Civic Integration of Immigrants in Western Europe

advertisement

Christian Joppke

Civic Integration Policies Reviewed:

National Models v. Policy Convergence

Since the late 1990s, “civic integration” has become the dominant immigrant integration policy in Western Europe. Even Switzerland, with its

Fördern und Fordern

, has partaken in the trend. There has been a debate whether the new policy is convergent across states or whether it merely prolongs, under different name, established “national models” of integration. I offer two arguments in favor of policy convergence. First, extant policy variation runs counter to “national model” expectations. Secondly, the few national-model type variations that you may still find are with respect to the form not substance of policy.

Since the late 1990s, “civic integration” policies for immigrants have been adopted by most

Western European states. The novelty of the policy seems to be at least twofold. First, integration is no longer left to the free play of society`s institutions, such as labor market or education, but is attempted to be brought under conscious, concerted state control. In this respect, civic integration is tantamount to the rise of state-led integration as such, replacing a previous rein of laissez-faire, complemented by mainly local interventions. Secondly, civic integration combines measures that further the integration of immigrants with their selection and control, so that integration and immigration policy are no longer separate domains.

There have been several lines of debate surrounding the new policy. One has been normative, asking whether the policy is “liberal” or “illiberal”, and whether, despite its name, civic integration marks a return from “integration” to “assimilation” (see Orgad, forthcoming; in part also Goodman 2014; an overview of the various positions is the collection of comments by xxx [anonymized], discussing citizenship tests as one instance of civic integration). A second debate has been over the question whether civic integration is a departure from previous multiculturalism policies, whose “retreat” has thus been processed in a civic integration idiom; or whether civic integration and multiculturalism policies may

1

coexist, the former merely having been “layered over” persistent multiculturalism policies

(see Banting 2011; Banting and Kymlicka 2013; Kymlicka 2012). A third debate has been over the question of continuity or discontinuity of policy, if not the very usefulness of the notion of distinct national styles or “models” of integration, and how civic integration fits into this. For one line of authors, civic integration flags the “end of national models” (if there ever were any) and rise of policy convergence (xxx: anonymized). A number of critics have objected that national models of integration continue to exist, even under the new cover of civic integration (especially Goodman 2012, 2014). It is this third debate that this paper taps into, tackling the question of national models v. policy convergence, and seeking to render plausible the “policy convergence” position.

In the first part (I), I provide a brief overview of civic integration, why it emerged at this point in time, and locating it within European immigration history. In the second part (II),

I offer two arguments in favor of policy convergence: first, extant policy variations, which of course cannot be denied, tend to run counter to national-model expectations; second, the few national-model type variations that still can be found are more with respect to the form than the substance of policy.

(I) What is Civic Integration?

Since the late 1990s, civic integration has become the dominant approach to immigrant integration across Europe. The term itself is an approximate English translation of the Dutch noun inburgering

, whose literal translation would be “naturalization”, “habituation”, or

“acclimatization”.

Inburgering became a legal term in the first of all European civic integration laws, the Dutch 1998 Newcomer Integration Law ( Wet Inburgering Nieuwkomers , in short WIN). WIN obliged new immigrants to the Netherlands to take an integration course, which consists of Dutch language and civics lessons. On English-language Dutch and

2

Flemish-Belgian government websites, inburgering has hence been referred to as “civic integration”. Other European states that quickly adopted the “Dutch model” (Michalowski

2004) have other words for the same policy—such as Integrationskurse in Germany,

Integrationsvereinbarung in Austria, Contrat d`acceuil et d`intégration (CAI) in France; also the Swiss integration policy under the motto

Fördern und Fordern

is a variant of civic integration (see Eule 2015). Their different names still cover a similar idea and content: the state-enforced formal obligation for immigrants to acquire the language of the host-society and to familiarize themselves with its political institutions, history, and culture (“civics”). Not meeting this obligation may forfeit one`s legal residence status or even first entry, as in the case of “integration from abroad” (more on which below).

The invention and meteoric proliferation of civic integration at this point in time reflects an important moment of change in Europe`s immigration history. Up to then immigration had been considered a finite episode of European post-WWII history, channeled in terms of “guestworker” or “postcolonial” immigration, or both (see xxx: anonymized). As different as they were in terms of origins and institutional processing, these immigrations were not to be repeated but to be brought to a close, humanely yet firmly (“firm but fair” was appositely the motto of British immigration policy). Of course, after the closing-down of

“new-seed” guestworker and postcolonial immigration in the late 1960s to early 1970s, there had immediately been other, unforeseen types of inflow, most importantly asylum-seeking and family migration, and also, though much more limited than in the United States, illegal immigration. But still in the early 1990s the dominant mindset among European political elites was that the goal of state policy should be to bring all immigration to a halt, immigration zéro

in the hopeful words of a hard-lining French interior minister at the time,

Charles Pasqua.

Integration in the context of notional zero immigration was a combination of nonpolicy and reflex-like continuation of old ways of dealing with cultural difference, within a

3

mindset of dealing in a humane and service-oriented way with frictions and adjustment problems of migrant streams that were considered historically unique and non-continuous. At the same time, there was a tight legal and ideational separation between the policy domains of immigration and integration, to the limited degree that the latter was a state-level concern at all (at local level, where immigrants settled, integration always was a concern). Overall, one cannot earnestly talk of an explicit integration policy in most European states before the arrival of civic integration. These were settled nation states, if not ideologically post-nation states, that had unlearned the great integration exercise, when “peasants” were turned into

“Frenchmen” in the late 19 th century, to use Eugene Weber`s evocative metaphor (1976). By the same token, when integration reappeared on the state radar at late 20 th

century`s end, it had to take on radically different, namely: less nationalistic and more liberal features than those known from classic nation-building.

The reappearance of integration occurred in the course of the 1990s, when European states` attitudes to immigration changed completely. Representative for many, the German government abandoned the long-held mantra that Germany was “not a country of immigration”. Also in France, the call for zero immigration could no longer be heard. If one looks for a game-changing event, it is the breakdown of Communism and the rise of globalization. The world was no longer two but one, with unprecedented people mobility as potential (and often actualized) consequence. Most of this mobility was still unwanted by states, which responded forcefully to live up to their residual function of caging people—the martial notion of “Fortress Europe” dates from this very moment. But, importantly, it dawned on policymakers that global markets and technologies could not be run and developed without globally mobile personnel. In the late 1990s, in Germany, a cosmopolitan, reform-minded

SPD and Green Party coalition government introduced the so-called “Green Card” scheme to recruit high-skilled migrants for the IT sector. Quickly there was no European state left without a policy to recruit high-skilled immigrants, which at EU level materialized in the so-

4

called “Blue Card” scheme. In addition, in 2000, the Population Division of the United

Nations Organization published its famous report outlining the dramatic degree and consequences of demographic shrinkage in Europe (for an overview, see xxx). In the context of chronic right-wing populist mobilization across Europe the demographic rationale for immigration has still to enter politicians` vocabulary. But it was the last nail in the coffin of zero immigration as mainstream political project.

The new reality of recurrent, rather than one-shot immigration, which is a historical novelty in Europe, catapulted integration from a low- or local-level concern to a central state concern. Across Europe, integration became tantamount to “civic integration”. Confirmed by many case and comparative studies (e.g., Permoser 2014; Goodman and Wright, forthcoming), there is an indelible symbolic dimension to civic integration, which is as much, if not primarily, directed at immigration-averse mass publics as at immigrants themselves.

The often harsh and disciplinary rhetoric of civic integration wishes to assure natives that

“their” government is in charge and that local habitats and traditional milieus are not going to be washed away by ongoing, no longer stoppable immigration, often from faraway places and cultures. Recent empirical work on the evolution of migration policies in a large swathe of

(mostly rich) countries further supports the view (first expounded by Freeman 1995) that, contrary to the ongoing strength of anti-immigration rhetoric, policies have actually become less restrictive over time (de Haas, Natter and Vezzoli 2014).

There is a second subtext to the rise of civic integration, which is that multiculturalism has failed to bring about the integration of immigrants, instead shoving the latter into anomic and deprived “parallel societies”. The “civic” in civic integration signals integration into society`s mainstream institutions, especially the labor market. The Dutch case epitomizes this thrust. Civic integration substituted the previous “ethnic minorities policy”, which had been adopted in the early 1980s to provide “equality of opportunity” for disadvantaged immigrant minorities, but weirdly by supporting a separate infrastructure and identities for the latter.

5

State-supported separatism was no invention of the age of multiculturalism but fed upon the

Dutch tradition of “pillarization” to mend the deep religious and ideological friction that had hampered Dutch nation-building through the ages. But it was now held responsible for the

“multicultural tragedy” (as the Dutch sociologist and Labour Party activist Paul Scheffer called it) of high unemployment, school failure, and residential segregation among immigrant ethnics, particularly Turks and Moroccans.

But even in countries that had never known multiculturalism policies, there has been a rhetorical retreat from a demonized multiculturalism and turn to civic integration instead (see xxx: anonymized). A juxtaposition of multiculturalism and civic integration helps calibrate the latter. In countries that never had it as official state policy, most typically Germany,

“multiculturalism” is another word for laissez-faire and drift, that is, for the state keeping out of the process of integration. This abstinence is now found wanting. If there is state intervention, it should be centrist and not reinforcing separateness—hence “civic integration”.

Moreover, “multiculturalism” is associated with the burden of adjustment being more on the receiving society than on the immigrants. This is reversed in civic integration, where the burden of adjustment is imposed almost exclusively on the immigrants. The Dutch case, again, shows this shift more clearly than other cases. Immigrants are not just expected to become economically self-sufficient (and thus no burden on the welfare state), but they are quite literally required to pay in full for the cost of civic integration courses and tests--the fees are accordingly much higher in the Netherlands than in any other country. “Privatized integration”, one might even argue, signals a “total retreat” of the state from supporting integration at all (Michalowski 2009: 275). This is also shown in the fact that, apart from a short film and small booklet, the Dutch state provides no infrastructure in terms of integration courses or course materials.

States now often use the notion of a “contract” with the immigrant, as the French contrat d`acceuil or the Austrian Integrationsvereinbarung . In this contract, admission to the

6

host state and society is exchanged against concrete and objectively verifiable integration efforts (and, in the Dutch case, results) on part of the immigrant, short of which a residence permit is denied. In this “contract”, there is no parallel obligation, not to mention adjustment effort, exacted on the host state. Civic integration, at least in its extreme version practiced in the Netherlands, thus disproves the official definition of “integration”, given out in the

European Council`s influential “Common Basic Principles of Immigrant Integration in the

E.U.” (2004), and reiterated in so many official state declarations. According to it,

“integration” is a “two-way” process of “mutual accommodation”, in which not only immigrants but also the receiving society has to change (see xxx: anonymized). In reality, civic integration is “one-way” only, the immigrant but not society being expected to change.

Thirdly, the obligatory, even punitive nature of civic integration in Europe is intrinsically connected to the demographic profile of immigration in Europe: the latter is overwhelmingly low-skilled family migration, with a high proportion originating from

Muslim countries. This linkage is especially visible in the most drastic variant of civic integration, which is “integration from abroad”. Invented, again, in the Netherlands, in 2006, it asks for elementary host society language and civic knowledge as precondition for being granted a temporary visa for first entry. The linkage between obligatory integration and lowskilled immigration from culturally distant regions of the world is also confirmed by certain national-origin exemptions granted in some countries, especially Germany and the

Netherlands. The Netherlands, for instance, exempts not only citizens of other EU and

European Economic Area countries (which is required by European Union law), but also citizens of the United States, Canada, Australia, New Zealand, Japan, South Korea, and other rich OECD countries. These exemptions are justified as favoring countries “comparable to

European countries in cultural, socioeconomic and societal respect”, and whose nationals “in general possess a certain insight into the societal relations we have in the Netherlands and into

Dutch norms and values” (quoted in Bonjour 2011: 53).

7

Fourthly, the demographic nature of the immigration to be processed by civic integration points to the policy`s perhaps most distinct feature, which is to link immigrant integration with immigration control and immigrant selection. Low-skilled immigration, after all, is structurally marked by the supply greatly exceeding the demand for it (see Bhagwati

2004: ch.14). The control feature is again most clearly expressed in the policy`s “integration from abroad” variant, where the failure to pass the exam is mostly tantamount to denied entry.

By contrast, the control element is more virtual than real in the denial of permanent residence for failing the post-entry civic integration hurdle (which is the classic variant of civic integration), because this hardly ever leads to deportation but simply the maintenance of temporary, though naturally more precarious residence status. Finally, the control and selection element is more fictitious still in the case of denied citizenship acquisition. This is the third step in the civic integration continuum, which ranges from pre-entry to post-entry

(“civic integration” proper) and citizenship. The citizenship-acquisition stage of civic integration is the one with the least teeth, because denied citizenship applicants simply continue to be legal permanent residents.

With respect to integration from abroad, the Dutch government nonchalantly called it

“selection mechanism”, and it allegedly rewarded not education and socioeconomic background but individual “motivation and severance” (quoted in Bonjour 2011: 57). While denying that a reduction of family immigration is the purpose, the Dutch government still counts this reduction as welcome “side effect”, originally expecting it to be in the 25 percent range (ibid. 58).

(II) End of National Models?

The four elements of recurrent immigration, (rhetorical) retreat from multiculturalism, targeting of unwanted family migration, and obligatory-cum-punitive character, the latter

8

tying civic integration to the previously separate immigration control function, can be found, in more or less developed form, in all instances of civic integration. They are elements of policy convergence i , “beyond national models” (xxx: anonymized). This notion still came to be instantly questioned (e.g. Jacobs and Rea 2007; Goodman 2012; Mouritsen 2013; Bonjour

2011; Borevi 2013). But it was never meant to deny “significant variation” across states (xxx: anonymized). Rather, the claim is that these variations:

 Either run counter to the usual (British) “multiculturalism” vs. (French)

“assimilationism” vs. (Austrian/German/Swiss) “segregationism” triplet that is the mainstay of “national model” reasoning (for typical examples, see Castles 1995, also

Koopmans et al. 2005);

Or affect at best the style and discursive presentation (or form) but not the substance of the policy.

In the following, I discuss both aspects in turn, complemented by a look at the contents of civic integration requirements, which are broadly “liberal”.

Model-Inconsistent Variation. When comparing civic integration policies across

European states, the first thing to notice is the bewildering variety and complexity of these policies. They cover the pre-departure, post-entry, and citizenship acquisition phases with often separate rules and rationales that, on top of it, are constantly changing (see the global overviews by Perching 2012 and Strik et al. 2010, both already in need of being updated). To detect patterns in this jungle is no easy matter. Let us still try to distill some of the more interesting features. Confirming the policy convergence hypothesis, Perching speaks of a

“reframing of `integration`”, from a “rights-based frame” that had predominated until the

1990s, with “legal equality” as the benchmark of immigrant integration, to a “duty-based concept” that defines the “individual migrant as the main actor of integration” (Perching

2012: 116). This seems to be the incontrovertible bottom line of civic integration, underneath

9

its various national incarnations and changes over time. But apart from this bottom line, rarely a country approximates the Dutch extreme case.

Consider only the example of “integration from abroad”. With respect to organization and cost , in sharp contrast to the Netherlands, Germany offers integration courses abroad, through its Goethe Institutes, and it provides ample learning materials; and the cost of the procedure is about one third of the Dutch (Strik et al. 2010: 12). France is particularly lenient, as a temporary visa is granted even if the applicant`s knowledge is deemed insufficient; an applicant with insufficient knowledge is merely obliged to take a course after arrival, the course- and test-taking being offered for free. Denmark, generally considered a hardliner much like the Netherlands, originally planned to adopt the Dutch scheme point by point. But cost-benefit considerations moved it to hold the test not abroad but in Denmark, and all applicants are provided with a provisional 3-month visa. Furthermore, the Danish exam is not done with a voice computer but through an officer orally examining the applicant. A negative decision can be legally challenged, which is not the case in the Netherlands.

With respect to level and content of the test, Dutch integration from abroad at first required only very basic Dutch language competence, at the A1- level on the Council of

Europe`s Common European Framework of Reference for Languages (CEFR). When 90 percent of applicants were found to pass the test at this low level, the requirement was moved up to the next higher A1 level. Germany from the start asked for A1 level language competence. But it abstained from asking for civics knowledge at this early stage, reserving it for the post-entry stage, within the Integrationskurse proper. France sets the language hurdle particularly low, even below A1, while “Republican values” are tested in the earliest moment-

-but in the language preferred by the applicant!

Finally, there are interesting variations with respect to target group exemptions .

Germany and the Netherlands exempt family immigrants from rich OECD countries, but also the highly skilled and work-contract holders. By contrast, France and Denmark do not grant

10

any nationality-based exemptions, except those required by EU law. In the case of Denmark, which otherwise was strongly inspired by the Dutch example, a blunt distinction between

“Western” and “non-Western” country applicants was not adopted due to lawyers` concerns that this would be found unlawful under the European Convention of Human Rights. And the

UK exempts applicants from certain English-speaking countries, like Australia, Canada, USA, and New Zealand. Delicately, however, other English-speaking countries, like India, Nigeria,

Pakistan, Ghana, and Malaysia, are not exempted (see Groenendijk 2011: 19).

In the so far most ambitious political science treatise on civic integration in Europe,

Sara Wallace Goodman (2014) seeks to explain these and other variations of civic integration with the help of two factors: first, existing citizenship regimes and legacies and, secondly, the political color of the government in charge ii

. The idea is that traditionally liberal countries will do light-touch civic integration (or none at all), which is more rights- and service- than dutyoriented and punitive (the prime example being Britain), unless there is right-wing political mobilization for restriction (as recently happened in France and the Netherlands). On the opposite end, traditionally restrictive countries will beef-up their exclusive citizenships with a second layer of restrictive civic integration at the level of legal permanent residence

(examples being Denmark, Austria, or Germany). In all cases, “new requirements do not signal departures from national approaches to citizenship, but rather fortify them” (Goodman

2012: 692). She also speaks of the “anchoring (of) citizenship in new content and rules”

(ibid.).

The problem with this analysis is to attribute too much grand strategy to what in reality is more likely to be a combination of copy-cat, muddling-through, and sheer inconsistency, which is often the result of political struggle and compromise (see the instructive critique by Michalowski and van Oers 2012: 170). The distinction between “state identity”, revolving around legal permanent residence, and “national identity”, reserved for citizenship, is opaque, and there is little evidence that states are operating in these terms; the

11

distinction, in fact, appears more imagined than real (Goodman 2014:ch.1). Most importantly, many of the new civic integration measures patently contradict national legacies of citizenship or of dealing with cultural difference, which are the hub of “national model” reasoning. Take only France`s risibly low language expectations on newcomers, which are a constant from pre-entry to naturalization. They run counter to France`s alleged obsessiveness with

“assimilation”, and appear to be more mundanely conditioned by low pressure on the language front due to most newcomers` status as francophone. Or take Britain`s cultural thickening of its identity projection in its most recently amended “Life in the UK” test (too late to be considered in a book published in 2014), which is much less practical-minded than its predecessor and now includes statements like “the UK is historically a Christian country”

(quoted in Orgad, forthcoming: ch.3). This latest change would not surprise in Germany, with its penchant for a “Christian-Occidental” self-description, but it is not what you would expect in always “liberal” Britain.

A particularly instructive case for deviation from national model expectations is

Austria. It figures in Goodman (2012; 2014) and in most other accounts as unrepentant hardliner in matters of immigration and citizenship. Its 2003 Integrationsvereinbarung was indeed pushed by the right-wing FPÖ (

Freiheitliche Partei Österreichs

, Liberal Party of

Austria), which railed against “failed integration” and “abuse” of the welfare state, and which construed Muslim immigrants as a “threat” to Austrian culture. But the Austrian Integration

Fund (AIF), which was mandated with putting flesh on the scheme, smuggled into it an amazingly liberal content. According to the AIF, the purpose of the obligatory integration course, which is offered for free, is to allow the immigrant to “integrate into Austrian society while at the same time maintaining his or her own identity” (quoted in Mouráo Permoser

2012: 191); the course curriculum is “pro-migrant and practice-oriented” (ibid.); and there is an “absence of value-laden questions” and preponderance of “everyday themes” (ibid.), much like in the once “liberal” UK test. Between 2003 and 2010, only three persons in Austria were

12

“threatened” with deportation for failing the lax civic integration requirement (p.193). Mouráo

Permoser even dismisses the idea that “control” is the gist of Austrian civic integration.

Instead, she sees it as “symbolic politics” that “helps in keeping the myth of sovereignty alive” (p.197).

Policy Form v. Substance. The mentioned variations in the operation and rationale of civic integration suggest not exaggerating the degree of convergence on the restrictive Dutch model. But they seem to be more problematic still for national-model reasoning. This is not to say that distinct national cultures and institutions do not matter. But, as I shall argue in the following, they matter more for the form than the substance of policy. A good example is the

“integration from abroad” policy recently introduced in the Netherlands and in France, among other countries. The two countries are quintessential representatives of “national models”, pluralist and multiculturalist in the Netherlands, and universalistic and assimilationist in

France. However, this cultural imprint shows less in the substance than in the form of the policy--after all, both countries do have “integration from abroad”, which is the tying of the admission of family migrants to their prior acquisition of language and civics competence.

The parliamentary debates surrounding the introduction of integration from abroad show that French and Dutch lawmakers addressed an identical problematic of home-countryoriented marriage choices by second- and third-generation Turkish and North African-origin ethnics, which stood to be contained, in strikingly different terms (see Bonjour 2011). French lawmakers, beholden to the French tradition of color-blindness and denial of ethnic group categorizing, only referred to the “quantity” but not the ethnic “quality” of the requisite family migration—its size was said to be twice as large as the student inflows and a hopping six times of the labor migrant inflows, not a small matter under any account. By contrast, Dutch lawmakers showed no hesitation to openly debate group characteristics, which were deemed

“adverse to a good integration into Dutch society” (ibid. 54). There was also no hiding of the rationale of the new restriction, which was to counteract the fact that more than half of

13

second-generation Turks and Moroccans in the Netherlands married somebody from their parents` country of origin.

In France, the same (or similar) ethnic groups were targeted in its integration from abroad, but they could not be explicitly named. That they were still meant slipped in only indirectly. Originally, the plan was to exempt the spouses of French citizens from the integration from abroad requirement, because of a “presumption of integration”. But Interior

Minister Hortefeux, less etiquette-strung than his “Republican” peers, retorted that the typical case to be regulated was not a French expatriate returning with a new wife from Australia or

Canada, but that over two thirds of the spouses of French citizens asking for a visa came from

Africa--and civic integration for this group “indeed seems necessary to us”, argued the minister (quoted in Bonjour 2011: 56). An exemption for the acquired spouses of returning expats was eventually made, but not for the spouses of French citizens who had never left

France (and who were mostly in the ethnic “problem” category).

As Saskia Bonjour (2011: 56) concludes, the “form” of the debate but not “its underlying purport and outcome” was shaped by “national models”, sensitively defined as

“country specific discursive and institutional structures”) (p. 62). Who would deny the existence and explanatory import of such “structures”? Without them, no comparative politics or sociology! As Bonjour`s incontrovertible definition of “national models” further suggests, not only “discourse” but also “institutions” matter, and this in an even stronger way. As she points out, the right to family life enjoys constitutional status under French, but not under

Dutch law. Accordingly, fearful of intervention by the Conseil Constitutionnel (France`s constitutional court reviewing new legislation), French lawmakers emphasized that integration from abroad could not be meant to limit family reunification, and the prescribed courses were free of charge with no test to be taken at the end. Compare this with the Dutch government`s not even offering courses, and with its legal requirement of a test, at the hefty fee of 350 Euro each (which could easily double or triple if more than one attempt had to be

14

waged). That integration from abroad evidently is more of a “service” in France and more of a

“selection mechanism” in the Netherlands is also conditioned by the fact that the only constitutional constraint for Dutch lawmakers is Article 8 of the European Convention of

Human Rights, which may protect “private and family life”, but, crucially, does not grant a right to family reunification (see Bonjour 2011: 58). Note again that this variation due to differential legal structures runs counter to the national-model expectation of “assimilation” in

France (which is surely not aided by strong family rights), and is at best loosely and contingently connected to whatever might be the Dutch approach to integration.

Liberal Convergence. If “national models” were the gist of civic integration, one also would expect that its content and identity projections would be aligned with countries` citizenship and nationhood traditions—say, being “civic” in France and “ethnocultural” in

Germany (to use Brubaker`s classic distinction [1992]). In such sense, Liav Orgad has interpreted civic integration as “cultural defense of nations” (forthcoming; see also 2010), as post-multiculturalist state support for besieged majority cultures that are no longer left to fend for themselves. Others have argued that civic integration marks a return to “cultural assimilation” (Entzinger 2005, discussing the case of the Netherlands). All this may well be the intention of states---civic integration`s tacit focus on majority groups is the gist of seeing it mainly as “symbolic politics”, and how could “assimilation” not be the desired endpoint of immigrant integration (see Brubaker 2002)? But “intention” does not guarantee that states have the legal-political means available for realizing it—liberal states “cannot mandate the practice”, as Goodman put it simply (2012: 321).

Empirical analyses of the contents of civic integration courses and tests suggest that they are mostly in a liberal, non-nationalistic register, inculcating and testing knowledge but not attitudes, and addressing topics that are related to the values and institutions of liberal democracy (xxx: anonymized; Michalowski 2011). Even Orgad, who is critical of “liberal democracies defin(ing) the essence of their citizenship…in cultural terms”, concedes that the

15

Leitkultur in Germany, to take only the standard bearer of his “cultural defense of nations”,

“reveals…a relatively thin version of Germanness” (forthcoming: 132). In a valuable comparison of citizenship tests in the United States, Austria, Germany, Britain, and the

Netherlands, Michalowski (2011) found that three of the four European countries prescribed a format and contents that were “liberal” in a Rawlsian sense, that is, covering only topics that dealt with “the political system, democracy and rights” and asking questions pertaining to

“what is right” (in a legal sense) instead of “what is good” (in a moral sense). This is an astonishing finding for Austria and Germany, the ethno-nationalistic hardliners in conventional “national model” reasoning.

Michalowski (2011) found one exception to the liberal mainline: unsurprisingly, the

Netherlands. She deems one-fifth of the questions in the Dutch citizenship test “illiberal” morality questions, that is, questions pertaining to “what is good”. These are things that are socially but not legally prescribed, like “etiquette” and “lifestyle”. Accordingly, applicants for

Dutch citizenship are expected to know that the proper Dutch way is to “make appointments for meetings, stand in line when waiting, bring along a small present if suitable, inform neighbours when having a party, and keep the front yard tidy” (Michalowski 2011: 14). The author called the latter “etiquette questions” that do “not appear in any of the other four citizenship tests” (ibid.). However, one might well argue that such etiquette or lifestyle questions are not irrelevant for navigating everyday life, much as in Britain it helps to know how to behave in a pub or queue for a bus, which are (or once were) questions in its “Life in the UK” test. It may appear strange that the Dutch ask about such things at the rather late stage of applying for citizenship, when one might presume people to know (note that the “Life in the UK” test mostly targets applicants for permanent residence, well ahead of citizenship acquisition). But Michalowski`s categorization of the Dutch questions as illegitimate morality questions ignores a pragmatic dimension to them. Furthermore, these lifestyle questions are still cognitive. They refer to things that are “considered as good by `the` receiving society”

16

(p.6), with no presumption that citizenship applicants themselves consider them as “good”.

After all, even the Dutch “`big state` trying to manage social norms beyond legal principles”

(p.19) does not have the means to assure that aspiring citizens adopt these norms in their own behavior.

Finally, one must consider that the “Dutch norms and values” that do fare prominently in Dutch civic integration, from the pre-entry to the citizenship acquisition phases, are liberal in content. The Netherlands are no exception to the “paradox of universalism” in which all contemporary liberal states are trapped, seeking to integrate newcomers into this particular state society but being constitutionally constrained from enforcing any particularism (xxx: anonymized). Duyvendak et al. (2009: 138) have pointed to the fact that the Netherlands are endowed with a “progressive monoculture”, in which homosexuality, nudity, and equality of the sexes are commonly accepted or required. In an interesting study of political party positions on civic integration in the Netherlands, Saskia Bonjour (2013) found that there was some disagreement between Dutch parties about whether the state or the immigrant should pay for it, leftist parties showing a pro-immigrant, welfarist instinct in this respect (that most of the time was defeated by the political right). However, she found mostly cross-party agreement on the importance of inculcating “Dutch norms and values”, which she dubs— somewhat alarmingly--an “authoritarian” stance. This consensus is nicely expressed by the following statement by a Social Democratic MP: “Progressive views, individualization, the expectation that you will do anything you can to strive for your own success, taking responsibility for your environment. Whoever participates in that, can count on our sympathy, regardless of their origins” (p. 847). “Progressive views” and “individualization” well summarize the liberal-cum-neoliberal gist of civic integration in the Netherlands and elsewhere. Who could find fault with it? More than anything nationally particular, civic integration is the universal idiom of global and further globalizing societies.

17

Conclusion:

Civic Integration as Diaspora Absorption

Civic integration policies evidently are not all of one cloth. But it is misleading to see them as

“fortification” or mere prolongation of nationally distinct ways of dealing with integration and citizenship. Something new has happened in Europe, which is the broad political elite acceptance of a new world of recurrent immigration. This has catapulted “integration” to the forefront of the political agenda, and states converge on understanding the latter in terms of

“civic integration”. Following Paul Collier (2013), one could define as its function the absorption of the immigrant diaspora that cannot but grow in this constellation. Among the few “big things” that we know about the drivers of contemporary migration is that a diaspora in host countries reduces the costs of further migration and is the main mechanism by which past migration begets more migration (Collier 2013:38). So it needs to be controlled, or even melted, precisely if a state wants to remain open to immigration. But why is the diaspora dangerous? The larger the size of the diaspora and the more culturally distant it is from the host society, the more “interaction within the group crowds out interaction with the indigenous population” (p.87). The perverse effect, Collier argues plausibly, is that “the culturally distant will be advantaged in migration decisions. Precisely because their diasporas take longer to be absorbed than the culturally proximate, these large diasporas facilitate further migration” (p.262). This is where multiculturalism, the enigmatic Other of civic integration, kicks in, or rather the contemporary opposition to it. Multiculturalism is diaspora reinforcement, and it “has a clear cost” (p.264), which is to reduce the absorption rate of the diaspora and to feed migration that gets sucked into ever growing “parallel societies” (which is just another word for diaspora). If countries want to stay open to immigration, they must melt the diaspora through civic integration. Of course, the premise of this imperative is that

“nations” are not anachronisms but “important and legitimate moral units” (p.25), “virtually

18

our only systems for providing public goods” like security and welfare (p.236). However, nations, these essential sources of “mutual regard” (p.61), stand the risk of being undermined or even supplanted by the “social models” imported by migrants, but which were obviously not strong or viable enough to keep them at home. As Collier breaks with political etiquette,

“not all cultures are equal” (p.35), because the “fruits of successful nationhood” is what

“attracts migrants” in the first (p.25).

The policy message is obvious. If countries open themselves up to recurrent immigration, as new-millennium Europe has done for economic and demographic reasons, the state`s migration policy must look to “increase the absorption of diasporas”. Following Collier

(2013:265), states have two tools at their disposal to accomplish this: rigorous antidiscrimination policies, on the one hand, and requiring indigenous language learning and promoting the “symbols and ceremonies of citizenship”. These are incidentally the dual prongs of the current “transformation of immigrant integration” in Western Europe that I had identified a few years ago (xxx: anonymized). And the second, or rather first, prong of diaspora absorption is the new policy commonly registered as “civic integration”.

Bibliography

Banting, Keith. 2011. Transatlantic Convergence? The Archaeology of Immigrant Integration in Canada and Europe. Paper presented at conference “The Political Incorporation of

Immigrants: Progress, Prospects and Pitfalls in Europe and North America”, University of

California at Berkeley, 4-5 March (typescript in author`s possession).

Banting, Keith and Will Kymlicka. 2013. “Is There Really a Retreat from Multiculturalism

Policies? New Evidence from the Multiculturalism Policy Index”, Comparative European

Politics 11(5), 577-598.

Bhagwati, Jagdish. 2004. In Defense of Globalization. New York: Oxford University Press.

Bonjour, Saskia. 2011. “Problematic Otherness: Defining and Dealing with the Other in

French and Dutch Civic Integration Abroad Policies”, in S.Bonjour, Andrea Rea, and Dirk

Jacobs, eds. The Others in Europe. Brussels: Editions de l`Université de Bruxelles.

19

Bonjour, Saskia. 2013. “Governing Diversity: Dutch Political Party Preferences on the Role of the State in Civic Integration Policies”, Citizenship Studies 17(6/7), 837-51.

Brubaker, Rogers. 1992. Nationhood and Citizenship in Germany and France. Cambridge:

Harvard University Press.

Brubaker, Rogers. 2002. “The Return of Assimilation?” in C.Joppke and E.Morawska, eds.

Toward Assimilation and Citizenship. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

Castles, Stephen. 1995.”How Nation-States Respond to Immigration and Ethnic Diversity”,

New Community 21(3), 293-308.

Collier, Paul. 2013. Exodus: How Migration is Changing Our World. Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

De Haas, Hein, Katharina Natter, and Simona Vezzoli. 2014. Growing restrictiveness or changing selection? The nature and evolution of migration policies. Demic project paper 22.

Oxford: IMI.

Duyvendak, Jan Willem, Trees Pels, Rally Rijkschroeff. 2009. “A Multicultural Paradise?

The Cultural Factor in Dutch Integration Policy”, in Jennifer Hochschild and John

Mollenkopf, eds. Bringing Outsiders In. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

Entzinger. Han. 2005. “Changing the Rules While the Game is On: from Multiculturalism to

Assimilationism in the Netherlands”, in Michal Bodemanm and G. Yurdakul, eds. Migration,

Citizenship, Ethnos. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Eule, Tobias G. 2015. „Willkommenskultur auf dem Prüfstand“. In Axel Franzen, Ben Jann, and Christian Joppke, eds. Ungleichheit und Integration in der Krise, Zürich: Seismo.

Freeman, Gary. 1995. “Modes of Immigration Politics in Liberal Democratic States”,

International Migration Review 29(4), 881-902.

Goodman, Sara Goodman. 2012. “Fortifying Citizenship: Policy Strategies for Civic

Integration in Western Europe”, World Politics 64(4), 659-98.

Goodman, Sara Goodman. 2014. Immigration and Membership Politics in Western Europe.

New York: Cambridge University Press.

Goodman, Sara Goodman and Matthew Wright. (Forthcoming). “Does Mandatory Integration

Matter? Effects of Civic Requirements on Immigrant Socioeconomic and Political

Outcomes”, Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies.

Groenendijk, Kees. 2011. “Pre-Departure Integration Strategies in the European Union:

Integration or Immigration Policy?” European Journal of Migration and Law 13, 1-30.

Jacobs, Dirk and Andrea Rea. 2007. “The End of National Models? Integration Courses and

Citizenship Trajectories in Europe”, International Journal of Multicultural Societies 6(2), 264-

83.

20

Koopmans, Ruud et al. 2005. Contested Citizenship. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota

Press.

Kymlicka, Will. 2012. Multiculturalism: Success, Failure, and the Future. Migration Policy

Institute, Washington, D.C., working paper.

Michalowski, Ines. 2004. “Integration Programmes for Newcomers: A Dutch Model for

Europe?” IMIS-Beiträge (Osnabrück), 24, 163-75.

Michalowski, Ines. 2009. “Liberal States—Privatised Integration Policies?” in E.Guild,

K.Groenendijk, S.Carrera, eds. Illiberal Liberal States. Farnham, Surrey: Ashgate.

Michalowski, Ines. 2011. “Required to Assimilate? The Content of Citizenship Tests in Five

Countries”, Citizenship Studies 15(6/7), 749-68.

Michalowski, Ines and Ricky van Oers. 2012. “How Can We Categorise and Interpret Civic

Integration Policies?” Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 38(1), 163-71.

Mouráo Permoser, Julia. 2012. “Civic Integration as Symbolic Politics: Insights from

Austria”, European Journal of Migration and Law 14, 173-98.

Mouritsen, Per. 2013. “The Resilience of Citizenship Traditions: Civic Integration in

Germany, Great Britain and Denmark”, Ethnicities 13(1), 86-109.

Orgad, Liav. 2010. “Illiberal Liberalism”, American Journal of Comparative Law 58(1), 53-

105.

Orgad, Liav (forthcoming). Cultural Defense of Nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

My quotes are from the typescript.

Perching, Bernhard. 2012. The National Policy Frames for the Integration of Newcomers:

Comparative Report. PROSINT project report, Vienna (typescript).

Strik, Tine et al. 2010. The INTEC Project: Synthesis Report. INTEC project report,

Nijmegen (typescript).

Weber, Eugene. 1976. Peasants into Frenchmen. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

XXX (anonymized).

Endnotes i Here and in the following, the notion of “policy convergence” refers to a similarity of goals and instruments of policy—in this case, the furthering of the integration of immigrants into mainstream institutions by means of mandatory language and civic knowledge courses and tests, which also fulfils a latent immigration control function. ii There has been a change of emphasis with respect to the second, political variable in various stages of her work. An earlier article (Goodman 2012) identified the political variable as mobilization and contestation by the

21

far right, the later book (Goodman 2014) identifies it as the orientation of the government in charge (left v. right).

22

Download