Principled Principals in the Founding Moments of the Rule of Law

advertisement
*This paper is still in process. Comments welcome.
Principled Principals in the Founding Moments of the Rule of Law
Margaret Levi and Brad Epperly
mlevi@u.washington.edu
Department of Political Science
University of Washington
May 2008
Institutionally, the rule of law consists of the laws that protect personal security and
private property and the means for monitoring and enforcing obedience with those laws.
Rule of law institutions are only effective to the extent that the powerful of the society
believe they, too, are subject to the law and the populace believes in the value of being
law-abiding. If office holders and the privileged act as if they are above the law, the rule
of law becomes fragile or non-existent. When coercion is the only or even primary
means to achieve compliance, laws may exist but not the rule of law. The rule of law
requires legitimacy, at least if legitimacy means reasoned deference to authority (Tyler
2006). This applies equally to corporate elites who manage the economy, state agents
who make and implement the laws, and the citizens asked to obey.
Achieving legitimacy and with it a relatively high degree of voluntary compliance
with the law is neither simple to achieve in the first place nor easy to sustain over time.
Without shared consensus on what the basic outlines of the law should be, competing
conceptions of law undermine the rule of law even in what appear to be stable societies.
Levi and Epperly, p. 2
As groups previously excluded from or even harmed by the laws gain power, they may
unsettle the status quo, particularly if the legal changes required mean major restructuring
of valued privileges. Whether such rifts tear a society apart depends partially on whether
the laws can easily be reformed to become universally fair and non-discriminatory and if
a generalized belief exists that the rule of law is worth having and preserving. Both of
these beliefs often have their source in the founding moments of a society, during the
process of constitution-making, institutional design, and articulation of national
principals through laws and nation-building rituals. Crucial to this process, we argue, is
principled leadership that credibly signals its type and commitments.
Suffice to say, important structural and institutional factors must inform a
complete analysis. Our emphasis here, however, is on those founding moments when the
requisite factors exist that make possible the design and maintenance of the rule of law.
Well-designed institutions are necessary but not sufficient. The rule of law also requires
leaders who can credibly commit to self-constraint, agents who can be trusted to abide by
the law as well as enforce it, and reasons for most of the population, both the powerful
elites and the general mass, to believe they will benefit from the existence of the rule of
law.
Once established, the rule of law can become a self-enforcing equilibrium in
which social actors are able and willing to defend against transgressions of their rights by
the state (Weingast 1997). This is a Madisonian model in which it is necessary to build
in protections against the knaves but in which most people prefer to maintain the rule of
law if possible. No one, save for some few outliers, desire to deviate from the
equilibrium. A situation in which the state is rife with corruption, favoritism, and other
Levi and Epperly, p. 3
activities anathema to the rule of law will be one in which few have any incentive to act
in a manner supportive of its development. This is law-breaking equilibrium is one in
which cooperation and compliance produce sucker payments. Both equilibria are stable,
and the critical issue is how to transform a law breaking into a rule of law equilibrium.
The existence of a rule of law equilibrium is self-enforcing in part because it can
create a virtuous circle of increasing levels of voluntary compliance (Levi and Sacks
2007). The expectation of its durability over time contributes to the production of
Tocqueville’s “self-interest rightly understood (Tocqueville 1990 [1840]);” individuals
believe that it is worth the costs of their compliance to obtain long-term benefits. In the
absence of a rule of law equilibrium, few incentives exist for state agents or subjects to
follow the rules. Individuals know they will end up being suckered, and they lack
confidence in downstream individual benefits to their compliance.
The conception of law as equilibrium captures a significant but static reality. It
fails to sufficiently credit the efforts put into the reproduction and maintenance of the rule
of law. Yes, once established, an effective rule of law should produce the incentives for
relevant actors to continue to uphold it. Yet, as definitions of rights change, and as new
actors become part of the polity, reproduction becomes both more problematic and more
important.
We know something about what maintains the rule of law once it is in place,
albeit not enough. We know far less about how to create it initially. Yet, in countries
throughout the world that is the pressing question. We are increasingly learning that
citizens will give their voluntary compliance to government if government is stable,
relatively effective in providing social welfare, and relatively fair and procedurally just
Levi and Epperly, p. 4
(Levi, Sacks, and Tyler forthcoming; Levi 1997; Tyler 1990). What we know
considerably less about is how to produce such governments in the first place (Levi
2006). Social scientists and policy-makers are fairly confident that the rule of law is
essential to effective state building but are considerably less certain about how to bring it
about.1
We model this process in four stages (see figure 1). At time 1 nature moves by
providing a leader (or leadership cadre) who has won a war, led a revolution, or
otherwise successfully established a basis for governing the society and, potentially,
creating or reforming its institutions. If this leader possesses a principled commitment to
developing the rule of law and to making herself subject to it, then the rule of law stands
some chance of developing. Unprincipled leaders or leaders with the wrong kinds of
principles (i.e., those with ideologies that discount the importance of the rule of law)
abound; those with the right principles are far scarcer. However, for discussion of the
rule of law, principled leaders of the right sort are the ones that matter. We know from
history that such people exist and can be used as models for other leaders trying to decide
the path to take.2
At time 2, the principled leader faces powerful others who choose to cooperate
1
“Order in the Jungle”, The Economist,
http://www.economist.com/displaystory.cfm?story_id=10849115 Accessed 11 May 2008.
2
We shall not spend time in this paper examining the ways in which such leaders might be
encouraged or even trained, but we recognize this is an essential component of a fuller
argument.
Levi and Epperly, p. 5
with the leader’s efforts to establish the rule of law—or not. If not, the game is over
(although, in fact, the leader and constituents may continue to interact in an effort to
realize cooperation). The defining moment, however, is when the leadership achieves
sufficient cooperation to engage in institutional design for the future. At time 3, the
leader, with the cooperation of powerful allies, chooses an institutional design. If the
design involves credible constraints on both the leader and on others with power, the
rule of law becomes possible. The combination of the institutional design, principled
leadership, and appropriately functioning bureaucracy should, at time 4, produce
legitimating beliefs and, therefore, compliance among the population served by the state.
A rule of law equilibrium results. If the design is poor or poorly implemented, the rule of
law is unlikely or, at best, exceedingly fragile. No equilibrium obtains unless the
institutions are redesigned to constrain powerful societal actors and government officials.
Many analyses of the emergence of the rule of law start from the point at which
society is already in one or another equilibrium state. The key actors have coordinated or
failed to. This analysis starts with the foundational moments for institutional design. It
begins to theorize rather than simply assume the leadership type and the interaction of
leaders with powerful others. It emphasizes the importance of constraining all those who
could undermine the rule of law, including societal actors, government leadership, and
the officials who staff government. It makes it clear where external agencies can
intervene and make a difference. They can do more than help write the constitution.
Their influence will also be constructive at time 2 when those in society are deciding
whether to cooperate with leadership; here is where external agents can provide resources
that will affect the incentives of those considering defection. Only then can institutions
Levi and Epperly, p. 6
emerge that are worth far more than the paper they are written on.
FOUNDING MOMENTS
The founding moments of states, indeed of any organization, are critical to the beliefs and
culture that will develop over time. Culture here refers not to the ethnographic, religious,
racial, or ideological features of a society—although they can play a role. It refers to the
defining norms and consensual values that influence the way members of the
organization interact with each other. It refers to both the horizontal relationships among
citizens and the vertical relationships with those who govern. It is culture in the sense
David Kreps used the term in his seminal discussion of “corporate culture” (Kreps 1990):
a set of principles that constitute the identity of the organization and establish the rules to
guide the behavior of its members. In his model, and in ours, leadership is key.
This is not the moment to rehearse the debate about the relative influence of
religion, geography, natural endowments, what the colonizing power did and when, or
other structural features of a society that can influence the nature of its laws and the
inclination of its people to support them.3 While important, these large structural factors
are the backdrop to the founding moments of institutions and constitutions.
Founding moments self-evidently occur at the birth of the state or other
3
The literature is long and getting longer. Important contributions include Acemoglu, Johnson
and Robinson 2001; Lipset 1959; Przeworski 2004; Acemoglu, Johnson and Robinson 2002;
Engerman, Sokoloff and Haber 1997; Sokoloff and Engerman 2006. North, Wallis and
Weingast forthcoming are soon to publish a relevant book, and both James Mahoney and
Steven Wilkinson have manuscripts in process.
Levi and Epperly, p. 7
organization. However, organizations can and do rebuild themselves and thus experience
renewed founding moments. Firms often do this. So do voluntary organizations.4 Much
can be learned from the behavior of such organizations, and much of what follows draws
on arguments and findings concerning these founding or, more accurately, refounding
moments, particularly in those instances when leaders design institutions that constrain
themselves as well as constituents and officials.5
Among states, few examples exist of a national government and organizational
culture arising totally de novo: the United States is an exception, not the rule. And even
it had a redefining moment as a consequence of the Civil War, as well as numerous
redefining moments as women and African-Americans gained the suffrage and as the
conception of protected civil rights changed. Older states went through major
transformations: France as a result of its Revolution; Britain in the aftermath of centuries
of traumatic wars, internal and external; Germany and Japan following World War II.
India’s founding moments came with its independence from Britain and the legacy of
institutions and values from which the Indian constitution-makers could pick and choose
while adding something of their own. South Africa very clearly had to revise and then
4
Notable examples include the transformation of the dockworkers’ union on the West Coast of
the US after its Big Strike of 1934 (Levi 2005) or the reinvention of itself by the Young Men’s
Christian Association when its traditional base was replaced by a very different demographic
group (Zald 1970).
5
This is research on the reasons for variation in the organizational cultures of unions, supported
by grants from the National Science Foundation SES-0717454 and SES-0517735 and from the
Harry Bridges Center for Labor Studies, University of Washington.
Levi and Epperly, p. 8
recommit to what it meant by the rule of law in the process of abolishing Apartheid. At
this very moment, Nepal is struggling with what it will become with the abolition of the
monarchy and the election of the former Maoists to power while Pakistan tries yet one
more time to establish a constitutional basis for governance and the rule of law.
Throughout the world countries are experiencing moments that could, in retrospect, be
foundational.
They are also struggling to incorporate multiple bases for law and authority.
Malaysia, Singapore and many Islamic countries are searching for ways to combine what
they value from the colonial legacy with sharia and other forms of both codified and
customary practice (Hussin 2007). Countries throughout Africa, both sub-Saharan and
northern, are still in conflict over the standing of traditional practices, such as female
circumcision. The battle over headscarves is a battle over what the rule of law means in
countries with histories as different as Turkey and France. Sweden, Denmark, and the
Netherlands must incorporate new laws along with new immigrants.
These conflicts vary in their likelihood of tearing governments apart. At least part
of the explanation for variable effects has to do with how the governing constitution
emerged as much as with what it contains. Certain features of these foundational
moments appear to be crucial to the emergence and survival of the rule of law. Their
presence does not ensure a stable equilibrium. Their absence appears to ensure a return
to chaos.
The first such feature is principled leadership. Without the right kind of
leadership, neither state agents nor the members of the polity will come to believe that
they are in a situation where corruption is unacceptable and laws likely to be upheld.
Levi and Epperly, p. 9
Principled leadership with the right motivations and incentives to make their
commitments credible is essential for the establishment of the institutional arrangements
that provide both rules and rights. The quality of leadership also matters when existing
rule of law arrangements are under stress due to major shifts in power relationships. They
may be key to whether repression or freedom is the outcome.
The second requirement, largely dependent on the first, is the existence of a
bureaucracy that is itself law-abiding, that implements the laws of the state in a way that
is both relatively honest and procedurally just. This is where the organizational culture
established by the founding leadership plays a significant role. Once the appropriate
organizational culture is in place, the rule of law becomes possible. It is still, however,
fragile. When the first mover dies, is replaced, or experiences a motivational change, the
rule of law may fall apart. To establish the rule of law as a stable equilibrium requires
the establishment of an incentive structure that encourages enough of the state agents to
uphold the law and, in addition, to report and punish those who break it. Only then will
citizens have good reasons to believe that they are in a state of the world where the rule
of law exists, and only then will they calculate that it makes sense to comply and ensure
that others do.
The third requirement is the existence of citizen beliefs that they should be subject
to the law and do their best to uphold it. Levi models popular compliance with
government demands as a problem of quasi-voluntary compliance (Levi 1988, 1997).
Compliance with and obedience to the law is contingent upon citizen (or subject)
perceptions that government is meetings its obligations to them, has the capacity to locate
and punish free riders, and is acting according to prevalent standards of fairness and
Levi and Epperly, p. 10
procedural justice. To the extent citizens (or subjects) believe their government is
trustworthy, fair, and capable of delivering on its promises, the more voluntary
compliance it is likely to elicit. Coercion is always a requirement and a backdrop to
quasi-voluntary compliance, providing assurances that law-breakers will be compelled to
obey or be punished. But an effective rule of law relies on consent as much or more than
coercion.
Quasi-voluntary compliance is essential for maintaining the rule of law, but it is
not the first step in the process of building an effective rule of law regime. The basis for
quasi-voluntary compliance has to be constructed. The emergence of the rule of law
requires the right set of institutions, yes, but it also entails beliefs—among leaders,
bureaucrats, and citizens—that the rule of law exists, will continue to exist, and is of
sufficient benefit to deserve their compliance, consent, and active support.
PRINCIPLED LEADERSHIP
Charismatic leaders, traditional authorities, and strongmen abound, but how often does a
Nelson Mandela appear or a cadre of political elites similar to the Founding Fathers of
the US or the constitution makers of independent India? Motivations that encapsulate the
interests of the general public,6 the possibility of long-term survival, and the capacity for
intelligent law making are rare in combination. Does this reduce the probability of
locating principled leadership to near zero? The goal is not to locate a new Solon. It is to
create an environment in which rulers—whatever the initial source of their authority—
6
This draw’s on Hardin’s conception of “encapsulated self-interest” (Hardin 2002).
Levi and Epperly, p. 11
find it in their interest to establish a reputation as a principled leader who stays true to
those principles even in unforeseen circumstance that require actions in violation of their
short-term interests.
Ideology and morality are the drivers for some leaders. Not all ideologies
encompass commitments to the rule of law, of course. Marxist and nationalist credos
motivate revolutions but may also include rationales for opposition to private property
rights or equal protection under the law. What matters are those ideologies that include a
commitment to a process for creating institutions that will ensure protection of persons,
property and rights over time. Moreover, the core principles must be shared beyond the
great men and women who are the heroes and martyrs of the story and the foundational
leadership cadre. The rule of law requires normative acquiescence as well by those with
the political power and influence to undermine the institutional arrangements of the state.
Assent is more likely when the principled leadership offers a model of action and not just
of ideas.
A demonstrated willingness to suffer for one’s principles enables a leader to offer
a costly signal of intentions to establish and then be bound by the rule of law. George
Washington fought a war. Gandhi lived in poverty. Nehru and Mandela went to prison.
Suu Kyi lives under house arrest. Others have suffered exile or torture for their cause.
Equally importantly, when the founding moment came, they discernibly worked hard to
translate their ideals into constitutions, laws, and governance practice. Most subjected
themselves to elections and term limits or left office willingly. Their principled action
embodied and conveyed the norms they hoped would underpin the governance structures
they helped create.
Levi and Epperly, p. 12
Principled leadership does not necessarily have to be democratic, however. What
defines its commitment to the rule of law is the willingness to be bound by the laws and
to ensure that the laws are implemented and enforced universally. Singapore offers a
contemporary case in point. Its leadership is autocratic, and its violations of democratic
rights and processes mean that it falls outside some broad definitions of the rule of law.
Nonetheless, it is a country famously governed by rules that are obeyed. Its prosperity
and stability are among the consequences.
Nor do all the founders who begin as principled leaders survive with their
principles intact. Power does, after all, corrupt. A recent example of such a phenomenon
is the presidency of Mikheil Saakashvili in Georgia. Coming into office in 2003 on a
wave of popular support during the Rose Revolution, he instituted a number of reforms,
including cracking down on corruption in many branches of the civil service, earning
Georgia accolades by the World Bank (2006). However, when substantial political
opposition appeared and protests similar to those led by Saakashvili in 2003 occurred, the
principles evaporated, and Saakashvili declared a state of emergency, cracking down on
protestors and curtailing media independence. A more extreme example is Robert
Mugabe in Zimbabwe, vaunted as a principled leader during the 1980s and by the end of
another decade considered one of Africa's worst authoritarians (Kohli 1987, 233-35).
Principled leadership is often grounded in moral and ideological motivation, but it
can also have sources in more instrumental stimuli. Membership in a group creates
dependencies that lead individuals to conform to the group norm, even coming to believe
it over time (Hechter 1987). It also creates networks of obligation and reciprocity in
which reputation is key for achievement of further goals (Cook, Hardin, and Levi 2005),
Levi and Epperly, p. 13
Membership has this effect as much for a privileged elite as for the participants in a
commune. The process of winning independence or toppling a previous regime further
forges and enforces a common worldview. The founding moment for establishing the
rule of law then institutionalizes that worldview and its concurrent norms.
A leader can abide by principles and use them as a basis for rule even if that
leader is instrumental. That’s what Machiavelli advocated in The Discourses
(Machiavelli 1950) and what Machiavellian has come to mean. Augustus Caesar offers a
classical case in point. Hardly a saint and most certainly personally ambitious, the desire
to create a dynasty, maintain peace, and nurture economic growth that would make
himself, his followers and his people better off and more loyal led him to encourage the
establishment of laws that would govern his officials as well as the people. The aim was
to ensure the predictability required for investment and trade.
Augustus initially stayed true to the principles he laid out, but before too long he
strayed. Without effective constraints that operate over time, it is not surprising that an
Augustus would deviate. Even the principles of the most principled of first movers are
susceptible to corrosion, as the previous examples of Saakashvili and Mugabe
demonstrate. Competition, dependency, and countervailing power are what constrain a
leader. They are in part a consequence of institutional arrangements that enhance or
delimit ruler power, but they are also determined by the resources available to the ruler
and to those with whom she must bargain (Levi 1988). In the founding moments, when
institutions, even if they exist, are fragile, who has and who uses their bargaining power
can make the difference as to whether the rule of law is even a viable option.
Levi and Epperly, p. 14
THE BUREAUCRACY AND RULE OF LAW REFORMS
Regardless of the level of commitment by principled leaders to establish the rule of law,
they will have to make it worthwhile for other powerful actors in the society to cooperate.
Political and economic elites—through action or inaction—can spur, hamper, or torpedo
moves towards the rule of law (Weingast 1997; Sachs and Pistor 1997). So, too, can the
judiciary (Widner 2001; Helmke 2005; Moustafa 2007; Guarnieri 2003). Our emphasis
here, however, is on those who staff the state (Levi 2008) and whose task it is to
implement the law. The influence of the bureaucracy has been inadequately explored,
but its impact on reforms can be determinative.
Bureaucrats and officials throughout state administrative agencies can engage in
corruption, shirk their mandates, and selectively enforce laws. They have the capability
to openly sabotage attempts by a leader or leadership cadre in moving to a rule of law
equilibrium. The strategic interaction between leaders and staff has consequences for the
preferences of the state leadership with regard to pursuing rule of law reforms. Greif
(2007) explores this aspect of what he labels administrative power, conceived as "the
extent to which the ruler's choices and outcomes are influenced by potential defiance by
those with administrative capacity.”7 A leader facing agents with high levels of
administrative power may decide reform is hopeless and make no attempt to pursue it. A
7
Greif suggests a number of potential equilibria that develop given the combination of the costs
of replacement and of technological, environmental, and cultural factors. He offers the
beginnings of a useful model that fits well with our purposes here.
Levi and Epperly, p. 15
leader, no matter how principled, who lacks the courage or capacity to transform the
bureaucracy, may instead be bowed by it.
Presuming, however, that leadership has pushed ahead, the founding moment
provides an opportunity to reestablish the administrative practices of the state. The
choice of institutional design and the content of the organizational culture not only ensure
the emergence of the rule of law but also facilitate its survival over the longue durée.
The moment of founding provides a strategic opportunity for leadership. Having solved
certain problems of establishing a state and the peace that makes state building possible, a
ruler has the confidence—however briefly—of the population and can undertake
institutional design (or redesign). How she uses this window in which her charisma and
potential are high can make all the difference for the possibility of an enduring rule of
law.
Principal-agent problems
Principal-agent problems are at the heart of the difficulties principled leaders face in
establishing the rule of law. Agency theory clarifies how asymmetric information and
divergence of interests between the agent and the principal can affect bureaucratic
behavior. If leaders are unable to solve their agency problems and motivate government
staff to implement the law and to do so fairly, then the rule of law is non-existent.
Bureaucratic recalcitrance through underperformance can make it impossible to establish
a rule of law equilibrium or upset it once established. Whether it is simply by shirking
job duties and failing to implement policies, or by the selective enforcement of laws,
underperformance has detrimental effects on the diffusion of the new organizational
Levi and Epperly, p. 16
culture the founders are attempting to create. Moreover, bureaucratic failure to
implement laws fairly undermines citizen beliefs that the rule of law actually exists.
At time 2 in Figure 1, principled leaders strive to obtain the cooperation of other
powerful actors in society. Our emphasis is on those who staff the state. Obtaining the
explicit cooperation of the myriad officials and bureaucrats who compose the staff is
highly unlikely but, thankfully, unnecessary. If leaders are able to constrain the
discretion of staff and prevent them from obstructing reforms, the bureaucrats are
effectively "cooperating" with such reforms and unable to meaningfully challenge the
establishment of the rule of law.
Mechanisms for constraining government officials and bureaucrats are of two
general types: vertical accountability; and horizontal control. Elections are the
archetypical form of vertical accountability in democratic politics. Retrospective voting
provides citizens with the opportunity to "toss the bums out" when state officials are
viewed as under-performing or abusing the positions to which they were elected
(O'Donnell 2004). Electoral mechanisms function effectively for officials whose
positions are contingent on the party or legislators in office, but it has little impact when
there is a civil service or other system that insulates bureaucratic jobs from electoral
changes. Another form of vertical accountability, similar to what some have called
"societal accountability" (Smulovitz 2003), depends on interest group lobbying,
grassroots campaigns, and watchdog groups as the monitors. This may be more effective
than elections in controlling bureaucratic behavior.
To produce societal accountability principled leadership must foster an
environment in which public associations, the media, and non-governmental
Levi and Epperly, p. 17
organizations are able to function freely, with a minimal number of regulations allowing
for bureaucrats (at any level) to interfere with their activities. Contemporary Russia
offers an exemplary negative case, where recent changes in the statutes governing nongovernmental organizations have created a situation of ambiguous rules and wide latitude
in enforcement, and the state control of media has hobbled the ability of society to
monitor the agents of the state (Blitt 2007; Fish 2005). The unprincipled leadership of
Russia produces policies aimed at dismantling, rather than building, those institutions that
might, in the right circumstances, help sustain a rule of law equilibrium.
Principled leaders possess a larger number of available mechanisms for
constructing effective means of horizontal control, that is, the use of state institutions to
monitor and sanction other arms of the state and hold other state actors accountable.
Competing arms of the state bureaucracy, oversight agencies, and offices designed to
elicit citizen reports of abuses are all mechanisms of horizontal accountability, in which
some institutional feature of the state is used to check another.
Many of the findings agency theory are more applicable to firms than to states.
Moreover, the literature generally assumes features of advanced industrial economies—
such as effective communications, transportation, and record-keeping—that ease
information transfer and effective monitoring and sanctioning, assumptions that do not
necessarily hold in analyses of less-developed countries (Kiser and Sacks 2008; Kiser
1994). The implication is that the mechanisms of horizontal control available in
advanced industrial economies may not necessarily exist elsewhere. The wholesale
transfer of institutions of accountability from the developed to the developing world will
not work without also transferring the infrastructure that supports the institutions.
Levi and Epperly, p. 18
Efforts at judicial reform in post-Soviet Estonia and Latvia are illustrative. The
two countries inherited identical institutions and highly similar economies at the collapse
of communism, and both sought to bring their judicial systems into line with European
Union standards. A decade after the collapse of communism, the Estonian judicial
system worked relatively well but Latvia's was corrupt and performing poorly. Estonia’s
leadership devoted resources to modernize its judicial infrastructure and to enhance
effective communication and information-sharing across the population. Latvia's courts
were still operating largely with Soviet-era technologies and practices (Open Society
Institute 2002).
Winning the cooperation of bureaucrats in time 2 partially depends on, among
other factors, the design of institutional arrangements that elicit staff effort, reduce
shirking and corruption, and at the same time signal the leader’s type as principled.
Ensuring the maintenance of that cooperation as well as achieving citizen compliance
requires, at time 3, the further institutionalization of arrangements that facilitate the rule
of law. If institutions are designed properly, future bureaucratic obstruction is
minimized. Moreover, the bureaucracy itself can serve as a constraint against potential
defection by the leadership.
Team production and leadership8
The foundational leadership has to be alert to the bureaucratic question. It cannot simply
establish the laws and institutions; it must also provide proper incentives for the staff.
8
This section draws from John Ahlquist and Margaret Levi’s on-going work (Ahlquist and Levi
2008).
Levi and Epperly, p. 19
This involves leadership transparency and credibility based upon principles that are
widely known and demonstrably enacted. Max Weber famously documented the
structural conditions for the emergence of different kinds of bureaucratic structures
(1968), and Herbert Simon provided an account of the individual decision making
processes within the organization, given the cognitive limits of agents (1947). The
emergence of the rule of law definitely depends on factors they identified, but the
interactions between the founding leadership and their staff is what concerns us here. It
is to the models economists have devised to explain the role of leadership in firms that we
now turn for guidance.
Coase (1937) initiated the argument that the nature of firms and other forms of
hierarchy involve a contracting problem between a principal (usually an employer) and
an agent (worker, staff, or contractor). Much of this literature focuses on how optimal
levels of effort (from the principal’s perspective) can be elicited from agents under
different information structures, levels of risk aversion, and more or less complicated
organizational structures. A specialized version of the collective action/public goods
problem, generally referred to as the “moral hazard in teams” or team production
problem, is instructive of why firm leadership establishes certain kinds of institutional
arrangements and why they continue to uphold them. The basic set up is like so:
1. There is a team consisting of N individuals.
2. Each individual can contribute some effort to the group project. Effort is costly
and each person decides non-cooperatively how much effort to supply.
3. Each individual’s effort level is unobservable and unverifiable. This effectively
means that it is impossible to write a contract stipulating how much effort each
person will supply. A related and usually implicit assumption is that agents
cannot be coerced into supplying effort.
4. There is some function that determines what the total team output is given the
cumulative effort. This team output is observable and can be contracted upon.
Levi and Epperly, p. 20
5. There is a stochastic component to the team production function that causes the
productivity of team effort to vary according to some distribution. Agents must
choose their level of effort before they learn the true value of the stochastic
productivity component. It is therefore impossible to write a contract
conditional on the realized value of this random variable. It is possible,
however, to write a contract on an ex ante announcement by one of the team
members as to the true value of the stochastic parameter.
6. A contract, then, is a series of payments to each individual member. These
payments can be made contingent on the team-level outcome and/or the
announced value of the stochastic component.
7. The final output of the team efforts must be completely divided up, i.e., the sum
of the payments to the team members cannot be more or less than total output.
This condition is referred to as the budget balancing constraint.
Holmstrom (1982) shows that, where there is a team production problem, there is no
Nash equilibrium incentive contract that is both budget balancing and Pareto efficient.
The intuition behind this result is that individuals will only contribute to the group project
up to the point that their individual marginal gain is equal to their individual marginal
cost even if their marginal cost of effort is far lower than the marginal team-level output.
Hermalin (1998, 2007) looks to the role of a leader to improve the situation. What
happens if there is some member of the team that can learn the value of this stochastic
productivity factor?9 Clearly this information is valuable to everyone. The problem
arises because this agent (referred to as the leader) has an incentive to lie. Hermalin
considers two possible avenues the leader can pursue for credibly transmitting her
valuable knowledge: “sacrifice” and “leadership by example.” In the first, the leader
makes a gift to the members out of her pocket. In the second, the leader exerts effort in
order to influence others to follow suit. Both, if successful, motivate members to exert
9
Whether this agent learns the true value with certainty or simply has better information as to the
distribution is irrelevant for the substance of his results.
Levi and Epperly, p. 21
themselves on behalf of the organization’s project. However, “sacrifice” contributes
nothing to the overall level of team production while “leading by example” contributes to
and increases it.
The “sacrifice” solution is really just a mechanism design problem: is there a
contract that will induce the leader to tell the truth and that makes the leader better off
than the situation in which her knowledge is not utilized? Hermalin proves that there is.
The gist of the result is that the optimal contract stipulates that in the high productivity
state, the leader distributes some fixed amount to the other team members. This amount
is just big enough such that a leader in the low productivity state has no incentive to copy.
This solution relies on the enforceability of this contract and only allows the team to take
advantage of the leader’s superior knowledge; it does not overcome the team production
problem. In this way, the “sacrifice” option is second best.
In the “lead by example” solution, Hermalin allows the leader to expend her effort
before the rest of the team decides how much effort to contribute. By doing so, the leader
signals to the team whether they are in a high or low productivity state based on her effort
levels. Since this action is costly, it is credible, and a separating Bayesian equilibrium
exists. The “leading by example” outcome is superior to the “sacrifice” option since the
leader’s action directly contributes to the overall level of team production.
The critical component underlying Hermalin’s solutions is the transmission of
information within the group, especially when leaders pursue the lead-by-example option.
Members must be able to observe the leader’s actions at low cost. Through repeat
interactions between members and their leaders, leaders can build up reputations for
credibility over time (Hermalin 2007). Those who begin their leadership roles already
Levi and Epperly, p. 22
embedded in a network of the organization’s members are more likely to have the trust of
members at the start (Ganz 2000). Those who make themselves regularly available to
membership or make their decisions transparent are more likely to retain that trust.
By institutionalizing constraints on themselves, principled leaders exemplify the
behaviors they want of others and provide information as to their type. Ceding final
determination of budgets to legislators, constitutional term limits, and establishing an
independent judiciary with enforcement capacity are among the institutional
arrangements that both delimit the power of leaders and signal their accountability. The
willingness of the leadership to bind its owns hands and ensure transparency of actions
can gain them credibility with both staffs and publics.10
Earlier work on the firm (Barnard 1938) as well as more recent research that
builds on Coasian insights emphasize that it is "…impossible for managers to realize the
full efficiency potential of team production processes through the manipulation of shortterm economic incentives alone” (Miller 1992, 198). They must inspire, and they must
gain the confidence of those they are trying to motivate. The team production literature
makes clear that the critical component is credible information and communication.
Information transmission is crucial to the formation and modification of individual
beliefs and affects the willingness of the staff to support leaders’ policies (Arrow 1974;
Levi 1997). Effective communication between the leader and those whose effort he is
trying to elicit is critical for persuasion (Lupia and McCubbins 1998).
10
This follows a line of reasoning developed by Ferejohn 1999 and then by Alt 2002. Also see
Levi 2005.
Levi and Epperly, p. 23
Corruption
The proposed solutions to team production problems presume that certain bureaucratic
problems are already resolved, namely that procedures are in place to monitor and
enforce staff behavior that would undermine relationships with those the bureaucrats are
meant to serve. Team production improves the capacity of leadership to elicit effort and
increase the loyalty of the staff to it, but it does not necessarily eliminate predation by the
staff on citizens and subjects of the state. Corruption is the bête noire of the rule of law.
Overcoming its prevalence among nineteenth century English tax collectors made it
possible for the English state to win parliamentary approval and relatively wide-spread
popular compliance with the income tax (Levi 1988; Brewer 1988). Similarly, in Hong
Kong the ability of the government to establish effective anti-corruption efforts resulted
in much higher levels of confidence in government (Manion 2004).
There are, of course, multiple reasons for corruption, and not all corruption is equal.
As Merton pointed out long ago, some forms of corruption may actually grease the
wheels of government in ways that better serve the public (Merton 1968 [1957]). He was
talking about ward heeling and not the rent seeking or extortion detrimental to state
effectiveness and trustworthiness. Devastating to the rule of law is high-level corruption
involving huge sums of money a la Bangladesh or the hidden bank accounts of the Papa
Docs of the world. But perhaps as important, particularly in the developing world, are
the police and other local officials who form protection rackets, who threaten and thieve
from those they are supposed to safeguard.
Solutions to high-level corruption require powerful actors within the polity who
possess the political will and resources to make a change, often with the support of
Levi and Epperly, p. 24
international NGOs such as Transparency International or the World Bank.11 Elimination
of predatory actions by local officials often requires an appropriate structure of payment
to street-level bureaucrats so that they depend on the state, rather than other sources, for
their incomes, advancement, and well-being. They can then come to calculate that they
are better off serving their clients than robbing them. At a minimum, they must receive a
sufficient salary from the state (Bates 2008). In post-communist contexts corruption
tends to be more prevalent when bureaucrats believe that their pay is below the cost of
living, which leads them to feel that corruption is a justifiably necessity, even when they
also consider it a social ill (Miller, Grodeland, and Koshechkina 2001).12
Corruption at every level of the bureaucratic ladder remains a serious barrier to the
establishment of a self-enforcing rule of law equilibrium. While corruption exists to
some degree in any state, the effects of systematic corruption are qualitatively different,
structuring interactions among state agents and between such agents and the populace
(Manion 2004). For higher-level bureaucrats, widespread corruption can be seen as a
signaling device, demonstrating to those at the same level of the hierarchy, as well as
those below, that any commitment expressed by a principled leader is at best quixotic,
and at worst fraudulent.
11
This is the current strategy in Bangladesh.
12
Interestingly, such opinions were also reported by many respondents who were themselves not
bureaucrats, suggesting that little (or in some cases no) pay has an effect on attitudes toward
corruption throughout the populace.
Levi and Epperly, p. 25
Again, the experiences of Estonia and Latvia are illustrative, demonstrating the
important role of well-defined and well-enforced sanctions on state officials and staff. In
the first years of independence, Estonia adopted some of the most extensive regulations
on corruption of any of the Eastern European countries seeking European Union (EU)
membership. A series of high-profile prosecutions of bureaucrats for the abuse of office
took place throughout the 1990s. Consequently, during the EU accenssion process,
Estonia was widely regarded as being the least corrupt of all new member countries
(Open Society Institute 2002). Latvia, on the other hand, half-heartedly embraced anticorruption efforts, waiting a decade to enact real civil service reform and pursuing anticorruption cases less than vigorously. Both high and low-level corruption remains
widespread. Without clear and credible sanctions, even well monitored bureaucrats may
be prone to deviant behavior. The benefits of corruption outweigh the costs if the costs
are ill-defined or rarely imposed.
Perceptions of widespread corruption signal to each bureaucrat a low return from
honest practices and from non-discriminatory enforcement of law. In such contexts, the
honest bureaucrat will end up being a sucker, shouldering the burdens and receiving none
of the benefits. Corruption also reduces citizen confidence in government whether it is
practiced by visible high-level bureaucrats whose behavior citizens learn about in media
accounts or the accessible low-level bureaucrats with whom they interact regularly
(Miller, Grodeland, and Koshechkina 2001). Citizen perceptions of shirking, preferential
treatment, and venality also negatively affect beliefs about the realization of the rule of
law and undermine the possibility of a rule of law equilibrium.
Levi and Epperly, p. 26
Leadership-bureaucratic interaction
Principled leadership is not sufficient to obtain the rule of law, but it is an important
component. By publicly shaming and punishing corrupt officials, principled leaders
provide information about their own principles as well as their commitment to creating a
rule of law.
Without principled leadership, the probability of obtaining bureaucratic respect for
the rule of law is minimal.13 Without principled leadership committed to rule of law
reforms, the threat of sanctions for transgressions against the dictates of the rule of law
will not be credible. Why would bureaucratic agents believe that the principal will
expend the resources required to effectively monitor and sanction the bureaucrats for not
complying with policies that the principal herself is clearly not committed to
implementing?
ACHIEVING LEGITIMACY AND QVC
Legitimating beliefs about the state and the quasi-voluntary compliance that follows are
essential to the successful establishment of the rule of law and to its maintenance over
time. Public support and conviction that it is normatively appropriate to obey the law,
ceteris paribus, transforms a coercive into a rule of law regime. But legitimating beliefs
are a consequence of other prior factors, most importantly the credible commitments of
principled leadership, bureaucratic performance and integrity, and institutional
13
Manion (2004) discusses this with regard to anti-corruption efforts in Hong Kong and the
People's Republic of China.
Levi and Epperly, p. 27
arrangements that ensure the continued observance by leaders and bureaucrats to the
principles of the culture of law they are trying to realize.
How populations develop such perceptions and beliefs is not always
straightforward, however, particularly when there are multiple groups within the polity.
Again, leadership plays a critical role in establishing a common set of values—or not.
Shared social norms of a group offer guidance to members about whether to consider
deference or resistance to authority. The group also creates a setting in which its
members develop a sense of reciprocity towards each other, making them more likely to
conform with each other and less likely to free ride on the others’ efforts. When a group
perceives the leaders and bureaucrats of a state as unfair and discriminatory—or worse—
it is likely to develop a normative stance of defiance. Shirking obligations, vandalism,
and even armed struggle can result, and the rule of law becomes far more difficult. The
francophones in Canada, the Irish Catholics in Northern Ireland, the Basques of Spain are
recent examples from the developed world. India still experiences communal riots, sixty
years after Partition. Ethnic, religious, linguistic, and racial conflicts are constantly
tearing apart countries with less governance capacity.
Those countries that can both experience strong tensions and maintain the rule of
law have several features in common. First, they have constitutions and constitutional
histories in which actual negotiations took place to ensure that all participating parties
had protection under the law.14 In India, this involved granting special rights to Dalits
and others who had previously enjoyed no civil rights. In Canada and the United States, it
14
This is an empirical claim we need to explore further.
Levi and Epperly, p. 28
produced forms of federalism to protect sectional and regional interests. Second, they
had leadership that produced organizational cultures based on principles of relative equity
and fairness. Such leadership facilitated the original constitutional negotiations, acted to
obtain the initial cooperation of powerful elites, and then designed institutions that
ensured that cooperation over time. Finally, these are countries whose institutions and
leadership continue to exhibit the capacity to reform institutions to incorporate new actors
and new understandings of appropriate law while, simultaneously, maintaining a
commitment to the core values that initially stimulated building the rule of law. The
combination of principled leadership and reasonably well-designed institutions give
citizens confidence they are dealing with a trustworthy and legitimate government whose
authority they feel obligated to obey.
Institutions are not sufficient on their own. It is principled principals who design,
transform, and breathe life into them, and it is bureaucrats and citizens who uphold them.
It is principled principals whose leadership by example signals to the elites, the staff, and
the populace the nature of the world they inhabit and the reasons for complying with the
rule of law.
Levi and Epperly, p. 29
REFERENCES
Acemoglu, Daron, Simon Johnson, and James A. Robinson. 2001. "The Colonial Origins
of Comparative Development: An Empirical Investigation." American Economic
Review 91 (5):1369-401.
———. 2002. "Reversal of Fortune: Geography and Institutions in the Making of the
Modern World Income Distribution." The Quarterly Journal of Economics:123194.
Ahlquist, John, and Margaret Levi. 2008. "Provoking Preferences by Changing Beliefs."
Seattle: University of Washington Department of Political Science.
Alt, James E. 2002. "Comparative Political Economy: Credibility, Transparency,
Accountability and Institutions." In The State of the Discipline: Power, Choice,
and the State, ed. I. Katznelson and H. Milner. New York: W. W. Norton.
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1974. The Limits of Organization. New York: W.W. Norton.
Barnard, Chester I. 1938. The Functions of the Executive. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press.
Bates, Robert H. 2008. Why States Fail. New York: Cambridge.
Blitt, Robert C. . 2007. "Babushka Said Two Things - It Will Either Rain or Snow; It
Either Will or Will Not: An Analysis of the Provisions and Human Rights
Implications of Russia's New Law on Nongovernmental Organizations as Told
Through Eleven Russian Proverbs." University of Tennessee Legal Studies
Research Paper No. 2. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1009400.
Brewer, John. 1988. "The English State and Fiscal Appropriation: Taxes and Public
Finance in England, 1688-1789." Politics & Society.
Coase, Ronald H. 1937. "The Nature of the Firm." Economica 4:386-405.
Cook, Karen S, Russell Hardin, and Margaret Levi. 2005. Cooperation Without Trust?
New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Engerman, Stanley L., Ken Sokoloff, and Steven Haber. 1997. "Factor Endowments,
Institutions, and Differential Paths of Growth Among New World Economies: A
View from Economic Historians of the United States." In Economic Growth and
Latin American Economic Historiography, ed. S. Haber. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Ferejohn, John. 1999. "Accountability and Authority: Toward a Theory of Political
Accountability." In Democracy, Accountability and Representation, ed. A.
Przeworski, S. C. Stokes and B. Manin. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Fish, M. Steven. 2005. Democracy Derailed in Russia: the Failure of Open Politics. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Ganz, Marshall. 2000. "Resources and Resourcefulness: Strategic Capacity in the
Unionization of California Agriculture, 1959-1966." The American journal of
sociology. 105 (4):1003.
Greif, Avner. 2007. "The Impact of Administrative Power on Political and Economic
Development: Toward Political Economy of Implementation." Palo Alto, CA:
Stanford University.
Guarnieri, Carlo. 2003. "Courts As An Instrument of Horizontal Accountability: The
Case of Latin Europe." In Democracy and the Rule of Law, ed. A. Przeworski and
J. M. Maravall. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hardin, Russell. 2002. Trust and Trustworthiness. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Levi and Epperly, p. 30
Hechter, Michael. 1987. Principles of Group Solidarity. Berkeley: University of
California.
Helmke, Gretchen. 2005. Ruling Against the Rulers: Court Executive Relations in
Argentina Under Dictatorship and Democracy. Edited by M. Levi. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Hermalin, Benjamin E. 1998. "Toward an Economic Theory of Leadership." The
American Economic Review 88 (5):1188-206.
———. 2007. "Leading for the long term." Journal of Economic Behavior &
Organization 62 (1):1-19.
Holmstrom, Bengt. 1982. "Moral Hazard in Teams." Bell Journal of Economics 13
(2):324-40.
Hussin, Iza. 2007. The Politics of Islamic Law: Local Elites and Colonial Authority in
India, Malaya and Egypt, Political Science, University of Washington, Seattle.
Kiser, Edgar. 1994. "Markets and Hierarchies in Early Modern Tax Systems: A PrincipalAgent Analysis." Politics & Society 22 (3):285-316.
Kiser, Edgar, and Audrey Sacks. 2008. "African Patrimonialism in Historical
Perspective: Assessing Decentralized and Privatized Tax Administration."
Kohli, Atul. 1987. The State and Poverty in India: the Politics of Reform. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Kreps, David M. 1990. "Corporate Culture and Economic Theory." In Perspectives in
Positive Political Economy, ed. J. Alt and K. Shepsle. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Levi, Margaret. 1988. Of Rule and Revenue. Berkeley: The University of California
Press.
———. 1997. Consent, Dissent and Patriotism. New York: Cambridge University Press.
———. 2005. "Inducing Preferences within Organizations." In Preferences and
Situations: Points of Intersection Between Historical and Rational Choice
Institutionalism, ed. I. Katznelson and B. R. Weingast. New York: Russell Sage
Foundation.
———. 2006. "Why We Need a New Theory of Government." Perspectives on Politics 4
(1):5-19.
Levi, Margaret, and Audrey Sacks. 2007. "Legitimating Beliefs: Concepts and
indicators." In Afrobarometer Working Papers: Michigan State University.
Levi, Margaret, Audrey Sacks, and Tom R. Tyler. forthcoming. "Conceptualizing
Legitimacy, Measuring Legitimating Beliefs." American Behavioral Scientist.
Lipset, S. M. 1959. "Some social requisites of democracy." Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 53:69.
Lupia, Arthur, and Mathew D. McCubbins. 1998. The Democratic Dilemma: Can citizens
learn what they need to know? New York: Cambridge University Press.
Machiavelli, Niccolo. 1950. The Prince and the Discourses. New York: The Modern
Library.
Manion, Melanie. 2004. Corruption by Design: Bribery in Chinese Enterprise Licensing.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Merton, Robert K. 1968 [1957]. Social Theory and Social Structure. 3rd ed. Glencoe, Ill.:
The Free Press.
Miller, Gary. 1992. Managerial Dilemmas. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Miller, William Lockley , Ase B. Grodeland, and Tatyana Y. Koshechkina. 2001. A
Levi and Epperly, p. 31
Culture of Corruption? Coping with Government in Post-Communist Europe.
Budapest: Central European University Press.
Moustafa, Tamir. 2007. The Struggle for Constitutional Power: Law, Politics, and
Economic Development in Egypt New York: Cambridge University Press.
North, Douglass C., John Wallis, and Barry Weingast. forthcoming. A Conceptual
Framework for Understanding Recorded Human History (tentative).
O'Donnell, Guillermo A. 2004. "Why the Rule of Law Matters." Journal of Democracy
15 (4):32-46.
Open Society Institute. 2002. "Monitoring the EU Accession Process: Corruption and
Anti-Corruption Policy." New York: Open Society Institute.
Przeworski, Adam. 2004. "Institutions Matter?" Government and Opposition 39 (4):52740.
Sachs, Jeffrey , and Katharina Pistor, eds. 1997. The Rule of Law and Economic Reform
in Russia. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Simon, Herbert A. 1947. Administrative Behavior. New York: MacMillan.
Smulovitz, Catalina. 2003. "How Can the Rule of Law Rule? Cost Imposition Through
Decentralized Mechanisms." In Democracy and the Rule of Law, ed. A.
Przeworski and J. M. Maravall. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sokoloff, Ken, and Stanley L. Engerman. 2006. Annual Review of Political Science 10.
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1990 [1840]. Democracy in America. Vol. II. New York:
Vintage.
Tyler, Tom R. 1990. Why People Obey The Law. New Haven: Yale University Press.
———. 2006. "Psychological Perspectives on Legitimacy and Legitimation." Annual
Review of Psychology 57 (1):375-400.
Weber, Max. 1968. "Bureaucracy." In Economy and Society, ed. G. Roth and C. Wittich.
New York: Bedminister.
Weingast, Barry R. 1997. "The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of
Law." American Political Science Review 91 (2):245-63.
Widner, Jennifer A. 2001. Building the Rule of Law. New York: W. W. Norton.
World Bank. 2006. "Doing Business 2007: How to Reform." Washington D.C.: World
Bank.
Zald, Mayer N. 1970. Organizational Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Time 1
Time 2
Time 3
Time 4
Nature moves
Powerful actors
Principled leader
Citizens
Chall enge
Compli ance
Good institutional
design
Principled
Leadership
Noncompli ance
Cooperate
Poor institutional
design
FIGURE 1: A model of the process of establishing the rule of law, given a principled first mover.
Stable rule
of law
Download