” understandings of the personal level does not
divide cleanly along behaviorist/non-behaviorist lines. Skinner’s analysis of
private events can be read as embracing both at one time or another. Dennett’s
cognitive approach concentrates on the objective, third-personal level, which he
associates unremittingly with a scientific standpoint, while Schnaitter’s (1999)
behaviorist view is ready to endorse the first-personal. Others, such as Searle
(1983), fully accept the necessity of speaking in terms of both the first- and the
third-personal, and that is the approach that I take.2
The difficulty for radical behaviorism—or any other brand of extensional
behaviorism—is that it deals inadequately with both first- and third-personal
aspects of the personal level, largely because it confuses them. First note that in the
case of the first-personal or subjective level of personhood, radical behaviorism
simply has no means of accounting for some behaviors without resorting to
intentional language. This stems from the irreducibility of intentional language to
extensional language and is illustrated by the following examples of people acting
contrary to their desires, beliefs, and expectations in ways that cannot be entirely
captured in a purely extensional description. Take, for instance, the couple who
found themselves married because they went through the motions of a Jewish
wedding ceremony, they with all the other participants thinking that they were
engaged in an elaborate joke, only to discover that they were, in fact, married. No
one intended this outcome; one member of the couple fully intended to marry
someone else. Another example concerns the Muslim acting with his real-life wife
in a television production who, having followed the script to the letter, found
himself divorced from both his screen wife and his actual spouse, unable to live
with her on pain of being found guilty of adultery. This, again, was contrary to the
expectations the entire cast and production team held about the situation (both
examples are taken from Juarrero, 1999). The point is not that a radical behaviorist
interpretation of these behaviors is impossible, or even whether they are actual or
2
I have defended elsewhere (e.g., Foxall, 2007a) the incorporation of non-causal subjective
experience into the framework of exposition I propose here. Such a view does not, of
course, form part of Dennett’s system of intentional ascription, but this does not affect the
current argument since it is sufficient for present purposes to confine the personal level, as
Dennett does, to a third-personal account. For the sake of completeness, however, I note
that my view of this dichotomy is closer to those of McGinn (1991, 2004) and Strawson
(1994)—and for that matter, Skinner (1945)—than that of Dennett (1969).
10
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
anecdotal, but that such an interpretation can never capture the entire behavior in
question without resorting to intentional idioms (i.e., without deviating from its
commitment to extensional behavioral science).
So how does it cope? Skinner’s approach to interpretation is to seek the
explanation of an individual’s current behavior in his or her history of
reinforcement and punishment (i.e., learning history). Despite the way in which the
three-term contingency is usually symbolized as showing the factors that cause a
response as the consequences that necessarily follow it, Skinner does not try to
explain behavior by reference to future events. He avoids teleology by explaining
current behavior in terms of the consequences that have followed similar
responding in the past. Hence, when we see someone rummaging about among the
objects on her desk, we infer that she is looking for her glasses. But the
information available to us to make sense of her behavior is identical to the
information she has to do the same. All she can say in explanation is that she has
found her glasses in the past when she has engaged in behavior of this kind. The
behaviorist strategy of “discovering” a learning history in order to interpret
complex behavior evidently accords with the philosophy of behaviorist explanation
(Baum & Heath, 1982). Although it eschews the mentalistic fictions Skinner so
strongly repudiated, it nevertheless extends the analysis of human behavior beyond
the confines of a scientific enquiry.
Very rarely, if at all, do we base statements about our emotions, say, on the
kind of observation of ourselves that a third person would make. A person does not
come to understand that he is nervous because he sees his hands shaking and hears
his voice quavering. He does not come to conclude that he is nervous on the basis
of evidence of this kind any more than his saying he has a headache depends on his
prior observation of his flushed features, his holding his temples, and his having
taken aspirin. As Malcolm (1977, p. 97) says, “If someone were to say, on that
basis, that he has a headache, either he would be joking or else he would not
understand how the words are used. The same is true of a first-person perception
sentence, such as ‘I see a black dog’.” He argues further that behaviorists have
erred by assuming that a psychological sentence expressed in first-personal terms
is identical in content and method of verification to the corresponding thirdpersonal sentence. We verify that another person is angry by the way the veins
stand out on her neck, by the redness of her face, and by her shouting. But we do
not verify our own anger in this way. We do not, as a rule, attempt to verify it at
all. Verification is simply not a concept or operation that applies to many firstperson psychological reports (those that are not founded on observation). An
individual’s statement of purpose or intention belongs in a different class from one
made by someone else on the basis of observing that individual. If we see someone
turning out his pockets and recall that on previous occasions he has done this
before producing his car keys from one of them we can reasonably conclude that
he is looking for this car keys this time too—but it would be odd indeed if he
himself were to work out what he was doing by observing that he was emptying
his pockets as he had done in the past when looking for his car keys. If he
announced that he must be looking for his car keys at present because he was
11
FOXALL
doing what he had done in the past when finding them had eventuated, we should
think him most odd and crazy, to be treated in future with circumspection.
Malcolm (1977, p. 99) also draws attention to speech acts such as “I was
about to go home,” which for Skinner present the problem that it “describes a state
of affairs which appear to be accessible only to the speaker. How can the verbal
community establish responses of this sort?” (Skinner, 1953, p. 262). Skinner’s
explanation is that as the speaker has previously behaved publicly, private stimuli
have become associated with the public manifestations: “Later when these private
stimuli occur alone the individual may respond to them. ‘I was on the point of
going home’ may be regarded as the equivalent of ‘I observed events in myself
which characteristically precede or accompany my going home.’ What these
events are such explanation does not say” (Skinner, 1953, p. 262). Malcolm
comments, “For Skinner ‘private stimuli’ would mean of course physical events
within the individual’s skin. The fact that Skinner regards this hypothesis as a
possible explanation of the utterances, even though he does not know what the
private stimuli would be, shows how unquestioningly he assumes that such a
remark as ‘I am on the point of going home’ must be based on the observation of
something” (Malcolm, 1977, p. 99). But the statement “I am on the point of going
home” is not a prediction based on the observation of anything: “The
announcement ‘I am about to go home’ is normally an announcement of intention.
Announcements of intention are not based on the observation of either internal or
external variables. . .” (Malcolm, 1977, p. 99).
Statements of intention are undoubtedly related to external events, and
someone who said he was about to go home would normally have a reason for
doing so, for example, that it was time for dinner. But this does not mean that
going home or making the utterance is under the “control” (in Skinner’s sense) of
dinner time. In Skinner’s technical sense of control, y is under the control of x “if
and only if x and y are connected by some functional relationship,” and if control
is given this sense then neither intentions nor statements of intention are
“controlled” by anything (Malcolm, 1977, p. 100). On the one hand is the claim of
some behaviorists that “psychological” language (that which deals with so-called
mental phenomena such as believing, intending, and wanting) has to be
conceptually linked with public phenomena. Otherwise, to put the matter in the
terminology of behavior analysis, the verbal community could not teach children to
use such terms appropriately. The psychological terms must have some external
referent in preverbal behavior. But, on the other hand,
. . .the employment of psychological terms outstrips their foundation in
preverbal behavior. Someone who has satisfied us that he understands certain
psychological terms begins to use them in first-person statements in the absence
of the primitive, preverbal behavior that had previously served as the basis for
judging that he understood those terms. He tells us that he feels ill, or angry at
someone, or worried about something when we should not have supposed so
merely from his demeanor. The interesting point is that in a great many cases we
will accept his testimony. We conclude that he is angry when, if we had been
judging solely on the basis of nonverbal behavior and visible circumstances, we
12
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
should not have thought it. We begin to use his testimony as a new criterion of
what he is feeling and thinking, over and above and even in conflict with the
earlier nonverbal criteria. (Malcolm, 1977, p. 101)
Nor does radical behaviorism have an adequate answer to the need to find a
third-personal level of analysis in order to make sense of observed behavior. This
is essentially the need for a heterophenomenological methodology for
reconstructing the beliefs, attitudes, desires, and motives that would render such
observations intelligible.3
The Continuity of Behavior
The plausibility of an extensional radical behaviorist interpretation depends
vitally upon its capacity to account for the continuity of behavior. Why should
behavior that has been followed by a particular (“reinforcing”) stimulus in the
presence of a setting stimulus be re-enacted when a similar setting is encountered?
Why should a rule that describes certain physical or social contingencies be
followed at some future date when those contingencies are encountered? Why can
I tell you now what I ate for lunch yesterday? The whole explanatory significance
of learning history is concerned with the continuity of behavior between settings,
and this implies some change in the organism—some means of recording the
experience of previous behavior in such a way that it will be available next time
similar settings are encountered. There is no other way in which the individual can
recognize the potential offered by the current behavior setting in terms of the
reinforcement and punishment signaled by the discriminative stimuli that compose
it.
The radical behaviorist account of behavioral continuity requires that a
common stimulus or some component thereof is present on each occasion that a
response is emitted. The stimulus must be either a learned discriminative stimulus
and/or a reinforcer. The difficulty with this is that it is not always possible to detect
each element of the three-term contingency when behavior is learned or performed.
The tendency is, then, to suppose that something occurs within the individual,
presumably at a physiological level, that will one day be identified as sufficient to
account for the continuity of behavior—but the problem is less one of ontology
than of methodology, of the theoretical imperatives involved in explaining the
continuity of behavior and therefore the language employed to account for it.
The issue revolves around what is learned. Whether one assumes that learning
takes place as a result of initial exposure to a reinforcing stimulus and that
behavioral control is transferred contingently to a paired setting stimulus that
acquires discriminatory significance (the standard radical behaviorism view) or
that learning usually occurs as a result of observing a conspecific’s behavior and
its consequences, the only way in which such learning can be described requires
3
Although Dennett (1991) presumably intends adoption of a third-personal
heterophenomenology to exclude a first-personal phenomenological position, there is no
reason why the separate adoption of latter is precluded by acceptance of the former.
13
FOXALL
the use of intentional idioms. A purely descriptive account can, where this is
possible, relate responses to the stimuli with which they correlate, and by which
they are therefore predictable and open to influence. This is the essential program
of an extensional behavioral science, and I do not wish in any way to argue that it
be other than enthusiastically executed. Indeed, it is important to my research
program that it is. However, I would like to discuss the possibility that it is not
always feasible to make the required connections between environment and
behavior, and that this acts as a stimulus to the discovery of an explanation rather
than a mere description of behavior and its contextual determinants. The quest for
explanation will always be there, should behaviorists choose to adopt it, but the
failure of the extensional approach is a catalyst to its implementation. Let us
examine these two separable claims in turn.
The Incompleteness of the Extensional Account
Although he does not use the term “behavioral continuity,” Bandura (1986)
provides a clear description of the problem. The arguments against radical
behaviorism he puts forth center on the impossibility of providing an account of
behavioral continuity that does not refer to cognitive processing. So long as people
are assumed to act automatically in response to the environmental consequences of
their past behavior or their thoughts are conceptualized as no more than
intervening events themselves under environmental control, so long will any
“internal link in the causal chain” be eschewed and agency assumed to reside in the
environment (p. 12). Yet there are instances in which environmental causation is
assumed to act without any apparent mechanism by which it produces behavior
over time.
First, consider his treatment of the fundamental behaviorist principle that
behavior is controlled by its immediate consequences. Bandura points to Baum’s
(1973) demonstration that the rate of emission of behavior is related to the aggregate
of its consequences. Such “molar” behavior is actually a feature of Skinner’s own
approach since it is learning history rather than present stimuli alone that determine
behavior. In fact, it was Herrnstein (1997) who most obviously defined and built upon
this phenomenon. Defining choice not as an internal deliberative process but as a
rate of intersubjectively observable events that are temporally distributed,
Herrnstein’s dependent variable was not the single response that needed contextual
explication in terms of a single contingent reinforcer—it was the relative frequency
of responding, which he explained by reference to the relative rate of
reinforcement obtained from the behavior. Animals presented with two
opportunities to respond (e.g., a pigeon pecking key A or key B), each of which
delivers reinforcers (brief access to grain) on its own variable interval (VI)
schedule, allocate their responses on A and B in proportion to the rates of
reinforcement they obtain from A and B. This phenomenon, known as “matching,”
has been replicated in numerous species, including humans, and has found
applications in behavior modification and organizational behavior management, to
name but two relevant fields. In particular, it provides a framework for the
14
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
behavioral analysis of consumption (Rachlin, 1989, 2000). However, Baum’s (1973)
molar approach, to which Bandura makes reference, is sufficient to suggest that
organisms are sensitive to how often a response is reinforced over a long period of
time and that their behavior is thereby regulated according to the aggregate level of
reinforcement. Such integration, Bandura asserts, requires cognitive skills and
actually suggests the need for a subsumptive level of analysis—cognitive,
environmental, physiological, behavioral, or otherwise—such as that called for by
Smith (1994). The absence of any convincing evidence for these (when cognition is
given a specific ontological status) leaves the ascription of intentional content as the
only safe possibility given the current state of knowledge.
A second consideration to which Bandura draws attention is that when behavior
is learned on intermittent schedules, only a small proportion of responses receive
reinforcement, and reinforcements are occasional—perhaps only every 50th or 500th
response is reinforced. Yet the behavior may strengthen over very long periods.
Similarly, extinction may be accordingly prolonged. The question is whether such
integration or behavioral continuity can be explained without positing some nonenvironmental determinant, presumably cognitive. Something other than external
causation is necessary to account for what happens in between. Bandura invokes the
distinction between the acquisition of a skill and its performance which, in turn,
evokes the question of what is learned. Cognitive processes are again implicated.
Despite (or because of) the fact that the delivery of reinforcement may be highly
intermittent on such schedules, consistent patterns of behavior are acquired that define
the continuity of behavior.
Bandura also points out that most complex behavior is learned by modeling
rather than by experienced reinforcement (1986, pp. 74-80). He is highly critical of
operant attempts at interpreting observational learning within the framework of the
three-term contingency, which portray the process as one in which the modeled
stimulus (SD) is followed by an overt matching response (R) which produces a
reinforcing stimulus (SR). The elements of the three-term contingency are often
missing from actual instances of observational learning. When the observer
performs the matching response in a setting other than that in which it has been
modeled—when neither the model’s behavior nor that of the observer is
reinforced, and when the modeled behavior is performed by the observer after the
passage of time (which may be several months)—the operant paradigm is unable to
explain the behavior. As Bandura (1986, p. 74) points out, “Under this set of
conditions, which represents the pervasive form of observational learning, two of
the factors (RÆSR) in the three-element paradigm are absent during acquisition,
and the third factor (SD, the modeling cue) is absent from the situation in which the
observationally-learned behavior was first performed.” Observational learning of
this kind also requires some mechanism to aid integration of vast amounts of
information. Acquisition of novel behavior in particular requires such integration of
modeled information. Bandura maintains that learning through modeling requires four
processes: attentional, retentional, reproductive, and motivational. Certainly,
observational learning is a process that must be comprehended at the personal level of
analysis. Neither sub-personal nor super-personal levels can cope with it.
15
FOXALL
Learning that involves rule acquisition and following must also require these
four procedures in some way or other. The individual acquiring rules from others
must pay attention to the behavior of others, verbal or nonverbal. Somehow this has to
be retained and compared, for instance, with earlier-gained knowledge and
experience. Then it must somehow be translated into overt behavior when there is
situational immediacy that makes the behavior in question possible or even likely. For
Bandura, all of this argues for cognitive representation and processing, and it becomes
all the more urgent to develop this line of reasoning if understanding rather than
prediction and control is the primary goal of scientific endeavor. But whether the
inclusion of cognitive processing will increase the predictability of behavior is an
empirical question. In fact, we must keep an open mind on whether invocation of
cognitive mechanisms adds to predictive accuracy. Their primary aim is to aid
understanding, to allow a complete account of human behavior acquisition and
maintenance. The environmental variables alone might contribute more to simple
prediction and control; however, the evidence is that cognitive factors alone add little
to prediction (Foxall, 1997).
Can the required account of behavioral continuity be achieved by introducing the
moderating effect of thought into the explanatory scheme? Bandura argues that a
fundamental principle of radical behaviorism is that thought cannot affect action.
He argues that, contrary to this, most external influences on behavior act via cognitive
processing. People develop beliefs about what is happening to them (i.e., the likely
consequences of their behavior) and the beliefs come to influence their behavior.
Moreover, “One can dispense with the so-called internal link in causal chains only if
thought cannot affect action” (1986, p. 13). It is a moot point, however, whether
thought influencing behavior is or is not part of radical behaviorist explanation.
Strictly, thought is a collateral response, the effect of the same environmental
events that determine the overt responses with which the thoughts are associated.
However, even Skinner came to recognize thoughts and other private events as
“non-initiating” causes in the sense that they might act as discriminative stimuli for
covert and overt behaviors but remained ultimately dependent on external
environmental stimuli for their power (as did the events of which they were local
or proximal causes). Other radical behaviorists have held that a private event can
function as any of the elements in the three-term contingency—hence, a thought
can reinforce other covert or overt behaviors, though this remains a subject of deep
controversy. More particularly, however, the role of thought in rule-governed
behavior is of interest here. Rules may inhere in thought, and thought, like other
verbal behavior that embodies or expresses rules, may thus control responses. This
is an interesting departure from the behaviorist view that behavior can predict other
behavior but not be the cause of it.
What Is Learned?
Dennett comments that “The difficulty the behaviorist has encountered is
basically this: while it is clear that an experimenter can predict rate of learning, for
example, from the initial conditions of his mazes and experience history of his
16
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
animals, how does he specify just what is learned?” (1969, pp. 33-34). “What [the
animal in the maze] learns, of course, is where the food is, but how is this to be
characterized non-Intentionally? There is no room for ‘know’ or ‘believe’ or ‘hunt
for’ in the officially circumscribed language of behaviorism; so the behaviorist
cannot say that the rat knows or believes that his food is at x, or that the rat is
hunting for a route to x” (p. 34).
Considerations such as these have led behavioral scientists to theorize about
the nature of learning. Mediational theories such as those of Hull and Tolman have
given way to the use of intentionality to explain behavior, not on the basis of
positing intervening variables but as an inevitable linguistic turn. Berridge (2000)
makes the progression from mediationism to intentionalism clear in his description
of the history of behavioral psychology. Bolles’s (1972) account of behavior in
terms of the expectation of hedonic consequences follows the S-S theory of
Tolman rather than the S-R theory of Hull but suggests that what are learned are
S-S associations of a particular kind and function: an association is learned
between a conditioned stimulus (CS) and a subsequent hedonic stimulus (S*) that
elicits pleasure. The first S does not elicit a response but an expectation of the
second S (S*). Bolles (1972) developed a “psychological syllogism” in which, as
Dickinson puts it:
Exposure to stimulus-outcome (S-S*) and response-outcome (R-S*)
contingencies leads to the acquisition of S-S* and R-S* expectancies,
respectively, representing these associative relations. The two expectancies are
“synthesized” or combined in a “psychological syllogism” so that in the
presence of the cue, S, the animal is likely to perform response R. (1997, p. 346)
The response becomes more probable as the strengths of the expectancies
increase and as the value of S*, which is influenced by the animal’s motivational
state, increases. Bolles employs this theory to explain why animals sometimes act
as though they have received a reward when they have not: for example, the
raccoon that washes a coin as though it were food, “misbehavior,” autoshaping, or
schedule-induced polydipsia—all empirical instances that research in the 1960s
and 1970s had shown to be contraindicative of the reinforcement model.
Berridge (2000) argues that useful as this is, it fails to explain why the animal
still approaches the reinforcer (say, food) rather than waiting for it to appear and
enjoying the S* in the interim. He discusses the approach of Bindra (1978), who
proposes the hedonic transfer of incentive properties to the CS. Bindra accepts the
S-S* theory but argues that the S does not simply cause the animal to expect the
S*—it also elicits a central motivational state that causes the animal to perceive the
S as an S*. The S assumes the motivational properties that normally belong to the
S*. These motivational properties are incentive properties that attract the animal
and elicit goal-directed behavior and, possibly, consumption. Through association
with the S*, the S acquires the same functions as the S*. An animal approaches the
CS for a reward and finds the signal (S) attractive; if the CS is food, the animal
wants to eat it. If it is an S for a tasty food S*, the animal may take pleasure in its
attempt to eat the CS (Berridge, 2000, p. 236; see also Bouton & Franselow, 1997).
17
FOXALL
But if CSs were incentives, one would always respond to them whether or not one
were hungry. The question is to explain how CSs interact with drive states. Toates
(1986), therefore, builds on the Bolles–Bindra theory by positing that both
cognitive expectancy and more basic reward processes might occur simultaneously
in the individual. All of these theories are necessarily intentionalistic since they
deal in expectancies.
Delimiting Behavioral Interpretations
The ubiquity of apparent three-term contingencies as we survey life beyond
the lab raises difficulties for an interpretative account, which is meant to be more
than “plausible.” As radical behaviorism stands, its program of interpretative
research is adjudged solely on the criterion of plausibility, thus there is no way of
successfully delimiting the scope of its interpretations so as to meet the standards
of validity and reliability decisive in qualitative as well as quantitative research.
This problem is inherent in Rachlin’s (1994) extensional interpretation of
observed behavior, teleological behaviorism, which proposes an interpretation of
complex behavior based on final causes (i.e., the consequences of behavior). Final
causes extend serially outward from the individual who behaves, each fitting or
nesting into the pattern of the next. Hence:
. . .eating an appetizer fits into eating a meal, which fits into a good diet, which
fits into a healthy life, which in turn fits into a generally good life. The wider the
category, the more embracing, the “more final” the cause. (Rachlin, 1994, p. 21)
The process of finding the causes of behavior is one of fitting the behavior
into an ever-increasing molar pattern of behavior and consequences. Rachlin’s
system has no place for private events or intrapersonal phenomena; yet, unlike both
radical and methodological behaviorism it freely employs mentalistic terminology.
Rachlin asserts that mind is behavior—sequences or patterns of behavior rather than
single acts. This molar view means that mental phenomena such as attitudes,
intentions, and even pain are all defined by extended patterns of behavior. We know
that our friend is in pain because of the behaviors he emits: grimacing, groaning,
holding his arm, and so on—but this is not the central concern of this account. That
lies in the fact that interpretations based on this system are unbounded and require
an intentionalistic overlay of interpretation in order to be useful.
A whole series of final causes may each be nested within one another,
diffused over time, with the whole sequence being necessary for a full explanation
of the behavior that produced them. But since the events that explain a behavior
are temporally extended, the compilation of its explanation may require the elapse
of a significant period before the full complexity of the behavior’s consequences
can be noted and understood (Rachlin, 1994, pp. 31-32). The search for final
causes as ultimate explanations may, nevertheless, be convoluted and unscientific
in the sense that the propositions employed in explication of a behavior may never
be brought into contact with the empirical events that could substantiate them or
lead to their refutation. Rachlin’s search for plausible extensions fails because the
18
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
extension identified is untestable (at least during the period of the interpretation). It
is a travesty to say that the death of millions of Japanese civilians was a (or the)
final cause of the physics research on atomic structure initiated by Rutherford and
his colleagues. The two events are undoubtedly linked, but the invocation of a
causal relationship between them is hardly adequate to account for either. More
complete explanations must be sought at the intentional level.
Rachlin gives the example of our seeing a snippet of film showing a man
swinging a hammer in order to explain Aristotle’s conception of final causation
(Rachlin, 2000, pp. 58-59; see also Rachlin, 1994, pp. 82-83, which is the subject
of the review by Lacey quoted below). What, he asks, is the man actually doing?
He might be swinging a hammer, hammering a nail, joining pieces of wood, laying
a floor, building a house, providing shelter, supporting his family, being a good
husband or father, or being a good person. All of these may be descriptions of his
behavior, all may be true. But in order to arrive at the final judgment of what the
man is doing we must look through the movie of the man’s entire life: “The
validity of any of the above descriptions may be settled by moving the camera
back or showing more film—earlier and later” (2000, p. 59). The whole point of
my criticism—the whole problem of the behavioral interpreter—is that there is no
such thing as this comprehensive movie, no means of obtaining the complete
behavioral history of this individual. We only get snippets of film and we need to
find a means of interpreting it that is readier-to-hand than the supposed universal
observation. Lacey hints at the kind of extra interpretation that is required:
Insofar as building a house is constituted by an extended behavioral pattern, a
particular act is part of the pattern only if it is performed because the builder
believes that it will contribute towards her goal of a house being built through
her own agency. In this analysis, which is Aristotelian, intentional categories are
essential for defining the behavior pattern. The applicability of intentional
categories to states of an organism cannot be grounded in the operant processes
of discrimination alone. (1995/1996, p. 69)
The behavior of the builder is predictable only insofar as we ascribe to her the
desire to build a house and the belief that placing this brick will lead to building a
wall, that building the wall will contribute to the fabrication of a room, and so on.
We need some mechanism for attributing these desires and beliefs. We do so partly
on the basis of an idea of rational behavior in the circumstances and partly by
inference from the builder’s behavior pattern, including her verbal behavior. This
displays an initial analysis based on the contextual stance (the operant behavior she
displays is likely to result in this consequence that will increase the probability of
her doing such and such next. . .), which is overlain by an intentional heuristic
based on optimality, the assumption of desires and beliefs appropriate to the
situation, and the ruling out of consequences that are improbable or nonmaximizing (i.e., are impossible ends to attach to her behavior). We can
immediately rule out the possibility that she is building a staircase to heaven,
therefore, or a marble palace, or a headquarters building for the Society for the
Protection of Small Disingenuous Wooden Italians with Extensible Noses. But can
19
FOXALL
teleological behaviorism? It may be significant that the predictive capacity of this
approach is greatest in the context of the narrowly-defined and measurable utility
functions of everyday economic life rather than in broader circumstances.
Statements couched in intentional terms are intentionally opaque: they are not
susceptible to coextensional substitution (Juarrero, 1999, p. 38). The alternative
consequences that could be spun out indefinitely by teleological behaviorism are
coextensives in an intentional sentence: “I intend to place one more brick/build a
wall/construct a cathedral.” The intentional form emphasizes that these alternatives
cannot be substituted one for another on the basis of the information the interpreter
has as he makes his observation of what the person is doing.
Ascribing Intentionality
It is one thing to propose that a psychological theory requires the ascription of
content to a pre-existing extensional theory such as that provided by physiology,
but quite a trickier endeavor to justify the proposed level of analysis in
psychologically-relevant terms, lay down procedures for the process of ascription,
and specify the relationship between the two. So Dennett (1969) finally explores
the manner in which content might be ascribed to physiological systems. This is
the crux of his argument against behaviorism and for a psychology that proceeds
by ascribing content to the extensional facts of physiology. The personal level of
explanation (which is Dennett’s focus here and which he contrasts with the subpersonal level at which physiology operates) is that of “people and their sensations
and activities” rather than that of “brains and events in the nervous system” (p. 93).
The sub-personal level provides mechanistic explanations, but they are not
appropriate to the explanation of so-called mental entities such as pain. While there
is a good understanding of the neurological basis of pain, Dennett raises the
question of whether the presumed evolutionarily-appropriate afferent–efferent
networks underlying this understanding are sufficient (they are certainly necessary)
to account for the “phenomena of pain.” This resolves itself into the question of
whether pain is an entity that exists in addition to the physical questions that
constitute this network (p. 91).
There are no events or processes in the brain that “exhibit the characteristics
of the putative ‘mental phenomena’ of pain” that are apparent when we speak in
everyday terms about pain or pains. Such verbalizations are non-mechanical, while
brain events and processes are mechanical. It is unclear, for instance, how an
individual distinguishes a sensation of pain from a nonpainful sensation. The only
distinguishing feature of pain sensations is “painfulness,” which is an unanalyzable
quality that allows for only circular definition. But people can do this, and the
personal level is the level at which pains are discriminated, not the sub-personal.
Neurons and brains have no sensation of pains and do not discriminate them.
Pains, like other mental phenomena, do not refer. Our speaking of them does not
pick out any thing; pain is simply a personal-level phenomenon that has,
nevertheless, some corresponding states, events, or processes at the sub-personal,
physiological level. This is not an identity theory; Dennett does not identify the
20
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
experience of pain with some physical happening. He maintains two separate
levels of explanation: one in which the experience of pain, while felt, does not
refer, and one in which the descriptions of neural occurrences refer to actual neural
structures, events, and states in which the extensionally-characterized science
deals.
The task now becomes that of ascribing content to the internal states and
events. The first stage is straightforward since intentional theory assumes that the
structures and events they seek to explain are appropriate to their purpose. An
important link in this ascription is provided by hypotheses drawn from the natural
selection not only of species but of brains and the nervous system—a system
which, through evolution, has the capacity to produce appropriate efferent
responses to the afferent stimulation it encounters. It clearly has the ability to
discriminate among the repertoire of efferent responses it might conceivably make.
Its ability to discriminate and respond to the stimulus characteristics of its complex
environment means that it must be “capable of interpreting its peripheral
stimulation” to engender inner states or events that co-occur with the phenomena
that arise in its perceptual field. In order for us to be justified in calling the process
intelligent, something must be added to this afferent analysis: the capacity to
associate the outcomes of the afferent analysis with structures in the efferent
portion of the brain.
For instance, in order to detect the presence of a substance as food, an
organism must have the capacity not only to detect the substance but, once
encountered, to stop seeking and start eating. Without this capacity to associate
afferent stimulation and efferent response, the organism could not be said to have
detected the presence of the substance as that of food. Dennett uses this point to
criticize behaviorists for having no answer to the question how the organism
selects the appropriate response. There is a need to invest the animal that has
discriminated a stimulus with the capacity to “know” what its appropriate response
should be.4
The content of a neural state, event, or structure relies on its stimulation and
the appropriate efferent effects to which it give rise, and in order to delineate these
it is necessary to transcend the extensional description of stimulus and response. It
is necessary to relate the content to the environmental conditions as perceived by
the organism’s sense organs so that it can be given reference to the real-world
phenomena that produced the stimulation. It is equally important to specify what
the organism “does with” the event or state so produced in order to determine what
that event or state “means” to the organism. An aversive stimulus has not only to
be identified along with the neural changes it engenders to signify that it means
danger to the animal; in addition, the animal has to respond appropriately to the
4
In fact, behaviorists have ducked this problem by designating it as part of the
physiologist’s assignment and drawing the conclusion that behavioral scientists need be
concerned with it no longer. The conventional behaviorist wisdom over the kind of
cognitive ascription to which Dennett refers is that it amounts to no more than “premature
physiology.”
21
FOXALL
stimulus (e.g., by moving away). Failure on its part to do so would mean that we
were not justified in ascribing such content to the physiological processes
occurring as a result of the stimulation. If we are to designate the animal’s
activities as “intelligent decision making,” then this behavioral link must be
apparent. Only events in the brain that appear appropriately linked in this way can
be ascribed content and described in intentional idioms.
How, then, are the intentional ascription and the extensionally descriptions
related? This ascribed content is not an additional characteristic of the event, state,
or structure to which it is allocated; some intrinsic part of it discovered within it as
its extensionally-characterized features are discovered by the physiologist. They
are a matter of additional interpretation. The features of neural systems,
extensionally characterized in terms of physiology or physics, are describable and
predictable in those terms without intentional ascription, which makes reference to
meaning or content. Such a scientific story, consisting in an account of behavior
confined to talk of the structure and functions of neural cells and so on, is entirely
extensional in character. But such an extensional story could not, according to
Dennett, provide us with an understanding of what the organism is doing. Only an
intentional account can accomplish this, “but it is not a story about features of the
world in addition to features of the extensional story; it just describes what
happens in a different way” (see Dennett, 1969, pp. 90-96). Such an extensional
theory would be confined to the description/explanation of the motions of the
organism rather than of its actions.
In practice, physiologists do not seem able to get along in their account of the
function of the central nervous system without viewing neural operations as
signals, reports, or messages (for modern corroboration see, for a typical textbook
treatment: Gazzaniga, Ivry, & Mangun, 1998; and inter alia for direct research
evidence: Angulo, Staiger, Rossier, & Audinat, 1999; Kandel, 2001). As Dennett
puts it:
Were the physiologist to ban all Intentional coloration from his account of brain
functioning, his story at best would have the form: functional structure A has the
function of stimulating functional structure B whenever it is stimulated by either
C or D. . . .No amount of this sort of story will ever answer questions like why
rat A knows which way to go for his food. If one does ascribe content to events,
the system of ascription in no way interferes with whatever physical theory of
function one has at the extensional level, and in this respect endowing events
with content is like giving an interpretation to a formal mathematical calculus or
axiom system, a move which does not affect its functions or implications but
may improve intuitive understanding of the system. (1969, p. 79)
The required ascriptions of content would thus not comprise intervening
variables within a physiological theory but a “heuristic overlay” on the extensional
account. Such a centralist theory would have two components:
. . .the extensional account of the interaction of functional structures, and an
Intentional characterization of these structures, the events occurring within
them, and states of the structures resulting from these. The implicit link between
22
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
each bit of Intentional interpretation and its extensional foundation is a
hypothesis or series of hypotheses describing the evolutionary source of the
fortuitously propitious arrangement in virtue of which the system’s operation in
this instance makes sense. (1969, p. 80)
The ascription of content to afferent and efferent operations is necessarily
imprecise since it depends on the inexact locutions we use in everyday life.
Taking Stock
I have argued that the legitimate ascription of content relies emphatically
upon the clear understanding of the nature of the personal level of analysis, a
matter on which Dennett, after the brilliant insight of his 1969 essay, has proved
somewhat flexible over the years. After the clear start he made in Content and
Consciousness (1969), Dennett subsequently loosened the argument that content
was ascribable only at the personal level of non-mechanical explanation and
proposed that mechanistic, sub-personal systems may be treated as intentional
systems in their own right via the ascription of content that permits their
prediction. Dennett’s introduction of the idea of sub-personal cognitive psychology
is a particular source of confusion of his original personal/sub-personal dichotomy.
The present paper now attempts, therefore, to lay an unambiguous basis for
behavioral psychology, in which the level of analysis at which content ascription
may properly be made is established as the personal level, and the range of nonpersonal levels of analysis which provide the basis for such attribution is extended
from the sub-personal to the super-personal in order that behavior may be
systematically incorporated in the scheme of explanation to which Dennett has
given rise. It argues, moreover, that only at the personal level is it possible to
ascribe intentionality in order to explain behavior. Of particular importance in the
present context, it is the only level at which cognition and consciousness can be
ascribed. The development in Dennett’s thought with respect to the personal/subpersonal distinction is specifically addressed, and the confusion in philosophical
psychology that has arisen from the proliferation of levels of explanation is
examined. It is argued that the personal level, which is at least severely deemphasized in Dennett’s continuing work, is of central importance to the
philosophical basis of cognitive psychology since it is the sole level at which
cognition can be said to occur.
The Categorical Distinction
The personal level of explanation is of central importance to both intentional
and behavioral psychologies—to the first because it is at this level alone that
intentional content can be legitimately ascribed, and to the second because of the
necessity of making sense of private events and their status in a causal theory. I do
not think that anyone has argued more convincingly for the theoretical necessity of
this level of analysis, nor done more to qualify its theoretical value, than Daniel
Dennett. The grounds provided by Dennett for the legitimate ascription of content
23
FOXALL
have, with time, become vaguer insofar as they have become explicitly detached
from the logic of evolutionarily-consistent reasoning that originally underpinned
the distinction. Admittedly, the rules for ascribing beliefs and desires to a rational
system in order to predict it (i.e., the execution of the intentional stance or, as
Dennett refers to it, the intentional strategy) include consideration of what beliefs
and desires such a system “ought” to have given its position and circumstances,
and this is bound to include considerations that stem from its phylogenetic history
as well as its current setting. But this is a less detailed and less logically
constructed version of the procedure for allocation content than that given in
Content and Consciousness (Dennett, 1969). This procedure involves the
ascription of content to the theories and findings of the extensional sciences that
proceed at the sub-personal level, but it leaves them intact in the process. There is
an additional level of interpretation that does not take place in the terms of the
extensional science on which it is built, thus it is not a contribution to
neuroscience; rather, it comprises a heuristic device that is composed of intentional
idioms, which do not belong in an extensional science. It exists on a level other
than the sub-personal, which characterizes neuroscience. It exists on the personal
level, the only level at which it is legitimate to ascribe content, according to the
early Dennett. This is the process in which the ascription of intentional idioms
takes place and the process that produces the personal level by prescribing in a way
that is highly circumscribed (by the logic of evolution by natural selection) the
content that an evolved entity “ought” to have by virtue of its phylogeny.
But there is more to the prediction and explanation of the organism’s behavior
than the ascription of content according to the principles of evolutionarilyconsistent reasoning. The intentional strategy (Dennett, 1987) assumes that the
behavior of an organism can be predicted only by the ascription of content relating
not only to its evolution but also to its current position, those of its circumstances
that signal the rewards and punishments of following a particular course of action
primed by the organism’s learning history gained in similar circumstances. It
requires, in other words, the ascription of content (again to arrive at the personal
level) on the basis of the theories and findings of extensional science, which deals
with the effects of social and physical context on the ontogenetic development of
the organism, including its acquisition of a behavioral repertoire. I submit that this
science is behavior analysis, in which the fundamental unit of analysis is the
environment–behavior contingency (Lee, 1988). Content may be legitimately
attributed to the findings of this science on the basis of the principle of “selection
by consequences” (Skinner, 1981), which includes not only natural selection but
the process in which a behavioral repertoire is acquired in the course of operant
conditioning. Behavior analysis thus provides an extensional basis for a superpersonal level of analysis. How would the process of ascription be determined in
this case?
Commentators on Content and Consciousness seem often to overlook the
ambitious nature of Dennett’s project: the resolution of the claims of extensional
science with the inevitability of intentional explanation of behavior. This is to be
achieved not by the super-conceptual integration of the two systems of
24
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
explanation, which retain their individual claims to uniqueness as explicators of
one or other facet of natural phenomena, but to ground the intentional in a basis of
materialism that rescues it from apparently unlimited phenomenological
speculation.
Dennett notes the unfeasibility of S-R theorists—under which term he seems
to subsume advocates of both respondent and operant behaviors—showing how a
novel stimulus can arrive at or select the appropriate response. He points out, for
instance, that an animal might detect a stimulus but not “know” what the
appropriate response is (the stimulus in question could just as well be a
discriminative stimulus as an unconditioned or conditioned one). No afferent can
be taken by the brain to have a specific significance unless it is recognized by the
efferent side of the brain has having just that significance (i.e., until the brain has
produced the appropriate response). The content of a neural event or state depends
not only upon its “normal state of stimulation” but also on whatever additional
efferent effects it produces. The determination of these factors necessarily takes us
beyond the extensional description of stimuli and responses. Indeed, as emphasized
earlier, the lack of an account of behavior at the personal level imposes a severe
restriction on radical behaviorist explanation (Foxall, 2004).
Content can accordingly be ascribed to a neural event when it is a link in an
appropriate chain between afferent and efferent that has been selected in the
course of the phylogeny of the organism in question. The content is not something
to be discovered within this neural event; it is an extra interpretation, the rationale
of which is not to understand better the operation of the subsystem per se but to
provide a local justification for the ascription of appropriate content at the personal
level. The ultimate justification for such ascription is provided by evolutionary
thinking: the intelligent brain must be able to select the appropriate response to a
specific stimulus. Why should this be less the case for the link between extensional
operant analysis and the personal level of analysis than for the link between
physiology and that level? Intentional ascription simply describes what a purely
extensional theory would describe—nothing more—but in a different way. This
different way may be useful to the physiologist, however. Neuroscience that does
not view neural events as signals, reports, or messages can scarcely function at all.
No purely biological logic can tell us why the rat knows which way to go for his
food. Nor can any purely contextualistic logic reveal this in the absence of some
sort of “Dennettian overlay.” In neither case does the proposed intentional
ascription detract from the extensional version of events; rather, it adds an
interpretation that provides greater intuitive understanding of the system.
Hence, the sub-personal level is coterminous with that of an extensional
science such as physiology, which is mechanistic in the explanations it provides.
Intentional explanation simply does not belong at this level and we cannot add
content to this level without violating its integrity as a conventionally scientific
(i.e., extensional) approach to theory. We can, however, use it as the basis of
appropriate content ascription (i.e., the attribution of intentional idioms that make
certain behaviors of the organism intelligible—pain, for instance, or other
emotional activity), but in so adding content we arrive at the personal level of
25
FOXALL
explanation. This is the sole level at which pain, etc. can be comprehended. There
is a sharp epistemological dichotomy here between the personal and sub-personal
levels of explanation, at one of which it is appropriate to include intentional
explanations, the other serving as a basis for legitimately doing so but remaining
intact as an extensional level of understanding. The guiding principle by which
content is added is evolutionary logic. The process of natural selection that
produced the findings identified at the level of physiology (or other sub-personal
science) must provide the logic by which activities that are proposed in order to
explain or predict the behavior of the whole organism.
The Intentional Stance
By the time of Dennett’s (1981) distinction among three kinds of intentional
psychology, however, his thinking demonstrates some subtle changes in the use of
the terms personal and sub-personal levels and their relationships with psychology.
He argues that folk psychology (the first kind of intentional psychology) provides
a source of the other two: “intentional systems theory” and “sub-personal cognitive
psychology.” Folk psychology provides a non-specific and unhelpful causal theory
of behavior; a more systematic and useful predictive tool requires refinement. The
distinction between logical constructs or abstracta and causally-interacting illata
provides a key. While the beliefs and desires of abstract and instrumental folk
psychology are abstracta, the interactive theoretical constructs of sub-personal
cognitive psychology are illata.
Each of the two additional intentional psychologies Dennett proposes rests
integrally on one or other. Intentional systems theory (the second kind of
intentional psychology) draws upon the notions of belief and desire but provides
them with a more technical meaning than they receive in folk psychology. It is a
whole-person psychology, dealing with “. . .the prediction and explanation from
belief–desire profiles of the actions of whole systems. . . .The subject of all the
intentional attributions is the whole system (the person, the animal, or even the
corporation or nation [see Dennett, 1976] rather than any of its parts. . .)” (Dennett,
1987, p. 58). Intentional systems theory is a competence theory in that it specifies
the functional requirements of the system without going on to speculate as to what
form they might take (Dennett, 1978, p. 74). The necessity of this general-level
theory is that of providing an account of intelligence, meaning, reference, or
representation. Intentional systems theory is blind to the internal structure of the
system. According to Dennett, the capacity of abstracta to interrelate, predict, and
partly explain behavior itself suggests some underlying mechanism to which
intentional systems theory does not, in principle, address itself. Any intentional
system of interest would surely have a complex internal structure, and chances are
that this will be found to resemble closely the instrumental intentional
interpretation. The third kind of intentional psychology, “sub-personal cognitive
psychology,” is tasked with explaining the brain as a syntactic engine as opposed to
the task of intentional systems theory, which is to explain it as a semantic engine
(see below). By contrast to intentional systems theory, which is a competence
26
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
model, sub-personal cognitive psychology is a performance model, one designed to
specify the workings of the system in terms of variables that can enter into a
scientific theory, that is, in terms of illata (Dennett, 1978, pp. 74-78).
Note that this terminology and leap in analysis is itself misleading and
confusing. The level of illata is simply that of cognitive psychology: there is no
need to designate it further as sub-personal. This immediately suggests a source of
confusion with the sub-personal level of analysis, especially as it has been defined
in terms of the extensional rather than the intentional. It appears, moreover, that
Dennett is thinking of cognitive psychology as requiring no other qualification
than sub-personal. He does not contrast this with super-personal cognitive
psychology, for instance—this does not enter into his thinking at all. The
distinction he is making is between the personal level, at which abstracta operate,
and that of another level at which illata operate. For him, this is the sub-personal.
But, as I aim to show in this paper, cognitive psychology may require sub-personal
and/or super-personal qualification, depending upon which source of justification
for the ascription of cognitive variables at the personal level of analysis is being
alluded to. In the case of sub-personal cognitive psychology this remains the
naturally selected afferent–efferent linkages embedded in neurology; in the case of
super-personal cognitive psychology it is environment–behavior linkages. I shall
argue, further, that both abstracta and illata are phenomena of the personal level.
The analysis appropriate to what is internal to the organism is neuroscience;
intentionalistic psychological theories must perforce deal at the personal level.
The underlying mechanism to which even abstracta appeal in their capacity to
explain and which (sub-personal) cognitive psychology attempts to uncover and
explicate must surely be physiological in nature and requires an extensional
neuroscience to reveal it. Cognitive psychology remains as theoretical an
enterprise as intentional systems theory: its focus is the explanation of the brain as
syntactical through its identification of the cognitive variables that may be
legitimately ascribed at the personal level. In doing this it draws upon both its subpersonal and super-personal inputs—neurology and behavior—both of which are
approached through an extensional science. But cognitive psychology itself
remains an intentional science. To deviate from this “pure” dichotomy of the
personal and sub-personal/super-personal is to invite the “mereological fallacy,”
the attribution to parts of a system of features that properly belong only to the
system as a whole (Bennett & Hacker, 2003; see box on the next page).
27
FOXALL
Mereological Confusion
The presupposition Dennett makes about sub-personal cognitive psychology (to the effect that
elements of sub-personal physiology such as the brain and the remainder of the nervous system can
be treated as intentional systems in themselves in order to predict their behavior) certainly comes
under considerable criticism from Bennett and Hacker (2003) on the grounds that it is intelligible to
ascribe intentionality only to systems that are known to bear beliefs and desires.
Bennett and Hacker (2003, p. 73) specifically criticize Dennett on the grounds that he has
committed the “mereological fallacy.” Mereology refers to the logical relations of parts and wholes.
The mereological principle says that psychological predicates that properly apply only to human
beings cannot be meaningfully attributed to parts of the human being such as the brain. Hence, the
ascription to a part of an organism the attributes that properly belong only to the whole organism is
the mereological fallacy: “Human beings, but not their brains, can be said to be thoughtful or
thoughtless; animals, but not their brains, let alone the hemispheres of their brains, can be said to see,
hear, smell and taste things; people, but not their brains, can be said to make decisions or to be
indecisive.” (ibid). This fallacy is widespread among neurophysiologists, they claim, citing scientists
who argue that “the brain has experiences, believes things, interprets clues on the basis of
information made available to it, and makes guesses. . .categorizes. . .and conceptually manipulates
rules. . . .[T]he brain knows things, reasons inductively, and constructs hypotheses on the basis of
arguments, and its constituent neurons are intelligent, can estimate probabilities, and present
arguments. [T]he brain poses questions, searches for answers, and constructs hypotheses. . . .[B]rains
decide, or at least ‘decide’, and initiate voluntary action. [T]here are symbols in the brain, and the
brain uses, and presumably understands, symbols. . . .[T]he brain makes classifications, comparisons,
and decisions” (pp. 68-70). However, these authors contend that we simply do not know what it is for
brains to do these things: we only know what it is for a person to do them. They further point out that
whether psychological behavior can be imputed to the brain is a philosophical matter rather than an
empirical one.
The mereological principle is non-empirical: it is not subject to confirmation or disconfirmation
by experimentation or other empirical means. It is a convention and could be overturned, but only at
the cost of changing a great deal else—changing the meaning of words and a host of familiar concept
(p. 81). These authors are, therefore, adamant that intentionality cannot be ascribed to artifacts like
computers, thermostats, molecules, brains: “Not only is it a subclass of psychological attributes that
are the appropriate bearers of intentionality and not animals or things, but, further, only animals, and
fairly sophisticated animals at that, and not parts of animals, let alone molecules, thermostats or
computers, are the subject of such attributes” (p. 423).
This seems equivalent to saying that there has to be an ontological basis for a being/entity’s
believing in order to ascribe rational beliefs to it. The problem with Dennett’s levels arises when he
switches from the sub-personal as a means of working out what intentional idioms can be ascribed at
the personal level to the idea that the raison d’être of intentional idioms is their capacity to predict
behavior. He then gets involved in how to predict sub-personal events, characterizes them as (parts
of) intentional systems, and applies the intentional stance.
“Given Dennett’s conception of the intentional stance, it is unclear what precisely he means by
claiming that the brain gathers information, anticipates things, interprets the information it receives,
arrives at conclusions, etc. Presumably he is ‘adopting the intentional stance’ towards the brain, and
is treating it as if it were a rational agent that believes what it ought to believe and desires what it
ought to desire and acts on its beliefs and desires. But this is not coherent. We know what it is to treat
a young child as if it were an adult, rational human being, but so we have any idea what it would be
like to treat a brain as if it were a rational being? The brain. . .is not a possible subject of beliefs and
desires; there is no such thing as a brain acting on beliefs and desires, and there is nothing that the
brain does that can be predicted on the basis of its beliefs and desires” (Bennett & Hacker, 2003, p.
426). This is precisely what Dennett does in his later work: treating the subsystem of the brain as an
intentional system. The answer is to restrict (a) the ascription of intentionality to the personal level of
people, (b) to use the intentional stance again only for persons, and (c) to use the intentional stance as
a device for explanation rather than prediction (cf. Elton, 2003).
28
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
The subtle difference that accompanies Dennett’s later usages inheres in his
argument (1978, p. 154) that the behavior of the person as a whole is the outcome
of the interactive behavior of its various subsystems (Hornsby, 2000, pp. 16-17).
This is a departure from his earlier insistence that to move to the sub-personal level
(i.e., to the operation of the central and peripheral nervous systems) is to leave
behind the personal level of explanation of sensations, intentionality, and behavior.
Hornsby argues that this is inconsistent with the proscription of using sub-personal
level findings to understand the personal level. Why-questions about the behavior
of an actor in an environment can be answered only at the personal level. The
problem is Dennett’s later claim that the program of sub-personal cognitive
psychology is to show how the physicalist findings of sub-personal extensional
science can be used to interpret a fully-realized intentional system operating at the
personal level.
Hornsby (2000, pp. 20-21) seeks to maintain the distinction between personal
and sub-personal levels of explanation by arguing that intentional phenomena are
real at the levels of persons but merely as-if constructions at the sub-personal level.
The attraction of this distinction is that it maintains the independence of the
personal level as a basis of explanation but permits the intentional stance to be
operated at the sub-personal level for purposes of predicting the behavior of
subsystems. Her somewhat arbitrary assertion, however, makes an ontological
distinction between persons and non-persons (animals, subsystems, machines) that
Dennett has sidestepped by adopting an instrumental approach to the ascription of
intentionality (ascription is justified if it facilitates prediction; to have a mind or its
constituent beliefs, desires, etc. is simply to have behavior that is predictable on the
assumption that one has a mind, beliefs, desires, etc.). Dennett seems to have dealt
with her position already (1978, pp. 272-273). Again, it is the distinction between
Dennett’s earlier and later positions on instrumentalism versus realism that seems
to be at the heart of the misunderstanding.
This problem clearly rests on the more limited project in Content and
Consciousness, which focused on the materialistic delineation of the intentional by
reference to a genuinely sub-personal level of neuroscience, and Dennett’s later
enterprise focusing on the development of sub-personal cognitive psychology as
the basis of a philosophy of cognitivism. In Content and Consciousness Dennett
was concerned primarily with establishing how the findings of an extensional
neuroscience could be brought into a single framework of analysis along with the
conclusions of a mental science which recognized, albeit critically, the reality of
intentional phenomena. The overall framework was to be consistent with
materialism and thus to eschew an easy metaphysical reconciliation. The aim was
to devise an a-ontological basis for the systematic ascription of content to the
findings of physiology (a science of the sub-personal), the purpose of which was
not to enhance or contribute to neuroscience per se but to justify the intentional
ascriptions that could be legitimately made to the whole person. What could this
physiology be said to have by way of beliefs and desires? The ascriptions are not
part of physiology but an additional interpretation that makes possible analysis at
29
FOXALL
the personal level that prevents the unwarranted ascription of intentional content
simply to explain behavior on mentalistic, uncritical, folk-psychological grounds.
The implications for cognitive psychology that are drawn in a rudimentary
way in Content and Consciousness are that it is an activity of the personal level
that inextricably involves intentional phenomena, but that it has been reconciled
with extensional science through the agency of natural selection. It is when
Dennett (1978) seeks to clarify the nature of intentional psychology by introducing
a distinction between intentional systems theory and sub-personal cognitive
psychology that potential confusion arises. The difficulty revolves around the
status of sub-personal cognitive psychology.
In seeking to resolve it, it is important to appreciate that the sub-personal level
of explanation that Dennett (1969) describes differs from the sub-personal
cognitive psychology he introduced later (1981). While the sub-personal level
consists of extensional science, sub-personal cognitive psychology, being derived
from folk psychology, adds to this the heuristic overlay of ascribed intentional
content that properly belongs at the personal level. However, many levels of
explanation emerge from Dennett’s scheme, the most prevalent current cognitive
psychology, social cognition, is founded upon another: the super-personal level, an
extensional psychology founded upon the “contextual stance,” which relates
behavior to the environmental contingencies that shape and maintain it (Foxall,
1999) and which is linked to the personal level of explanation by means of the
ascription to the theories and findings of that extensional science of intentional
content (Foxall, 2004). The three stances (pre-empirical methodological
prescriptions for the prediction and partial explanation of systems) that Dennett
proposes provide a key to the number of levels of explanation at which psychology
may operate and clarify some of their interrelationships. In particular, the design
stance, which Elton (2003) shows to be bifurcated in Dennett’s writings, is highly
relevant to the distinction between the sub-personal level of explanation and subpersonal cognitive psychology.
Sub-Personal Cognitive Psychology
As useful as a competence theory is, there has to be some underlying internal
structure that accounts for the capacity of the various abstracta that are the
components of intentional systems theory to predict systemic behavior at the
personal level so well. Discovering this structure and its workings is the task of the
third kind of intentional psychology: sub-personal cognitive psychology, the task
of which consists in “[d]iscovering the constraints on design and implementation
variation, and demonstrating how particular species and individuals in fact succeed
in realizing intentional systems” (Dennett, 1987, p. 60).
The task of the brain, according to intentional systems theory and
evolutionary biology, is semantic: it must decipher what its stimulus inputs mean
then respond with appropriate behavior. But, in fact, to the physiologist the brain is
no more than a syntactic engine: it “discriminate[s] its inputs by their structural,
30
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
temporal, and physical features and let[s] its entirely mechanical activities be
governed by these ‘syntactic’ features of its inputs” (Dennett, 1987, p. 61). Hence:
. . .it is the task of sub-personal cognitive psychology to propose and test
models. . .of pattern recognition or stimulus generalization, concept learning,
expectation, learning, goal-directed behavior, problem-solving—that not only
produce a simulacrum of genuine content-sensitivity, but that do this in ways
demonstrably like the way people’s brains do it, exhibiting the same powers and
the same vulnerabilities to deception, overload and confusion. It is here that we
will find our good theoretical entities, our useful illata, and while some of them
may well resemble the familiar entities of folk psychology—beliefs, desires,
judgments, decisions—many will certainly not. . . .The only similarity we can be
sure of discovering in the illata of sub-personal cognitive psychology is the
intentionality of their labels (see Brainstorms [Dennett, 1978], pp. 23-38). They
will be characterized as events with content, bearing information, signaling this
and ordering that. (Dennett, 1987, p. 63)
In order to give the illata these labels, in order to maintain any intentional
interpretation of their operation at all, the theorist must always keep glancing
outside the system, to see what normally produces the configuration he is
describing, what effects the system’s responses normally have on the
environment, and what benefit normally accrues to the whole system from this
activity. . . .The alternative of ignoring the external world and its relations to the
internal machinery. . .is not really psychology at all, but just at best abstract
neurophysiology—pure internal syntax with no hope of a semantic
interpretation. Psychology “reduced” to neurophysiology in this fashion would
not be psychology, for it would not be able to provide an explanation of the
regularities it is psychology’s particular job to explain: the reliability with which
“intelligent” organisms can cope with their environments and thus prolong their
lives. Psychology can, and should, work toward an account of the physiological
foundations of psychological processes, not by eliminating psychological or
intentional characterizations of those processes, but by exhibiting how the brain
implements the intentionally characterized performance specifications of subpersonal theories. (Dennett, 1987, p. 64)
Evaluation
We should now appraise Dennett’s altering conception and attribution of
importance to the distinction of personal and sub-personal levels of explanation.
Four distinct phases are apparent in his thought. The first is the so-called
“categorical” distinction (held in varying forms by Davidson, 1980; Davies, 2000;
Elton, 2000; Gardner, 2000; Hornsby, 2000), which maintains the analytical
difference between these levels of explanation that Dennett set out in 1969.
Dennett here holds to a strict personal/sub-personal distinction, using the latter to
ascribe intentionality at the personal level. He also maintains a strict difference
between extensional and intentional sciences, claiming that both are necessary. The
role of behavior appears important here because it is to its explanation that the
31
FOXALL
ascription of intentionality is ostensibly directed. It receives no explicit definition
or analysis, however; it is taken as a given, albeit an important one.
In the 1970s, and certainly by 1980, Dennett’s criterion for the ascription of
content changed from one that was explicitly justifiable on biological grounds to
that of the predictability of behavior. This progression, by means of the
introduction of the intentional stance, marks the abandonment of the personal level
as a seriously entertained analytic category. The distinction between personal and
sub-personal, crucial to the originally argued basis for the legitimate ascription of
content, is lost as the intentional stance comes to be applied to sub-personal units
in order to predict them (see also Hornsby, 2000). The mereological fallacy,
inherent in Dennett’s reasoning, rules out such a move despite the stand on realism
that Dennett takes. Behavior is still important because its predictability is a
criterion of the legitimate ascription of the mental—but it still receives no
additional analysis, nor even a definition.
The third phase comes with Dennett’s attempt to include cognitive
functioning at the sub-personal level, the so-called “sub-personal cognitive
psychology” that he has made the center of his philosophy of psychology. The subpersonal that is now the focus of attention is an intentional level of analysis that
spans the divide between neurology and the personal. The categorical distinction is
being further eroded. Behavior now is more sidelined than before. But is the notion
of sub-personal cognition sustainable, or does cognition belong at the personal
level?
The final phase (so far) is Dennett’s explanation of consciousness. By now
any suggestion that the personal is important appears to have been lost—though
Elton (2000) disagrees—as the quest is for the heterophenomenological
interpretation of behavior at the third-personal level. But Elton claims that
consciousness can only be entertained at the personal level. Behavior again
assumes importance if only because it must form the referential basis of
heterophenomenological attribution of the content of consciousness. Without a
firm basis for such attribution, however (in the form of rules for the legitimate
ascription of intentional content that carry the same epistemological force that
extensional neuroscience provided for intentionality advanced in Content and
Consciousness), the use of mental idioms relapses into the loose mode of content
attribution that Dennett’s scheme in that work was specifically designed to guard
against. I shall argue that the solution lies in the adoption of an extensional
behavioral science paralleling that of extensional neuroscience. However, before
exploring further the place of behavioral science in a comprehensive model of
human behavior, two points about the sub-personal level of explanation remain to
be made. The first arises out of Dennett’s use of two apparently related terms, the
“sub-personal level of explanation” and “sub-personal cognitive psychology.” The
latter term concerns the appropriate level of explanation to which cognitive
psychology belongs.
32
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
The Sub-Personal Level and Sub-Personal Cognitive Psychology
The definition of the sub-personal level as being a target for intentional
ascription (i.e., the view that the intentional stance can be used at any level of
analysis at which it permits prediction superior to that provided by other stances),
something which jars with Dennett’s views in Content and Consciousness (though
not with his later opinion), reflects the fact that Dennett uses the term “subpersonal” in two ways (Elton, 2000). In the first, the sub-personal level is devoid
of ascribed intentionality in its own right. In Content and Consciousness he speaks
of neuroscience in this capacity; the intentionality is something additional to the
extensional science, and bringing them together results in the personal-level
analysis by making legitimate (in terms of evolutionary reasoning) the ascription
of appropriate content at that level. The extensional science is coterminous with
the sub-personal level of analysis. In the second usage, the sub-personal level
incorporates intentionality per se: this is the sub-personal cognitive psychology he
speaks of in “Three Kinds of Intentional Psychology” (Dennett, 1981). There is no
contradiction here since the sub-personal level he defines in Content and
Consciousness and the sub-personal cognitive psychology he speaks of later are
different levels of explanation, each of which draws upon the design stance in its
own way (Elton, 2003, pp. 38-41). The first is the “causal blueprint perspective,”
in which the design of a system is closely related to its causal structure: whether
the system is performing as designed can be ascertained by comparing its
functioning with the blueprint of its causal structure. For instance, how well a
chess computer is operating can be judged by comparing its operation with that
specified by the program that regulates it. This design gives no indication of what
the system is for; even a non-chess playing person could make a judgment of the
efficacy of its operations in this manner. The design purpose of the machine does
not attract consideration. The “teleological interpretation” of the design stance is,
however, vitally concerned with the purpose of the system. The purpose that the
system was designed to fulfill can be specified and its progress toward fulfilling
that purpose monitored without reference to the causal blueprint of the system. We
may know what a spark plug is designed to do and determine its success without
knowing how it does it at the level of its sub-operations. We can nevertheless make
predictions about the behavior of the spark plug and assess its efficacy in reaching
its goal. In the case of the teleological perspective we are concerned with what the
system as a whole is designed to do; with the causal blueprint perspective we are
concerned with what the subsystems are designed to accomplish and with their
interactions.
Acknowledging the two kinds of sub-personal analysis results, however, in
the proliferation of levels of analysis and raises the question of where any
particular psychological theory fits among them. This is quite clear in the case of
social cognitive psychology, which is revealed to have connections with both the
personal level and sub-personal cognitive psychology but to derive its distinctive
purview of human behavior predominantly from yet another level of analysis, the
super-personal level of explanation. The sub-personal level that Dennett identified
33
FOXALL
in Content and Consciousness is guided, in practice, by that design stance that
Elton (2000) understands in terms of the causal blueprint perspective in which
physiology attempts, by reverse engineering, to establish how the organism’s
subsystems have been designed in the process of evolution by natural selection.
The physical stance is also apparent here. By contrast, sub-personal cognitive
psychology involves the teleological perspective of the design stance in which
intentionality is invoked and ascribed in the attempt to reverse engineer the system
as a psychological entity in order to permit the prediction of the system as a whole.
Now Dennett claims that sub-personal systems can be treated as intentional
systems (i.e., the intentional stance can be adopted toward them). Elton (2000, p.
4) notes that contrary to Dennett’s initial clear distinction between the personal and
sub-personal levels, he later (notably in Consciousness Explained, 1991) spoke as
though the autonomy of the personal level were in doubt and as though an analysis
in personal terms could be given of the sub-personal. He notes McDowell’s (1994)
claims that instead of maintaining the distinction between on the one hand (1) the
relationship between a person and her environment and on the other (2) the
relationship between different components of a person, Dennett conflates them.
Hence, Dennett’s claim that consciousness inheres in a person’s capacity to access
the content carried by a subsystem mixes stories that, must by their nature, be kept
separate. According to Elton, however, Dennett does indeed want to pursue the
idea of sub-personal processing as a prelude to his conclusions about
consciousness, and the problem is reconciling this with the force of Dennett’s
original distinction between the personal and sub-personal. He claims that this is
possible if pursued with understanding of how Dennett conceptualizes the
ascription of content to systems and their component parts. Dennett has never
denied that subsystems can be content-bearing, but he has not provided many clues
as to how such ascription is to take place. Elton suggests that the procedure is as
follows: Intentional states (attitudes towards contents) can be attributed, Dennett
says, to intentional systems, which include people, frogs, chess machines, and
robots. They can (Elton says of Dennett) also include parts of such systems, which
can be seen as constituting smaller systems in themselves. On the assumption that
the system under investigation has some goals (e.g., to survive, to win, to avoid
injuring humans) and some “rational” means to achieve them (e.g., perceptual
apparatus, powers of action), “one then ascribes a whole network of intentional
states (both cognitive and motivational) that best make sense of the system’s
behavior” (Elton, 2000, p. 6). The constraint on this ascription process is
knowledge of what intentional states the system “ought” to have, given its
circumstances, and what, in view of the imperfections of the system, it is likely to
have in actuality. This is the adoption of the intentional stance.
Elton proposes, as a means of comprehending so wide a range of systems and
of remaining true to Dennett, that a content-bearing state be understood liberally as
. . .no more than a state that is semantically evaluable and behavior guiding
. . .what the state represents may or may not be the case and the behavior of the
system will, in appropriate circumstances, be suitably affected by the presence
of the state. Thermostats represent the temperature of the room—but of course a
34
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
thermostat may do so incorrectly if placed it in a draught—and this
representation affects what they do, e.g. switch the boiler on or off. (Elton, 2000,
p. 6)
So general a view of content requires that different kinds of content must be
distinguished. Elton distinguishes content ascribed to a dog from that (less
structured content) ascribed to a frog or (less structured still) that ascribed to a
chess machine:
The content ascribed to persons has a structure such that it can figure in chains
of reasoning, in expressions of justification and explanation, and so forth, the
content ascribed to less cognitively sophisticated systems does not have a
structure that is amenable to such uses. It does not, because there is no behavior
that such systems can engage in that could count as, say, deliberative reasoning,
justifying, or explaining. And ascription of content, in the view in question,
cannot be divorced from the cognitive capacities of the system in question.
(2000, pp. 7-8)
Elton also states that to adopt the intentional stance is to use “an autonomous
level of explanation of the activity of that system” (2000, p. 8). The behavior of the
person (say) whose behavior is predicted by the intentional stance is not being
explained in terms of the component parts of that person qua intentional system,
whether this is treated as an intentional system in itself or otherwise. Confusion
arises because on the one hand, in the earlier Dennett, intentional ascription is
something that can be justified only in terms of appropriate afferent–efferent
linkages, while on the other, the later Dennett argues that intentional idioms,
consonant with a broader understanding of the system’s evolution and its present
position, can be ascribed as long as they enable the system to be predicted.
Although there may be an argument that any system that is so evolved and so
placed that it can be predicted must have evolved the apt afferent–efferent
linkages, this is too easy a way of overcoming the fact that we are presented in the
earlier and later Dennett with essentially alternative devices for legitimately
ascribing intentionality.
The complication that arises from this analytical uncertainty might be
overcome in two ways: (1) by accepting that Dennett is speaking of sub-personal
cognitive psychology when he says subsystems can be treated as intentional
systems, or (2) by arguing that any system can be addressed with any of the stances
he proposes and can, therefore, be studied as either a personal-level system or a
sub-personal system. However, the conclusion is that whatever the merits of
adding content at the sub-personal level, this action removes the justification in
evolutionary terms of adding content to extensional science in order to arrive at
what may be legitimately explained in intentional terms at the personal level. It
opens the way for the identification of neurological activities as behavioral
substrates, a rather different emphasis.
35
FOXALL
Cognition as a Personal Level Phenomenon
It is important to maintain the original personal/sub-personal distinction
because cognition, whatever else it might be, appears to be a phenomenon of the
personal level. This location is, moreover, crucial to our ideas of what cognition is,
what determines it, and whether it is behaviorally causal. I argue that (1) the
definition of cognition is such that it cannot be other than a personal level
occurrence, and (2) what is normally understood as cognition overlaps sufficiently
with Elton’s understanding of consciousness, which he argues is a personal-level
phenomenon, to make cognition locatable only at that level.
First consider what cognition is. Among many definitions from which we
might select, Heyes (2000, p. 20) portrays it in terms of “theoretical entities
providing a functional characterization of the operations of the central nervous
system, which may or may not be objects of conscious awareness, and that are
distinct from perceptual and motor processes.” Theoretical entities are ascribed
entities, and ascription belongs at the personal level. Cognitive terms are
intentional and belong at the personal level. Sub-personal cognitive psychology
attempts to link the intentional and the neurological—best if these are kept distinct
conceptually for the reasons already given. The theoretical entities of cognition
refer to functions of the central and peripheral nervous systems which, of course,
make them material, but because they are entities of the kind exemplified by
parallelograms of forces they are not physical in the sense that tables and neurons
are. They are both invented entities and intentional objects; hence, they belong at
the personal rather than sub-personal level. They are not part of an extensional
science since they cannot be tested/verified in the same way as physically
measurable entities. Therefore, they do not belong at the sub-personal level.
Second, consider Elton’s argument that a distinction is in order between the
intentional stance and the personal level/stance, both of which belong to the
overarching category of rationalizing stances. The personal level arises when an
individual can give reasons for his or her actions and when such reasons can be
adjudged good or bad reasons. We can ask a consumer “Why did you buy the more
expensive brand?” and receive the reply that “It will last longer” or “My friends
expect me to.” It does not follow that the behavior was actually motivated or
caused by these reasons, only that they can be given in explanation. Some systems
cannot give such reasons—animals and computers, for instance. We can use the
intentional stance to predict their behaviors, but the personal stance can be taken
only by humans. Elton’s point is that consciousness is a property only of systems
capable of providing the narrative accounts of their behavior. Such accounts
require the ability to take the personal stance. Only such can reason, decide,
deduce, and so on—or at least only such can describe their doing so. This can, I
think, be tied into the personal phenomenology of thinking and knowing, feeling
and emoting, that is part and parcel of what is generally called personal experience
or consciousness. Unlike Dennett (1978), and perhaps like Skinner (1974), I do not
deny its existence.
36
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
Taking Stock Again
Although Dennett refers often to behavior as that which is to be explained, he
does not incorporate an extensional behavioral science into his scheme of
explanation to counterbalance the extensional neurology on which he (at least
originally) relies. Yet behavior is the criterion of the intentional and needs to be
systematically related to its causal environment so that it may play its vital role in
the framework of analysis proposed here. Radical behaviorism, which we have
already explored as the extensional behavioral science par excellence, is now
integrated to the development of intentional behaviorism. In order to fix the
a-ontological nature of this philosophy of psychology, it is contrasted with a
“super-personal cognitive psychology” that is in some ways its logical extension
but not a necessary consequence of seeking a level of explanatory detail in the
realm of intentionality. The remainder of this paper, therefore, proposes an
alternative source of content ascription to that of Dennett’s sub-personal
neurology: super-personal environment–behavior linkages. In doing so it outlines
an alternative strategy to the more usual philosophy-to-psychology approach that
has often characterized the philosophy of psychology despite the naturalistic
protestations of many of its exponents. If, however, instead of constructing our
idea of the nature of social cognitive psychology on the basis of a priori
philosophical assumptions we observe how social psychologists of cognition–
behavior relationships operate, we shall the more easily find an adequate
philosophical foundation for the scientific analysis of social cognition. The
argument is that the ascription of content requires the incorporation of an
extensional behavioral science as well as an extensional neuroscience; the position
arrived at is a-ontological intentional behaviorism.
The Place of Extensional Behavioral Science
The intentional strategy provides only outline information on the attributions
that are to be made in order to predict an intentional system. To say that these
attributions consist in the beliefs and desires it “ought” to have is, of itself, little
more than an abstract formula. Yet, the heterophenomenological device that
Dennett (1982, 1991) proposes—in which the intentionality that “explains” an
individual’s behavior is reconstructed in much the same manner as that by which a
literary critic analyses characterizations in a novel or play—invites a careful
scrutiny of the system’s prior behavior, applying the intentional stance to people’s
verbal behavior, treating it as a text to be interpreted in terms of their beliefs and
desires. Much as one examines the text of a character in a novel in terms of what
he or she says, what they do, and what others say of them plus background
information about the author and his or her other writings, so one can produce an
intersubjective account of the text provided by another person. The
heterophenomenology of the person consists in an account of “what it is like to be
that subject—in the subject’s own terms, given the best interpretation we can
37
FOXALL
muster” (Dennett, 1991, p. 98). The resulting account is, like a scientific
hypothesis, subject to testing in the face of the evidence, hence corrigible.
Now, this is only a highly generalized method of interpretation. It does not
amount to a systematic means of incorporating behavior and its determinants into
the framework. In order to accomplish that we shall need a more complete
understanding of the requirements for a behavioral science, with its attendant
means of interpretation and its role in a comprehensive framework for
psychological research that incorporates both the intentional and the behavioral.
For now, however, we face the immediate problem of determining what the link
between behavior and ascribed intentionality might be in a more specific context.
Corrigible Behavior
A clue is that the correct beliefs and desires arise out of consideration of the
logical consequences of the beliefs the system has previously held, which
introduces issues that the contextual stance would attribute to learning history plus
the current behavior setting and the consequences it portrays as contingent on
behaving. The big problem is that Dennett does not give a concise and useable
answer to the question of just which of the many available potential consequences
of behavior are to be taken into consideration in this process. Dennett raises the
problem that the logical consequences of behavior are infinite in number. Webb
(1994) seeks the answer in the witnessed behavior of the system, a thesis he
expands by discussing the three sources of attributable desires identified by
Dennett (1987, p. 20) in what he described as his “flagship” exposition of the
intentional stance.
First, there are the fundamental desires for basic goods: survival, the absence
of pain, food, comfort, and entertainment—what some behaviorists might refer to
as primary reinforcers. Second are those desires that can be rationally deduced
from the system’s goals and situation—perhaps conditioned reinforcers. Finally,
Dennett introduces a form of witnessed behavior as a source of intentional
ascription, one that is confined to consideration of verbal behavior. This raises
problems of its own, however, since “The capacity to express desires in language
opens the floodgates of desire attribution” (Dennett, 1987, p. 20). Dennett says
little more about this means of belief attribution other than that these are beliefs the
agent could not have had without language. As Webb (1994) points out, it would
be useful here had Dennett made clear “just how we recognize utterances that call
for desire attributions and how we know (based on what we hear) which desires to
attribute” (p. 460). He notes, however, that Dennett’s proposed method of
intentional attribution allows for the attribution of desires on the basis of linguistic
behavior. Dennett, moreover, is silent concerning any other attributions on the
basis of witnessed behavior, but without some means of making these delimiting
ascriptions of content any attributions made in order to operationalize the
intentional stance are likely to be implausible.
If the intentional stance is to be practically applicable as a means of accurate
behavioral prediction it is necessary that the process of intentional ascription be
38
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
corrigible in the light of accruing information about the behavior of the system and
its environment. There is no means to this end other than the incorporation of
witnessed behavior. It is interesting that Webb (1994) adopts something closely
akin to reasoning that is at the heart of radical behaviorism here. Ideally, he argues,
only behavior that has actually been witnessed should be considered, but this is
impracticable. For instance, a person who has never smoked cigarettes before may
write on a shopping list “Carton of cigarettes”: the attribution of intentionality here
cannot depend on whether someone else reads the shopping list. It is thus
necessary to consider behavior that is only available in principle (Webb, 1994, p.
463). In radical behaviorist terms, the person making the list is a witness to his/her
own behavior; it is immaterial that this opportunity is available only to him/her.
An important boundary condition that Webb introduces is that any behavior
that the intentional stance considers must be displayed at the surface of the system
that is being predicted (Webb, 1994, p. 464). Neuronal activity cannot be brought
in to solve problems of the stance; only external behavior is permissible. Using
information about brain states would make the intentional stance a subset of the
design stance and make impossible the intended capacity to identify a pattern of
behavior more abstract that that given by the design stance. Only behavior that
systems display at their surface is thus admissible. This is witnessed behavior.
Webb’s initial plan is to
. . .incorporate all behavioral evidence available in principle into the intentional
stance. An intentional state is thus defined as whatever intentional state would
be attributed on the basis of the intentional system’s environment and exhibited
behavior, where the “exhibited behavior” is to include all and only the behavior
which (actually) occurred prior to its attribution.” (p. 464)
The import of Webb’s analysis is that Dennett has shown no means by which
the intentional stance can attribute intentionality on the basis of witnessed
behavior. Webb suggests that in incorporating some such method, Dennett would
reveal himself as a behaviorist, a designation he does not necessarily deny but
which he claims to abhor. None of this impinges on the argument being pursued
here. My reading of Dennett fully accepts the necessity of attributing intentionality
on the basis of witnessed behavior; Webb’s analysis is a useful corroboration.
Social cognitive psychology has evolved its own method of incorporating both the
contextual and intentional stances and provides a means of overcoming the
problems Webb raises, at least on a practical level. To this we now turn to lay the
groundwork for two arguments: first, that the program of social cognitive
psychology is incapable of implementation without the prior use of the contextual
stance, and second, that the methods evolved by social cognitivists can be usefully
employed to provide the necessary link between the extensional behavioral science
and intentional cognitive psychology.
We need a system of behavior science that brings behavior in successfully
(relating it to its environmental correlates) and avoids mereological problems.
Hullian and Tolmanian systems will not do (Foxall, 2004); radical behaviorism is
the sole survivor.
39
FOXALL
The Strategy of Intentional Behaviorism
What is Intentional Behaviorism?
The problem is not, however, the number of levels Dennett and his
commentators posit. There is no single framework of analysis to be determined
here but a series of pragmatic responses to an array of intellectual questions.
Specifically, in the present context we are concerned with the adequacy of any of
these levels to capture the essence of social cognitive psychology and to account
for the phenomena it seeks to unravel. The import of the foregoing is that we must
retain the sub-personal level of analysis and for present purposes demarcate its role
as physiological, to which content is ascribed in order to enable prediction at the
personal level. This is apparently Dennett’s original position. The question arises
as to the adequacy of this arrangement for the prediction and explanation of
behavior.
The first difficulty it raises is the practical one of arguing from closely
demarcated and localized physiological phenomena to mental constructs that are
appropriate to the personal behavior of the organism. It has proved notoriously
difficult for cognitive neuropsychology to isolate the neural substrates that can be
convincingly correlated with closely-defined psychological or mental events other
than those involved in basic sensory activity (Uttal, 2001). This is not a debate in
which I wish to become embroiled since it is ultimately one that is open to
specialists. I wish to note, however, the strong possibility that the kinds of
neurocognitive inference Dennett wants to make may be considerably more
controversial in practice than he assumes.
The second difficulty is that the sequence of logical reconstruction is, in any
case, the reverse of what would be expected from the methods of modern cognitive
neuroscience. In order to bring this into current focus, I should like to introduce the
extended framework of analysis that I have called intentional behaviorism, which
incorporates two bases of explanation.
Fig. 1. Intentional Behaviorism.
40
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
The first, basically Dennett’s (1969) approach, runs from the neural substrate
of cognitive activity to the personal level of intentional ascription. Dennett’s
account begins, we have seen, with the neural event—specifically its role in an
afferent–efferent process—and ascribes content on the basis of the resulting
evolutionarily consistent logic. In other words, the direction of ascription is from
neurology to intentionality, from the sub-personal level to the personal level of
explanation. But this is not the actual procedure followed by neurophilosophy
(Churchland, 1986, 2002), where the quest is for the physical substrate of behavior,
including the expression of emotion, which is intentional. Take, for instance, the
investigation of binocular rivalry. If two different and separate visual images are
presented so that each can be seen by only one eye, they do not meld into a single
image but compete for visual awareness. This phenomenon, in which each eye
receives different inputs, is known as binocular rivalry. The resulting phenomenon
is bistable perception in which, after a short period of confusion, the brain comes
to receive the stimuli in an alternating sequence. Each stimulus is perceived for
about one second, after which the other is received for the same interval, and so on,
in an alternating fashion (Churchland, 2002, pp. 136-137.) This phenomenon can
be investigated only if the experimental subject is conscious and able to report
which of the images is currently perceived; there is no other means of establishing
the neural correlates of the consciousness of each image.
Hence, the logical sequence of investigation is from the super-personal level
to the sub-personal—from the verbal behavior of the participant to the
physiological correlate(s) of both that behavior and any personal-level ascriptions
of content that may be made. Intentional behaviorism requires that the procedure
embrace the super-personal level of analysis, in which intentional ascription at the
personal level is achieved via the observation of operant behavior (environment–
behavior relationships) through extensional behavioral science. This is the second
basis of explanation on which intentional behaviorism draws.
The purpose of the philosophical exercise that Dennett advances is, as he
proposes, to ascertain what intentional content can be ascribed to the findings of
neurological science, but the de facto procedure is more likely to entail using
physiology and the logic of natural selection as a means of checking whether preordained desires and beliefs can be rationally ascribed at the personal level. The
consequent methodological procedure is thus: (1) the observation of
environmental–behavioral relationships (including self-reports of emotion) at the
super-personal level, leading to (2) the ascription of emotional content at the
personal level, leading to (3) the search for the neural correlates of emotion at the
sub-personal level. Desires and beliefs, and other mental content, are thus decided
upon at the super-personal level as a result of the uncovering of environment–
behavior links. Their appropriateness to this personal level ascription is further
confirmed, however, by reference to the degree to which they can provide an
additional heuristic overlay to the theories and findings of neurocognitive research
at the sub-personal level on the basis of evolutionarily consistent reasoning.
Evidence of neural substrates of cognition (e.g., from fMRI scans) can show
areas of the brain associated with mental activity such as thinking and emoting.
41
FOXALL
However, they cannot reveal the content of these mental events. This can be done
only by probing the environment–behavior superstrates of cognition (e.g., by using
the contextual stance). Therefore, Dennett’s strategy in Content and Consciousness
(1969) logically requires the further incorporation of the super-personal level of
explanation through which confirmation of that the appropriate content is being
ascribed. This requirement is doubtless implicit in his description of his strategy,
but if his logical argument is to be completed it needs to be made explicit in terms
of an extensional behavioral science based on the contextual stance. The
superordinate framework of conceptualization and analysis presented by
intentional behaviorism incorporates both Dennettian and Skinnerian analyses
within a single, comprehensive account.
Strictly speaking, the contextual stance need not be restricted to operant
psychology. It is simply a means of suggesting environment–behavior
relationships that are consistent with selection-by-consequences and which can,
therefore, act as indicators of the intentional content to be ascribed at the personal
level.
Implementation of the Strategy
The strategy that Dennett advocates for the addition of content to
physiological research may be followed in the case of operant behavioral science
in order to generate a psychology of the person that takes environment–behavior
relationships into consideration. The question arises: on what basis is content to be
ascribed to theories and findings at the super-personal level in order to arrive at a
psychology of the person that takes environment–behavior relationships into
consideration? In order to find an answer to this question it is necessary to go back
to Dennett’s strategy of ascribing content to the sub-personal theories and findings
of neuroscience, and it may be worthwhile reviewing its central themes now. At
the same time, if the analogy between a sub-personal/personal-level linkage and a
super-personal/personal level linkage is to be confirmed, it should be possible to
show how the reasoning that develops for adding content to the extensional
findings on environment–behavior relationships applies to the resolution of the
problems of personal level psychology, behavioral continuity, and delimitation.
The ascription of content to the theories and findings of extensional
behavioral science cannot be pursued in the absence of a convincing rationale.
Recall that Dennett’s strategy is to assume that the sequence of events that are to
be intentionally explained are appropriate from an evolutionary perspective; the
next step is to propose structures that will account for these appropriate sequences.
The environmental significance necessary for the brain (in Dennett’s terms) to
discriminate useful from non-useful neural events is extrinsic to those neural
events; the brain’s necessary distinctions cannot stem solely from extensional
descriptions of extrinsic stimulation and past behavior. The brain has to be able to
discriminate and store fortuitously appropriate structures. Some close analogy of
natural selection must be sought to provide for the capacity of the brain to do this.
The necessary capacity could itself be an outcome of the evolution of species. An
42
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
intentional system has to be able to discriminate and respond to the environmental
factors that impinge upon it, and to do this it must be able to “interpret peripheral
stimulation.” This entails producing within itself not representations but states or
events that “co-occur” with the conditions or objects in its perceptual field.
Information abstracted from the environment will nevertheless remain nonintelligent unless something else is added to it; what must be added consists in the
detection of afferent and efferent links.
The links between the sub-personal/personal and super-personal/personal
levels of analysis can, in each case, be characterized in Skinner’s (1981) term
“selection by consequences.” The first is dependent on an evolutionary history that
produced phylogenic consequences which determined the structure of the brain and
its functioning, the neural afferent–efferent relationships to which content is added
in the process of intentional ascription in order to delineate the personal level of
analysis. The second also depends, indirectly, on this process since it is through
natural selection that the organism’s capacity to change as a result of contact with
environmental consequences presumably came about. However, in a more direct
way, this link is the result of ontogenic consequences through which behavior is
shaped in the course of a lifetime. Again there is a need for intentional ascription,
even if (or possibly, especially if) operant behavior instantiates physiological
change within the organism. Donahoe, Palmer, and Burgos (1997, p. 196) state that
“In a stable context, control by consequences (as opposed to antecedents) stands as
a behavioral law, but we propose (at another level of analysis) that the effects of
those consequences are implemented by changes in synaptic efficacies,” an idea
they trace back to Watson. But this argument merely addresses the sub-personal–
personal levels of linkage that Dennett proposes and has no direct bearing on the
relationship between the super-personal/personal levels, which are proposed here
as a function of ontogenic development.
Intentional Ascription Revisited
We have seen that an extensionally-based system of radical behaviorist
interpretation attempts to account for these necessary linkages by resorting to (a)
physiological mechanisms, (b) private events, and (c) rules, and that there is no
reason for taking any of these seriously at the explanatory level since they do not
provide the necessary continuity, even in the terms required by an extensional
science of behavior. The required interpretative device is that of content ascription
in terms of the desires and beliefs it would be rational for the individual to have in
view of his or her situation defined by the intersection of his or her learning history
and the behavior setting he or she faces. Both evolutionary reasoning and the
behavioral analysis of matching phenomena suggest that the contingencies with
which an individual will have come most obviously into contact in the course of
phylogenic and ontogenic histories will be those producing behavior that tends
toward optimization of outcome. In any situation, therefore, we can assume beliefs,
attitudes, and intentions that are consistent with this objective. As long as the
conceptualization and—at the level of empirical research—measurement of these
43
FOXALL
cognitive constructs is in line with those pursued by attitude theorists, there is a
convincing rationale for the attribution of content to the findings of extensional
behavioral science based on the contextual stance (i.e., the location of behavior at
the intersection of learning history and behavior setting). These constructs directly
link the elements of the contextual stance with the process of content ascription.
The import of intentional ascription must, however (in the course of the
present argument) go thus far and no further. It retains the a-ontological
assumption about cognitive events, states, processes, and structures with which,
along with Dennett, we began. There is no justification for uncritically accepting
the entire apparatus of the information processing account of behavior whether
based on cognitive conjecture or neurophysiology. The justification of intentional
behaviorism lies in the necessity of connecting efferent–afferent processes in some
way that (a) physiology cannot, (b) behavioral science cannot, and (c) that aids the
coherent explanation and prediction of behavior. What Dennett calls a centralist
theory, therefore, has two explanatory components. The first is an extensional
account of the interaction of functional structures. The second is an intentional
characterization of these structures, the events occurring within them, and states of
the structures resulting from them. The links between the extensional account and
the intentional interpretation consists of a hypothesis or hypotheses describing the
evolutionary source of the fortuitously propitious arrangement in virtue of which
the system’s operation in this instance makes sense. These hypotheses are required,
in principle, to account for the appropriateness which is presupposed by the
intentional interpretation but which requires a genealogy from the standpoint of the
extensional, physical theory. Despite the inevitable imprecision of this approach,
the challenge is to make the case that the ascription of content to the theories and
findings of behavioral science can be of use to the behavior analyst, and in
particular to the process of radical behaviorist interpretation.
As Gunderson (1972) summarizes Dennett’s argument, humans are not
simply neurophysiological organisms but also persons who exhibit complex
behaviors. Dennett’s case for the ascription of content rests on the understanding
that because some neural events, states, and structures are about other things (i.e.,
intentional) it is possible to ascribe content to them. The basis of the contextual
stance is similarly that humans are persons as well as organisms whose behavior is
determined by the contingencies of reinforcement. Moreover, some of the
environmental elements on which our behavior is contingent are about things (i.e.,
are such that it makes sense to attribute content to them, to add an extra layer of
interpretation that is relevant to the personal level). While Dennett speaks of only
two levels of analysis, however, we have distinguished three. We have noted his
argument for a personal level, at which the individual as a whole discriminates
such “mental” entities as pain, and a sub-personal level of brains and neurons, at
which level the physiological correlates of pain behavior can be detected:
. . .[T]he terms in our mentalistic vocabulary are nonreferring. Rather like
“sakes” or “miles”, [or centers of gravity] mentalistic terms in appropriate
contexts tell us something, but succeed in doing so without thereby referring to
44
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
any entities any more than the words “sakes” or “miles” refer to sakes or miles.
(Gunderson, 1972, p. 593)
At the super-personal level we turn to the environmental contingencies that
shape and maintain responding in order to find an extensional basis for the
ascription of such content. Several factors distinguish this level from both the
personal and the sub-personal level based on neuroscience that Dennett identifies.
First, the super-personal level cannot capture anything of the personal level,
including some essential components of what it is to be human such as being able
to discriminate pain. No matter how we grimace and howl and hold our painful
heads, no matter what consequences these overt actions have by way of producing
sympathy or medicine or exemptions from work from others, these super-level
events are entirely separate from the discrimination of pain. Second, the superpersonal level constitutes an extensional approach to the science of behavior, one
which can explain much behavior at that level but which is incapable of dealing
with the things that can only be discriminated at the personal level such as pain,
that it is time to go home, and other intentional matters. Only by the addition of a
heuristic overlay of interpretation can these personal-level matters be
accommodated. Third, even though neither level reduces to the other, it is
incumbent upon us to show how they are linked if we are to make legitimate and
convincing interpretive ascriptions. The link, moreover, must be consistent with
evolutionary reasoning. There are several strands to be considered here:
(a) The capacity for operant reinforcement is bestowed by natural selection.
What Skinner (1981) calls “selection by consequences” is the analogy/homology
that links the two processes at least at the level of phylogenic and ontogenic
consistency.
(b) In the case of linking the personal and sub-personal levels, the links must
supervene (i.e., add appropriate interpretation) between the afferent and efferent
processes of the brain. The corresponding processes in operant conditioning are
stimuli and responses. The heuristic overlay of intentionality must link these in
ways that an extensional account cannot. There are three such ways: (i) to elucidate
the personal level, (ii) to demonstrate continuity of behavior from setting to setting,
and (iii) to solve problems of equifinality by delimiting operant interpretations that
(attempt to) proceed solely at the extensional level.
These considerations bring the interpretation within the scope of an
evolutionarily consistent framework of conceptualization and analysis. How? The
animal that is to be successful in negotiating its environment must be differentially
sensitive to discriminative and other setting stimuli in order to act appropriately
(with behavior that will be reinforced).
There is no more reason to believe that a physiological account will
eventually be available to show how this occurs any more than there is a possibility
that a physiological account will be able to demonstrate an individual’s
discrimination of pain. The discriminative control of appropriate behavior occurs
at the personal level. The recognition of appropriate inaugurating stimuli is a
similar process. At the very least, the intentional mode of explanation cannot be
45
FOXALL
abandoned until the physiological link is demonstrated. To trust in eventual
physiology is superstitious in a way in which the ascription of intentionality is not
(if the latter strategy results in more effective predictions of behavior). Physicists
who shun the concept of center of mass in favor of a belief in some more remote
physical explanation would be showing a similar level of superstition. That
physicists are not embarrassed to include centers of mass in their predictive work
should be an example to the psychologist.
Intentional Behaviorist Interpretation
The alternative to an extensional system of radical behaviorist interpretation,
then, is the amalgamation of extensional operant behavioral science and Dennett’s
intensional stance, by which content would be ascribed to its theories and findings
in order to provide a basis for radical behaviorist interpretation. The reality of this
may be closer to us than we have imagined. The point is sometimes made that
radical behaviorists often incorporate the language of intentionality in their popular
accounts of behavior, the implication being that the extensional operant account is
thereby diminished and perhaps incapable of adequately describing the events that
are the subject of the accounts in question. Skinner (e.g., 1974) argues that in order
to communicate to a non-specialist audience it is useful to adopt everyday
language, as does the professional astronomer speaks of the sun “rising” and
“setting” when addressing children. Many behaviorists have taken this at face
value and not concerned themselves further with the charge that the use of such
language necessarily invokes a theoretical stance that is inevitable in the
explanation of behavior. In view of the import of the current argument, this is a
serious matter that behavior analysts ought not to ignore so easily.
The accounts in question are generally interpretations rather than reports of
experimental work, and this suggests that at least at the level of interpretation
intentional language is inevitable not only to communicate to pedestrians but to
express the ideas involved in accounting for complex activity in operant terms.
“Thinking” and “feeling,” the very stuff of private events, are almost always
spoken of in intentional language: we do not just think, we think about or think
that; we do not just feel, we feel that; and so on. We can treat such events as
stimuli and responses that do not differ in kind from those that are publicly
available, though this is to make an enormous ontological leap that can never be
the subject of a scientific analysis—but to insist that thoughts and feelings are
simply discriminative stimuli (or establishing operations, or other source of
antecedent stimulation), associating them in the process with a physiological level
of extensional analysis, is to leave out entirely the personal level to which Dennett
draws attention, the level without which no psychological explanation can be
complete.
The suggested program is not a call for the use of mediating events or the
kinds of theory that Skinner repudiated. Even less is it a regurgitation of the
sometimes argued notion that the intentional and contextual stances might be
conjoined or a synthesis generated that would combine “the best of each.” This is
46
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
not possible in practice because their respective intentional and extensional bases
are incommensurable (Foxall, 1999). But the adding of content to an extensional
account is not a synthesis or amalgamation. It is not adding anything to the
findings and theories derived from the experimental analysis of behavior. Rather, it
is the derivation of another level of interpretation in order to facilitate
understanding and prediction by taking the personal level of experience into
account.
In order to advance the debate between cognitivists and behaviorists, this
account takes Dennett’s thesis about the relationship between extensional science
and intensional psychology at face value. To do this is to share, again for the sake
of argument, (a) his assessment of the (literal) shortcomings of purely extensional
science as a means to understand behavior: such science simply does not go far
enough in the quest to explain all behavior, and (b) his judgment that the link
between the two is found in the imperatives of behavioral science is, like
physiology, an autonomous approach to knowledge in its own right, but it is
incapable of explaining all human behavior within its own theoretical and
methodological purview. Nor can it even engender plausible interpretations
(expressed in non-convoluted language) of all behavior. Here is an important
parallel with Dennett’s analysis leading to a major conclusion: the extensional
science of physiology is to Dennett’s intensional physical psychology what an
extensional behavioral science is to the intensional psychology of social cognition.
In other words, the extensional science provides the evolutionary basis for
understanding behavior biologically to which intensional cognitive interpretation
verbally ascribes an a-ontological, initially non-empirical dimension which yields
predictions of certain behaviors that the extensional approach (of itself) can neither
explain nor predict. What is true for the centerpiece of social cognitive
psychology—attitude research—is likely to be generally the case.
The strategy of ascribing optimality (rationality) to systems in order to predict
their behavior is a methodological simplification that involves further ascription—
of posited entities such as beliefs, attitudes, and intentions which, as we have seen,
have the function of fine-tuning the prediction by linking it to the system’s
environmental history and behavior setting. The three stages of the intentional
strategy make its dependency on the prior application of the contextual strategy
clear. Dennett takes pains to avoid this conclusion. He denigrates (radical)
behaviorism by, firstly, casting it as a simplistic S-R paradigm, and, secondly, by
asserting, in the absence of any adduced evidence, that it has proved to be
unsuccessful in predicting behavior. The first of these caricatures fails to engage
with the operant behavior analysis of the last thirty years, especially the analysis of
behavior at the molar level, the post-Skinnerian analysis of the verbal behavior of
the listener, etc. The second ignores a mass of empirical evidence, and both
overlook the possibility of radical behaviorist interpretation, that is, the use of the
contextual stance to account for the behavior that is not amenable to an
experimental analysis. Indeed, the use of the intentional stance is advocated here
only in the context of radical behaviorist interpretation. It is important that the
extensional science of operant behavior analysis continue its program for two
47
FOXALL
reasons: firstly, to provide an evolving and expanding base for the content
ascription to which content can be ascribed in the process of interpretation; and
secondly to provide alternative, competing, and challenging explanations. Insofar
as the growth of knowledge depends on “the active interplay of competing
theories” (Feyerabend, 1975), it is essential to have (i) a thriving experimental
analysis of behavior, (ii) operant interpretations which themselves attempt to
function on an extensional level only, and (iii) operant interpretations that contain
the intentional overlays necessary to provide accounts of behavior at the personal
level. Their interaction is, indeed, a sine qua non of intellectual progress. Hence,
what characterizes the intentional behaviorist approach is the incorporation of both
the contextual and the intentional stances into a single framework of analysis.
Social cognitivists must reconstruct desires and beliefs in the context of the
individual’s rationality by considering its situation. The contextual stance
facilitates this reconstruction by deconstructing the notion of situation in terms of
(a) a learning history, (b) the current behavior setting, and (c) their interaction.
This is both consistent with and a means of operationalizing Dennett’s view that
the organism will have those desires and beliefs that are appropriate to it given its
situation.
Intentional behaviorism differs from the other systems of explanation in its
comprehensive inclusion of the various elements of the contextual and intentional
stances as well as in the understanding that the ascription of intentionality
reinforces rather than detracts from the prior existence of an extensional behavioral
science. It follows Dennett’s subtle recognition that the addition of an intentional
layer of interpretation does not discover anything new but tells another story about
the theories and findings produced by operant psychology. The result is not just an
extra story that maps on to the original in a one on one fashion; rather, it extends
the scope and relevance of the interpretation. Moreover, intentional behaviorism
recognizes that social cognitive psychology proceeds in a similar manner and it
raises the possibility that psychology will find a platform on which it might unite.
The Strategy of Super-Personal Cognitive Psychology
What is Super-Personal Cognitive Psychology?
Another kind of contextual psychology, super-personal cognitive psychology,
represents the refinement of the intentional terms employed in intentional
behaviorism so that they can enter into scientific theories that employ the
contextual stance. This is a performance theory, but the questions remain (a) of the
ontological status of the entities proposed, and (b) of their causal significance.
There is no need to accord them either table-and-chair reality (though they may be
real in Dennett’s sense that parallelograms of forces are “real”) or causal efficacy
unless this is derived from molar patterns of environment–behavior relationships in
which the contingencies can be shown to control behavior. There is limited
acceptance that humans can be creative in formulating personal or self-rules, but
there is not (and cannot be) any evidence that these procedures are not
48
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
environmentally determined through environmental–behavioral conditioning. The
link with evolution may come in this case through evolutionary psychology. The
reason is that we are now seeking cognitive ascriptions that can be justified
directly in terms of evolutionary processes. Evolutionary psychology is concerned
with the development of cognitive structures that were appropriate during the
Pleistocene period and which are an amalgam of biological and mental/behavioral
selection. Moreover, it is possible for super-personal cognitive psychology to point
the way toward a comprehensive cognitive–behavioral psychology.
Theories that deal only in identifying the necessary intentional idioms to
explain behavior (e.g., the Bolles-Bindra-Toates expectancy theory) function at the
level of intentional behaviorism. They are competence models, and as such they
seek semantic understanding. A fully realized super-personal cognitive
psychology, like Dennett’s sub-personal cognitive psychology, has the potential to
uncover the syntax of the brain but through (unlike Dennett) relating environment–
behavior consistencies to physiological structures and functions. One familiar
component of this project is the attempt to relate environment–behavior
relationships to dopamine release. If this can be shown to be evolutionarily
consistent, it justifies the ascription of the appropriate intentional content at the
personal level. Similarly, research shows that pain is a personal-level phenomenon
that can be systematically related to operant conditioning (Flor, Knost, &
Birbaumer, 2002) as well as neural substrates. This is more than establishing that
operant conditioning leads to dopamine release, or the differential locations of
neurons that fire when alternative brands of soft drinks are presented, or when
different kinds of decision making are occurring—though all of these are relevant.
It means establishing relationships between sequences of environmentallymaintained behavior (operant conditioning) and neurological activity, a link
between the super-personal and the sub-personal, from the whole complex of
which an inference can be made about what the organism is doing at the personal
level. Pain, for instance, would not be inferred from either a sub-personal
physiological pattern of afferent–efferent linkages or a super-personal relationship
between certain verbal and nonverbal behaviors like screaming or holding one’s
thumb after hitting it with a hammer, but from evidence that connected the two.
Flor and her colleagues (Flor, Knost & Birbaumer, 2002) have demonstrated, for
instance, that the reports of pain made by back pain sufferers are susceptible to
operant control. The solicitous behavior of a spouse, or their mere presence in the
same room, provides reinforcement of the pain sufferer’s verbal reports of pain;
brain wave activity associated with pain has been identified only when the spouse
was present to complete the operant training.
Implementation of the Strategy
The tentative strategy of super-personal cognitive psychology outlined here
has four stages. It begins with the intentional idioms found to be useful at the level
of intentional behaviorism, but, additionally (and wherever possible), those that
have been supported by empirical testing. An example of the intentional
49
FOXALL
behaviorism phase of this stage is incorporation of the S-S* and R-S* links
proposed by Bolles’s syllogism. Dickinson’s (1997) program to substantiate these
proposed links comprises an empirical program. Indeed, in the absence of
empirical evidence, at least for epistemological usefulness of the content
introduced in the process of intentional behaviorism, one would have to rethink the
program before proceeding to this stage. There is room, however, for theoretical
reasoning as to the mental processes that would be required to accomplish prebehavioral information processing.
The second stage is to employ the psychological structures further by
enquiring how they are implemented in the brain. The necessary sequence in
super-personal cognitive psychology is that followed by Dickinson:
Whereas in the theoretical vacuum of the 1960s I had hoped that the pattern of
behavioral dysfunction produced by neural interventions would reveal the
psychological structures and processes of instrumental action, I now have
sufficient confidence in the present psychological understanding to reverse the
research strategy and ask how the brain implements these processes and
structures. (Dickinson, 1997, p. 361)
The third stage involves relating the brain processes to specific afferent–
efferent linkages and their evolution in the process of natural selection. This
reinforces the original ascription of intentionality made in intentional behaviorism
at the personal level. That level is, of course, where they remain.
Finally, it is necessary to relate the behavior–environment relationships on the
basis of which the intentional behaviorism ascriptions were made to the evolution
of such behaviors in the process of evolutionary psychology. This procedure is not
a prescribed route for empirical science but reflects how some scientists have
worked and how, as a result, science has progressed in the direction of what I have
called super-personal cognitive psychology. Above all, it is iterative and corrigible.
Summing Up
The difference between intentionalistic explanation and that which
characterizes radical behaviorism is a difference between the sentences employed
to express them. Specifically, the propositions in terms of which intentionalistic
explanation is expressed are not substitutable for other propositions even though
they are equivalent in meaning. The essence of radical behaviorism as a
philosophy of psychology is the explanation of behavior without recourse to
propositional attitudes, without attributing propositional content to its statements
of behavior–environment relations. Hence the components of the patterns of
contingency that provide its fundamental explicatory device are all defined in
extensional terms, be they establishing operations, discriminative stimuli,
responses, or positive/aversive consequences. Private events as well as overt
behaviors and verbal as well as non-verbal behaviors are all defined in terms that
exclude the intentional idioms. The extensional language, which is generally taken
to be the only form that scientific discourse ought properly to take, is said to be
50
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
“transparent” in that coextensive terms can be substituted one for another. We can
equally say that the animal’s behavior is reinforced by the food contingent on it
and that it is reinforced by the protein pellet that is presented after each response.
“Food” and “protein pellet” have the same extension in this context.
Radical behaviorism’s explanation of behavior is deficient in three ways.
These are particularly evident in its attempt to interpret complex behavior (i.e.,
behavior not amendable to direct experimental analysis) by reference to behavioral
principles established through the basic and applied analysis of behavior conducted
in the laboratory and the field. I do not mean by this that radical behaviorism fails
to predict behavior or to make possible its influence or control. I do not, therefore,
deny that it identifies environmental events that are the independent variables of
which behavior is a function. Indeed, I have no criticism of radical behaviorism in
terms of its own pragmatic success criterion, the prediction (often plausible
postdiction) and control (influence) of behavior. Here it undoubtedly succeeds, not
only in the closed settings of the operant laboratory and therapeutic community but
in the open settings presented by the economics of everyday life. Nor am I
unaware that for many behavior analysts this is sufficient to constitute an
explanation of behavior, as it is in the Machian positivism that guided Skinner’s
early construction of this paradigm and from which he never departed. In other
words, I am not criticizing the capacity of radical behaviorism to succeed on its
own terms. I am arguing that on those terms radical behaviorism cannot account
for (a) behavior at the personal level (as opposed to accounting for behavior–
environment relationships), (b) the continuity of behavior over time and space, and
(c) the delimitation of interpretations of behaviors. The picture is complicated by
dint of the insistence of radical behaviorists that these putative problems can be
overcome by means of private events, verbal behavior, rule-governance, relational
frames, and other devices. I argue that none of these, in fact, provides the
necessary conceptual framework for a science of behavior that succeeds in
accounting for the three requirements in which I find it deficient.
Hence, I am not advocating that radical behaviorism as it stands is in need of
radical change. It is as important to the program I advocate as it is to its own that it
continue to develop as a science of behavior that elucidates behavior–environment
relationships. It is a means of predicting and influencing behavior, one of several
psychologies that attempt these tasks, and it is important that it continue to provide
a limiting statement of how behavior may be determined by its consequences. But
it is equally important that it be challenged by a theoretical approach that identifies
its deficiencies in the realm of explanation into providing a robust experimental
program charged with showing that such empirical work can provide a full
explanation of behavior. I do argue, however, that explanation which deals with
the personal level of explanation, which accounts for continuity, and which is
delimited requires that subtle use be made of the intentional psychology that
underlies cognitivism. This takes nothing away from radical behaviorism; it adds
what is necessary to explain and interpret rather than simply to predict and control.
The paper has not argued against any philosophy of psychology; rather it has
sought to propose a synthetic framework within which each may contribute to the
51
FOXALL
explanation of complex human behavior. Each is essential to the research program
of intentional behaviorism in its own right. It is essential, for instance, that research
within the extensional behavioral science context of radical behaviorism continues,
that the possibility of accounting for behavior in its terms alone be explored
comprehensively. It is equally important that a cognitive program proceed in its
own right. It is also vital that they interact tenaciously, for it is the competitive
collisions of the explanations produced by these schools of thought as well as the
development within each of their confines that engender the progress of science.
References
Angulo, M. C., Staiger, J. F., Rossier, J., & Audinat, E. (1999). Developmental synaptic
changes increase the range of integrative capabilities of an identified neocortical
connection. Journal of Neuroscience, 19, 1566-1576.
Bandura, A. (1986). Social foundations of thought and action: A social cognitive theory.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Baum, W. (1973). The correlation based law of effect. Journal of the Experimental
Analysis of Behavior, 20, 237-253.
Baum, W. M., & Heath, J. L. (1982). Behavioral explanations and intentional explanations
in psychology. American Psychologist, 47, 1312-1317.
Bechtel, W. (1988). Philosophy of mind: An overview for cognitive science. Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Berridge, K. C. (2000). Reward learning: Reinforcement, incentives, and expectations. In: D.
L. Medin (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation, 49 (pp. 223-278). San
Diego: Academic Press.
Bindra, D. (1978). How adaptive behavior is produced: A perceptual-motivation alternative
to response reinforcement. Psychological Review, 81, 199-213.
Bolles, R. C. (1972). Reinforcement, expectancy, and learning. Psychological Review, 79,
394-409.
Bouton, M. E., & Franselow, M. S. (Eds.) (1997). Learning, motivation, and cognition: The
functional behaviorism of Robert C. Bolles. Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association.
Catania, A. C. (1992). Learning (3rd ed). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving: A philosophical study. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Churchland, P. S. (2002). Brain-wise: Studies in neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on action and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davies, M. (2000). Persons and their underpinnings. Philosophical Explorations, 3, 42-62.
Dennett, D. C. (1969). Content and consciousness. London: Routledge.
Dennett, D. C. (1976). Conditions of personhood. In: A. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of
persons (pp. 175-196). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Dennett, D. C. (1978). Brainstorms. Montgomery, VT: Bradford.
Dennett, D. C. (1981). Three kinds of intentional psychology. In: R. Healy (Ed.),
Reduction, time, and reality (pp. 37-61). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
52
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
Dennett, D. C. (1982). How to study human consciousness empirically, or nothing comes
to mind. Synthese, 59, 159-180.
Dennett, D. C. (1983). Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The “Panglossian
paradigm” defended. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6, 343-390.
Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown.
Dickinson, A. (1997). Bolles’s psychological syllogism. In: M. E. Bouton & M. S.
Fanselow (Eds.), Learning, motivation, and cognition: The functional behaviorism of
Robert C. Bolles (pp. 345-268). Washington, DC: American Psychological
Association.
Donahoe, J. W., Palmer, D. C., & Burgos, J. E. (1997). The S-R issue: Its status in behavior
analysis and in Donahoe and Palmer’s Learning and complex behavior. Journal of the
Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 67, 193-211.
Elton, M. (2000). Consciousness: Only at the personal level. Philosophical Explorations, 3,
25-41.
Elton, M. (2003). Daniel Dennett: Reconciling science and our self-conception.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: NLB.
Flor, H., Knost, B., & Birbaumer, N. (2002). The role of operant conditioning in chronic
pain: An experimental investigation. Pain, 95, 111-118.
Foxall, G. R. (1997). Explaining consumer behavior: From social cognition to environmental
control. In: C. L. Cooper & I. T. Robertson (Eds.), International review of industrial and
organizational psychology, 12 (pp. 229-287). Chichester: Wiley.
Foxall, G. R. (1999). The contextual stance. Philosophical Psychology, 12, 25-52.
Foxall, G. R. (2004). Context and cognition: Interpreting complex behavior. Reno, NV:
Context Press.
Foxall, G. R. (2007a). Explaining consumer choice. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Foxall, G. R. (2007b). Explaining consumer choice: Coming to terms with intentionality.
Behavioral Processes, 75, 129-145.
Gardner, S. (2000). Psychoanalysis and the personal/sub-personal distinction.
Philosophical Explorations, 3, 96-119.
Gazzaniga, M. S., Ivry, R. B., & Mangun, G. R. (1998). Cognitive neuroscience: The
biology of the mind. New York: W. W. Norton.
Gunderson, K. (1972). Content and consciousness and the mind-body problem. The
Journal of Philosophy, 69, 591-604.
Hayes, S. C., Zettle, R. D., & Rosenfarb, I. (1989). Rule-following. In: S. C. Hayes (Ed.),
Rule-governed behavior: Cognition, contingencies, and instructional control (pp. 191220). New York: Plenum.
Hempel, C. G. (1980). The logical analysis of psychology. In: N. Block (Ed.), Readings in
philosophical psychology, Vol. I (pp. 14-23). London: Methuen.
Herrnstein, R. J. (1997). The matching law: Papers in psychology and economics. (H.
Rachlin & D. I. Laibson, Eds.) New York: Russell Sage Foundation; Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Heyes, C. (2000). Evolutionary psychology in the round. In: C. Heyes & L. Huber (Eds.),
The evolution of cognition (pp. 3-22). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hornsby, J. (2000). Personal and sub-personal: A defence of Dennett’s early distinction.
Philosophical Explorations, 3, 6-24.
Juarrero, A. (1999). Dynamics in action: Intentional behavior as a complex system.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
53
FOXALL
Kandel, E. R. (2001). The molecular biology of memory storage: A dialogue between
genes and synapses. Science, 294, 1030-1038.
Lacey, H. M. (1995/1996). Behaviorisms: Theoretical and teleological: A review of John
Staddon’s Behaviorism: Mind, mechanism, and society, and Rachlin’s Behavior and
mind: The roots of modern psychology. Behavior and Philosophy, 23, 61-78.
Lee, V. L. (1988). Beyond behaviorism. London: Erlbaum.
Mach, E. (1896/1959). The analysis of sensations and the relation of the physical to the
psychical [C. M. Williams, Trans.]. New York: Dover.
Mach, E. (1905/1976). Knowledge and error: Sketches on the psychology of enquiry [T. J.
McCormack & P. Foulkes, Trans.]. Boston, MA: Reidel.
Malcolm, N. (1977). Behaviorism as a philosophy of psychology. In: N. Malcolm (Ed.),
Thought and knowledge (pp. 85-103). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. First
published in T. W. Wann (Ed.) (1964), Behaviorism and phenomenology: Contrasting
bases for modern psychology (pp. 141-162). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McGinn, C. (1991). The problem of consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell.
McGinn, C. (2004). Consciousness and its objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Moore, J. (1999). The basic principles of behaviorism. In: B. Thyler (Ed.), The
philosophical legacy of behaviorism (pp. 41-68). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers.
Morse, W. H., & Kelleher, R. T. (1977). Determinants of reinforcement and punishment.
In: W. K. Honig & J. E. R. Staddon (Eds.), Handbook of operant behavior (pp. 174200). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rachlin, H. (1989). Judgment, decision, and choice: A cognitive/behavioral synthesis. San
Francisco, CA: Freeman.
Rachlin, H. (1994). Behavior and mind: The roots of modern psychology. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Rachlin, H. (2000). Teleological behaviorism. In: W. O’Donohue & R. Kitchener (Eds.),
Handbook of behaviorism (pp. 195-215). San Diego: Academic Press.
Schnaitter, R. (1999). Some criticisms of behaviorism. In: B. A. Thyer (Ed.), The
philosophical legacy of behaviorism (pp. 209-249). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, B. F. (1945). The operational analysis of psychological terms. Psychological
Review, 52, 270-277.
Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New York: Macmillan.
Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviorism. New York: Knopf.
Skinner, B. F. (1981). Selection by consequences. Science, 213, 501-504.
Smith, L. D. (1986). Behaviorism and logical positivism: A reassessment of the alliance.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Smith, T. L. (1994). Behavior and its causes: Philosophical foundations of operant
psychology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Staddon, J. E. R., & Cerutti, D. T. (2003). Operant conditioning. Annual Review of
Psychology, 54, 115-144.
Strawson, G. (1994). Mental reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Toates, F. (1986). Motivational systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Uttal, W. R. (2001). The new phrenology: The limits of localizing cognitive processes in the
brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
54
INTENTIONAL BEHAVIORISM
Webb, S. (1994). Witnessed behavior and Dennett’s intentional stance. Philosophical
Topics, 22, 457-470.
Zettle, R. D., & Hayes, S. C. (1982). Rule-governed behavior: A potential framework for
cognitive–behavioral therapy. In: P. C. Kendall (Ed.), Advances in cognitive–
behavioral research and therapy (pp. 73-117). New York: Academic Press.
55
Download