WORD - The University of Sydney

advertisement
1
LAW EXTENSION COMMITTEE
UNIVERSITY OF SYDNEY
2004
JURISPRUDENCE OUTLINE
ALL STUDENTS PLEASE NOTE:
The outline below is intended to assist students in following the lectures in the course
and in understanding the recommended reading. The outline is not a substitute for the
lectures and reading. The outline is not intended to be comprehensive. Students who
have merely familiarised themselves with the outline but not attended the lectures and
read the prescribed text and readings will be inadequately prepared for the exam and at
substantial risk of failure.
Commencing with the November 2001 semester, examination questions will increasingly
ask students to apply the concepts and arguments taught in the course to an issue or
problem. Students will be best prepared to deal with the paper who have attended the
lectures or weekend schools and read widely.
LECTURE 10
LAW AND ECONOMICS
Introduction
This lectures looks at the principles that underpin the modern law of civil wrongs. The lecture
assumes that behind the legal rules and principles applied by lawyers lies some general
rationale for tort law which explains its purpose and function. This rationale may be a moral
or political theory. The two principal contenders in the scholarly literature are the argument
that tort law promotes economic efficiency, and the view that tort law reflects a principle of
corrective justice.
Economic Efficiency
Economists use the notion of efficiency in a technical sense. A distribution of resources
amongst a population will be most efficient when it would not be possible to increase the
Christopher Birch
April 2004
2
satisfied preferences of any member of the population without decreasing the level of satisfied
preference of others (a so-call Pareto equilibrium, named after the economist Vilfedo Pareto).
This notion of efficiency depends upon the following assumptions:1.
That members of the population are rational maximisers of their own self interest;
2.
That there exists free exchange in accordance with the principles of a perfect market
amongst each member of the population; and
3.
There has been an allocation of goods to individuals to hold privately in which they
may trade.
The concept of a perfect market depends upon the following assumptions: 1.
A private stable allocation of resources;
2.
The absence of force or fraud in regard to all transactions within the market;
3.
That no one person can influence prices;
4.
That each person acts in accordance with their own rational self interest;
5.
That transactions are costless;
It is sometimes also specified that each participant should have full appropriate knowledge
regarding any transactions they enter into. If they lack such knowledge transactions will not
be costless as they will need to expend effort in obtaining knowledge necessary to know
whether the transaction will be more beneficial than not.
The Market Principle and Political Economy
The notion of rational maximisation of the satisfaction of preferences is at least conceptually
related to the utilitarian doctrine of the maximisation of the happiness of the greatest number.
The advantage of market theory is that it avoids the problem of judging inter-subjective
preferences. Rather than someone making a decision about what is to be considered in the
best interests of all, a market allows each person to determine what exchanges they wish to
make.
Fredrick Hayek, the Austrian economist, considered that markets were an efficient means of
distributing resources because they were better at exchanging information about individual
preferences than central government planners (See his principles of Taxis and Cosmos)
Christopher Birch
April 2004
3

It must however be recognised that while a market may be efficient in the Pareto sense it
need not be just.

The Pareto equilibrium will be different in every case for each different original allocation
of resources.

If the original allocation of resources was unjust, the Pareto equilibrium may also be
unjust.
Further, Coase demonstrated by way of a careful thought experiment that in a perfect market
given any initial distribution, and the marginal profitability of activities, people will agree to
produce in accordance with the highest marginal profitability whatever be the legal liabilities
imposed upon those various activities (Coase’s theorem).
Market Failure
Some economists argued that even a perfect market ignored certain costs because they were
not costs to the parties to the transactions. They referred to these costs as externalities. (A
typical example is the pollution cost of buying a motor vehicle borne by the community at
large rather than the parties to the transaction). It was argued that legal intervention was
required to impose external costs upon the parties to ensure that society did not otherwise
over invest in such activities. Coase’s theorem casts doubt upon some of these arguments
regarding externalities.

Coase’s theorem shifted the emphasis from the notion of externality to the problem of
transaction cost.

Efficient outcomes will only be arrived at in a perfect market, which is one in which
transactions are costless, and the parties have complete knowledge.

Legal intervention will therefore be necessary to seek to produce the efficient outcome a
market could have produced if transactions were possible but where they have been
prevented by transaction costs.
The Prisoners Dilemma
Another famous example of market failure is generated wherever the participants in a market
have a conflict between the maximisation of their individual preferences and the collective
Christopher Birch
April 2004
4
good.
PRISONERS DILEMMA
You
Confess
Remain Silent
Each gets 10 years
1 go free
You get 12 years
1 get 2 years
You go free
Each gets 2 years
Confess
I
Remain Silent
For further discussion of the prisoner’s dilemma, see: Parfitt; D
Reasons and Persons, Oxford Up, Oxford, 1984, Chapter 2
Nozick; R
Rationality, Princeton UP, Princeton, 1993, p.50-59.
Moser; PK
Rationality in Action, Cambridge UP, Cambridge, 1990, p.280-282
Tort Law as Reflecting a Utilitarian or Economic Principle
In United States v Carol Towing 150 Fdd 169 at 173 Learned Hand J based his judgment on
the following formula:If
P
=
Probability of injury
L
=
Injury – cost of injury
B
=
Burden of injury (being the cost of precautions)
Then where B > than P x L no liability will be imposed. Where B < rather than P x L liability
will be imposed.
On cost benefit analysis of safety precautions see also Flemings “Law of Tort”, 9th Edition,
p.131-132.
Posner’s Theory
Richard Posner has sought to analyse all bodies of law from the point of view of economic
Christopher Birch
April 2004
5
efficiency, arguing that this is the underlying principle of all legal doctrine.

In explaining tort law, Posner argues that compensatory damages are paid to a victim to
give the victim an incentive to sue. This is essential to the maintenance of the tort system
as an effective credible deterrent to negligence.

The economic function of compensation in tort, according to Posner, is the deterrence of
inefficient accidents.

Posner argues that the legal principles aim to achieve an outcome comparable to that
which would represent the most economically efficient outcome if the matter was capable
of being handled by a market.

The reason the law intervenes is because the conduct with which law is concerned is
usually one in which a market is inappropriate because of the cost of the transactions or
some other cause of market failure.
Criticisms of Posner’s Theory
One peculiarity of Posner’s theory is that it argues that law generally, and tort law in
particular, seeks through its principles of negligence and the like, to emulate market
efficiency, and yet, few judgments refer to economic efficiency as a reason or explanation of
the legal principles applied.
Posner suggests that legal principles that promote economic efficiency will be more likely to
be promoted and applied than ones that do not, rather like survival of the fittest.
A further difficulty with Posner’s theory is that it is hard to know whether the outcomes
produced by law truly reflect how a society would organise itself if market principles could be
applied.
Corrective Justice

In the last 20 years a number of jurists have suggested that the principles underpinning
tort law are not the promotion of economic efficiency but rather those of corrective
justice. The concept can be traced to Aristotle’s Nicomachean ethics.

As explained by Aristotle, the concept of corrective justice involved depriving a
wrongdoer of the gain and providing compensation to the sufferer.
Christopher Birch
April 2004
6

The aim is to ensure that each party is returned to the position that he or she was in before
the wrong was committed.

The notion of corrective justice is related to and dependent upon the concept of
distributive justice.

Distributive justice concerns those principles that govern the overall distribution of goods
(using that term in the widest possible sense).

If we assume that the pre-accident distribution was just, then the effect of a wrong is to
disturb that just distribution.

Corrective justice demands that the original just distribution be restored.
Justice and Proportionality
There are many obstacles to explaining modern tort law as an application of corrective justice.
It troubles many commentators that a wrongdoer could be liable for damages out of all
proportion to the level of wrongdoing committed.

Judith Thompson has argued that we should have an “at- fault” pool to compensate
victims. Everyone contributes to the pool a sum for any wrongdoing proportionate to their
level of wrongdoing, and those injured are compensated from the pool in an amount
necessary to put them back in their pre-accident position to the extent money can. This
seeks to neutralise the effect of luck.

Joel Feinberg has argued that we can explain the tort principle on the “fault forfeits first”
principle. Once someone has been injured the loss must be borne. It is better that it be
borne by the party at fault then by the innocent party.

Jeremy Waldron has argued that the modern law of tort cannot satisfy principles of
corrective justice as the liabilities of the defendant cannot be shown to correlate with
culpability or moral dessert.
Ironically, despite the difficulty of jurists in coming up with a consistent theory of corrective
justice that explains modern tort law, judgments in tort are usually expressed in the language
of blame and wrongdoing rather then economic efficiency.
Further, modern tort law is to a substantial degree underpinned by insurance and the
consequent spreading of risks, although this is rarely adverted to in judgments. Should this
Christopher Birch
April 2004
7
matter to judicial decision makers?
Conclusion
It may well be that modern tort law is built upon a mix of inconsistent principles and
justifications. The difficulty presently experienced by superior appellate courts in defining the
circumstances in which recovery of pure economic loss will be permitted may be a reflection
of this deeper conceptual confusion. See Perre v Apand (1999) 198 CLR 180.
Christopher Birch
April 2004
Download