Slides - Harvard University: Program in Ethics & Health

advertisement
“Forcing the Poor to Buy Volvos?”
When, if Ever, Is It Permissible for a Government to Require
People to Buy More Comprehensive Health Insurance than
They Want?
Alex Voorhoeve
Princeton & LSE
papers on: http://personal.lse.ac.uk/voorhoev
1
Structure
1. Core case
2. Sunstein’s argument
3. Counterargument
2
1. Core case
Single plan, provided by government, either
mandatory or the only reasonable option for
insurance.
Financed by (i) donors; or (ii) individuals
through tax or an insurance premium.
Decision-maker who must decide what to
include in the plan.
Under certainty, this decision-maker rightly
gives some priority to improving the well-being
of those who are worse off than others (is NOT
utilitarian).
Simplified example:
1,000 young adults.
A disease will affect one person in this population.
Each person’s chance of developing it is 1/1,000.
If untreated, the affected person will die young.
If treated, he/she will be cured.
The cost of universal coverage for this treatment is $10 to each
person. If there is no UC, no treatment will be available.
As far as each person’s self-interest is concerned, everyone in this
population is willing to pay up to $9 for this treatment to be
included.
Given their information, this is a rational preference.
INCLUDE: Expected utility: 50 for each.
Final utility: 1,000 have a life-time utility of 50.
EXCLUDE: Expected utility: 50.06 for each.
Final utility: 999 have a life-time utility of 50.08;
1 person has a life-time utility of 30.
Assume: In a case of certainty, the distribution of final utilities
under INCLUDE would be superior.
But we are dealing with a risky case. From the perspective of
each person’s expected utility, EXCLUDE is superior.
This is just to say that each person’s current Willingness to Pay for
INCLUDE ($9) is less than its cost ($10).
Should the decision-maker nonetheless choose INCLUDE?
2. Sunstein’s argument for “no”.
(“Valuing Life”, Duke Law Journal, 2004.)
The case for respecting WTP is based on
considerations of welfare and autonomy.
Welfare: “If people are willing to pay [$9] but no
more to eliminate a [mortality] risk of [1/1,000],
their welfare is decreased by asking them to pay
more.” (p. 400).
“If poor people are required to pay an amount for
risk reduction that exceeds their WTP, desirable
redistribution will hardly result” (p. 394).
Autonomy: “People should be sovereign over their
own lives and government should respect
individual choices about how to use limited
resources (so long as these choices are informed).
If regulators do not use people’s actual [WTP]
judgments, then they are insulting their dignity”
(pp. 400-1).
Conclusion:
“Requiring poor people to buy Volvos is not the
best way of assisting them” (p. 395).
3. Counterargument -- Welfare
It is not true that every individual’s final utility is lowered if we
include treatment. One individual’s final utility will be greatly
improved.
This also means that there is redistribution in favor of the worst
off individual through INCLUDE.
Unanimity in favor of EXCLUDE is due to individuals’ lack of
information of what is truly in their interest.
If they all knew what was truly in their interest, 999 would favor
EXCLUDE for themselves, but 1 would favor INCLUDE.
Insofar as final welfare is of concern:
If the decision-maker knew what was truly in the well-being
interests of each, she would be aware of this conflict of interest.
And she would also (by hypothesis) know how to resolve it: in favor
of the worst off.
So the decision-maker knows that there is an alternative she
would, rightly, invariably regard as best if she had full information:
INCLUDE.
A decision rightly reached with full information is at least as good
as a decision reached with partial information.
So, whenever possible, a decision-maker should decide as she
would with full information. She should choose INCLUDE.
Autonomy Scenario 1: Donor pays and decides.
Suppose INCLUDE would use funds that would otherwise redound
to the population on a $10 per person basis (e.g. lower taxes
because of direct budget support).
It is not a violation of a person’s autonomy to give her health
insurance that she/he values at $9 rather than give her $10.
Autonomy Scenario 2. Individual versus social preferences
Now suppose the government decides and citizens pay.
The preferences that underlie the WTP are typically based on what
an individual values for himself.
“How much would you be willing to pay for you to be covered
against this illness, which affects 1 in 1,000?”
Similarly, standard practice for eliciting health utilities is to use this
person’s preferences concerning what happens to him only.
But individuals also have social preferences. And the decision to
include or exclude treatment affects the distribution of well-being
in society.
Some who prefer EXCLUDE for themselves may prefer INCLUDE,
considering the impact on themselves and the distribution of final
well-being.
If a majority favors INCLUDE on grounds of solidarity, then this
majority’s autonomy is not violated by INCLUDE.
The minority is forced to buy a more comprehensive package of
coverage against their will, but this does not seem a problematic
limitation of their autonomy.
Autonomy Scenario 3. Creating goods versus banning transactions.
Suppose the government decides, citizens pay, and all citizens favor
EXCLUDE in spite of its distributional effects. Compare:
(I) The government creates beneficial health insurance, which did
not exist. It decides for INCLUDE.
(II) Health insurance contracts INCLUDE and EXCLUDE are offered in a
private market. Everyone chooses EXCLUDE. The government
bars EXCLUDE.
(I) There is no interference with free choice, just a failure to give
individuals what they want most (because of lack of info).
(II) A violation of autonomy, though perhaps justifiable.
Summary: May the decision-maker choose INCLUDE?
Donor pays
& decides
Government decides; citizens pay
Social
Government
preferences
creates
favor INCLUDE insurance
Insurance
exists; ban on
EXCLUDE
Considering
Welfare
Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes
Considering
Autonomy
Yes
Yes
Yes
No
Considering
both
Yes
Yes
Yes
?
The most common cases in very poor countries.
Conclusion
Ex ante Individual Willingness to Pay > Individual Cost for a
service is not a necessary condition for inclusion in a
health care package.
The decision which health services to include is not merely
answered by asking what each individual wants coverage
for (given the cost to them). It must also take into account
the distribution of final well-being.
Download