Uploaded by asaduzzamanrasel03

gilboa microeconomics slides

advertisement
Microeconomics
1
Is Economics a Science?
2
Issues
• Economics doesn’t predict well
• All its assumptions are wrong
• It isn’t even done in good faith
3
Economics doesn’t predict
Three replies:
• No one predicts
• Economics actually does (sometimes)
• Who needs to predict?
4
No one predicts
• Large, complex systems are hard to predict
• Chaos theory – even something as simple as
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘₯
with
𝑓 π‘₯
1
4 π‘₯
0.5
5
Chaos
𝑓 π‘₯
1
4 π‘₯
0.5
0
0.01
0.02
0.03
0.04
0.05
1
0.0396
0.0784
0.1164
0.1536
0.19
2
0.152127 0.289014 0.411404 0.520028
0.6156
3
0.515939 0.821939 0.968603 0.998395 0.946547
5
0.00406 0.970813 0.427388 0.025467
0.6457
10
0.795154 0.503924 0.524371 0.836557 0.999652
15
0.393686 0.015682 0.494768 0.466403 0.316366
20
0.079928 0.590364 0.027768 0.774441 0.069137
6
Chaos
• If a single variable with such a simple equation can
generate chaos…
• Just imagine what happens with the weather (the
butterfly effect)
• Or the entire global economy
• Or the geopolitical system
7
Two additional complications
In the social sciences:
• We don’t even have the basic rules
(no equivalents of flow equations in physics)
• We’re dealing with self-reflective systems
(a hurricane doesn’t change its mind if predicted correctly)
8
Economics actually does predict
• Sometimes it doesn’t do too badly
• Nice quantitative results on
•
•
•
Supply-and-demand in a single good market
Auctions
Matchings
• Many qualitative insights
9
It is easier to predict when
• The system is “small” and isolated
• There are many “repetitions” –
• similar examples that are causally independent
• Experiments are possible
• … Maybe we should learn when to expect a theory to
predict
10
Who needs to predict?
• Economics would surely like to be a predictive science
• But it can be useful even if it isn’t
• For instance, even if it can only critique reasoning
• Compare with history
11
All assumptions are wrong
• Well, yes
• But think of
• Robustness of findings?
• Relevance to economic decisions?
12
The Ultimatum Game
There is a sum of $100 to share between Players I and II
Player I offers a way to divide the sum (say, integer values)
Player II can say Yes or No
Yes – they get the amounts offered
No – they both get nothing
What will happen?
What does the theory say?
13
The Ultimatum Game
Bernd Schwarze (b. 1944)
Werner Güth (b. 1944)
Güth, Schmittberger, Schwarze (1982)
14
Reference
An Experimental Analysis of Ultimatum Bargaining
Werner Güth, Rolf Schmittberger, Bernd Schwarze
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 3, No. 4 (Dec., 1982), pp.
367-388
Abstract
There are many experimental studies of bargaining behavior, but suprisingly enough
nearly no attempt has been made to investigate the so-called ultimatum bargaining
behavior experimentally. The special property of ultimatum bargaining games is that on
every stage of the bargaining process only one player has to decide and that before the
last stage the set of outcomes is already restricted to only two results. To make the
ultimatum aspect obvious we concentrated on situations with two players and two stages.
In the ‘easy games’ a given amount c has to be distributed among the two players,
whereas in the ‘complicated games’ the players have to allocate a bundle of black and
white chips with different values for both players. We performed two main experiments for
easy games as well as for complicated games. By a special experiment it was
investigated how the demands of subjects as player 1 are related to their acceptance
decisions as player 2.
15
What does the theory say?
100
𝑦𝑒𝑠
100,0
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
𝑦𝑒𝑠
99,1
99
π‘›π‘œ
…
50
…
20
…
𝑦𝑒𝑠
…
0,0
80
50,50
…
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
0
…
…
…
16
Well,
We are tempted to predict:
100
𝑦𝑒𝑠
100,0
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
𝑦𝑒𝑠
99,1
99
π‘›π‘œ
…
80
…
20
…
𝑦𝑒𝑠
…
0,0
50
50,50
…
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
0
…
…
…
The “Backward Induction” solution
17
Backward Induction
In a finite game of perfect
information we can go down to
the leaves and work our way
backwards to find the players’
choices
Ernest Zermelo (1871-1953)
18
Backward Induction assumptions
• Rationality
• Common knowledge (or common belief) in rationality
• To be precise, as many levels of belief as there are
steps in the game
19
So in this case
The backward induction seems to be
100
𝑦𝑒𝑠
100,0
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
𝑦𝑒𝑠
99,1
99
π‘›π‘œ
…
50
…
20
…
𝑦𝑒𝑠
…
0,0
80
50,50
…
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
0
…
…
…
– But this assumes that the monetary sums are the “utilities”
20
Important
• In a game as simple as the Ultimatum Game, it is
impossible to test basic decision/game theoretic
assumptions (such as transitivity)
• We can only test them coupled with the assumption that
only material payoffs matter
21
Emotional payoffs
• Player II might be angry/insulted at a low offer
• Player II as well as Player I might care for fairness
• Player I might be altruistic
• etc.
• A way to tell some explanations apart: the Dictator
Game
22
Is it rational to respond to emotions?
In “Descartes’ Error” (1994) argued that it
is wrong to think of emotions and
Antonio Damasio (b. 1944)
rationality as divorced; rather, rationality
relies on emotions
23
Back to the Ultimatum Game
• Having said all that, emotional payoffs should not be
overstated
• In the Ultimatum Game, if the payoffs were in millions of
dollars rather than dollars, acceptance of low offers
would likely to be higher
• As well as when Player II has to wait before responding
24
The Ultimatum Game with delay
Let Me Sleep on It: Delay Reduces Rejection Rates in Ultimatum
Games
Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel
Economics Letters, Vol. 111, No. 2 (2011) pp. 113-115
Abstract
Delaying acceptance decisions in the Ultimatum Game drastically increases
acceptance of low offers. While in treatments without delay less than 20% of
low offers are accepted, 60-80% are accepted as we delay the acceptance
decision by around 10. min.
25
Not even in good faith
• Can science be objective?
• Aren’t we always affected by personal history, social class, our
incentives?
• If so, can we trust the “truths” that economists pretend to have
“established”?
• Should we check how many economists who believe in the free
market also benefit from it (serve on boards of directors etc.) ???
26
Can science be objective?
Path-breaking studies on the history
of madness, sexuality
Michel Foucault (1926-1984)
27
Shouldn’t we be suspicious?
• Well, yes
• But – we can try to be (more) objective
• Objectivity is a direction, not a place
• Let’s remind ourselves of the distinction between Positive
and Normative social science
• And then ask the question about Postmodernism
28
Positive vs. Normative
• Positive (~ descriptive)
IS
• Normative (~ prescriptive)
OUGHT
• Normative physics is called SciFi
• But in the social sciences it makes sense
29
How do we judge theories
• Positive
– How close to reality it is
• Normative
– ???
• The king in “The Little Prince”
30
The Little Prince
"It is contrary to etiquette to yawn in the presence of a king," the monarch
said to him. "I forbid you to do so."
"I can't help it. I can't stop myself," replied the little prince, thoroughly
embarrassed. "I have come on a long journey, and I have had no sleep ..."
"Ah, then," the king said. "I order you to yawn. It is years since I have seen
anyone yawning. Yawns, to me, are objects of curiosity. Come, now! Yawn
again! It is an order."
"That frightens me ... I cannot, any more ..." murmured the little prince,
now completely abashed. "Hum! Hum!" replied the king. "Then I—I order
you sometimes to yawn and sometimes to—" He sputtered a little, and seemed
vexed.
For what the king fundamentally insisted upon was that his authority
should be respected. He tolerated no disobedience. He was an absolute
monarch. But, because he was a very good man, he made his orders
reasonable.
"If I ordered a general," he would say, by way of example, "if I ordered a
general to change himself into a sea bird, and if the general did not obey me,
that would not be the fault of the general. It would be my fault."
Antoine de SaintExupery (1900-1944)
31
So what is a good normative theory?
• I suggest: one that captures the kind of people/society we
want to be
• Normative as second-order positive
• What type of a decision maker do I want to be?
• What kind of a society/economy do I want to live in?
32
Be that as it may
• Let’s not mix up positive and normative
• There may never be eternal peace (positive)
But this doesn’t mean we should start shooting each other
(normative)
• Our theories may never be perfectly objective (positive)
But this doesn’t mean we shouldn’t try (normative)
33
Utility Maximization
34
Who maximizes utility ?
Or rather, who behaves as if they did?
Logical positivism and the emphasis on observables
The revealed preferences paradigm
35
What’s observable ?
Choices: between pairs or out of sets?
Deterministic or stochastic?
If sets – all sets? Only budget sets?
These are all questions of modeling…
36
Binary relations
𝑋
a set of alternatives
𝑅 ⊂ 𝑋
𝑅 is
𝑋 – a binary relation
reflexive if
π‘₯𝑅π‘₯ for all π‘₯
symmetric if 𝑦𝑅π‘₯ whenever π‘₯𝑅𝑦
transitive if
π‘₯𝑅𝑧 whenever [π‘₯𝑅𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦𝑅𝑧]
complete if
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 π‘œπ‘Ÿ 𝑦𝑅π‘₯ (or both) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
37
Equivalence relations
𝑅 is a equivalence relation if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive
For example: equality
is
reflexive if
π‘₯
π‘₯ for all π‘₯
symmetric if 𝑦
π‘₯ whenever π‘₯
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑧 whenever [π‘₯
𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦
transitive if
𝑧]
38
Equivalence relations – examples
𝑅 is a equivalence relation if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive
For example:
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff π‘₯ and 𝑦 have the same (first) last name
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff π‘₯ and 𝑦 have the same height
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff π‘₯ and 𝑦 have the remainder after division by 3
39
Equivalence relations – examples
More generally, define π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff 𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 𝑦 for some function 𝑓: 𝑋 → 𝑍
Then 𝑅 is
reflexive if
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 π‘₯ for all π‘₯
symmetric if
𝑓 𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯ whenever 𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 𝑦
transitive if
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 𝑧 whenever [𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑓 𝑦
𝑓 𝑧 ]
Are there others?
40
Equivalence classes
An equivalence relation 𝑅 divides the set 𝑋 into equivalence classes:
There is a partition of 𝑋, 𝐴 (finite or infinite) such that
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff both π‘₯, 𝑦 belong to the same 𝐴
This also means that 𝑅 is an equivalence relation iff there is some (set 𝑍 and some)
function 𝑓: 𝑋 → 𝑍 such that
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff 𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 𝑦
41
Preference relations
≽ is a preference relation if it is complete and transitive
A fact: a complete relation is reflexive
42
Preference relations – weak and strict
For a relation ≽ define ≻ and ~ by
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
(Define also β‰Ό and β‰Ί )
Facts:
If ≽ is transitive, then so is ~
If ≽ is transitive, then so is ≻
43
If
Recall that
is transitive, then so is
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
If we have
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ~ 𝑧
then
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
π‘₯≽𝑧
So that we have
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘
𝑧≽π‘₯
π‘₯~𝑧
44
If
is transitive, then so is
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
Recall that
We need to show that
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ≻ 𝑧
Implies
π‘₯≻𝑧
Or: IF
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
THEN
and
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ π‘₯
45
We have
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ≻ 𝑧
that is,
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
and
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
then, by transitivity (of ≽)
π‘₯≽𝑧
46
We have
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ≻ 𝑧
that is,
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
and
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
Could it be that 𝑧 ≽ π‘₯ also holds?
No, because then we would have
𝑧≽𝑦
47
Utility representation
For a relation ≽ on a set 𝑋 and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ we say that 𝑒
represents ≽ if, for all π‘₯, 𝑦,
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
48
Different notions of representation
For a relation ≽ on a set 𝑋 and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞
(i) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
(ii) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
(iii) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
Fact: If ≽ is complete, (i) and (ii) are equivalent, and each implies (iii)
(but not the other way around)
49
Equivalence of (i) and (ii)
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯β‰½π‘¦βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
(ii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯β‰»π‘¦βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
Given completeness, this is just using the contrapositive:
to say that
𝑝⇒π‘ž
is equivalent to saying that
π‘ž⇒
𝑝
50
Contrapositives
The (“material”) implication
𝑝⇒π‘ž
is equivalent to
π‘ž⇒
In fact, the material implication 𝑝 ⇒ π‘ž is defined as
And the truth value of
𝑝
π‘β‹π‘ž
π‘β‹π‘ž is
Value of
π‘β‹π‘ž
π‘ž
π‘ž
𝑝
∨
–
∨
∨
𝑝
– the same as the truth value of
π‘ž⇒
𝑝 which is (again) defined as
π‘ž ⋁
𝑝
π‘β‹π‘ž
51
Back to the equivalence of (i) and (ii)
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯β‰½π‘¦βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
(ii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯β‰»π‘¦βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
Given completeness:
π‘₯≽𝑦⇒𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
iff
𝑒 𝑦 ⇒ π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 iff
𝑒 𝑦
𝑒 π‘₯ ⇒𝑦≻π‘₯
𝑦≻π‘₯⇒𝑒 𝑦
𝑒 π‘₯
Hence (i) is equivalent to
For all π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦≻π‘₯βŸΊπ‘’ 𝑦
𝑒 π‘₯
– which is (ii) with π‘₯, 𝑦 reversed
52
And (i) [hence (ii)] implies (iii)
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯β‰½π‘¦βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
(iii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯~𝑦 βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
Because
π‘₯~𝑦 ⟺
π‘₯≽𝑦
⟺
𝑦≽π‘₯
⟺
𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
𝑒 𝑦
𝑒 π‘₯
π‘₯~𝑦
βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
53
Why doesn’t (iii) imply (i) ?
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯β‰½π‘¦βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
(iii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯~𝑦 βŸΊπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
Because representing indifference doesn’t guarantee that preference is
also “faithfully” represented
For a given ≽ and 𝑒 that represents it, consider 𝑣 π‘₯
𝑒 π‘₯
54
Conditions for utility representation
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋,
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists a function 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
55
Interpretation I: meta-scientific
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
• What is “utility” ?
• The term derives its meaning from its usage (Ask not, “What?”, Ask, “How?”)
• We’ll explain what it means to maximize utility in terms of observables
56
Logical Positivism
• What is [good] “science”?
• Theoretical terms should be defined by
observations
• Culminated in the “Received View”
(Carnap, 1923)
Rudolf Carnap (1891-1970)
57
Logical Positivism +
Popper (1934)
• A theory is meaningful only if it is refutable
• It can never be verified, only refuted, or not-yetrefuted
• Famous targets of critic: Marx’s historicism,
Freud’s psychoanalysis
Karl Popper (1902-1994)
• (Evolution? Game theory?)
58
Logical Positivism and economics
• Popper (1934) criticizes psychology
• Samuelson (1938) pioneers “revealed
preference theory”
• Room for speculation…
Paul Samuelson (1915-2009)
59
Economics and psychology
Loewenstein (1988) suggested that,
maybe, in the 1930s, economics didn’t
think that psychology was such great
company
George Loewenstein (b. 1955)
60
Was it really Logical Positivism?
Moscati is a serious historian who argues
that I’m selling you fake history
But the story is too good to kill
Ivan Moscati (b. 1955)
61
Utility and marginal utility
Adam Smith (as Plato) thought that there is no
relationship between value and price
Cf. water and diamonds
Adam Smith (1723-1790)
The Marginalist Revolution
William Stanley Jevons 1835-1882
Carl Menger 1840-1921
Léon Walras 1834-1910
Alfred Marshall 1842-1924
Be that as it may
A theorem such as:
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
endows “utility” with meaning
64
Interpretation II: normative
Suppose you ask me how to make a decision
And I ask you, would you like your ≽ to be complete ?
• Many would say yes
• Incompleteness is absence of decision (Kafka and his wedding engagements…)
And then: would you like your ≽ to be transitive ?
• Again, many would say yes
• An intransitive relation, let’s say a cyclical one (that’s more than just intransitive!)
isn’t very useful
65
The normative interpretation – cont.
And then I point out to you that
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
And I can convince you that you would like to behave as if you were
maximizing a utility function, or maybe just maximize one (consciously)
66
Interpretation III: descriptive
Suppose I tell you that, when I analyze an economic problem, I assume
that agents are utility maximizing.
• Does it make sense?
• Do you know many such agents?
• What gives me the right to make predictions and give advice based on
such a preposterous assumption?
67
The descriptive interpretation – cont.
And then I point out to you that
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
… and I may convince you that more agents might be described by my
analysis than you would have imagined
68
Comments
• Why do I need to convince you that this is how people behave?
• Why not just test?
• Indeed, if we test, it doesn’t matter which formulation we use
• The whole point is that they’re equivalent
• In fact, a characterization theorem is a sort of a framing effect
• If economics were a successful science, it would not need
axiomatizations
• But it isn’t so successful. So it leaves room for rhetoric.
69
Compare with Social Choice
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
• Pareto domination: transitive but not complete
• Majority vote: complete but not transitive
70
Pareto Domination
• Basically, unanimity
(At least one has strict preference, the others – weak [or strict] )
• Transitivity seems obvious
(A bit involved because of this “at least one strict” issue)
• But completeness is utopian
71
Majority vote
Condorcet showed that even if all
individuals have complete and transitive
preferences, the majority vote of them
as a society might not be transitive
Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas de
Caritat, Marquis of Condorcet (1743-1794)
72
Condorcet’s Paradox
Individuals 1,2,3 ; alternatives π‘₯, 𝑦, 𝑧
Preferences are given by:
1
2
3
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑧
𝑦
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑦
73
Condorcet’s Paradox – cont.
Majority vote:
π‘₯
2,3
1,3
1
2
3
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑧
𝑦
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
𝑧
1,2
74
The social choice perspective
Shows that it isn’t trivial to assume that a relation ≽ is complete and
transitive
complete
Pareto domination
Majority vote
transitive
+
+
75
Indeed, it can happen in one’s mind
• If we have different criteria for decision making, and we’re trying to
aggregate them
• Each can be thought of as an “individual”
• Looking for unanimity we may not get completeness
• Using majority – we may lose transitivity
• The representation result suggests we should aggregate by a numerical
trade-off
76
Is the utility unique?
…There exists and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
Can we say that we found the utility of the consumer?
Well, all we asked is
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯
So 𝑣 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
10𝑒 π‘₯ could also work
77
How unique is the utility?
OK,
𝑣 π‘₯
10𝑒 π‘₯
is just a change of the unit of measurement – we’re used to that
And
𝑣 π‘₯
10𝑒 π‘₯
15
Also involves “shifting” the zero; as in temperature
78
Cardinal utility
If the data allow for any transformation
𝑣 π‘₯
where π‘Ž
π‘Žπ‘’ π‘₯
𝑏
0 , but only those, we say that 𝑒 is cardinal
As in
𝐹 π‘₯
9
𝐢 π‘₯
5
32
𝐢 π‘₯
5
𝐹 π‘₯
9
160
9
79
But
For
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 𝑦
to hold we can also use
𝑣 π‘₯
𝑣 π‘₯
if 𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑒 π‘₯
0
And many others. The function 𝑒 π‘₯ is only ordinal.
80
Conditions for utility representation –
beyond finite
For a relation ≽ on a countable set 𝑋,
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
81
Conditions for utility representation –
beyond countable
But: let π‘Ž, 𝑏 ≽ π‘Ž , 𝑏
iff
π‘Ž
or
[π‘Ž
π‘Ž
π‘Ž and 𝑏
𝑏′ ]
It is complete and transitive
82
Lexicographic preferences
Complete?
Transitive?
π‘Ž ,𝑏
… but has no representation by any realπ‘Ž, 𝑏
valued function
83
Why is there no representation?
If there were, we would need to have an entire
(positive length) interval of utility values
between
π‘Ž ,1
𝑒 π‘Ž, 0
π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑒 π‘Ž , 1
For any
π‘Ž
π‘Ž, 0
π‘Ž
Which is a bit too much for the real line (as the
𝑒 range) to carry
84
Continuity
The relation ≽ is continuous iff π‘₯ → π‘₯ implies that
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
and
π‘₯ β‰Ό 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯ β‰Ό 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
85
Continuity is very reasonable
If π‘₯ → π‘₯ then
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
and
π‘₯ β‰Ό 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯ β‰Ό 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
Almost everything we can think of, in terms of physical and physiological
mechanisms, is continuous
An exception: a vegetarian’s preferences for the amount of meat
More generally, meaning may behave discontinuously
86
Lexicographic preferences
aren’t continuous
For any such π‘Ž,
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 for all 𝑛
But
𝑦
π‘Ž, 1
π‘₯≽𝑦
does not hold – we have
π‘₯
π‘Ž, 0
π‘₯
π‘Ž
1
,0
𝑛
𝑦≻π‘₯
87
Is continuity reasonable, then?
• I would argue that the lexicographic preferences don’t typically appear in
reality – apart from the case of endowing quantities with meaning
• They do appear in speeches (“we will never risk human lives, but, given that, we will…”)
• This may say more about the speeches than about real preferences
• Anyway…
88
Continuous utility representation
For a relation ≽ on 𝑅 ,
≽ is complete, transitive, and continuous
IFF
There exists and a continuous function 𝑒: 𝑋 →
∞, ∞ that represents ≽
89
Background:
Countable and uncountable sets
90
A puzzle
You run a hotel with infinitely many rooms
β„•
1,2,3, …
They’re all occupied, and a new person comes along and asks to be
hosted
Can you give them a room?
91
Well, you can:
We start with
β„•
1,2,3, …
And, say, person 0
The set
β„•∪ 0
has “as many elements” as β„•
0,1,2,3, …
1,2,3, …
92
“As many elements as’’
We can have a 1-1 mapping between
β„•
1,2,3, …
and
β„•∪ 0
0,1,2,3, …
β„•
1
2
3
4
5
…
β„•∪ 0
0
1
2
3
4
…
93
What about all the integers?
Again, we can have a 1-1 mapping between
β„•
1,2,3, …
and
β„€
0, 1, 1, 2, 2, 3, 3, …
β„•
1
2
β„€
0
1
3
1
4
2
5
2
…
…
94
And the rationals?
β„š
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„• ∪ 0 , 𝑏
0
𝑏
1
3
4
5
…
1
2
1
3
1
4
1
5
…
2
5
…
3
5
…
4
5
…
π‘Ž
1
1
1
1
2
2
1
2
be “counted” too.
3
3
1
3
Consider π‘Ž, 𝑏
4
4
1
4
5
5
1
5
And it turns out they can
0
2
…
…
2
2
2
3
1
3
2
4
2
3
3
2
3
4
1
4
3
1
2
2
4
4
4
1
5
2
5
3
5
4
…
…
…
5
5
1
…
…
…
95
For any table…
We can count the cells…
1
2
4
7
3
5
8
…
6
9
…
10
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
96
And thus
β„š
𝑏
1
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„• , 𝑏
0 can be “counted”, too
2
3
4
5
…
1
2
1
3
1
4
1
5
…
1
2
4
7
2
5
…
3
5
8
…
3
5
…
6
9
…
4
5
…
10
…
π‘Ž
1
1
1
1
2
2
1
2
3
3
1
3
4
4
1
4
5
5
1
5
…
…
2
2
2
3
1
3
2
4
2
3
3
2
3
4
1
4
3
1
2
2
4
4
4
1
5
2
5
3
5
4
…
…
…
5
5
1
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
97
So it turns out that
The naturals
β„•
1,2,3, …
the integers
β„€
0, 1, 1, 2, 2, 3, 3, …
and the rationals
β„š
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„€, 𝑏
0
all have “as many elements as” each other
They are all countable
98
Admittedly, it’s weird…
That a set
β„•
1,2,3, …
would have “as many elements as” supersets thereof
β„€
β„š
0, 1, 1, 2, 2, 3, 3, …
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„€, 𝑏
0
But we simply don’t have a better definition of the (same) “number of elements”
for infinite sets
99
And it can also happen with intervals
That a set 0,1
has “as many elements as” its superset 0,2
In fact,
𝑓 π‘₯
0.5π‘₯
is a 1-1 mapping from 0,2 to 0,1
0,1
0,2
100
Any two intervals
would clearly have the same “number of
elements” (“cardinality”)
In fact,
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑐
𝑑
𝑏
𝑐
π‘₯
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
is a 1-1 mapping from π‘Ž, 𝑏 to 𝑐, 𝑑
𝑐, 𝑑
π‘Ž, 𝑏
101
Even infinite and finite
And even the non-negative part of the line
0, ∞ has the same cardinality:
𝑓 π‘₯
1
𝑒
is a 1-1 mapping from 0, ∞
to 0,1
102
And since we have
mappings from the entire line ℝ
into
∞, ∞
1,1 , such as
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘Žπ‘Ÿπ‘π‘‘π‘” π‘₯
103
All intervals
of positive length have the same
“number of elements” (“cardinality”)
Because
𝑓 π‘₯
1
π‘Žπ‘Ÿπ‘π‘‘π‘” π‘₯
2
is a 1-1 mapping from ℝ
1
∞, ∞
into 0,1
104
So maybe all infinities are the same?
Maybe the reals
ℝ
∞, ∞
are also countable?
Is there a 1-1 mapping from the reals to
the naturals
β„•
1,2,3, …
?
105
Well, they aren’t
Even
0,1 ⊂ ℝ
∞, ∞
isn’t countable
There is no 1-1 mapping from the reals to
the naturals
β„•
1,2,3, …
Georg Cantor (1845-1918)
106
isn’t countable
Assume it were
Then we’d have 0,1
π‘₯ ,π‘₯ ,π‘₯ ,π‘₯ ,…
For each π‘₯ ∈ 0,1 there is 𝑛
1 such that π‘₯
π‘₯
Each π‘₯ can be written in a decimal expansion (not always in a unique way):
π‘₯
0. 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 …
Where 𝑑 ∈ 0,1,2, , … , 9
107
If
were countable
We’d have
π‘₯
0. 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 …
π‘₯
0. 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 …
π‘₯
0. 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 …
π‘₯
0. 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 𝑑 …
We can construct
π‘₯
with 𝑏
𝑑
0. 𝑏 𝑏 𝑏 𝑏 …
2 π‘šπ‘œπ‘‘ 10 so that π‘₯
π‘₯ – for all 𝑖
108
Why
?
The decimal expansion isn’t unique
so that fact that 𝑑
1
2
0. 500000 …
1
2
0. 499999 …
𝑑 isn’t yet a proof that π‘₯
π‘₯
… but we get the point
109
Consumer theory
110
Consumer theory:
Basic concepts and preview
111
A basic distinction
What we can do and what we want to do are logically independent
• Aesop’s fox: “sour grapes”
• Groucho Marx: “I refuse to join any club that would have me for a member”
• The fox is psychologically healthier
• But they both commit the same “rationality sin”
• And a converse one is “wishful thinking”
112
What can we choose
π‘₯
𝑦
– quantity of good 1
– quantity of good 2
𝑝
– price of good 1
𝑝
– price of good 2
feasible set – what are the possible values we
𝐼
– income
may choose for these variables
decision variables – what is up to us to control
113
The budget constraint
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝
𝐼
𝑝
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯, 𝑦
0
𝐼
π‘₯
114
The objective function
𝑦
Maximization of utility : π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯ π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐼
𝑝
We thus ask, which of the points in the
feasible set has the highest π‘ˆ value?
𝐼
𝑝
π‘₯
115
Indifference curves
Even with two goods, it’s hard to visualize the utility : π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯ π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
In fact, because utility is only ordinal, it’s not clear we want to
visualize it
The information we’d miss is not very meaningful anyway…
116
Indifference curves
𝑦
Connect points with equal utility
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑐
Each is an indifference class of ≽
π‘₯
117
Optimization
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝
Match the indifference curves with
the feasible set
Try to find the highest indifference
curve you can still be on
𝐼
𝑝
π‘₯
118
Sneak preview
Optimality is often found at the equality of slopes which will be identified by the marginality
condition:
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
or
119
The marginality condition
𝑦
A basic optimization tool: look for a point with
𝐼
𝑝
equal slopes
Generally, neither necessary nor sufficient, but
let’s see its logic first
𝐼
𝑝
π‘₯
120
Why equate slopes?
𝑦
If the budget line is steeper than the
𝐼
𝑝
indifference curve…
π‘₯
121
Why equate slopes?
𝑦
If the indifference curve is steeper than the
𝐼
𝑝
budget line…
π‘₯
122
The slope of the budget constraint
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘Ž
𝑝 𝑏
𝐼
𝑏
𝐼
0
𝑦
𝑏
π‘Ž
π‘₯
123
The slope of the indifference curve
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘Ž
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦
𝑏
π‘Ž
π‘Ž, 𝑦
𝑐
𝑏
𝑐
π‘ˆ 𝑏 ≅0
𝑐
𝑏
π‘ˆ
≅
π‘ˆ
π‘Ž
π‘₯
124
… So, we want equality of slopes:
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝
or:
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
125
The economic meaning of
the marginality condition
$1 ≅
units of π‘₯ ≅
utility
$1 ≅
units of 𝑦 ≅
utility
126
Thus…
If:
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
And vice versa if
we’ll be better off moving $1 from 𝑦 to π‘₯
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
Unless…
127
Unless this is impossible, say
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
and
𝑦
0
… which can happen (“corner solution”)
128
Example
π‘₯
# of six-pack of water bottles
𝑦
# of single water bottles
𝑝
15
𝑝
3
price for a single
60
budget for water
𝐼
price for a six-pack
129
The budget constraint
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝
60
3
15π‘₯
3𝑦
60
20
π‘₯, 𝑦 – a bundle
𝐼
𝑝
60
15
4
π‘₯
130
Example: linear utility
For example
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
6π‘₯
𝑦
Which can happen:
π‘₯ = six-packs of bottles
𝑦 = single bottles
For such a function corner solutions will not be exceptional
131
Graphically
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
6π‘₯
𝑦
The six-packs are a better deal:
𝑝
𝐼
𝑝
15
6∗3
6𝑝
Comparing the slopes:
20
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝
𝐼
𝑝
4
6, π‘ˆ
1
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
15
3
5
6
π‘ˆ
𝑝
1
3
6
15
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘₯
132
What is exactly meant by
A partial derivative of a function is the derivative relative to one variable while
the others are held fixed
The partial derivative of π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 relative to π‘₯:
π‘₯, 𝑦 =
,
= π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯, 𝑦 =
,
= π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
and relative to 𝑦:
?
Partial derivatives graphically
Examples of partial derivatives
For
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑏𝑦
The partial derivatives are
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
And for
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯𝑦
We get
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘¦
π‘Žπ‘₯
The economic meaning of
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
$1 ≅
units of π‘₯ ≅
utility
$1 ≅
units of 𝑦 ≅
utility
136
We could also have…
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
6π‘₯
𝑦
And if 𝑝
𝐼
𝑝
𝑝
𝑝
Can 𝑝
𝐼
𝑝
6
6𝑝
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
6𝑝 happen???
π‘₯
137
Finally…
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
6π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
If 𝑝
𝑝
𝑝
𝐼
𝑝
6𝑝
6
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
No unique solution
𝐼
𝑝
π‘₯
(isn’t it a knife-edge case?)
138
Summing up
The solution to the water consumption problem is:
If
If
And if
6
6
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐼
,0
𝑝
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐼
0,
𝑝
6 – anywhere in
𝐼
𝐼
, 0 , 0,
𝑝
𝑝
Decreasing marginal utility
•
In the water bottles problems, the marginal utilities were
constant
•
It might be more intuitive that the “extra utility” we get from a
good decreases as we have more of it
The utility from money
Back in 1738, Daniel Bernoulli wrote,
“And, because the marginal utility from
money is in inverse proportion to the amount
of money we have…”
Daniel Bernoulli 1700-1782
141
“The marginal utility is inversely
proportional…”
𝑒′ π‘₯
𝑒 π‘₯
𝑐∗
𝑐 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
𝑑
𝑐
0
𝑐
0
π‘™π‘Žπ‘› π‘₯
142
But what do you mean, Daniel?
Rudolf Carnap (1891-1970)
Karl Popper (1902-1994)
• Theoretical terms should be defined by
observations
• How do you measure this “marginal utility”???
143
Two possible answers:
• Look, guys, you’re going to talk about this
200 years after me. Com’n.
• In between us, there will be a psychologist
who will show that more is observable
than what these economists will choose to
admit
Daniel Bernoulli 1700-1782
144
Weber’s law in psychophysics
Ernst Heinrich Weber
1795-1878
βˆ†π‘†
𝑆
πœ†
𝑆 – stimulus
βˆ†π‘† – increase in the stimulus (that can be discerned with a fixed
probability, usually 75%)
λ – a positive constant
Weber’s law – cont.
A person would notice, with probability 75% or more, that a change has
occurred, namely that
𝑆
βˆ†π‘†
𝑆
Only if the physical change is large enough
𝑆
βˆ†π‘†
𝑆
1
πœ†
Or:
π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑆
βˆ†π‘†
π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑆
π‘™π‘œπ‘” 1
πœ†
– a constant
The
function
Hence, for physical
quantities, the π‘™π‘œπ‘”
function plays a special
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
role
π‘₯
A comment re
Unless otherwise stated, we’ll take the base
of π‘™π‘œπ‘” to be 𝑒
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘™π‘Žπ‘› π‘₯
Recall that any other base π‘Ž
1 is a positive
multiple thereof :
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘Ž
π›Ύπ‘™π‘Žπ‘› π‘₯
for
𝛾
0
Cobb-Douglas Preferences
(After Charles Cobb, Paul Douglas)
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
We started with
6π‘₯
𝑦
Or, more generally, a linear function:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑏𝑦 π‘Ž, 𝑏
0
We can now look at a simple function that allows for decreasing marginal
utility:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
π‘Ž, 𝑏
0
Indifference curves for Cobb-Douglas
π‘ˆ π‘₯,𝑦
𝑦
π‘Žπ‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
For example, for π‘Ž
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ
𝑐
π‘ˆ
𝑐
π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
𝑏
1
π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑐
⟺
𝑐
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯𝑦
⟺
π‘₯𝑦 𝑑
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯𝑦
Decreasing marginal utility
𝑦
Suppose
100
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘™π‘œπ‘”
π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘”
𝑦
Consider the indifference curve
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
10
π‘™π‘œπ‘”
π‘₯
π‘₯𝑦
10
100
π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘”
𝑦
3
1000
and two points on it
10,100 , 100,10
151
Indifference curves become less steep
(going from left to right)
𝑦
Imagine that at 10,100 we
reduce 𝑦 by 1. How much π‘₯
100
should we add to compensate for
this reduction?
10
10
100
π‘₯
152
Let’s use the partial derivatives
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘™π‘œπ‘”
π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘”
𝑦
And thus
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
(For 𝛾
π‘™π‘œπ‘”′
π‘™π‘œπ‘”′
π‘₯
𝛾
π‘₯
𝑦
𝛾
𝑦
1/π‘™π‘Žπ‘› 10 )
153
At
The partial derivatives (marginal utilities) are
𝑦
As 𝑦 decreases from 100 to 99 the utility loss is
100
approximately
and in order to compensate fot that we
need extra π‘Ž of product 1 (increase π‘₯ ) that satisfies, roughly,
10
π‘Ž
10
100
π‘₯
π‘Ž
154
By contrast, at
The partial derivatives (marginal utilities) are
𝑦
As 𝑦 decreases from 10 to 9 the utility loss is approximately
100
and in order to compensate fot that we need extra π‘Ž of
product 1 (increase π‘₯ ) that satisfies, roughly,
10
π‘Ž
10
100
π‘₯
π‘Ž
10
155
A general point
𝑦
When the marginal utility of each
product is decreasing, we will
have indifference curves that are
less steep as we go from upper
left to lower right
π‘₯
156
Optimal solution for CD preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝
π‘Žπ‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘Ž
, π‘ˆ
π‘₯
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝐼
𝑝
π‘₯
π‘π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
π‘Ž
π‘₯
𝑏
𝑦
𝑏
𝑦
π‘Žπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
157
The slope of the indifference curves for CD
𝑦
When π‘₯ tends to 0 (and 𝑦 doesn’t) they
become very steep
When 𝑦 tends to 0 (and π‘₯ doesn’t) they
become very flat
The slope is the same along any ray from
π‘₯
the origin (homothetic preferences)
158
Homothetic preferences
𝑦
Along every ray that starts at the origin
0,0 , the slope of all indifference curves
is the same
But it can change from one ray to another
π‘₯
159
Solving the CD problem – cont.
Looking for π‘₯, 𝑦 where:
𝑝 π‘₯
and
or
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝
π‘Žπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
𝑝
𝑝
𝐼
160
Solving the CD problem – cont.
π‘Žπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
𝑝
𝑝 π‘₯
⟹
𝑝
𝑝 𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
Let’s denote
𝐸
𝐸
So that
𝐸
𝐸
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
which has to hold for all 𝑝 , 𝑝 , 𝐼 !
161
Solving the CD problem – nearly done…
𝐸
𝐸
𝐸
𝐸
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝑝 π‘₯
Hence
𝐸
𝐸
𝑝 𝑦
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝑏
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝐼
𝐼
𝐼
162
(Was that too quick?)
𝐸
𝐸
π‘Ž
𝑏
⟹
π‘Ž
𝐸
𝑏
𝐸
Plug these in
𝐸
to get
and thus
π‘Ž
𝐸
𝑏
𝐸
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝐸
𝐸
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝑏
𝑏
π‘Ž
and
𝐼
𝐼
1 𝐸
𝐸
𝐸
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
𝑏
𝐼
𝐼
𝑏
π‘Ž
𝐸
𝑏
𝐼
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝐼
163
Solving the CD problem – wrapping up
𝐸
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝐼
⟹π‘₯
𝐸
𝑝 𝑦
𝑏
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑏𝑝
𝑏
1
𝐼
𝑏𝑝
π‘Ž
𝐼
βŸΉπ‘¦
π‘Ž
164
Consumer theory:
Lagrange Multipliers
165
Or, using Lagrange multipliers
The “real” problem
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
,
𝑝 𝑦
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐼
0
166
Simplify our lives
𝑦
If π‘ˆ is monotone (the consumer
𝐼
𝑝
prefers more to less), it’s safe to
assume the solution will be on
𝑝 π‘₯
Can’t be
optimal
𝐼
𝑝
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
π‘₯
167
Let’s simplify our lives even further
Let’s ignore the non-negativity constraints
π‘₯, 𝑦
0
(Make a mental note not to forget these)
And then there’s only one constraint, which is an equality:
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑠. 𝑑.
,
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
168
Lagrange’s idea
•
We’ll build the constraint into the utility function
•
As if it could be violated, though at a cost
•
At the optimal solution it won’t be violated after all
•
But the trick will also have an economic meaning
Joseph-Louis Lagrange 1736-1813
169
Solving using Lagrange multiplier
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑠. 𝑑.
,
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
Becomes
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
, ,
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
πœ†π‘ π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
πœ† – a new variable, the cost of violating the constraint
170
Lagrange’s method – cont.
To find
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
, ,
β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
we take all partial derivatives and set them to zero
πœ•β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
πœ•π‘₯
0
πœ•β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
πœ•π‘¦
0
πœ•β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
πœ•πœ†
0
171
The partial derivatives
β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
πœ•β„’
πœ•πœ†
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
πœ†π‘ π‘₯
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘₯
π‘ˆ
πœ†π‘
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘¦
π‘ˆ
πœ†π‘
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
𝐼
172
Setting them to zero
πœ•β„’
πœ•πœ†
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘₯
π‘ˆ
πœ†π‘
0
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘¦
π‘ˆ
πœ†π‘
0
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
0
173
The resulting equations
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘¦
πœ•β„’
πœ•πœ†
0
0
0
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑝 𝑦
πœ†π‘ ⟹ πœ†
π‘ˆ
𝑝
πœ†π‘ ⟹ πœ†
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝐼 βŸΉπ‘ π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
174
Conclusions
πœ•β„’
πœ•πœ†
0βŸΉπ‘ π‘₯
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘¦
0 βŸΉπœ†
π‘ˆ
𝑝
0 βŸΉπœ†
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
π‘ˆ
𝑝
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
⟹
𝑝
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝
175
And in the CD problem
We are again looking for π‘₯, 𝑦 where:
𝑝 π‘₯
and
or
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝
π‘Žπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
𝑝
𝑝
𝐼
176
And the solution is, again
𝐸
𝑝 π‘₯
𝐼
⟹π‘₯
𝐼
𝐸
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
βŸΉπ‘¦
𝐼
Clearly, we didn’t need Lagrange here, but in more complex problem
his method can really help…
177
Consumer theory:
Ordinality
178
Ordinality
Recall that the utility function is (only) ordinal
• We won’t take the specific function too seriously
• Any monotone transformation thereof is equally good
• We should better verify that we only discuss properties that
are common to all such transformations
179
“How unique” is
?
We won’t be able to tell
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
log π‘₯
log 𝑦
from
log π‘₯
log 𝑦
π‘₯𝑦
π‘Š π‘₯, 𝑦
5π‘₯𝑦
or
𝑑
π‘₯𝑦
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
or even
𝑐
π‘₯
𝑍 π‘₯, 𝑦
5π‘₯𝑦
10
180
Yet, the slope of the indifference curve
is the same
π‘ˆ
?
π‘ˆ
π‘Ž ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Ž
π‘₯
𝑏
𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑉
𝑉
𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑏π‘₯ 𝑦
𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
π‘₯ 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
181
More generally:
If 𝑓 is monotonically increasing
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑓 π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑉
𝑓 π‘ˆ ∗ π‘ˆ
𝑉
𝑓 π‘ˆ ∗ π‘ˆ
𝑉
𝑉
𝑓′ ∗ π‘ˆ
𝑓′ ∗ π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
… a great relief
182
Hence the marginality condition
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑝
𝑝
Does not depend on the transformation
because the slope
is independent of 𝑓
183
But ...
How about
?
• The transformation 𝑓 (𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
in the same way: multiply by 𝑓
𝑓 π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 ) will modify both sides
0
• The values on both sides can change, but whether they’re equal
or not – will not change
• (Nor will the answer to the question, “which one is larger?”)
184
… Therefore…
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Ž ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Š π‘₯, 𝑦
𝛼 log π‘₯
1
𝑍 π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
π‘₯ 𝑦
𝛼 log 𝑦
,
𝛼
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘₯ 𝑦
… all describe the same preferences, and we can switch among
them shamelessly
185
The normalized CD function
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝛼 log π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝐸
𝑝 𝑦
𝐸
𝛼 log 𝑦
𝛼𝐼
1
𝛼 𝐼
1
𝛼 𝐼
𝑝
π‘₯
𝑦
1
1
1
𝐼
𝛼
𝑝
186
Consumer theory:
Monotonicity
187
Monotonicity of
In bold strokes, “more is preferred to less”
But:
• What exactly is “more”? More π‘₯, more 𝑦,
more both?
• What exactly is “preferred to”? Strictly
better? Just not worse?
188
Basic monotonicity
π‘ˆ cannot decrease in any of the variables:
If
π‘₯
π‘₯
then
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
and 𝑦
𝑦′
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
Typically justified by free disposal
189
Free disposal
If you don’t like it – throw it away
•
The quantities π‘₯, 𝑦 designate what’s legally yours, not
necessarily what went into your stomach
•
Used to be less of an issue when I was a student
•
Less obvious when we think about the environment
•
And can even be an emotional problem (if we cherish values
that are compromised by production/consumption of these
goods)
190
Basic monotonicity – cont.
Obviously allows
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
But also
20
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
min π‘₯, 10
min 𝑦, 20
– the consumer can reach satiation
10
π‘₯
191
Satiation
• A type of nirvana
• Luckily, doesn’t happen too naturally
• Luckily?
192
A preview of the welfare theorem
We will discuss general equilibrium
And will find out that, under certain conditions, it is “nice” in
the sense of Pareto
The First Welfare Theorem: A general equilibrium yields
Pareto optimal allocations
193
Pareto efficiency/optimality
•
An allocation is Pareto
optimal/efficient if we can’t make
some people better off without
hurting others
•
Says nothing about justice or
fairness
Vilfredo Pareto 1848-1923
194
“Efficient” or “Optimal”?
• “Efficient” sounds like we only try to produce as
much as possible, and that’s not the case
• "Optimal” sounds like it’s the “best”, at least as
good as anything else – and it only means that
there’s nothing better
195
The First Welfare Theorem
•
In any event, Pareto optimality/efficiency is a nice property
to have
•
The First Welfare Theorem says that any allocation that is
the result of a general equilibrium has this property
•
But consumer who reach satiation can destroy it
•
That’s why, as economists, we see something positive in
the fact that people don’t reach satiation so easily…
196
Strict monotonicity
π‘ˆ is strictly increasing in each variable:
If
π‘₯
π‘₯
and
𝑦
𝑦′
or
π‘₯
π‘₯
and
𝑦
𝑦
then
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
– necessarily satisfies basic monotonicity as well
197
Is strict monotonicity plausible?
• How much water can you drink?
• In many good we will reach satiation
• Even if we still want something else (diamonds?)
198
Weak monotonicity
Basic monotonicity +
If
π‘₯
π‘₯
and
𝑦
𝑦′
then
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
There may be satiation in some goods, but not in all
199
Example: weak but not strict monotonicity
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
10
min π‘₯, 10
𝑦
π‘₯
200
Weak monotonicity suffices
• For the consumer to be on the
budget line
𝑦
• …and wish to sell any extras in
the market
• For the equilibria to be Pareto
π‘₯
efficient/optimal
201
Consumer theory:
Convexity
202
Problems
• There are more complex feasible sets
• The marginality condition doesn’t always help
203
More interesting “budget” sets
Suppose you have to decide how many movies and how many
theater shows to watch
Good
Price
Minutes
π‘₯
movie
40
120
𝑦
theater
100
60
Budget
400
600
204
The budget(s) set
𝑦
40π‘₯
100𝑦
400
120π‘₯
60𝑦
600
10
π‘₯, 𝑦
4
0
3.75,2.5
5
10
π‘₯
205
Let’s maximize utility
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
.
𝑦
.
10
4
3.75,2.5
5
40π‘₯
100𝑦
400
120π‘₯
60𝑦
600
π‘₯, 𝑦
10
0
π‘₯
206
Looking for a tangency point, say…
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
.
𝑦
.
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™
120π‘₯
4
3.75,2.5
5
πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š
πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
60𝑦
600
π‘₯, 𝑦
10
0
π‘₯
207
Indeed,
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™
π‘₯
4
3,2.8
3.75,2.5
5
𝑦
10
π‘₯
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
π‘₯
πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š
.
𝑦
.
πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
0.3
1
400
40
3
𝐼
0.7
400
2.8
The tangency with the first line is within the
relevant range and we’re happy
208
But if preferences were different…
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™
π‘₯
4
3.75,2.5
𝑦
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
π‘₯
πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š
.
𝑦
.
πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
0.8
1
400
40
8
𝐼
0.2
400
0.8
8,0.8
5
10
π‘₯
The tangency point with this line is outside the
range and we’re very unhappy
209
Looking for tangency with the other segment
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
10
πŸπŸπŸŽπ’™
π‘₯
4
3.75,2.5
4,2
5
𝑦
10
π‘₯
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
.
π‘₯
πŸ”πŸŽπ’š
.
𝑦
πŸ”πŸŽπŸŽ
0.8
1
600
120
𝐼
0.2
4
600
2
And again there’s tangency with one line that’s in
the relevant range (for this line) and we’re happy
210
Will this always work?
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™
π‘₯
4
3.75,2.5
5,2
5
𝑦
10
π‘₯
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
π‘₯
πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š
.
𝑦
.
πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
0.5
1
400
40
5
𝐼
0.5
400
2
The tangency point with this line is again
outside the range and we’re again unhappy
211
On the other hand…
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
10
πŸπŸπŸŽπ’™
π‘₯
2.5,5
4
3.75,2.5
5
𝑦
10
π‘₯
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
.
π‘₯
πŸ”πŸŽπ’š
.
𝑦
πŸ”πŸŽπŸŽ
0.5
1
600
120
𝐼
0.5
2.5
600
5
The tangency point with the other line is also outside
the relevant range and we’re very unhappy
212
So what’s going on?
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
10
4
3.75,2.5
5
10
π‘₯
π‘₯
.
𝑦
40π‘₯
100𝑦
400
120π‘₯
60𝑦
600
π‘₯
3.75
𝑦
2.5
.
Well, we can’t call it tangency, but we
do have separation
213
More generally
𝑦
•
When there are several linear inequality and they all
have to be satisfied (“and”) we look for tangencies
•
If one of them is in the relevant range we’re happy
•
If not, we look at the extreme points
•
(We don’t need to look at all of them – if one of them is
“in between” slope we’re done)
•
(And something like this works in higher dimensions,
too)
π‘₯
214
Encouraged and cheered up,
Let us now assume that
𝑝
𝑝
1,
𝐼
200
But there are discounts for large quantities: above 100 the
price of π‘₯ per unit goes down by 50%
𝑝
if π‘₯
100
215
Which bundles are feasible
Distinguish between
𝑦
100
π‘₯
100
and
200
150
π‘₯
𝑝
1
𝑝
0.5
100
100
200
300
π‘₯
216
The budget set
In the range
𝑦
π‘₯
100
the price is
200
𝑝
1
𝑦
200
and the budget line:
150
π‘₯
100
And, as usual,
π‘₯, 𝑦
100
200
300
0
π‘₯
217
The budget set – cont.
In the range
𝑦
π‘₯
100
the price is
𝑝
200
0.5
and the constraint is
150
0.5 π‘₯
100
100
𝑦
200
100
100
(Because we already spent 100 on the first 100 units)
or
100
200
300
0.5π‘₯
π‘₯
(and π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦
150
0)
218
The budget set, therefore:
𝑦
And we see we could also write
π‘₯
𝑦
200
200
or
0.5π‘₯
150
𝑦
150
and, as usual
100
π‘₯, 𝑦
100
200
300
0
π‘₯
219
Let’s maximize
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
200
π‘₯
𝑦
.
𝑦
.
200
or
150
0.5π‘₯
100
100
200
300
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘₯, 𝑦
150
0
220
Looking for tangency
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
.
𝑦
.
Let’s try tangency with
200
150
𝒙
π‘₯
90,110
100
𝑦
100
200
300
π‘₯
π’š
𝟐𝟎𝟎
1
1
𝐼 0.45 200 90
𝑝
1
1 π‘Ž
𝐼 0.55 200
π‘Ž
110
We made it!
221
But there’s another tangency point
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
.
𝑦
.
Tangency with
200
150
𝟎. πŸ“π’™
π‘₯
90,110
𝑦
135,82.5
100
100
200
300
π‘₯
π’š
πŸπŸ“πŸŽ
1
1
𝐼 0.45
150 135
𝑝
0.5
1 π‘Ž
𝐼 0.55 150 82.5
π‘Ž
… and in this case
135 . 82.5 .
102.96
.
.
90 110
100.50
222
Generally
𝑦
•
If there are several linear inequalities and only
one should be satisfied (“or”), we will look for all
tangency points
•
We will need to compare them
•
And the intersection points
•
(We can save a bit: the intersection between two segments
will not be better than both tangency points on them)
π‘₯
223
An “or” condition between inequalities
𝑦
•
May appear when there are discounts
•
Or when we can buy in one of several
markets, but not to mix between them
•
Or to order from one of several
suppliers…
π‘₯
224
Convex sets
For every two points in the set, the entire interval
connecting them is also in the set
225
Non-convex sets
There exists at least one pair of points in the set, such
that some of the interval connecting them is outside
the set
226
The interval connecting two points
𝑦
5
For example, the interval connecting
1,5
1,5
and
3,1
3,1
1
1
3
π‘₯
227
The interval formula – cont.
𝑦
5
Consider, for example, the mid-point
1,5
What’s its π‘₯ value ?
1
2
3,1
1
1
2
3
3
2
π‘₯
228
And, similarly
𝑦
5
The midpoint’s 𝑦 value is
1,5
5
1
2
3
3
3,1
1
1
3
π‘₯
229
In short,
𝑦
5
The midpoint is 2,3
1,5
In other words, the average values:
2,3
3
1
1,5
2
3,1
1
3,1
2
2,3
1
1
2
3
π‘₯
230
And what about other points?
𝑦
5
Their coordinates are weighted average of
1,5
those of the extreme points – while always
using the same weights
𝑦
π‘Ž 1,5
3,1
1
π‘Ž∗1
3
π‘₯
π‘Ž 3,1
π‘Ž ∗ 3, π‘Ž ∗ 5
1
π‘Ž
1 we get
1,5
and for π‘Ž
0 we get
3,1
For
1 π‘₯
1
1
π‘Ž ∗1
231
Convex budget sets
𝑦
Obviously, the classic one:
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐼
0
π‘₯
232
As well as…
𝑦
Anything we can get by
intersection (“and”) of linear
inequalities
(or, more generally, the
intersection of any convex sets)
π‘₯
233
But not…
𝑦
The union of convex sets need not
be convex
π‘₯
234
A non-convex budget set
𝑦
Can be problematic: the
marginality condition is no longer
sufficient for optimality
π‘₯
235
Non-convex preferences
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
Increasing marginal utility (in each
variable):
π‘ˆ
2π‘₯
π‘ˆ
2𝑦
π‘₯
236
The marginality condition without
convexity
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
The tangency point might be the
worst point on the line
π‘₯
237
Examples of increasing marginal utility
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
•
π‘₯, 𝑦 – minutes of watching a movie
•
π‘₯, 𝑦 – amount of heroin and cocaine
•
π‘₯, 𝑦 – practice time of two athletes for the
Olympic games
238
Convex preferences
𝑦
The “better than” sets
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑐
are convex,
(for every 𝑐)
π‘₯
239
How can we tell if preferences are convex?
𝑦
•
Drawing “better than” sets
•
Comparing the slope (marginal rate
of substitution) of the curve along it
•
And another useful rule:
π‘₯
240
A sufficient condition for convex preferences
If it so happens that
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯
π‘ˆ 𝑦
where each of π‘ˆ and π‘ˆ is concave (in its own variable)
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Ž∗π‘₯
π‘Ž ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘Ž∗π‘₯
𝑏∗𝑦
𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
… then the preferences are convex
241
How come that concave
imply convex preferences?
𝑦
•
Assume they are concave
•
Decreasing marginal utility of each
product
•
And we get a less steep indifference
curve as we slide downwards (and to
the right)
π‘₯
242
The importance of convexity
•
As we just argued, it simplifies our lives as economists who
try to predict choices
•
But it also makes the optimization story more likely
•
How does the household “behave as if” it were maximizing a
utility function?
•
Under convexity: small improvements would lead to an
optimal solution
243
Consumer theory:
Comparative statics /
Sensitivity analysis
244
Consumer theory:
Changes in income
245
Changing income
• ICC—Income-Consumption Curve
• Its habitat is the consumption bundles space
• Income isn’t represented graphically
•
Ernst Engel 1821-1896
Engel Curve
•
Lives in the Income-Good (quantity) space
•
The quantities of the other goods are not
represented graphically
246
The ICC for CD preferences
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
Recall that these preferences are
homothetic:
𝑦
ICC
The slope
is constant along any
ray that emanates from the origin
0,0
π‘₯
247
The Engel Curve
Consider the optimal solution
𝒙
π‘₯
𝑦
𝒂
𝟏
𝑰
𝒑𝒙
1
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
Focus on the demand for one good
and observe how it changes as a
function of income
𝐼
248
The Engel curve and income elasticity
𝒙
𝑦
𝒂
𝟏
𝑰
𝒑𝒙
1
1
𝐼
π‘Ž
𝑝
πœ‚
π‘₯
πœ‚
=
=
1
For CD preferences,
income elasticity is 1
≡ 1 if and only if the demand for
π‘₯ is a linear function of income, that
is π‘₯
𝐼
𝑐𝐼 for some 𝑐
249
The general concept of elasticity
• Given a function 𝑧
𝑧 𝑀 we wonder how sensitive 𝑧 is relative to
changes in 𝑀
• We have the (partial) derivative
πœ•π‘§
πœ•π‘€
• But we want a “pure” measure, independent of measurement units:
πœ•π‘§
πœ•π‘€
πœ‚ ,
𝑧
𝑀
250
Elasticity
πœ‚
,
πœ•π‘§
πœ•π‘€
𝑧
𝑀
πœ•π‘§
𝑧
πœ•π‘€
𝑀
Constant elasticity:
𝑧
π‘Žπ‘€ , π‘Ž
0 ⟺ πœ‚
𝑐
,
For instance:
𝑧
𝑧
π‘Žπ‘€ ⟺ πœ‚ ,
π‘Ž
⟺ πœ‚ ,
𝑀
1
1
251
Constant Elasticity
If
𝑧
Then
πœ‚
,
πœ•π‘§
πœ•π‘€
𝑧
𝑀
π‘Žπ‘€
π‘Žπ‘π‘€
π‘Žπ‘€ /𝑀
π‘Žπ‘π‘€
π‘Žπ‘€
𝑐
252
Constant Elasticity – cont.
πœ‚
And if
𝑐
,
Then
c·
𝑑 log 𝑧
for
and
log 𝑧
π‘Ž 𝑒
𝑐 · log 𝑀
𝑐 · 𝑑 log 𝑀
𝑏
log 𝑀
𝑧
log 𝑒
log π‘Žπ‘€
π‘Žπ‘€
253
Responses to income changes
πœ‚
,
0 – π‘₯ increases, a “normal” good
πœ‚
,
0 – π‘₯ doesn’t change, a “neutral good”
πœ‚
,
0 – π‘₯ decreases, an “inferior” good in a certain range
… why “in a certain range” ?
254
Further distinction among normal goods:
πœ‚
,
1
– a luxury good
πœ‚
,
1
– a proportional good
0
πœ‚
,
1
– a basic/essential good
255
For CD preferences
We got
πœ‚
,
πœ‚
,
1
And this makes sense: if there are only two goods, and one has
income elasticity of 1, so should the other one:
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
Suppose we increase income by 1%
𝑝 1.01 π‘₯
𝑝 1 ? 𝑦
1.01 𝐼
256
More generally
Some weighted average of income elasticities (across all
goods) is equal to 1
απœ‚
,
1
α πœ‚
,
1
Hence it is impossible that all goods be luxury goods
Or that all be basic goods
257
The ICC for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑏𝑦
Surely homothetic:
𝑦
The slope
is constant not
only along each ray (emanating
from the origin), but also across
rays
π‘₯
258
ICC for linear preferences – cont.
If we have
𝑝
𝑝
𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
That is
ICC
𝑏
𝑝
π‘Ž
𝑝
The solution is
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘₯
0
1
𝐼
𝑝
259
Engel Curve for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑏𝑦
π‘₯
The optimal solution is
Say,
𝑦
0
1
𝐼
𝑝
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐼
𝐼
260
The ICC for linear preferences…
And if
𝑝
𝑝
𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
That is
𝑏
𝑝
π‘Ž
𝑝
The solution is
ICC
π‘₯
π‘₯
1
𝐼
𝑝
𝑦
0
261
Engel Curve for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑏𝑦
π‘₯
1
𝐼
𝑝
𝑦
0
The optimal solution is
Say,
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐼
𝐼
262
The ICC yet again
Wait, but what if
𝑝
𝑝
𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
That is,
𝑏
𝑝
ICC
?
π‘Ž
𝑝
Any point on the budget line is a solution
and the ICC becomes the entire orthant
π‘₯
263
Consumer theory:
Changes in price
264
Changing price
•
•
•
PCC (Price Consumption Curve)
•
Resides in the bundles space
•
Price isn’t represented graphically
Demand curve
•
Resides in the price-quantity space (for a given good)
•
The other quantities are not represented graphically
Demand and cross demand curve
265
The PCC for CD preferences
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝
PCC 1
π‘₯
266
Demand curve
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
=
(πœ‚
≡
1
=
hyperbola )
𝑝
267
Cross demand curve
𝑦
𝑦
1
π‘Ž
1
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
𝐼
𝑝
=
πœ‚
≡0
constant)
𝑝
268
The slope of the demand curve
π‘₯
We’d expect
And this is indeed typical. Almost
always true. Why almost?
𝑝
269
What happens when a price changes?
Suppose 𝑝 ↑
𝑝′
𝐼
𝑝
𝐼
𝑝′
𝑝
•
The budget line is “tighter”
•
Its slope changes, too
𝐼
𝑝
270
Income and substitution effects
𝑝′
𝑝
π‘₯
π‘₯
Indeed
𝐼
𝑝
Why?
A
B
π‘₯
𝐼
𝑝′
π‘₯
•
The consumer is “poorer”
•
The price ratio has changed
𝐼
𝑝
271
Trying to tell these apart
Budget line C goes through the old point, but with the
𝐼
𝑝
new slope
C
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
Overall change = income effect + substitution effect
A
B
π‘₯
𝐼
𝑝′
π‘₯
𝐼
𝑝
272
For example
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
60
𝑦
𝐼
log π‘₯
log 𝑦
120, 𝑝
2, 𝑝
π‘₯
𝐼
· · 120
30
𝑦
𝐼
· · 120
30
2
A
30
π‘₯
30
60
π‘₯
273
Suppose the price has gone up
𝑦
𝑝
60
3
2
𝑝
From budget line A
𝐴 2,2,120 → 30,30
We switch to line B
𝑦
B
30
π‘₯
20 π‘₯
A
𝐡 3,2,120 → 20,30
30
60
π‘₯
274
Introduce the third budget line
𝐢 3,2, ?
The price are the new ones 3,2
Which level of income would go through
𝐴 30,30 ?
𝐼
3 · 30
2 · 30
90
60
150
275
Hence we compare between…
𝐴 2,2,120 → 30,30
60
𝐡 3,2,120 → 20,30
C
𝐢 3,2,150 → 25,37.5
A
20
B
30
20
25
25
30
Overall change = income effect + substitution effect
π‘₯
20 π‘₯
π‘₯
30
25
60
276
The substitution effect cannot be positive
π‘₯
If the price of a good goes up, the
substitution effect will not make us
C
want more of it
A
𝑝
277
The substitution effect can be zero
π‘₯
Say
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
min π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑐
A,C
𝑝
278
Income effect
Price increase
real income has gone down
The income effect is
•
negative for a normal good
•
zero for a neutral good
•
positive for an inferior good
For a normal good the income and substitution effects are in the same
direction
279
Giffen goods
•
For inferior goods, the income and substitution
effects are in opposite directions
•
Typically, the substitution effect is stronger (that’s
an empirical fact)
•
If this isn’t the case, the good is referred to as a
Giffen good.
Robert Giffen 1837-1910
πœ‚
0
280
Let us not confuse Giffen goods with
• Uncertainty about quality (a $10 Rolex)
• conspicuous consumption
281
Compensations: Slutsky and Hicks
Back to the example
60
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐼
C
37.5
𝑝
A
30
log π‘₯
B
2, 𝑝′
log 𝑦
120
3, 𝑝
2
Suppose that the consumer is compensated so
that she can consume bundle A
π‘₯
20 π‘₯
π‘₯
30
25
60
282
What’s the impact on utility?
𝑝 , 𝑝 , 𝐼 → π‘₯, 𝑦 → 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯𝑦
log π‘₯
log 𝑦
𝐴 2,2,120 →
30,30
→
900
𝐡 3,2,120 →
20,30
→
600
𝐢 3,2,150 →
25,37.5 → 937.5
Evgeny Evgenievich Slutsky 1880-1948
150 – the compensated income, according to Slutsky
Slutsky compensation: 150-120=30
283
Neither shocked nor upset
𝑦
•
60
It’s natural that rotating the budget line
around a point (A) would change the
optimal bundle
C
•
A
60
And that’s perfectly fine with us…
π‘₯
284
However
𝑦
• Maybe the compensation shouldn’t be
60
that high?
• Maybe it’s enough to go back to the old
D
utility level, rather than the old physical
A
quantities (which are no longer
30
optimal)?
30
60
π‘₯
285
The compensation according to Hicks
Consider the table again
𝑝 ,𝑝 ,𝐼
→
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐴 2,2,120 →
30,30
→ 900
𝐡 3,2,120 →
20,30
→ 600
𝐢 3,2,150 →
25,37.5 → 937.5
𝐷 3,2, ?
→
π‘₯, 𝑦
→ 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
John Hicks 1904-1989
→ 900
286
Hicks compensation – cont.
For 3,2, 𝐼 we have
1 1
· ·πΌ
2 3
1 1
· ·πΌ
2 2
π‘₯
𝑦
To get 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯𝑦
1
𝐼
6
1
𝐼
4
900 we will require
1 1
𝐼· 𝐼
4 6
𝐼
900 · 24
𝐼
900
21,600
146.96
287
The compensations of Slutsky and Hicks
Slutzky: changes income to be able to be consume the
original bundle
Hicks: changes income to be able to be consume at the
original utility level
Hicks' sounds more fair, but requires knowledge (/estimation)
of the utility function
288
The PCC for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝
𝑏𝑦
If
the solution is
If
the solution is 0,
,0
PCC 1
If
π‘₯
it's any point in between
289
The demand "function"
π‘₯
For 𝑝
𝑝
it's π‘₯
For 𝑝
𝑝
it's π‘₯
(And for 𝑝
𝑝
0
any value 0
π‘₯
)
The elasticity is
πœ‚
π‘Ž
𝑝
𝑏
𝑝
≡
1
π‘π’š and not well
in the range 𝑝
defined outside it
290
The cross demand "function"
𝑦
For 𝑝
𝑝
it's 𝑦
For 𝑝
𝑝
it's 𝑦
(And for 𝑝
𝑝
0
any value 0
𝑦
)
𝐼
𝑝
The elasticity is
πœ‚
π‘Ž
𝑝
𝑏
𝑝
≡0
π‘π’š and not well
in the range 𝑝
defined outside it
291
An example of a Giffen good
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
min π‘₯
𝑦, 100
0.5π‘₯
Both goods can satisfy hunger, but only good 1 has nutritional value
π‘₯ – amount of nuts
𝑦 – amount of Styrofoam
π‘₯
𝑦 – total amount that fills the stomach
0.5π‘₯ – amount of nutritional food
100
0.5π‘₯ – the addition of 100 guarantees that the consumer starts seeking
nutrition only after the hunger is somewhat satisfied
292
Describing the preferences
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
min π‘₯
𝑦, 100
0.5π‘₯
Which need is the dominant one? Hunger or
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
100
0.5π‘₯
nutrition? This depends on
π‘₯
100
𝑦 β‹› 100
0.5π‘₯
or
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦 β‹› 100
𝑦
200
0.5π‘₯
π‘₯
293
Indifference curves
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
min π‘₯
𝑦, 100
0.5π‘₯
We distinguish between the two regions:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
100
0.5π‘₯
π‘₯
100
𝑦 β‹› 100
𝑦 β‹› 100
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
200
0.5π‘₯
0.5π‘₯
π‘₯
294
Let’s get the budget line into the picture
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
min π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
100
0.5π‘₯
𝑦, 100
𝑝 𝑦
0.5π‘₯
𝐼
And if
𝑝
𝑝
100
The consumer will only buy the first good
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
200
π‘₯
295
And this will be true for any income
𝑦
As long as
𝑝
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
100
0.5π‘₯
𝑝
Only the first good is consumed
100
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
200
π‘₯
296
The interesting case
𝑦
If
𝑝
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
100
0.5π‘₯
100
𝑝
– for low income the optimal bundle is on
the 𝑦 axis
– for high income the optimal bundle is on
the π‘₯ axis
– and in between on the dotted line
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
200
π‘₯
297
The ICC
𝑦
If
𝑝
𝑝
– The ICC will first climb up the 𝑦 axis
– then it will slide down the dotted line
100
– and finally – flatten onto the π‘₯ axis
200
π‘₯
– along the dotted line the second
good is inferior
298
Next consider a change in price
Let’s start with
𝑝
and increase 𝑝
𝑦
𝑝 ,
𝐼
200𝑝
At low prices the optimal solution will be on the
dotted line
100
When 𝑝 is high enough, the optimal solution will
be on the 𝑦 axis
𝐼/𝑝
200
π‘₯
And when 𝑝 is higher (above 𝑝 ) – on the π‘₯ axis
299
A possible PCC
𝑦
Importantly, there is a range in which it
goes down
In this range, an increase in the price of
100
good 2 (𝑝 ) results in an increase in the
demanded quantity 𝑦
200
π‘₯
300
Endowments
301
Income as endowments
• In a general equilibrium, there is no “income”
• Rather, there is an initial endowment
• A bundle of good that can be sold in the markets
• Including leisure that will be sold in the labor
market
302
The budget constraint
π‘₯ – initial endowment of good 1
𝑦 – initial endowment of good 2
𝑝 , 𝑝 – prices
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
or
𝑝 π‘₯
303
Graphically
𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘₯
304
Optimization
𝑦
If, say, we pick π‘₯, 𝑦 so that
‫ביקוש‬
𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
‫היצג‬
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
supply in market 1
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
demand in market 2
π‘₯
305
Will the consumer offer and demand
or the other way around?
𝑦
Compare slopes:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
with
𝑝
𝑝
π‘₯
306
The effect of preferences
𝑦
For a given budget line with slope
we can find preferences such that
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
as well as preference for which the
opposite holds
π‘₯
π‘₯
307
The effect of prices
𝑦
For given preferences, we can
typically find prices such that
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦
as well as prices for which the
opposite holds
π‘₯
π‘₯
308
Why “typically”?
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦=
4
min π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯
6
𝑦
4
Here the indifference curve has a
slope of zero, and for any positive
prices the consumer will wish to sell
good 1 and buy good 2
π‘₯
6
π‘₯
309
Example
π‘₯ – pears
𝑦 – apples
π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
10,
𝑦
2log π‘₯
10
log 𝑦
310
A reminder – CD solution
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘Žlog π‘₯
π‘Ž
1
π‘₯
π‘ˆ
1
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ŽπΌ
1
π‘Ž
1
π‘Ž log 𝑦
=
1
𝑦
π‘Ž 𝐼
π‘Ž
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝐼
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘Ž
1
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
311
If pears are (relatively) expensive
𝑦
𝑝
𝐼
𝑦
3
3 ∗ 10
1 ∗ 10
1
40
π‘₯
2 1
𝐼
3𝑝
2 1
· · 40
3 3
8.88
𝑦
1 1
𝐼
3𝑝
1 1
· · 40
3 1
13.33
supply of pears π‘₯
π‘₯
demand for apples 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑝
10
𝑦
8.88
13.33
1.11
10
3.33
π‘₯
312
And if apples are (relatively) expensive
𝑦
𝑝
𝐼
2
2 ∗ 10
π‘₯
2 1
𝐼
3𝑝
𝑦
1 1
𝐼
3𝑝
𝑦
demand for pears π‘₯
supply of apples 𝑦
π‘₯
𝑝
2 1
· · 70
3 2
1 1
· · 70
3 5
π‘₯
𝑦
5 ∗ 10
23.33
10
4.66
5
70
23.33
4.66
10
13.33
5.33
π‘₯
313
The Labor Market
314
A simple model
𝐿 – leisure (in hours/day)
π‘Œ – an aggregate good
π‘Š – wage per hour – the price of leisure
𝑃 – the price of the aggregate good
𝐿
24, π‘Œ
0
the initial endowment
315
The budget constraint
π‘ŠπΏ
𝑃 π‘Œ
π‘Š · 24
𝑃 ·0
24π‘Š
or:
𝑃 π‘Œ
𝐿
24
π‘Š 24
𝐿
– consumed leisure
𝐿
– hours sold on the labor market
316
Graphically
π‘Œ
π‘ŠπΏ
24π‘Š
𝑃
24
𝑃 π‘Œ
24π‘Š
𝐿
317
Real wages
Rather than π‘Š, 𝑃 we can use only their ratio
𝑀
π‘Š
𝑃
Generally, if income is given by an initial endowment, only
price ratios matter
𝑀–
how many units of π‘Œ can be purchased for one hour
of labor
318
The budget constraint in real terms
Rather than
π‘ŠπΏ
𝑃 π‘Œ
we have
𝑀𝐿
π‘Œ
Or, rather than
𝑃 π‘Œ
π‘Š 24
𝐿
π‘Œ
𝑀 24
𝐿
we get
24π‘Š
24𝑀
319
π‘Œ
How much to work and how much to
consume?
𝑀𝐿
24𝑀
π‘Œ
24𝑀
Say,
π‘ˆ 𝐿, π‘Œ
1
π›Όπ‘™π‘œπ‘”πΏ
1
𝛼 π‘™π‘œπ‘”π‘Œ
then
𝛼 24𝑀
𝐿
24𝛼
24
𝐿
π‘Œ
1
1
𝛼
24𝑀
𝑀
1
𝛼
24𝑀
1
24𝛼
1
𝛼 24𝑀
320
Supply of labor
How much labor 24
𝐿 will be offered as a function of
𝑀?
𝐿
24𝛼
The labor supply is totally inelastic, independent of 𝑀
Does it make sense?
321
Makes sense or not...
π‘Œ
24π‘Š
It can't surprise us:
... we know by now what the PCC
looks like for Cobb-Douglas
24𝛼
24
𝐿
322
Some weaknesses of the model
•
Assumes that labor itself doesn't affect well-being (one
way or another)
•
Ignores psychological and social effects of work
•
Luckily, the world of economics has not been so naive
323
Some advantages of the model
•
Relates labor supply to leisure
•
Allows the analysis of a general equilibrium
•
Illustrates that the economic logic applies also to labor
and leisure
324
A slightly more interesting story
π‘Œ
π‘Œ
An initial endowment π‘Œ
24𝑀
0
on top of 24 hours of leisure
The budget set is still convex
So it makes sense to look for tangency,
π‘Œ
and then verify it's in the relevant range
24
𝐿
325
Strict monotonicity could be helpful
π‘Œ
π‘Œ
Weak monotonicity may not suffice
24𝑀
for the consumer to use all their
resources
Say,
π‘Œ
π‘ˆ 𝐿, π‘Œ
24
𝐿
min π‘Œ, 0.5π‘Œ
𝐿
326
Solving the consumer problem
π‘Œ
π‘Œ
π‘ˆ 𝐿, π‘Œ
24𝑀
π›Όπ‘™π‘œπ‘”πΏ
𝐿
𝛼
π‘Œ
1
𝐿
π‘Œ
π‘Œ
Valid if
1
π‘Œ
1
π‘Œ
𝑀
1
24𝑀
𝛼 π‘Œ
𝛼
π‘Œ
𝑀
𝛼 π‘Œ
24𝛼
𝛼 π‘™π‘œπ‘”π‘Œ
24𝑀
24𝛼
1
𝛼 24𝑀
24
and otherwise it is at 24, π‘Œ
24
𝐿
327
Labor supply
Demand for leisure is
(as long as L
𝐿
π‘Œ
24𝛼
24)
Labor supply:
24
𝐿
24
𝛼
π‘Œ
𝑀
24𝛼
1
𝑀↑ ⇒
24
𝐿 ↑
𝛼 24
𝛼
π‘Œ
𝑀
(as long as it's non-negative)
upward sloping labor supply curve
328
There will be a corner solution
π‘Œ
If
π‘Œ
𝛼
π‘Œ
𝑀
24𝛼
24 1
𝛼
1
π‘Œ
𝛼
24
α
24𝑀
π‘Œ
Given 𝑀, π‘Œ : if 𝛼 is sufficiently close to 1
(That is, if the consumer "likes leisure
24
𝐿
sufficiently"
329
Or...
π‘Œ
Given 𝛼, π‘Œ : if 𝑀 isn't sufficiently high
𝛼
1
is equivalent to
𝑀
π‘Œ
24
24𝑀
π‘Œ
𝛼
𝛼
1
π‘Œ
𝛼 24
𝐿
330
Alternatively
π‘Œ
Given 𝛼, 𝑀: if π‘Œ is high enough:
π‘Œ
𝛼
1
is equivalent to
π‘Œ
24
𝛼
24𝑀
π‘Œ
1
𝛼
𝛼
24𝑀
𝐿
331
Producer Theory
332
A model of the producer
π‘₯ – input, such as labor hours
𝑦 – output
𝑝 – price of π‘₯
𝑝 – price of 𝑦
𝑓 – technology
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
333
The feasible set
𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑓
𝑓 π‘₯
0
π‘₯
334
Firm’s goal: maximize profit
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
,
πœ‹ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
Or is it?
• OK, it’s just a model
• Organizational Behavior suggests many other theories
• And yet, it is the stated purpose
• And “profit” is a known and (roughly) measurable concept, more than is
“utility” for the household
335
Profit maximization
𝑦
πœ‹ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
,
𝑝 π‘₯
πœ‹ π‘₯, 𝑦
Iso-profit line:
πœ‹ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝
π‘₯
𝑝
𝑐
𝑝
𝑐
π‘₯
336
In search of an optimum
𝑦
We’re looking for
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯
,
πœ‹ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
Subject to
𝑦
𝑓
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
0
π‘₯
337
Again, looking for tangency
𝑦
Between the highest iso-profit line
πœ‹ π‘₯, 𝑦
whose slope is
𝑦
𝑓
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝
π‘₯
𝑝
𝑐
𝑝
𝑐
and the technology constraint
𝑦 𝑓 π‘₯
with slope
𝑦′ 𝑓′ π‘₯
π‘₯
338
Example
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑝
10, 𝑝
100
Let’s take a derivative of the production function and equate slopes:
1
𝑓 π‘₯
2 π‘₯
1
10
10
100
𝑝
𝑝
we get
π‘₯
π‘₯
25
10
2
5
𝑦
5
and we can plug these into the profit function
πœ‹
100 · 5
10 · 25
250
339
Example – cont.
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑝
10, 𝑝
25
𝑦
100
Note that in the solution
π‘₯
πœ‹
100 · 5
10 · 25
5
250
the marginal value/revenue of labor is
100 ·
100 ·
10
and the cost of labor (per hours) is
𝑝
10
340
Generally,
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
Tangency yields
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑝
𝑝
or
𝑝 𝑓 π‘₯
marginal revenue
𝑝
marginal cost
341
Not too surprising
In search of the maximum of
πœ‹ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
if we plug
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
we obtain a maximization problem in one variable:
πœ‹ π‘₯
πœ‹′ π‘₯
𝑝 𝑓 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑓′ π‘₯
𝑝 𝑓′ π‘₯
𝑝
0
𝑝
342
Verbally,
π‘ƒπ‘Ÿπ‘œπ‘“π‘–π‘‘
𝑅𝑒𝑣𝑒𝑛𝑒𝑒
πΆπ‘œπ‘ π‘‘
Equating the derivative to zero yields
π‘€π‘Žπ‘Ÿπ‘”π‘–π‘›π‘Žπ‘™ 𝑅𝑒𝑣𝑒𝑛𝑒𝑒 𝑀𝑅
π‘€π‘Žπ‘Ÿπ‘”π‘–π‘›π‘Žπ‘™ πΆπ‘œπ‘ π‘‘ 𝑀𝐢
and, indeed, if
𝑀𝑅
𝑝 𝑓′ π‘₯
𝑝
𝑀𝐢
It would pay off to increase π‘₯
And a converse inequality suggests it would pay off to decrease π‘₯
343
Convexity, again
•
As in consumer theory, we really like it, as economists
•
The marginality condition becomes sufficient for optimality (under convexity)
•
But, beyond that: it also provides a reasonable story about optimization
•
Again, small improvements can lead to a global optimum
344
Optimization dictates behavior in markets
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑝
𝑝
Determines
demand in the input market π‘₯
𝑓
and supply in the output market 𝑦
𝑦
(say, demand in the labor market and supply in
the apples market)
π‘₯
345
Changes in demand and supply
Suppose that the price of π‘₯ goes up – or that the price of
𝑦 goes down: in both cases, the ratio
goes up
The firm’s demand for π‘₯ will go down
𝑓
as will the supply of 𝑦
𝑦
– which is what we’d expect as a downward sloping
𝑦′
demand curve (in the input market) and an upward
π‘₯′ π‘₯
sloping supply curve (in the output market)
346
Another example
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘₯
πœ‹
100 · 0.0025
𝑝
2π‘₯
10, 𝑝
100
10
100
0.05, 𝑦
10 · 0.05
𝑝
𝑝
0.0025
0.25
0.5
0.25
347
Just a sec…
𝑦
If 𝑓 isn’t concave, tangency might
not be such a great idea
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
348
Tangency and convexity
•
𝑓 π‘₯
As in consumer theory, or in optimization without
constraints, tangency isn’t a sufficient condition for
0
optimality
•
In a maximization problem, we also need concavity of
the function
•
In consumer theory – convexity of two sets (the
feasible and the desirable)
349
If both sets are convex
If the feasible and all the desirable sets are
𝑦
convex, tangency is sufficient for optimality
desirable
This time we have the desirable set defined by a
linear function (via the prices), and the feasible
often “strictly” convex
feasible
In consumer theory this was the other way around,
π‘₯
but the main idea is the same
350
The technology function
Is it likely to be
𝑦
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
convex
increasing returns to scale
?
concave
decreasing returns to scale
351
Wait – is it concave or convex?
The question is whether the set that is above/below the graph is convex
𝑦
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘₯
Convex function
the set above the graph is convex
π‘₯
Concave function
the set below the graph is convex
352
The strings and the graph
A string is never above the graph
A string is never below the graph
𝑦
for a convex function
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
for a concave function
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘₯
Convex function
the set above the graph is convex
π‘₯
Concave function
the set below the graph is convex
353
Decreasing marginal productivity
Makes sense in a variety of examples:
• Climb a tree to pick apples
• Study for an exam
• Add workers to a limited space
354
Fixed and variable costs
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑓 π‘₯ is neither convex nor concave
355
Several production factors
π‘₯ – quantity of production factor 1
π‘₯ – quantity of production factor 2
𝑦 – quantity of the output
Technology is given by
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯ ,π‘₯
356
The profit function
πœ‹ π‘₯ ,π‘₯ ,𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 – price of π‘₯
𝑝 – price of π‘₯
𝑝 – price of 𝑦
357
Optimization
Looking for
π‘₯ ,π‘₯ , 𝑦
to maximize
πœ‹ π‘₯ ,π‘₯ ,𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
subject to
𝑦
𝑓 π‘₯ ,π‘₯
358
Here Lagrange is really helpful
β„’ π‘₯ , π‘₯ , 𝑦, πœ†
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
0
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘₯
𝑝
πœ†π‘“ ⟢ πœ†
𝑝
𝑓
0
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘₯
𝑝
πœ†π‘“ ⟢ πœ†
𝑝
𝑓
𝑝
πœ†βŸΆπœ†
0
πœ•β„’
πœ•π‘¦
0
πœ†π‘¦
𝑓 π‘₯ ,π‘₯
𝑝
πœ•β„’
πœ•πœ†
359
And then
πœ†
𝑝
𝑓
𝑝
𝑓
𝑝
𝑝
𝑝
Is this
familiar?
𝑝 𝑓
𝑝 𝑓
familiar
360
Cost minimization
Suppose that the quantity 𝑦 is fixed for us
Whatever it is, it’s better to produce it at lower cost
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯ πœ‹ π‘₯ , π‘₯ , 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
revenue
𝑝 π‘₯
cost
So we can think of
𝑀𝑖𝑛 [ cost ]
subject to
𝑓 π‘₯ ,π‘₯
𝑦
361
That is…
π‘₯
We will try to be on the lowest isocost line subject to the constraint
of having enough 𝑦
… and then
𝑓 π‘₯ ,π‘₯
𝑦
doesn’t look too surprising…
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑐
π‘₯
362
π‘₯
If the equality doesn’t hold
Say, the iso-cost line is steeper than the
iso-product line
𝑝
𝑝
𝑓 π‘₯ ,π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
we can go down (to have lower cost)
𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑓
𝑓
without leaving the feasible set
𝑐
π‘₯
363
π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑐
In this situation
The condition
𝑝
𝑝
𝑓
𝑓
𝑝
𝑓
𝑝
𝑓
is equivalent to
𝑓 π‘₯ ,π‘₯
𝑦
which means that production factor 1 is
(relatively) more expensive than 2 (and we’ll be
better off using more of the second and less of the
π‘₯
first)
364
And maybe someone will notice that
A unit of π‘₯ yields, roughly, 𝑓 units of 𝑦
hence
1 unit of 𝑦 ≅
units of π‘₯ ≅
dollars
1 unit of 𝑦 ≅
units of π‘₯ ≅
dollars
and if, indeed,
𝑝
𝑓
𝑝
𝑓
Then production factor 1 is (relative to marginal productivity) more
expensive than is 2
365
A special case
π‘₯ – input in plant 1
π‘₯ – input in plant 2
Overall output:
𝑦
and the condition
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑓 π‘₯
or
will define the right mix
(again, under convexity assumptions, that is, concavity of both 𝑓 , 𝑓 )
366
Example
𝑓 π‘₯
𝑦
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
1
π‘₯
1
π‘₯
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝
𝑝
367
Markets and Equilibria
368
Market
𝐢 – Quantity of good 1
𝐷 – Quantity of good 2
No production
Many consumers (many = 2)
(But – they are price takers)
369
Consumer A’s preferences
𝑦
𝐷
𝐢
π‘₯
370
Consumer B’s preferences
𝑦
𝐷
𝐢
π‘₯
371
Consumer’s B preferences again
𝑦
π‘₯
𝐢
𝐷
𝐢
π‘₯
𝑦
372
Edgeworth’s Box: putting them together
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐷
𝑦
π‘₯
𝐢
373
Preferences in Edgeworth’s box
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐷
𝑦
π‘₯
𝐢
374
What’s wrong with…?
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
375
Pareto domination
An allocation
,
,
Pareto dominates another allocation
,
,
if
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
And at least one of these
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
is strict
376
Back to…
π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
,
,
Pareto dominates
π‘₯
,
,
377
Pareto Optimality
An allocation
,
,
is Pareto optimal
(≡ Pareto Efficient) if
there is no feasible allocation that Pareto dominates it
378
For example…
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
Getting A to be better off within the feasible set will make B worse
off (and vice versa).
379
There are many P.O. allocations
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
The Contract Curve connects all such allocations
380
Words of warning
“Pareto Efficient” sounds too weak
•
It is not only about producing a lot
•
It is also about producing the right products
•
And allocating them efficiently
381
More warnings…
“Pareto Optimal” sounds too strong
•
“Optimal” sounds like “best”
•
But we may prefer an allocation that is not
Pareto optimal to one that is.
382
The utility frontier
π‘ˆ
Each allocation defines a point.
𝑃𝑂
The frontier corresponds to
Pareto Optimal allocations
π‘ˆ
383
Pareto optimality
π‘ˆ
𝑧 is Pareto optimal
𝑧
𝑑 isn’t
𝑑
π‘ˆ
384
But…
π‘ˆ
𝑧, 𝑀 are Pareto optimal, 𝑑 is not.
𝑧 Pareto dominates 𝑑, but that’s all
𝑧
𝑑
𝑑, 𝑀 , 𝑧, 𝑀 are incomparable
𝑀
π‘ˆ
385
Pareto domination - incomplete
• Not every two allocations can be compared
• It is basically a unanimity relation
• In this case, “optimal” says much less than
“optimum”
386
The contract curve & the pareto frontier
𝑒
𝐷
𝐢
𝑒
387
Competitive equilibrium
Equilibrium – a list of prices, such that, when
everyone responds optimally to them, markets clear
(No excess demand, and excess supply only if the price is
zero)
388
“Everyone responds optimally“
•
In general, there are also firms
•
Which have demand in input markets (such as labor) and
supply in output markets
•
Their profits are divided among households according to
ownership
•
But let’s focus on equilibrium without production
389
Agent
Endowment π‘₯ , 𝑦
Given prices 𝑝 , 𝑝
Has a budget constraint:
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
390
Graphically
𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
391
Will agent
buy good 1 and sell 2?
𝑦
As above, it depends on the slope
of A’s indifference curve at π‘₯ , 𝑦
𝑦
π‘₯
π‘₯
392
Conversely,
𝑦
Given the preferences, there will
typically be prices for which A will
want to sell good 1 and buy good 2,
𝑦
and prices for which the opposite is
true.
π‘₯
π‘₯
393
Equilibrium
Looking for prices where demand = supply, as in:
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐷
𝑦
𝐢
π‘₯
394
Existence Theorem
Kenneth J. Arrow (1921-2017)
Gérard Debreu (1921-2004)
Under certain assumptions… there exists (at least one)
competitive equilibrium
395
Existence in the 2x2 case
(Misleadingly simple)
If
0, both want to sell 𝑦 and buy π‘₯
If
∞ – vice versa
As the line tilts, equilibrium is reached
396
Properties an equilibrium might have
•
Existence
•
Uniqueness
•
Dynamic stability (relative to perturbations)
•
Robustness (to initial conditions)
397
Existence
Is there a point that is a “steady state” ?
398
Uniqueness
Is the steady state unique?
399
Dynamic stability
Will a small perturbation result in a
big change?
Will dynamic forces push us back
to the equilibrium? Far away?
400
Different notions of dynamic stability
Will dynamic forces push us back
to the equilibrium? Far away?
Neither?
401
Robustness
If we missed the initial conditions by a bit, will the prediction
change dramatically?
402
Partial equilibrium was so nice…
𝑃
𝑆
𝐷
•
Existence
•
Uniqueness
•
Dynamic stability (relative to
perturbations)
𝑃
•
𝑄
Robustness (to initial conditions)
𝑄
403
Existence of partial equilibrium
If demand is a continuous decreasing curve,
𝑃
𝑆
𝐷
and supply is a continuous increasing curve,
mild conditions suffice to have an intersection
𝑃
𝑄
𝑄
404
Uniqueness of partial equilibrium
If demand is a continuous decreasing curve,
𝑃
𝑆
𝐷
and supply is a continuous increasing curve,
the intersection has to be unique
𝑃
𝑄
𝑄
405
Dynamic stability of partial equilibrium
We could tell plausible stories about the way
𝑃
𝑆
𝐷
market forces would push the price towards the
equilibrium price in case of excess demand or
excess supply
𝑃
𝑄
𝑄
406
Robustness of partial equilibrium
If the demand or the supply curve was not quite
𝑃
𝑆
𝐷
what we had in mind, it’s not the end of the
world
For “nearby” initial conditions there will be a
“nearby” equilibrium
𝑃
𝑄
𝑄
407
Unfortunately
For general equilibrium we only have existence (in general)
•
Existence
+
•
Uniqueness
–
•
Dynamic stability
–
•
Robustness
–
408
Pareto optimality of equilibrium
(Simple, but not misleading)
At equilibrium both indifference curves are tangent to the same
line, HENCE TO EACH OTHER
409
The First Welfare Theorem
All competitive equilibria define Pareto optimal allocations
Intuition: prices carry information
They serve as a communication device among the
agents, allowing decentralization
410
Decentralization
•
Just imagine how hard it is for a central planner to solve
the “problem of the economy”
•
How much misinformation can be involved
•
Decentralize: no risk of deception; using everyone to
solve their bit of the puzzle
411
Why are equilibria allocations efficient?
Suppose 𝑝 , 𝑝 is an equilibrium (“price list” or “price vector”)
and that
,
,
is an allocation corresponding to it
Could another feasible allocation
,
,
Pareto dominate
,
,
?
412
Equilibrium assumes optimality
,
,
is the allocation of an equilibrium (price list) 𝑝 , 𝑝
The bundle π‘₯ , 𝑦
is optimal for 𝐴 given 𝑝 , 𝑝
The bundle π‘₯ , 𝑦
is optimal for 𝐡 given 𝑝 , 𝑝
413
Optimality for
The bundle π‘₯ , 𝑦
𝑦
is optimal for 𝐴 given 𝑝 , 𝑝
Hence if
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯ ,𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
then
π‘ˆ
π‘₯
π‘₯ ,𝑦
(wherever π‘₯ , 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
is in the feasible set)
π‘₯′ , 𝑦′
414
Optimality for
plus monotonicity
Moreover, if
𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
then
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘₯′ , 𝑦′
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘₯
415
Why?
𝑦
π‘₯ ,𝑦
We claim that
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
Implies
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
Otherwise, i.e., π‘ˆ π‘₯ , 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
There would be another point π‘₯′′ , 𝑦′′
π‘₯′′ , 𝑦′′
and is (strictly) preferred to both
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘₯′ , 𝑦′
that is feasible
π‘₯
So π‘₯ , 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
couldn’t have been optimal
Note: weak monotonicity suffices here (but not basic)
416
Hence, with monotonicity,
optimality for 𝐴 implies
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
⟹
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
⟹
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
and
𝑝 π‘₯
417
Contrapositives
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
⟹
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
IFF
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
and
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
⟹
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
IFF
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
418
Using these,
optimality for 𝐴 (with weak monotonicity) implies
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
and
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
419
For the two agents
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ˆ
and
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
420
If we didn’t have Pareto optimality
,
,
Pareto dominates
,
,
means that
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
and
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘₯ ,𝑦
with at least one of these inequalities being strict
421
Putting these together
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘₯ ,𝑦
with at least one strict, given
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
π‘ˆ
π‘₯ ,𝑦
⟹
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
422
We get
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
Important: these are
the same prices!!!
with at least one strict
Adding them up
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
423
But this contradicts feasibility:
Feasibility of
,
,
means that
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
424
Multiplying by prices
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
yield
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦 )
and, adding up,
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
(while Pareto domination implied
𝑝 π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝 𝑦
𝑦
425
The proof
•
Works the same way with any number of goods and
consumers
•
Requires some extra work if we allow production
•
Still, simple enough to be convincing
•
While not entirely trivial – basically, changing the order of
summation
426
The theorem relies on
Explicitly:
•
Optimization
•
Weak monotonicity
•
Same prices
Implicitly:
•
Price taking behavior
•
No explicit uncertainty – in fact, no asymmetry of information
•
No externalities
427
Correspondingly
The conceptual message of the first welfare theorem may not
be valid if one:
• Agents are not “rational”
• Some have market power
• There are asymmetries of information
• There are externalities (as in the case of public goods)
428
And the conceptual message is limited
𝑒
Only guarantees Pareto optimality.
… says nothing about equality, fairness…
𝑒
429
How do we deal with inequality?
To competitive equilibrium answer: use lump-sum transfers
What’s that?
430
Lump-Sum Transfers
• Transfers of goods between agents before we let them
start the economic activity
• Changing the initial endowments once and not touching
equilibrium allocations that result
• The point: we don’t want to meddle with economic
incentives
431
The Second Welfare Theorem
(Under some conditions) for any
𝐷
Pareto Optimal allocation, there
𝑦
exists lump-sum transfers for
π‘₯
𝐢
which the allocation is an
equilibrium allocation (posttransfers)
432
The message and its limitations
• If you’re concerned about inequality, try to solve it without
messing up the price mechanism
• Don’t kill the coordination device
• The problem: we don’t really know any examples lumpsum transfers
• Most reasonable ideas won’t be “lump-sum” if used more
than once
433
The assumptions
• The second welfare theorem needs to assume more than
the first (basically, also convexity)
• But less than the existence proof (which isn’t constructive
and doesn’t come with a convergence result)
434
Preferences over
Consumption Streams
435
We haven’t dealt with
• Saving for the future
• Uncertainty
• In fact, these are two things that financial markets do for us:
• Smoothing consumption over time (saving and borrowing)
• Smoothing consumption over states of nature (insurance)
436
Multiple periods
𝑦 – income in period 0
𝑦 – income in period 1
𝑐 – consumption in period 0
𝑐 – consumption in period 1
π‘Ÿ – interest rate
437
Preferences
The classical model
π‘ˆ 𝑐 ,𝑐 ,𝑐 …
0
𝛿
𝑒 𝑐
𝛿𝑒 𝑐
𝛿 𝑒 𝑐
…
1 – the discount factor
with two periods: π‘ˆ 𝑐 , 𝑐
𝑒 𝑐
𝛿𝑒 𝑐
438
The budget set
Without financial markets: only (𝑦 , 𝑦 )
With saving/borrowing at π‘Ÿ:
every $1 today can be converted to $ 1
every $1 tomorrow can be converted to $
π‘Ÿ tomorrow
today
439
The budget set
𝑐
1
π‘Ÿ 𝑦
1
𝑐
𝑦
1
π‘Ÿ
𝑐
𝑦
1
1
π‘Ÿ
𝑦
or:
1
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
1
1
π‘Ÿ 𝑐
𝑐
1
π‘Ÿ 𝑦
𝑦
𝑐
π‘Ÿ
𝑦
440
Optimal choice
π‘ˆ 𝑐 ,𝑐
𝑐
𝑦
log 𝑐
π‘ˆ
1
𝑐
π‘ˆ
𝛿
𝑐
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
𝑦
𝛿 log 𝑐
𝑐
𝛿𝑐
𝑐
441
We might have
𝑐
𝑐
𝑦
𝑦
saving
loan
𝑦
𝑐
𝑦
𝑐
442
Will I save or borrow?
Depends on:
• The endowment 𝑦 , 𝑦
• The time preferences
• The interest rate 1
π‘Ÿ
443
Effect of endowment:
𝑐
𝑐
𝑦
loan
𝑦
saving
𝑦
𝑐
𝑦
𝑐
444
Effect of time preferences
𝑐
slope of indifference curve:
𝑐
high 𝛿
𝑦
𝑦
low 𝛿
𝑦
𝑐
𝑦
𝑐
445
Effect of interest rate
slope: 1
π‘Ÿ
𝑐
𝑐
high π‘Ÿ
𝑦
𝑦
low π‘Ÿ
indifference
slope:
𝑦
𝑐
𝑦
𝑐
446
A special (but important) case:
Fixed income: 𝑦
𝑐
1
π‘Ÿ
𝑦
1
𝛿
𝑐
1
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
𝑐
𝑦
π‘Ÿ
1
𝛿
𝑐
447
The above is a bit more general…
π‘ˆ 𝑐 ,𝑐
𝑒 𝑐
𝛿𝑒 𝑐
π‘ˆ
𝑒 𝑐
π‘ˆ
𝛿𝑒 𝑐
𝛿
But at 𝑦
𝑦 we are left with 𝛿
448
Back to Cobb-Douglas
π‘ˆ 𝑐 ,𝑐
log 𝑐
𝛿log 𝑐
Budget constraint: 1
For 𝑦
𝑦
𝑐
2
π‘Ÿ 𝑦
𝑦
𝑐 *
𝑐 *
π‘Ÿ 𝑐
2
2
π‘Ÿ 𝑦
π‘Ÿ 𝑦
𝑐 *
𝑦 ⇔
𝛿
𝑐 *
𝑦 ⇔
𝛿
449
Equilibrium with time preferences
Agent A: π‘ˆ
log 𝑐
𝛿log 𝑐
𝑐
𝑑
2𝑦
Agent B: π‘ˆ
log 𝑑
πœ‡log 𝑑
𝑐
𝑑
2𝑦
Equilibrium should be at π‘Ÿ such that:
1
πœ‡
1
𝛿
π‘Ÿ
or:
1
𝛿
1
π‘Ÿ
1
πœ‡
1
450
Indeed…
𝑐 *
y
𝑦
𝑦
The sum of demands should be zero
+
𝑑 *
0
y
𝑦
𝑦
2
and we can divide by 𝑦
The equilibrium interest rate is
sort of an average of those
corresponding to the agents’ time
preferences
451
Overlapping generations
Identical preferences:
π‘ˆ
π‘ˆ
log 𝑐
𝛿 log 𝑐
But different endowments:
𝐴:
𝑦 ,𝑦
𝐡:
𝑦 ,𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
452
Edgeworth box for young & old
𝑦
𝐡
𝑦
𝑦
𝐴
𝑦
453
For A:
π‘ˆ 𝑐 ,𝑐
1
𝑐 *
𝑐 * 𝑦
π‘Ÿ 𝑦
1
𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
π‘Ÿ 𝑐
log 𝑐
𝑐
𝛿 log 𝑐
1
π‘Ÿ 𝑦
𝑦
Demand in period 0
For B (reverse 𝑦 and 𝑦 ):
𝑑 * 𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
Equilibrium:
𝑐 * 𝑦
𝑑 * 𝑦
𝑦
𝑦
𝛿
Sum of demands should be zero
0
𝑦
𝑦
454
Conclusions
• Financial markets allow agents to smooth
consumption over time
• There might be trade between agents with different
time preferences
• Or with different endowments
• Or both. Or…
455
Preferences under
Risk and Uncertainty
456
Uncertainty
Has been with us since days of yore:
6 ”And
the messengers returned to Jacob, saying, We came to thy
brother Esau, and also he cometh to meet thee, and four hundred
men with him.
7 Then Jacob was greatly afraid and distressed: and he divided
the people that was with him, and the flocks, and herds, and the
camels, into two bands;
8 And said, If Esau come to the one company, and smite it, then
the other company which is left shall escape.”
King James version, Genesis chapter 32, 6-8.
457
Preferences
The most common model: Expected Utility maximization
Implicit in Pascal’s Wager (1670)
Explicit in Bernoulli’s resolution to the St. Petersburg Paradox (1738)
Became dominant with von-Neumann and Morgenstern (1947)
458
Expected utility
Maximize the expectation, not of the variable, but of its utility:
𝑁𝑂𝑇
𝐸 π‘₯
π΅π‘ˆπ‘‡
πΈπ‘ˆ π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑒 π‘₯
β‹―
𝑝 π‘₯
𝑝 𝑒 π‘₯
β‹―
𝑝 𝑒 π‘₯
459
Betting
Starting with wealth level π‘Š
You’re offfered a bet:
𝑋
It’s a fair bet if 𝐸 𝑋
0 or 𝐸 π‘Š
100 .5
100 .5
𝑋
π‘Š
Expected value maximization ⟹ indefference
460
But…
𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 π‘Š
0.5𝑒 π‘Š
+
0.5𝑒 π‘Š
100
100
𝑒 concave ⟹ 𝐸 𝑒 π‘Š
π‘Š
100
π‘Š
π‘Š
100
𝑋
𝑒 π‘Š
π‘₯
461
And vice versa for convex
:
𝑒 π‘₯
0.5𝑒 π‘Š
+
0.5𝑒 π‘Š
𝑒 convex ⟹ 𝐸 𝑒 π‘Š
100
𝑋
𝑒 π‘Š
100
𝑒 π‘Š
π‘Š
100
π‘Š
π‘Š
100
π‘₯
462
Risk aversion
Defined as:
For any fair bet 𝑋 𝐸 𝑋
0 and any wealth level,
π‘Š is at least as good as π‘Š
𝑋
Risk loving: the other way around
463
Under EU maximization
Risk aversion ⟺ 𝑒 concave
Risk loving ⟺ 𝑒 convex
(Both can be defined in the strict sense)
464
Insurance problem
Car worth 100,000
might be stolen with probability 1%
Insurance premium 2,000
Expected value maximization: don’t insure
0.99 100,000
0.01 0
99,000
98,000
465
Insurance problem - cont.
𝑒 π‘₯
𝑒 98,000
0.99𝑒 100,000
+
0.01𝑒 0
However, a risk averse agent might have:
0.99
98
100
𝑒 100,000
0.01
𝑒 0
𝑒 98,000
π‘₯
466
How do we know…
that the premium is greater than expected loss?
•
Because insurance companies make money
•
At least those who are around
•
What’s the difference between the insurance company and
the agent?
467
Law of large numbers (LLN)
If 𝑋 are i.i.d. (identically and independently distributed)
and 𝑋
Then: 𝑋 → πœ‡
∑
𝑋
where πœ‡
𝐸 𝑋
468
Law of large numbers – cont.
Important:
•
Identicality (or something close)
•
Independence (or something close)
•
Large 𝑛
469
Gambling and state lottery
The state lottery offers us a gamble with negative expectation
Say, pay $1 to get $1M with probability 0.000,000,5
How do we know that?
470
State lotteries
𝑒 π‘₯
A risk averse agent will not buy it
1
1
𝑒 π‘Š
2𝑀
1
𝑒 π‘Š
2𝑀
Not even risk neutral
1
But…
1𝑀
𝑒 π‘Š
π‘Š
1
π‘Š
π‘Š
1𝑀
471
Back to the consumer’s problem:
States of nature:
π‘₯, 𝑦 – (wealth in state 1, wealth in state 2)
𝑦
π‘₯
472
The betting example
Tail
Bet on Tail
π‘Š
100
π‘Š
π‘Š
100
Bet on
Head
π‘Š
100
π‘Š
π‘Š
100
Head
473
Preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Š
𝑝·π‘’ π‘₯
1
𝑝 ·π‘’ 𝑦
For example:
100
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 · log π‘₯
1
𝑝 · log 𝑦
π‘Š
π‘Š
100
Risk aversion: concave 𝑒
π‘Š
100
π‘Š
π‘Š
100
474
The budget constraint
Say, a fair bet on any amount:
π‘₯
𝑦
π‘Š
π‘Š
A risk averse agent will choose to
remain at π‘Š, π‘Š
π‘Š
475
The insurance problem
𝑦
π‘Š – wealth
apart from car
car stolen
1 𝑝 0.01
π‘Š
car not
stolen
𝑝 0.99
π‘Š
100,000
π‘₯
476
The insurance problem – cont.
𝑦
Preferences:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘Š
0.99𝑒 π‘₯
0.01𝑒 𝑦
98
Budget constrains:
π‘Š
Say, any amount up to 100,000 can be
insured with premium of 2%
π‘Š
98 π‘Š
100
π‘₯
477
The insurance problem – cont.
Insure at π‘Ž,
0
π‘Ž
100,000
Pay 0.02π‘Ž for sure
⟹ π‘Š
100
0.02π‘Ž, π‘Š
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
0 π‘Š
π‘Š
0.02π‘Ž
100, π‘Š
98, π‘Š
π‘Ž
100
98
The segment connecting them is
0.98π‘₯
0.02𝑦
W
98
478
Insurance problem– solution
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
0.99 log π‘₯
Budget line: 0.98π‘₯
π‘₯*
0.99
𝑦*
0.01
.
.
0.01 log 𝑦
0.02𝑦
W
98
π‘Š
98
.
.
π‘Š
98
π‘Š
98
π‘Š
98
.
.
π‘Š
98
π‘Š
98
The agent will not be fully insured
479
Why?
At full insurance, π‘Š
98, π‘Š
98
the slope of the indifference curve is:
.
π‘ˆ
.
,π‘ˆ
.
.
β”‚ π‘₯
𝑦
99
while the slope of the budget constraint is:
𝑝
0.98, 𝑝
0.02
.
.
49
480
Thus…
the indifference curve is steeper:
𝑦
certainty line
π‘Š
98
π‘Š
π‘Š
98 π‘Š
100
π‘₯
481
And this is quite general:
With Expected Utility: π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝·π‘’ π‘₯
1
𝑝 𝑒 𝑦
So that:
β”‚ π‘₯
𝑦
The slopes of all indifference curves along the certainty line are the same,
and independent of 𝑒
482
Financial markets
1,0 – An asset that pays 1 in state 1 and 0 in state 2 costs 𝑏
0
𝑏
1
0,1 – An asset that pays 1 in state 2 and 0 in state 1 costs 𝑐
0
𝑐
1
𝑏
𝑐
1
It stands to reason that
Why?
483
No Arbitrage
Imagine that
1,0 costs 𝑏
0.4
0,1 costs 𝑐
0.5
and
Then I could buy both, and at a total cost of 0.9 have 1 for sure, making a
sure gain of 0.1
(ignoring transaction costs)
484
No Arbitrage – part II
And now imagine that
1,0 costs 𝑏
0.6
0,1 costs 𝑐
0.5
And, say,
Then I could sell both, and this means I will get 1.1 but will have to pay
only 1 – whatever the state: I’ll be making a sure gain of 0.1
(again, ignoring transaction costs)
485
No Arbitrage – conclusion
1,0 – An asset that pays 1in state 1 and 0 in state 2 costs 𝑏
0,1 – An asset that pays 1in state 2 and 0 in state 1 costs 𝑐
If
𝑏
𝑐
1
doesn’t hold, market forces will push the prices in this direction.
So, for some 0
πœ‹
1,
1,0 costs πœ‹
0,1 costs 1
πœ‹
486
The market odds
1,0 costs πœ‹
0,1 costs 1
Hence
1
πœ‹, πœ‹
1
πœ‹
πœ‹ ,πœ‹
each has a net worth of 0
And so does
π‘Ž 1
πœ‹ , π‘Žπœ‹
For any π‘Ž (positive or negative)
487
The no arbitrage theorem
In a perfect market (no transaction costs,
buying and selling of any amount is allowed
with linear pricing)
there are no arbitrage opportunities
IFF there is a probability such that
each asset is valued by its
Stephen A. Ross (1944-2017)
expectation (relative to that probability)
488
The geometry of No Arbitrage
𝑦 (state 2)
Suppose
0,1
0.6,0.6
1,0 costs 𝑏
0.6
0,1 costs 𝑐
0.5
0.5,0.5
1,0
π‘₯ (state 1)
489
In that case…
𝑦 (state 2)
0,1
1,0 costs 𝑏
0.6
0,1 costs 𝑐
0.5
0.5 1,0
0.5 0,1
0.5,0.5
which is strictly lower than
0.6,0.6
0.5,0.5
0.5 0.6,0.6
0.5 0.5,0.5
0.55,0.55
1,0
π‘₯ (state 1)
so selling both assets pays off
490
Similarly
Similar sure-gain trades can be
𝑦 (state 2)
generated whenever the two line
segments (each connecting an
0,1
uncertain asset to its certainty
equivalent on the diagonal) are not
parallel
1,0
π‘₯ (state 1)
491
But
If they are parallel then, by Thales’s
𝑦 (state 2)
Theorem we get two similar
triangles and the average of the
0,1
certainty equivalent equals the
certainty equivalent of the average
1,0
π‘₯ (state 1)
492
And
the same holds if the two assets we
𝑦 (state 2)
start out with are not the unit
vectors,
or not symmetric around the
diagonal
π‘₯ (state 1)
493
Or
on the same side of the diagonal
𝑦 (state 2)
π‘₯ (state 1)
494
The budget constraint
An agent with endowment 𝐢, 𝐷 can purchase π‘Ž π‘Ž
and add π‘Ž 1
0 π‘œπ‘Ÿ π‘Ž
0 units of 1
πœ‹, πœ‹
πœ‹ , π‘Žπœ‹ to her endowment
The agent’s budget constraint consists of points π‘₯, 𝑦 such that for some π‘Ž :
𝐢
π‘Ž 1
πœ‹ ,𝐷
πœ‹π‘Ž
π‘₯, 𝑦
Or: we can think of the budget line as all the points π‘₯, 𝑦 that have the same cost as
𝐢, 𝐷 at prices πœ‹, 1
πœ‹
:
πœ‹π‘₯
1
πœ‹ 𝑦
πœ‹πΆ
1
πœ‹ 𝐷
495
Agent’s demand & supply
𝑝 log π‘₯
Max
Budget:
π‘₯*
𝑦*
𝑝
πœ‹π‘₯
πœ‹πΆ
1
𝑝
1
1
1
πœ‹ 𝑦
𝑝 log 𝑦
πœ‹πΆ
1
πœ‹ 𝐷
πœ‹ 𝐷
πœ‹πΆ
1
πœ‹ 𝐷
496
Will the agent buy the asset?
That is, will the agent want more in state 1, π‘₯*
𝑝
πœ‹πΆ
𝑝𝐢
1
𝑝
𝐷
In case 𝐢
𝐷: only if
In case πœ‹
𝑝: only if 𝐷
πœ‹ 𝐷
𝐷
𝐢
𝐢
𝐢
that is, if
𝐢
𝐢?
πœ‹
𝑝
497
Two main reasons for agents to trade:
•
Consumption smoothing across states: the agent agrees with
the market, 𝑝
𝐷
•
πœ‹, but experiences uncertainty
𝐢
Thinking they know better: the agent faces no uncertainty,
𝐷
𝐢, but thinks a state is more likely than evaluated by the
market
𝑝
πœ‹
… And we often have combinations of the above
498
Equilibrium in financial markets
𝐷
Suppose the agents agree on probabilities:
𝐢
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 log π‘₯
1
𝑝 log 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 log π‘₯
1
𝑝 log 𝑦
But have uncertain endowments
𝐢, 𝐷 , 𝐷, 𝐢
𝐷
𝐢
499
What will be the equilibrium price?
Agent’s A demand (in state 1):
π‘₯*
𝐢
𝑝
πœ‹πΆ
1
πœ‹ 𝐷
𝐢
𝑝 log π‘₯
1
𝑝 log 𝑦
And recall that, for CD…
1
𝑝 𝐢
𝑝
𝐷
Agent’s B demand 𝐢 ⟷ 𝐷 :
1
Sum to zero implies 𝑝
1
𝑝 𝐢
𝑝 𝐷
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑝
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
1
π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝
𝐢
πœ‹:
𝐷
𝑝
𝐢
𝐷
500
Thus
With identical preferences:
𝑝 log π‘₯
1
𝑝 log 𝑦
And endowments: 𝐢, 𝐷 , 𝐷, 𝐢
•
No aggregate uncertainty: 𝐢
𝐷, 𝐢
𝐷
•
The equilibrium price is the probability πœ‹
𝑝, and the
equilibrium allocations are “full insurance”
501
But the agents can disagree:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 log π‘₯
1
𝑝
log 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝 log π‘₯
1
𝑝
log 𝑦
Suppose that 𝐢, 𝐢 is the endowment of each…
502
𝐢
𝐢
𝐢
𝐢
Say, 𝑝
𝑝
Agent A thinks state 1 is more likely than does agent B.
503
Equilibrium with disagreement:
Sum
π‘₯∗
𝐢
1
𝑝 𝐢
𝑝
π‘₯∗
𝐢
1
𝑝 𝐢
𝑝
𝑝
𝑝
1
πœ‹
πœ‹
1
πœ‹
πœ‹
𝐢
𝐢
0⟹
2
𝑝
∗
∗
for
𝑝
𝑝∗
πœ‹ will be the “average” belief.
504
Puzzles and Anomalies
505
Puzzles : Time preferences
•
Do you prefer $100 today, or $110 in a week?
•
Do you prefer $100 in 50 weeks to $110 in 51 weeks?
506
Dynamic consistency
What we plan today to do tomorrow is also what we indeed
wish to do tomorrow.
Violated in the previous example…
507
Puzzles : EU
Do you prefer $3000 for sure to $4000 with probability 80%?
And how about
$3000
with 𝑝
0.25
to:
$4000
with 𝑝
0.20
508
Puzzles - cont.
You get $1000.
You get $2000.
Do you prefer:
Do you prefer:
a.
$500 for sure
b.
$1000 with 𝑝
0.5
a.
$500 for sure
b.
$1000 with 𝑝
0.5
509
Prospect theory
Kahneman and Tversky:
•
Small probabilities loom large
•
Reference points matter
510
Other anomalies:
•
Decoy and Compromise Effects
•
Mental Accounting
•
Disposition Effect
511
Download