Uploaded by alfredgriffith514

Dylan Lino - The Rule of Law and the Rule of Empire

advertisement
THE
MODERN LAW REVIEW
Volume 81
September 2018
No. 5
The Rule of Law and the Rule of Empire: A.V. Dicey
in Imperial Context
Dylan Lino∗
The idea of the rule of law, more ubiquitous globally today than ever before, owes a lasting
debt to the work of Victorian legal theorist A. V. Dicey. But for all of Dicey’s influence, little
attention has been paid to the imperial entanglements of his thought, including on the rule of
law. This article seeks to bring the imperial dimensions of Dicey’s thinking about the rule of
law into view. On Dicey’s account, the rule of law represented a distinctive English civilisational
achievement, one that furnished a liberal justification for British imperialism. And yet Dicey was
forced to acknowledge that imperial rule at times required arbitrariness and formal inequality at
odds with the rule of law. At a moment when the rule of law has once more come to license all
sorts of transnational interventions by globally powerful political actors, Dicey’s preoccupations
and ambivalences are in many ways our own.
‘The precise issue we raise is this – that throughout our empire the British rule
shall be the rule of law . . . ’1
In the speeches of developmental experts and the policy documents of international institutions, in the reports of think tanks and global indices of good
governance, a four-word phrase has become more ubiquitous than ever. That
phrase is, of course, ‘the rule of law’. As Martin Krygier has put it, the rule of
law is ‘so totally on every aid donor’s agenda that it has become an unavoidable
cliché of international organizations of every kind’.2 Spreading the rule of law
is now both the means and the end for an array of international interventions of varying scale and intensity, especially in the Global South. Promoting
the rule of law has, for instance, become a core objective of the World Bank
in supporting development projects, the United Nations Security Council in
authorising sanctions and peacekeeping missions, the International Criminal
∗
Lecturer, University of Western Australia Law School. Special thanks are due to Samuel Moyn for
his help in developing the ideas in this article. Thanks also to John Allison, Duncan Bell, Donal
Coffey, Ann Curthoys, Coel Kirkby, Priyasha Saksena and Oren Tamir.
1 F. Harrison, Martial Law: Six Letters to ‘The Daily News’ (London: The Jamaica Committee,
1867) 4.
2 M. Krygier, ‘The Rule of Law: Pasts, Presents, and Two Possible Futures’ (2016) 12 Annual
Review of Law and Social Science 199, 200.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
Published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
bs_bs_banner
Court in prosecuting international crimes and occupying forces in seeking
to restore order following military interventions.3 With increasing efforts to
establish the rule of law in the Global South by powerful Western states, nongovernmental organisations and international institutions, the ideal may have
become ‘our modern mission civilisatrice’.4
That ubiquitous four-word phrase has, it would seem, travelled a great
distance from its more provincial inception in the constitutional theory of
late-Victorian England. The idea of ‘the rule of law’ was first elaborated by
the Oxford law professor Albert Venn Dicey (1835–1922), who developed a
deeply influential account in his seminal Introduction to the Study of the Law of the
Constitution (LOTC), first published in 1885.5 To be sure, others before Dicey
had occasionally used the phrase, if only in passing, in a similar way.6 More
fundamentally, in Britain, ideas about the importance of law and lawfulness had
possessed a powerful hold in earlier times and on the minds of earlier thinkers:
the rule of law existed as an ideal avant la lettre de Dicey.7 And contrary to what
Judith Shklar caustically described as ‘Dicey’s unfortunate outburst of AngloSaxon parochialism’, political and intellectual traditions of legality had also
developed in places outside England.8 But it was Dicey who first congealed ‘the
legality of English habits and feelings’ into an extended constitutional account
of ‘the rule of law’ and elevated it to ‘the distinguishing characteristic of English
3 A classic statement identifying this trend is T. Carothers, ‘The Rule of Law Revival’ (1998) 77
Foreign Affairs 95. See further, for example, D. M. Trubek and A. Santos (eds), The New Law and
Development: A Critical Appraisal (Cambridge: CUP, 2006); S. Humphreys, Theatre of the Rule of
Law: Transnational Legal Intervention in Theory and Practice (Cambridge: CUP, 2010); J. Farrall and
H. Charlesworth (eds), Strengthening the Rule of Law Through the UN Security Council (Abingdon:
Routledge, 2016); J. Stromseth, D. Wippman and R. Brooks, Can Might Make Rights? Building
the Rule of Law After Military Interventions (Cambridge: CUP, 2006); B. Rajagopal, ‘Invoking the
Rule of Law in Post-Conflict Rebuilding: A Critical Examination’ (2008) 49 Wm & Mary L
Rev 1347.
4 T. Ginsburg, ‘In Defense of Imperialism? The Rule of Law and the State-Building Project’ in J.
E. Fleming (ed), Getting to the Rule of Law: NOMOS L (New York, NY: New York University
Press, 2011) 224. See also R. Brooks, ‘The New Imperialism: Violence, Norms, and the “Rule
of Law”’ (2003) 101 Mich L Rev 2275.
5 A. V. Dicey, Lectures Introductory to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (London: Macmillan
and Co, 1885).
6 For a use of the phrase ‘the rule of law’ before Dicey used it, see the epigraph to this article. See
also J. W. F. Allison, The English Historical Constitution: Continuity, Change and European Effects
(Cambridge: CUP, 2007) 157 n 2.
7 cf Krygier, n 2 above, 200–201. See, for example, H. W. Arndt, ‘The Origins of Dicey’s Concept
of the “Rule of Law”’ (1957) 31 ALJ 117; J. A. Sempill, ‘Ruler’s Sword, Citizen’s Shield: The
Rule of Law and the Constitution of Power’ (2016) 31 J L & Pol 333; N. McArthur, ‘Laws
Not Men: Hume’s Distinction Between Barbarous and Civilized Government’ (2005) 31 Hume
Studies 123; E. P. Thompson, Whigs and Hunters: The Origin of the Black Act (London: Allen
Lane, 1975); D. Hay, ‘Property, Authority and the Criminal Law’ in D. Hay et al (eds), Albion’s
Fatal Tree: Crime and Society in Eighteenth-Century England (London: Allen Lane, 1975); B. Z.
Tamanaha, On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory (Cambridge: CUP, 2004) especially 25–27,
chs 3–4.
8 J. Shklar, ‘Political Theory and the Rule of Law’ in A. C. Hutchinson and P. Monahan (eds), The
Rule of Law: Ideal or Ideology (Toronto: Carswell, 1987) 5. See further, for example, Tamanaha,
ibid, chs 1–2; M. Loughlin, Foundations of Public Law (Oxford: OUP, 2010) ch 11. Note that
Shklar, Tamanaha and Loughlin still tell a Eurocentric story about the rule of law and its
importance. For a non-European approach to lawfulness, see C. F. Black, The Land is the Source
of the Law: A Dialogic Encounter with Indigenous Jurisprudence (London: Taylor & Francis, 2010).
740
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
institutions’.9 Alongside its commitment to the sovereignty of parliament, the
English constitution was, said Dicey, defined by its instantiation of the rule of
law.
To Dicey, we owe not only the phrase ‘the rule of law’ but also one of the
idea’s most influential expositions. Dicey’s account of the rule of law emphasised three elements: first, government through legal norms and procedures
rather than unrestrained discretion; second, formal equality before the law;
and third, the establishment of individual rights through gradual, bottom-up
(common-law) development. These ideas continue to impact contemporary
debates over the rule of law – within their conventional home of constitutional theory (especially in the common-law tradition) and beyond.10 Dicey’s
account is typically understood as formalist and ‘thin’, focusing on institutional
arrangements rather than normatively substantive or ‘thick’ political ideals.11
When understood in historical context, Dicey’s rule of law has also often been
seen (correctly) as a defence of laissez faire individualism.12 While the Diceyan
rule of law has accumulated many critics over the years, it still has its admirers.13
Loved or loathed, Dicey remains a point of departure for thinking about the
rule of law today.
But even as Dicey’s rule of law continues to influence contemporary debates, an important facet of his account – its entanglement with imperial rule –
remains almost entirely neglected. Certainly, lawyers and historians have undertaken many invaluable studies of how the rule of law ideal has fared in practice
under imperial and colonial conditions.14 Scholars have also traced the place
9 Dicey, n 5 above, 168, 171. On the originality of Dicey’s account, see J. W. F. Allison, ‘Turning
the Rule of Law into an English Constitutional Idea’ in C. May and A. Winchester (eds), The
Edgar Elgar Handbook on the Rule of Law (forthcoming, 2018); B. J. Hibbits, ‘The Politics of
Principle: Albert Venn Dicey and the Rule of Law’ (1994) 23 Anglo-Am L R 1, 26–27.
10 In constitutional theory, see, for example, T. R. S. Allan, The Sovereignty of Law: Freedom,
Constitution, and the Common Law (Oxford: OUP, 2013) especially ch 3. Outside constitutional
theory, see, for example, Tamanaha, n 7 above; Humphreys, n 3 above, chs 1–2; Krygier, n 2
above.
11 P. P. Craig, ‘Formal and Substantive Conceptions of the Rule of Law: An Analytical Framework’
[1997] PL 467, 470–474; Allison, n 6 above, 158–161; cf T. R. S. Allan, Constitutional Justice: A
Liberal Theory of the Rule of Law (Oxford: OUP, 2003) 18–21.
12 See, for example, Hibbits, n 9 above.
13 For admiring recent discussions and appropriations, see, for example, T. Bingham, The Rule of
Law (London: Allen Lane, 2010); Allan, n 10 above; M. D. Walters, ‘Public Law and Ordinary
Legal Method: Revisiting Dicey’s Approach to Droit Administratif’ (2016) 66 UTLJ 53.
14 See, for example, D. Neal, The Rule of Law in a Penal Colony: Law and Power in Early New
South Wales (Cambridge: CUP, 1991); A. W. B. Simpson, ‘Round Up the Usual Suspects: The
Legacy of British Colonialism and the European Convention on Human Rights’ (1996) 41
Loy L Rev 629; L. Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–
1900 (Cambridge: CUP, 2002); N. Hussain, The Jurisprudence of Emergency: Colonialism and the
Rule of Law (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 2003); R. Kostal, A Jurisprudence
of Power: Victorian Empire and the Rule of Law (Oxford: OUP, 2005); H. Foster, B. L. Berger
and A. R. Buck (eds), The Grand Experiment: Law and Legal Culture in British Settler Societies
(Vancouver: UBC Press, 2008); E. Kolsky, Colonial Justice in British India: White Violence and the
Rule of Law (Cambridge: CUP, 2011); J. McLaren, Dewigged, Bothered, and Bewildered: British
Colonial Judges on Trial, 1800–1900 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2011); S. Humphreys,
‘Laboratories of Statehood: Legal Intervention in Colonial Africa and Today’ (2012) 75 MLR
475; M. F. Massoud, Law’s Fragile State: Colonial, Authoritarian, and Humanitarian Legacies in Sudan
(Cambridge: CUP, 2013).
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
741
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
of ideas of law and lawfulness within projects of imperial and colonial rule.15
However, when it comes to the man who effectively coined the phrase ‘the rule
of law’, the imperial dimensions of his thought about that ideal are still to be
properly explored.16 And yet, for Dicey, who was writing during the height of
the ‘age of empire’, the rule of law was also bound up with the rule of empire:
the British Empire in particular, at whose metropolitan centre he resided.17
Indeed, as the epigraph shows, one of the few scattered references to ‘the rule
of law’ before Dicey – by Dicey’s friend and fellow lawyer-intellectual Frederic
Harrison – occurred during an especially intense mid-Victorian debate over
the nature of British imperial rule.18
This article seeks to bring the imperial dimensions of Dicey’s thinking about
the rule of law into view. It does so as a study in intellectual history, situating
Dicey’s writings within the imperial historical context in which they were
composed. The article examines Dicey’s treatment of the rule of law in LOTC
across its 30-year lifespan of eight editions, as well as in Dicey’s extensive other
academic and journalistic works.19
Within Dicey’s thought, the rule of law and the rule of empire were in
a complex and unstable relationship. In David Sugarman’s astute observation, ‘Dicey, like most people, was not internally consistent’.20 On the one
hand, Dicey believed British imperialism to be justified by Britain’s possession of the rule of law – the pinnacle of civilisational achievement – and by
Britain’s capacity to spread that achievement abroad. Dicey’s masterwork, the
LOTC, was on this score an apology for a liberal version of the British Empire.
15 See, for example, E. Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India (Oxford: OUP, 1959) esp 55–80,
ch 3, 273–310; M. Chanock, Law, Custom, and Social Order: The Colonial Experience in Malawi
and Zambia (Cambridge: CUP, 1985); S. E. Merry, ‘Law and Colonialism’ (1991) 25 Law and
Society Review 1889; J. Comaroff, ‘Colonialism, Culture, and the Law: A Foreword’ (2001) 26 L
& Soc Inquiry 305; D. Kirkby and C. Coleborne (eds), Law, History, Colonialism: The Reach of
Empire (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2001); D. J. Hulsebosch, Constituting Empire:
New York and the Transformation of Constitutionalism in the Atlantic World, 1664–1830 (Chapel
Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 2005); L. Benton and L. Ford, Rage for Order:
The British Empire and the Origins of International Law, 1800–1850 (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard
University Press, 2016); K. McBride, Mr Mothercountry: The Man Who Made the Rule of Law
(Oxford: OUP, 2016).
16 For important analyses putting Dicey’s rule of law in an imperial context, see T. Poole, Reason of
State: Law, Prerogative and Empire (Cambridge: CUP, 2015) 197–206; D. Dyzenhaus, ‘The Puzzle
of Martial Law’ (2009) 59 UTLJ 1; Kostal, n 14 above, 456–458. For a recent exploration of
Dicey’s imperialism, focusing on his treatment of parliamentary sovereignty, see D. Lino, ‘Albert
Venn Dicey and the Constitutional Theory of Empire’ (2016) 36 OJLS 751.
17 E. Hobsbawm, The Age of Empire 1875–1914 (New York, NY: Pantheon Books 1987). See
further Lino, ibid.
18 The debate was over Governor Edward Eyre’s violent suppression of the 1865 Morant Bay
uprising in Jamaica, discussed further below. Dicey and Harrison were like-minded Liberals
who studied together at Oxford and moved in the same intellectual circles. See C. Harvie, The
Lights of Liberalism: University Liberals and the Challenge of Democracy 1860–86 (London: Allen
Lane, 1976).
19 Much of Dicey’s journalism was written anonymously. I have substantiated his authorship for
materials cited using D. Haskell, The Nation: Volumes 1–105, New York, 1865–1917: Index of
Titles vol 1 (New York, NY: New York Public Library 1951); Wellesley Index to Victorian
Periodicals, 1824–1900 at http://wellesley.chadwyck.com (last accessed 9 January 2018).
20 D. Sugarman, ‘The Legal Boundaries of Liberty: Dicey, Liberalism and Legal Science’ (1983)
46 MLR 102, 111.
742
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
On the other hand, Dicey was forced to recognise at various points that sustaining the Empire’s hierarchical relations could necessitate oppressive departures
from the rule of law – in deference to the sometimes lawless and frequently
discriminatory practices of settler-colonial self-government and to the exigencies of governing rebellious colonial subjects. These departures from the rule of
law in turn undercut the Empire’s very reason for existence. More fundamentally, Dicey recognised on occasion that the rule of law could itself be arbitrary
and oppressive when imposed on the Empire’s ‘uncivilised’ peoples, for whom
he believed it was foreign and too advanced. In Dicey’s thought on the rule
of law, liberal imperialism was thus not only undermined by its own internal
contradictions but also susceptible to a culturalist critique – associated with the
work of Henry Maine – which emphasised the need to rule colonial subjects
according to their own level of ‘civilisation’.
Gaining a deeper insight into the imperial entanglements of Dicey’s thinking
on the rule of law is a worthwhile undertaking. It is, in the first place, valuable for better understanding Dicey himself. For a thinker who has retained
remarkable intellectual currency, bringing to light the overlooked imperial dimensions of Dicey’s ideas helps those engaging with Dicey today to gain a fuller
appreciation of his thought and its potential implications.
Recovering these facets of Dicey’s thought can also help in understanding the
rule of law more generally and the liberalism whence it springs. Highlighting
the imperial commitments and dilemmas within one of the most canonical
accounts of the rule of law can reveal, to quote Krygier again, ‘concerns that
have motivated the vocabularies we have inherited’ and disclose ‘intellectual
dispositions, sensibilities, and traditions of thought and practice that have left
significant residues in our culture’.21 Dicey’s thought demonstrates the rule of
law’s potential to serve as a justification for imperial projects, at the same time
as it reveals some of the difficulties in sustaining the rule of law and the rule
of empire simultaneously, as well as the potential for the rule of law to collapse
into its own form of arbitrary domination when imposed by one society on
others. It uncovers, in other words, strong affinities but also real tensions at the
conjunction of liberalism and imperialism.22 At a moment when the rule of
law has once more come to license all sorts of transnational interventions by
globally powerful political actors, Dicey’s preoccupations and ambivalences are
in many ways our own.23
The article begins by outlining Dicey’s account of the rule of law and showing how it relied upon hierarchical nineteenth-century notions of ‘civilisation’.
For Dicey and many of his contemporaries, Britain – with its supposedly unique
possession of the rule of law – sat atop the civilisational hierarchy. Next, situating Dicey’s writings against Victorian controversies over British rule in India,
Jamaica and Ireland, the article demonstrates how Dicey’s rule of law, especially
21 Krygier, n 2 above, 202.
22 For an excellent overview of recent work on the relationship between liberalism and imperialism,
see D. Bell, Reordering the World: Essays on Liberalism and Empire (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2016) ch 2.
23 For a similar but broader point, see S. E. Merry, ‘From Law and Colonialism to Law and
Globalization’ (2003) 28 L & Soc Inquiry 569.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
743
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
as articulated in LOTC, served as a liberal apology for the British Empire. The
article then turns to fissures within the edifice of Dicey’s liberal imperialism:
first, by focusing on moments when Dicey was forced to confront the potential incompatibilities between the rule of law and the rule of empire; and
second, by showing how a culturalist critique of liberal imperialism at times
undermined Dicey’s confidence in imposing the rule of law on ‘uncivilised’
peoples.
THE RULE OF LAW AS CIVILISATIONAL ACHIEVEMENT
Dicey was one of the leading legal scholars of late nineteenth century Britain,
as well as a well-known ‘public moralist’ of a Liberal – and after 1886, a Liberal
Unionist – persuasion.24 It was while serving as Vinerian Professor of English
Law at Oxford from 1882 to 1909 that Dicey wrote his most influential academic works: LOTC, a treatise on private international law, and a historical
study of English law and its relationship to public opinion in the nineteenth
century.25 While Dicey has often and with good justification been pegged
as a classic practitioner of a formalistic analytic jurisprudence, his methods
were less pure and more eclectic than this, displaying repeated (and sometimes
criticised) engagement with historical and comparative approaches in particular.26 As a public intellectual, Dicey reviewed books prodigiously and wrote
extensively on the controversies of his day in periodicals and several books.27
Inclined towards a liberal Radicalism in his youth, Dicey, like many Victorian
intellectuals, became markedly more Whiggish – even conservative – in later
life, tenaciously keeping faith with laissez faire individualism in an increasingly
collectivist world while exhibiting a growing scepticism of democracy in a
democratising world.28 In the Liberal split over Irish Home Rule in 1886,
Dicey followed the Liberal Unionists and quickly established himself as one
of the most visible and forthright intellectual forces opposed to Home Rule,
producing screed after screed attacking each fresh iteration of the idea.29 As the
twentieth century moved into its second decade, an elderly Dicey, while maintaining an enduring commitment to liberal values, was also espousing a range
24 S. Collini, Public Moralists: Political Thought and Intellectual Life in Britain, 1850–1930 (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1991) 287–301. See further R. A. Cosgrove, The Rule of Law: Albert Venn
Dicey, Victorian Jurist (Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Harvie, n 18
above.
25 Dicey, n 5 above; A. V. Dicey, A Digest of the Law of England with Reference to the Conflict of Laws
(London: Stevens & Sons, 1896); A. V. Dicey, Lectures on the Relation Between Law and Public
Opinion in England During the Nineteenth Century (London: Macmillan and Co, 1905).
26 M. D. Walters, ‘Dicey on Writing the Law of the Constitution’ (2012) 32 OJLS 21; J. W. F. Allison,
‘History in the Law of the Constitution’ (2007) 28 Journal of Legal History 263; Allison, n 6 above,
7–14, ch 7. For the conventional view of Dicey, see, for example, Cosgrove, n 24 above, 23–28;
Sugarman, n 20 above, 104–110.
27 Collini, n 24 above, 287–301.
28 See further Cosgrove, n 24 above; Hibbits, n 9 above, 12–18; J. Roach, ‘Liberalism and the
Victorian Intelligentsia’ (1957) 13 Cambridge Historical Journal 58; Harvie, n 18 above, chs 8–9.
29 H. Tulloch, ‘A.V. Dicey and the Irish Question, 1870–1922’ (1980) 15 IJ 137; Cosgrove, ibid,
especially chs 6–7, 10.
744
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
of reactionary views, including the denial of women’s suffrage and extreme
measures to thwart Home Rule.30
In keeping with his strident Unionism, Dicey was also, at least from the
mid-1870s, a faithful imperialist, committed to maintaining the unity of the
British Empire.31 This attitude reflected a wider growth in imperial sentiment
during the late-Victorian era – a shift that Dicey, ever the astute observer of
public opinion, himself diagnosed.32 As will be outlined in greater detail below,
Dicey’s imperialism was in large degree a liberal imperialism: he saw the British
Empire as a vital means of spreading English liberty, order, justice and peace
around the globe.33 Dicey also embraced the British Empire as a necessary basis
for British self-preservation in a world of imperial states, as well as a patriotic
project of national greatness.34
Turning to Dicey’s account of the rule of law, his classic treatment in LOTC
separated the idea – at heart ‘the security given under the English constitution
to the rights of individuals’ – into three analytically distinct senses.35 The first
was rule through law: government was to be carried out in accordance with
legally established procedures and norms rather than by way of unrestrained
and potentially arbitrary power.36 In its second sense, the rule of law meant
that ‘every man, whatever be his rank or condition, is subject to the ordinary
law of the realm and amenable to the jurisdiction of the ordinary tribunals.’37
This was a norm of formal equality before the law, especially as applied to
government officials, who were not to be given special dispensations from the
ordinary law of the land, such as the rules of tort and criminal law.38 Third, the
rule of law consisted of individual rights established through the bottom-up,
case-by-case process of common-law development, rather than by a top-down
declaration in a codified constitution.39
Like his account of the British Constitution generally, Dicey’s account of
the rule of law reflected a well-established ‘whig’ interpretation of British constitutional history.40 The trajectory of that history was towards ever-greater
individual liberty, which in Dicey’s account was manifest in the curtailment of
arbitrary executive power through its subjection to parliamentary sovereignty,
the rule of law and unwritten constitutional conventions. Dicey’s rule of law,
especially in its third sense as the product of slow and steady common-law
30 On women’s suffrage, see A. V. Dicey, Letters to a Friend on Votes for Women (London: John
Murray, 1909). On Home Rule, see the discussion below.
31 Lino, n 16 above, 761–764. For an early expression of scepticism about the value of large imperial
states like the German Confederation, see A. V. Dicey, ‘The Influence of an Historical Idea’
(1864) 11 Macmillan’s Magazine 155, 160.
32 Lino, ibid, 757–758. See further D. Bell, The Idea of Greater Britain: Empire and the Future of World
Order, 1860–1900 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007).
33 See also, Lino, ibid, 762–763.
34 ibid, 763.
35 Dicey, n 5 above, 168.
36 ibid, 172.
37 ibid, 177–178.
38 ibid, 178 (discussing this as ‘the idea of legal equality’), 207 (‘equality before the law’).
39 ibid, 208.
40 W. I. Jennings, ‘In Praise of Dicey, 1885–1935’ (1935) 13 Public Administration 123, 130–133;
W. I. Jennings, The Law and the Constitution (London: University of London Press, 3rd ed, 1943)
285–297; Allison, n 6 above, 165–184.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
745
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
development, tapped into whig histories of progressive and continuous
English constitutional growth.41 Unlike in France – bête noire of the ‘diffused
Burkeanism’ in nineteenth-century British political thought and historiography – constitutional rights and principles in Britain were the product of gradual
accumulation rather than quixotic revolutionary declaration, grounded in the
political and legal life of the people rather than theoretical abstraction divorced
from society.42 In England, said Dicey, the rule of law was so embedded in
society that it ‘could hardly be destroyed without a thorough revolution in the
institutions and manners of the nation’.43
Along with reflecting a whig interpretation of the British Constitution,
Dicey’s account of a rule of law achieved through slow accretion also tied in
with notions of ‘civilisation’.44 The concept of civilisation was widely used in
the nineteenth century by European thinkers as a framework for understanding
differences between societies.45 The idea of civilisation typically envisioned a
universal process of historical development, a common trajectory along which
societies progressed (if they were not stationary). As Dicey articulated it in
a 1902 lecture on ancient and modern constitutionalism, a civilised society
possessed a state; it had moved beyond the Darwinian ‘struggle for existence’
involved in fighting off animal and human enemies and meeting basic material
needs; it had ‘acquired the arts and knowledge which contribute to the ease and
comfort of life’; and its ‘leading members possess intellectual cultivation and
are acquainted with art, science, and letters’.46 In its late nineteenth century
uses, including by Dicey, civilisation was generally a hierarchical concept, with
different societies ranked according to their level of civilisation.47 Thinkers
typically made a broad distinction between civilised and uncivilised societies –
generally mapping onto the distinction between European societies (and their
settler-colonial offshoots) and non-European societies – as well as finer-grained
rankings within those broad categories.48
41 Dicey, n 5 above, 208–215.
42 On Dicey’s ‘diffused Burkeanism’, see Collini, n 24 above, 293; and see further S. Collini, D.
Winch and J. Burrow, That Noble Science of Politics: A Study in Nineteenth-Century Intellectual
History (Cambridge: CUP, 1983) 20–21, ch 6; E. Jones, Edmund Burke and the Invention of
Modern Conservatism, 1830–1914: An Intellectual History (Oxford: OUP, 2017). For Dicey’s
manifestation of this attitude, see Dicey, ibid, especially 211–212. Dicey further elaborated on
‘historical constitutions’ such as Britain’s (extensively contrasted with France’s ‘non-historical
constitution’) in his 1900 lectures on comparative constitutionalism: A. V. Dicey, The Oxford
Edition of Dicey: Comparative Constitutionalism vol 2 (Oxford: OUP, J. W. F. Allison ed, 2013) 171–
191. France figures heavily in Dicey’s account of the rule of law, invariably to prove by negative
contrast England’s superior possession of the rule of law: see Allison, n 6 above, 172–184. For an
excellent contextualisation of Dicey’s thinking within a long tradition of common-law thought,
going back to the sixteenth-century discourse of ‘ancient constitutionalism’, see Walters, n 13
above, 57–65.
43 Dicey, n 5 above, 214.
44 Lino, n 16 above, 764–765. cf Tulloch, n 29 above, 145.
45 D. Bell, ‘Empire and Imperialism’ in G. S. Jones and G. Claeys (eds), The Cambridge History of
Nineteenth-Century Political Thought (Cambridge: CUP, 2011) 867–872; P. Mandler, ‘“Race” and
“Nation” in Mid-Victorian Thought’ in S. Collini, R. Whatmore and B. Young (eds), History,
Religion, and Culture: British Intellectual History, 1750–1950 (Cambridge: CUP, 2000).
46 Dicey, n 42 above, 196–197.
47 Bell, n 45 above, 867.
48 ibid.
746
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
For Dicey, a society’s civilisational progress was fundamentally intertwined
with its stage of legal development.49 This idea – of a connection between civilisational attainment and legal development – was longstanding and widespread
in British and European political and legal thought.50 In mid-Victorian Britain,
the supposed correspondence between civilisational and legal development had
been most prominently traced, in historical fashion, by Henry Maine, especially
in his enormously influential Ancient Law (1861).51 According to Maine, the
law of a given society was an index of progress along a more or less universal
continuum from uncivilised to civilised. Though Dicey was not a classical practitioner of the historical and comparative methods that Maine did so much to
popularise, and indeed was at times critical of those methods, he was undoubtedly influenced by their underlying intellectual premises.52 As Dicey observed
in an 1883 review of Maine’s Dissertations on Early Law and Custom, Maine had
forcefully and persuasively pressed a point hitherto overlooked by historians:
namely, ‘the close connection between the legal and political development of
the nation’.53 Reviewing another of Maine’s books three years later, Dicey observed that ‘[s]ince Maine’s “Ancient Law” appeared, every thinker or historian
of average intelligence has become conscious of the fact that a nation’s law is
the record of a nation’s genius’.54
The rule of law was, according to Dicey, a distinctive accomplishment of
the English people, placing them at the pinnacle of civilisation. As several
historians have emphasised, Dicey played an influential intellectual role in
the late nineteenth century in connecting English national character with
lawfulness, especially through his account of the rule of law.55 In Dicey’s very
first treatment of the rule of law – penned in an 1875 review of William Stubbs’s
Constitutional History of England – he waxed lyrical over
that rule of the severe but always fixed and definite law which is the real glory of
English institutions, and which, in ages when arbitrary government was universally
established throughout the rest of Europe, made the English constitution, with all
49 Lino, n 16 above, 764–765.
50 See, for example, B. Bowden, The Empire of Civilization: The Evolution of an Imperial Idea (Chicago,
Ill: University of Chicago Press, 2009) ch 5.
51 H. S. Maine, Ancient Law: Its Connection with the Early History of Society, and Its Relation to Modern
Ideas (London: J Murray, 1861). See further G. Feaver, From Status to Contract: A Biography of
Sir Henry Maine (London: Longmans, 1969); R. Cocks, Sir Henry Maine: A Study in Victorian
Jurisprudence (Cambridge: CUP, 1988); K. Mantena, Alibis of Empire: Henry Maine and the Ends
of Liberal Imperialism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010).
52 See [A. V. Dicey], ‘Stubbs’s Constitutional History of England’ (1875) 20 Nation 152, 152; [A.
V. Dicey], ‘Maine’s Early History of Institutions’ (1875) 20 Nation 225; [A. V. Dicey], ‘The
Influence of India on English Opinion’ (1876) 22 Nation 82; [A. V. Dicey], ‘Maine’s Early Law
and Custom—I’ (1883) 37 Nation 165; [A. V. Dicey], ‘Maine’s Early Law and Custom—II’
37 Nation 187; [A. V. Dicey], ‘Maine’s Popular Government—I’ (1886) 42 Nation 263; [A.
V. Dicey], ‘Maine’s Popular Government—II’ (1886) 42 Nation 281; A. V. D. [A. V. Dicey],
‘Book Review’ (1886) 2 LQR 88, 88–89; Dicey, Law and Public Opinion n 25 above, 411–412,
455–462.
53 Dicey, ‘Maine’s Early Law and Custom—I’, ibid, 165.
54 Dicey, ‘Maine’s Popular Government—I’ n 52 above, 264.
55 Collini, n 24 above, 287–301; J. Stapleton, ‘Dicey and His Legacy’ (1995) 16 History of Political
Thought 234, 234–239.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
747
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
its obvious defects, seem the most beautiful phenomenon in the history of mankind
to all statesmen and theorists interested in the welfare of the human species.56
Such sentiments, which Dicey continued to espouse into later life, were of a
piece with the sense of English superiority that marked the Victorian era.57
They were also commonplace in the British legal scholarship of the time.58
As Dicey went on to spell out in the first edition of LOTC, the rule of
law had emerged within England before any other state, having prevailed ‘at
all times since the Norman Conquest’.59 Whereas England had before the end
of the sixteenth century ‘passed through that stage of development . . . when
nobles, priests, and others could defy the law’, it took most other European
nations two more centuries to achieve the same feat.60 Against a common
belief that the rule of law was ‘a trait common to every civilised and orderly
state’, Dicey insisted that it was, at least in its most developed form, ‘peculiar
to England, or to those countries which, like the United States of America,
have inherited English traditions’.61 This differential attainment of the rule
of law was, of course, a distinction between those peoples characterised as
civilised; it was a distinction even more marked between the English and
‘the fanciful caprice of the torments inflicted by Oriental despotism’.62 As
Dicey remarked in an 1898 article on the legal relations between England
and America, ‘the spirit of legalism’ was ‘the main point on which the AngloSaxon race has reached a stage of civilization to which other nations have hardly
attained’.63
THE RULE OF LAW AS JUSTIFICATION FOR EMPIRE
The unique attainment of the rule of law by the British – and their capacity to
spread its blessings of order and liberty abroad – furnished, in Dicey’s view, one
56 Dicey, ‘Stubbs’s Constitutional History of England’ n 52 above, 154. Hibbits has identified a
fleeting earlier reference by Dicey to ‘the rule of regular law and the abolition of torture’ in his
1860 essay on the Privy Council, subsequently published in 1887: A. V. Dicey, The Privy Council
(London: Macmillan & Co, 1887) 130–131, cited in Hibbits, n 9 above, 24 n 82.
57 See, for example, P. Mandler, The English National Character: The History of an Idea from Edmund
Burke to Tony Blair (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006) chs 3–4. Compare LOTC,
where Dicey styled himself not as an apologist or eulogist for the Constitution but simply as its
expounder: see Dicey, n 5 above, 1–4.
58 D. Sugarman, ‘“A Hatred of Disorder”: Legal Science, Liberalism and Imperialism’ in
P. Fitzpatrick (ed), Dangerous Supplements: Resistance and Renewal in Jurisprudence (Durham, NC:
Duke University Press, 1991) 34, 57.
59 Dicey, n 5 above, 167. Dicey seems to have taken this idea from William Stubbs: see Dicey,
‘Stubbs’s Constitutional History of England’ n 52 above, 154; J. W. Burrow, A Liberal Descent:
Victorian Historians and the English Past (Cambridge: CUP, 1981) 138–144.
60 Dicey, n 5 above, 179. See also Dicey’s new Notes in the sixth edition on French droit administratif
– which he originally understood as proof of Continental lawlessness but subsequently presented
as the nineteenth-century growth of that stage of lawfulness achieved in England several centuries
earlier: A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (London: Macmillan
and Co, 6th ed, 1902) 485–502.
61 Dicey, n 5 above, 172.
62 ibid, 176. On the idea of Oriental despotism, see Hussain, n 14 above, 44–55.
63 A. V. Dicey, ‘England and America’ (1898) 82 Atlantic Monthly 441, 444.
748
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
of the chief justifications for the British Empire.64 Here Dicey was working
within a well-established intellectual tradition that posited English lawfulness
as a central normative pillar for colonial rule.65 Dicey’s imperialism was in large
part a liberal imperialism (albeit a complex and ambiguous one, as later sections
of this paper will demonstrate). ‘The maintenance of the British Empire’,
Dicey observed in his 1905 book Lectures on the Relation Between Law and Public
Opinion in England During the Nineteenth Century, ‘makes it possible, at a cost
which is relatively small, compared with the whole number of British subjects,
to secure peace, good order, and personal freedom throughout a large part of
the world’.66
In his journalism, Dicey penned paeans to the magnificent imperial diffusion
of English law and liberty throughout the globe. A common comparator was
the Roman Empire. An 1875 article speculated that English law, ‘the most
original creation of English genius’, would be, ‘like the law of Rome, the most
permanent record both in East and West of the greatness of its creators.’67 In
an 1897 article proposing, as the title put it, ‘A Common Citizenship for the
English Race’ between England and the US, Dicey observed:
When at some distant period thinkers sum up the results of English as they now sum
up the results of Grecian or of Roman civilisation, they will, we may anticipate,
hold that its main permanent effect has been the diffusion throughout the whole
world of the law of England, together with those notions of freedom, of justice,
and of equity to which English law gives embodiment.68
Only Rome could rival England ‘in the capacity for establishing her own law
in strange lands’, a capacity revealed in India through the codification project
undertaken there by British officials.69 This was a view Dicey also expressed in
private, telling his American friend Oliver Wendell Holmes in 1900 that ‘I am
more and more convinced that to spread English ideas of law and justice is the
one vocation of the English people as it will probably be our one permanent
achievement’.70 The rule of law was, it seemed, destined for successful export
through British imperialism, and one of the primary rationales underlying that
imperialism.
Dicey’s liberal vision of empire led him at times to denounce British policies
that he believed threatened the rule of law in the imperial periphery. For
instance, in an 1883 article titled ‘The Prevalence of Lawlessness in England’ –
penned in the same year Dicey began writing LOTC – Dicey singled out
for especial critique the departure from the rule of law in India presaged by
64
65
66
67
68
See further Lino, n 16 above, 762–763.
Hussain, n 14 above, 3–5.
Dicey, Law and Public Opinion n 25 above, 453.
[A. V. Dicey], ‘Digby on the History of English Law’ (1875) 21 Nation 373, 373.
A. V. Dicey, ‘A Common Citizenship for the English Race’ (1897) 71 The Contemporary Review
457, 470. See further D. Bell, ‘Beyond the Sovereign State: Isopolitan Citizenship, Race and
Anglo-American Union’ (2014) 62 Political Studies 418.
69 Dicey, n 68 above, 470.
70 Letter from A. V. Dicey to O. W. Holmes, Jr 3 April 1900 at http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn3:HLS.Libr:5348002?n=42 (last accessed 9 January 2018).
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
749
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
the so-called ‘Ilbert Bill crisis’.71 The controversy centred upon legislation put
forward by Courtenay Ilbert, Law Member of the Viceroy’s Executive Council,
which sought to subject white British subjects in India to the jurisdiction of
Indian magistrates. According to Dicey, who supported the Ilbert Bill, at stake
in the debate was
whether our government of India shall or shall not be carried on upon the principle
that a native of Bengal is as truly a British subject as a native of Middlesex, and that
the aim of our English rule should be ultimately to place all subjects of the Queen
in a position of legal equality. Whenever this is accomplished the rule of law will
prevail throughout the whole British Empire.72
He criticised those Conservatives who believed that British rule in India ought
to be based
upon force, upon privilege, upon that kind of permanent inequality of classes
which is absolutely opposed to the true supremacy of legality, which is but another
name for systematic justice.73
Forming a backdrop to Dicey’s rule of law were mid-century rebellions within
the colonies, which had raised questions of law and lawlessness to especial
prominence in Victorian political consciousness.74 The 1857 Indian Rebellion
and the severe British military force deployed in response were part of that story.
Dicey saw these developments as seminal to modern English and European
history, when England’s imperial greatness was rescued from potential ruin.75
On one occasion, he likened Lord Canning, the Indian Governor-General
during the rebellion, to Abraham Lincoln – ‘[t]he one saved the unity of the
British Empire, the other the unity of the United States’ – and ascribed their
success and virtue to a trust in law and exercise of mercy over unrestrained
violence.76 But he elsewhere acknowledged the brutality and severe force that
had accompanied the British response to the revolt, thereby raising questions
as to the compatibility of the rule of law with empire.77
Another event that, as Rande Kostal has shown, demonstrated the centrality
of law to Victorian England was the 1865 Morant Bay rebellion and its violent
crushing under martial law – ‘lawless suppression’ as Dicey called it some two
decades later – by Jamaican Governor Edward Eyre.78 The actions of Eyre and
71 A. V. D. [A. V. Dicey], ‘The Prevalence of Lawlessness in England’ (1883) 37 Nation 95. See
further E. Hirschmann, “White Mutiny”: The Ilbert Bill Crisis in India and the Genesis of the Indian
National Congress (New Delhi: Heritage, 1980).
72 Dicey, ibid, 96.
73 ibid.
74 A. W. B. Simpson, Leading Cases in the Common Law (Oxford: OUP, 1996) 228–229. See also
Kostal, n 14 above.
75 [A. V. Dicey], ‘Green’s “History of the English People” – II’ (1880) 31 Nation 188, 188; [A. V.
Dicey], ‘Thirty Years of European History – I’ (1890) 51 Nation 327, 327.
76 Dicey, n 68 above, 471–472.
77 Dicey, ‘Green’s “History of the English People” – II’, n 75 above, 188; A. V. Dicey, ‘What is the
State of English Opinion About Ireland?’ (1882) 34 Nation 95, 96; A. V. Dicey, ‘English Popular
Opinion About Egypt’ (1882) 35 Nation 418, 419.
78 Kostal, n 14 above; A. V. Dicey, ‘Ireland and Victoria’ (1886) 49 The Contemporary Review 169,
173.
750
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
other British officials, which resulted in the killing of over 400 black Jamaicans,
became an English cause célèbre, with various criminal and civil proceedings
unsuccessfully attempting to hold the perpetrators accountable.79 Playing the
pivotal role in seeking to bring Eyre to justice for what were seen as unlawful
and unconstitutional actions was the Jamaica Committee, established and led by
a mixture of evangelicals and high-profile Liberals and Radicals, among them
John Stuart Mill and John Bright.80 Dicey himself, at the time a young mover
in Liberal circles, paid a subscription to the Jamaica Committee in 1867 and
provided legal advice to one of the controversy’s more senior protagonists.81
Dicey’s cousin and legal luminary James Fitzjames Stephen was retained by
the Committee to advise on privately prosecuting Eyre and others.82 In the
eventual prosecution of several of the figures, Stephen put the legal question
as ‘whether law was to be paramount within the British Empire, or whether
officers could set aside the law and establish a military despotism with power
of life and death’.83 That none of the criminal or civil proceedings ultimately
succeeded could seem, at least for their proponents, to suggest the latter.
More proximate to when and where Dicey was writing LOTC was the
battle by British authorities to contain civil and political unrest in Ireland.
Simmering since the middle of the nineteenth century, Irish agrarian and
nationalist struggles came to a head in the sustained agitation of the Land
War between 1879–82.84 Gladstone’s Liberal Government responded with the
Protection of Person and Property (Ireland) Act 1881 (UK), which for an 18-month
period enabled executive detention without trial of anyone who the Lord
Lieutenant declared to be suspected of treason or crimes undermining law and
order.85 This legislation was the latest but by no means the last in a lengthy list
of ‘Coercion Acts’ passed throughout the century to quell Irish unrest.86
In an extended 1882 article titled ‘How is the Law to be Enforced in Ireland?’, Dicey condemned the 1881 Coercion Act as arbitrary and despotic,
no better than the public disorder it was supposed to correct.87 ‘To oppose
despotism to anarchy is in reality to pit one kind of lawlessness against another’, he proclaimed.88 Dicey favoured the restoration of ordinary law, albeit
accompanied by the partial abolition of jury trial – a ‘grave inroad on constitutional traditions’, Dicey admitted, but a necessary measure for overcoming the
79 See B. Semmel, Jamaican Blood and Victorian Conscience: The Governor Eyre Controversy (Boston,
Mass: Houghton Mifflin, 1962); C. Hall, Civilising Subjects: Metropole and Colony in the English
Imagination, 1830–1867 (Cambridge: Polity, 2002); J. Evans, Edward Eyre, Race and Colonial
Governance (Dunedin: University of Otago Press, 2005) chs 7–8; Kostal, ibid.
80 Semmel, ibid, 62–65.
81 ibid, 117; Kostal, n 14 above, 456.
82 Kostal, ibid, 46, 48–53.
83 James Fitzjames Stephen, quoted in Hussain, n 14 above, 5.
84 P. Bew, Land and the National Question in Ireland 1858–82 (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1978);
R. F. Foster, Modern Ireland 1600–1972 (London: Allen Lane, 1988) 402–415.
85 Bew, ibid, 145–155; C. Townshend, Political Violence in Ireland: Government and Resistance Since
1848 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983) 136–137.
86 Townshend, ibid, 55–66; A. W. B. Simpson, Human Rights and the End of Empire (Oxford: OUP,
2001) 78–80.
87 A. V. Dicey, ‘How is the Law to be Enforced in Ireland?’ (1881) 30 The Fortnightly Review 537.
See also A. V. Dicey, England’s Case Against Home Rule (London: John Murray, 1886) 110–121.
88 Dicey, ‘How is the Law to be Enforced in Ireland?’, ibid, 541.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
751
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
partiality of Irish juries towards agrarian agitators.89 While jury trial would
indeed be partially abolished later in 1882 by the Prevention of Crime (Ireland)
Act 1882 (UK), so too would a range of other protections of individual liberty,
in what was one of the most far-reaching Coercion Acts to date.90
If these and other suppressions of rebellion in the imperial periphery suggested a tenuous foothold for the rule of law in the constitutional space outside the metropole, Dicey’s original account in LOTC overwhelmingly suggested otherwise. His analysis was peppered with cases and examples from the
Empire – as, for instance, when substantiating his argument that the rule of
law emerged through the accretion of common-law precedent.91 To demonstrate that the rule of law as formal equality ‘had been pushed to its utmost
limit’ under the British Constitution, Dicey explained that colonial governors
were, like ordinary citizens, accountable for their unlawful actions.92 He cited
cases from British possessions in Senegal and Spain as well as a recent Jamaican
case – though not, notably, any of the Eyre proceedings.93 Military officers too,
Dicey maintained, were amenable to regular legal processes from one end of the
British Empire to the other, whether ‘in England or in Van Diemen’s Land’.94
The ‘Jamaica affair’ of some two decades earlier loomed large in the background of LOTC’s treatment of the rule of law.95 In discussing the subjection
of military officers to the ordinary law of the land, Dicey cited in support the
1870 civil action against Governor Eyre for his conduct during the rebellion,
despite the fact that the action had failed.96 The reason why the civil case
against Eyre had failed was that the Jamaican legislature had passed an Act of
Indemnity protecting him. But this parliamentary intervention Dicey held up
as the ‘legalisation of illegality’ and so an instantiation of the rule of law.97 If
the Act of Indemnity covering Eyre’s actions contrasted with the ‘moderateness’ of Acts of Indemnity passed at Westminster, it was nonetheless far from
the lawlessness of martial law.98 Martial law, Dicey confidently declared, was
‘unknown to the law of England’, at least insofar as martial law meant ‘the
suspension of the ordinary law and the temporary government . . . by military
tribunals’.99
In examining martial law, Dicey adopted the Liberal line taken by Fitzjames
Stephen in arguing the early Jamaica affair prosecutions: during times of public
emergency, the common law continued at all times to govern and constrain
89 ibid, 547.
90 See further Townshend, n 85 above, 172–180.
91 Dicey, n 5 above, 208 n 2. Of the four cases cited by Dicey to make this point at the outset of
his discussion, two – Campbell v Hall (1774) 1 Cowp 204, relating to Grenada, and Mostyn v
Fabrigas (1774) 1 Cowp 161, relating to Minorca – were colonial.
92 Dicey, ibid, 178.
93 ibid, 178 n 1. The cases were Mostyn v Fabrigas n 91 above; Governor Wall’s Case (1802) 28 St Tr
51; Musgrave v Pulido (1879) 5 App Cas 102.
94 Dicey, n 5 above, 306–307, 178.
95 Simpson, n 74 above, 228–229; Kostal, n 14 above, 456–458; Dyzenhaus, n 16 above, 10.
96 Phillips v Eyre (1870) LR 6 QB 1, cited in Dicey, n 5 above, 178 n 3. See further Kostal, ibid,
450; P. Handford, ‘Edward John Eyre and the Conflict of Laws’ (2008) 32 MULR 822.
97 Dicey, ibid, 249. For a critical but ultimately supportive account of Dicey’s argument, see
Dyzenhaus, n 16 above.
98 Dicey, ibid, 249–250.
99 ibid, 249–250, 294–295.
752
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
the actions of public officials.100 Violence meted out by agents of the Crown
to suppress unrest could be lawful, even legally required, but only if it satisfied
the quite stringent common-law defence of necessity.101 At a time when the
status of martial law remained deeply uncertain, this was a partisan move on the
side of the Jamaica Committee to which Dicey had subscribed in his younger
days.102 Dicey was utterly dismissive of the alternative arguments – promulgated
by Eyre’s largely Conservative defenders during the Jamaica controversy, and
reflected in the jurisprudence of Continental countries like France – that martial
law allowed for the law to be wholly suspended.103 To borrow a line that FH
Lawson applied to LOTC overall, ‘[h]aving come down on one side of the
fence, he acted as though there had never been any fence at all’.104
As to the situation in Ireland, Dicey’s brief discussions in LOTC presented
only a partial exception to his portrayal of imperial peripheries firmly under
the rule of law. LOTC contained a succinct account of how the ‘extraordinary
powers’ conferred by the 1881 and 1882 Coercion Acts had departed from
the rule of law in one of its key applications, the right to personal freedom.105
This implied critique was consistent with Dicey’s earlier writings denouncing
the ‘lawlessness’ of British efforts to suppress Irish political and agrarian unrest
using coercion.106
But this brief treatment of contemporary British despotism in Ireland was
subsumed within Dicey’s broader, repeated affirmation of the uniquely lawgoverned character of the British Empire, and it was also offset by LOTC’s
other discussions of Ireland.107 Thus, as one of his main examples of martial
law’s constitutional foreignness to Britain, Dicey lauded Wolfe Tone’s Case,108
a decision of the Irish King’s Bench issued during the failed 1798 Irish rebellion.109 The decision concerned Wolfe Tone, an Irish rebel leader captured
during the unrest and sentenced to death by court-martial, even though he
was not a British officer. Upon a legal challenge to Tone’s detention, the Irish
King’s Bench granted habeas corpus. Dicey’s account of the case, as J. W. F.
Allison has noted, was highly selective and formalist: Dicey failed to acknowledge that, by the time habeas corpus was granted, Tone had cut his throat,
could not be safely moved and would die a week later still in prison.110 For
Dicey, Wolfe Tone’s Case demonstrated ‘the noble energy with which judges
100 ibid, 294–301. See Kostal, n 14 above, 9–10, ch 5, 456–457.
101 Dicey, ibid, 295–298.
102 On the uncertain legal status of martial law in this period, see Kostal, n 14 above, 9–10; C.
Townshend, ‘Martial Law: Legal and Administrative Problems of Civil Emergency in Britain
and the Empire, 1800–1940’ (1982) 25 The Historical Journal 167, 167–176.
103 Dicey, n 5 above, 294–295, 298–300. See further Poole, n 16 above, 199–202; Kostal, ibid,
228–245, 415–427, 456–458; Townshend, ibid, 167–176.
104 F. H. Lawson, ‘Dicey Revisited’ (1959) 7 Political Studies 109, 113.
105 Dicey, n 5 above, 243–244.
106 Dicey, ‘How is the Law to be Enforced in Ireland?’, n 87 above.
107 For a related point, see I. C. Fletcher, ‘“This Zeal for Lawlessness”: AV Dicey, The Law of the
Constitution, and the Challenge of Popular Politics, 1885–1915’ (1997) 16 Parliamentary History
309, 318.
108 (1798) 27 St Tr 614.
109 Dicey, n 5 above, 300–301. See further Foster, n 84 above, ch 12, especially 278–282.
110 Allison, n 6 above, 160–161.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
753
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
have maintained the rule of regular law, even at periods of revolutionary violence’: there was ‘no more splendid assertion of the supremacy of law’.111
Compared with the more arbitrary methods of British rule in contemporary
Ireland discussed earlier in LOTC, the case presented a marked – and perhaps
an intentionally critical – contrast. But it also reasserted Dicey’s dominant message: that the rule of law ran throughout Britain and the many lands under its
sovereignty.
Overall, the impression Dicey conveyed in the original LOTC was of an
Empire under the constitutional sign of lawfulness. In keeping with Dicey’s own
liberal vision of the Empire, his account of the rule of law can be understood as
an apology for liberal imperialism. As David Sugarman has argued, the classical
British law textbook tradition – of which LOTC was a shining example –
also served a tutelary function: such works neatly packaged English law and its
underlying liberal principles for ready export to the colonies.112 While Dicey’s
account of the rule of law can be seen as an exercise in imperial justification and
colonial instruction, in largely overlooking the many departures from Dicey’s
own rule-of-law ideal within the British Empire, it was also an exercise in
wishful thinking.113
THE RULE OF LAW VERSUS THE RULE OF EMPIRE
If Dicey’s original edition of LOTC evaded the potential incompatibility between the rule of law and the rule of empire, there were moments in Dicey’s
career where he was compelled to confront that tension more directly. In these
moments, Dicey was faced with the reality that, to hold the Empire together,
the imperial centre might have to tolerate or initiate departures from the rule
of law in the periphery. For the most part, Dicey’s liberalism gave way, albeit
reluctantly, to his imperialism.
One major imperial challenge to Dicey’s rule of law occurred in the field
of martial law. Dicey’s rigidly liberal account of martial law was profoundly
tested by the jurisprudence that emerged from the Second Anglo–Boer War
of 1899–1902.114 Dicey himself was an enthusiastic supporter of the war and
was buoyed by the imperial sentiment it corralled among the British public
and in the colonies.115 The conflict was, he celebrated in 1903, ‘as much a war
for the unity of the Empire as the war against secession was a war for the
unity of the United States’.116 But what was the price of that imperial unity?
Would it be constitutionally permissible to purchase such unity by sacrificing
the rule of law? Emphatically suggesting an affirmative answer to that question
111 Dicey, n 5 above, 300–301.
112 Sugarman, n 58 above, 56–57; Sugarman, n 20 above, 107. On Dicey’s educative purposes in
writing LOTC more generally, see J. W. F. Allison, ‘Editor’s Introduction to Volume One’ in A.
V. Dicey, The Oxford Edition of Dicey: The Law of the Constitution vol 1 (Oxford: OUP, J. W. F.
Allison ed, 2013) xxiv–xlii.
113 M. Taggart, ‘Ruled by Law?’ (2006) 69 MLR 1006, 1025.
114 Townshend, n 102 above, 174–182; Dyzenhaus, n 16 above, 31–33; Poole, n 16 above, 202–206.
115 Cosgrove, n 24 above, 199–201.
116 A. V. Dicey, ‘To Unionists and Imperialists’ (1903) 84 The Contemporary Review 305, 311.
754
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
was the case of Ex parte Marais,117 a 1902 Privy Council decision arising from
the war.
The decision in Ex parte Marais delivered a serious blow to Dicey’s theory
of martial law. In Ex parte Marais, the Privy Council upheld the arrest and
detention of a civilian under martial-law regulations in the Cape Colony during wartime, and shielded such military actions from review by the ordinary
civilian courts, even where the courts were still functioning as normal.118 The
Privy Council also rebuffed the petitioner’s Diceyan attempt to test his detention against the stringent common-law standard of necessity.119 Notably, the
decision was delivered by Lord Chancellor Halsbury, who as a Conservativeaffiliated barrister had defended Governor Eyre in the prosecutions arising from
Eyre’s suppression of the Morant Bay rebellion.120
The Marais decision – having unsettled the harmonious vision of a lawgoverned Empire that Dicey had promulgated in earlier editions of LOTC –
occasioned a defensive and strained response from Dicey in his 1902 edition.
Drawing heavily on colonial legal materials which supported his own case,
especially materials relating to the Morant Bay prosecutions, Dicey appended
a lengthy new Note to his treatise which did its best to minimise the Marais
decision’s significance.121 He did so partly by advancing the narrowest possible
readings of Marais – a narrowness justified, Dicey strangely claimed, by ‘the very
width of the language’ in the judgment.122 Most significantly, Dicey relegated
the Marais decision to one that affected the rule of law in the colonies, rather
than the rule of law in England.123 Against his proud claim that martial law
was ‘unknown to the law of England’, Dicey was forced to admit in a footnote
that ‘[t]his statement has no reference to the law of any other country than
England, even though such country may form part of the British Empire’.124
In other words, the rule of law might just be held onto in the metropole, but if
rebellious colonies were to be held onto, the rule of law in those places might
have to be let go.
The tension between maintaining imperial rule and the rule of law could
manifest even in the most apparently loyal and ‘civilised’ parts of the British
Empire: the settler colonies. There, the tension arose primarily from the wide
powers of self-government conferred upon the settler colonies, powers accompanied by an increasingly strident imperial constitutional ethos of noninterference.125 If some statesmen had originally seen colonial self-government
as a step towards the colonies’ eventual independence, the watchword by the
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
C
[1902] AC 109.
ibid.
ibid, 110–111.
Townshend, n 102 above, 182; Kostal, n 14 above, 305–315, 382–389.
Dicey, n 60 above, 502–519. The decision was momentous enough to prompt a symposium in
the 1902 Law Quarterly Review, the contributions to which (by Frederick Pollock among others)
Dicey variously drew on and critiqued.
ibid, 510–511.
ibid, 283 n 3, 503, 511.
ibid, 283 n 3.
On the evolution of the settler colonies’ independence, see further J. M. Ward, Colonial
Self-Government: The British Experience, 1759–1856 (London: The Macmillan Press, 1976);
K. Roberts-Wray, Commonwealth and Colonial Law (London: Stevens & Sons, 1966) 247–257.
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
755
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
end of the nineteenth century was imperial unity.126 Somewhat paradoxically,
the tempering of the Imperial Government’s involvement in settler-colonial
governance came to be seen as the price of maintaining ultimate imperial
supremacy. With an eye to the lessons of the American War of Independence,
many British statesmen came to believe that if the bonds of empire were to be
sustained, the Imperial Government would have to grant the settler colonies
a wide latitude in governing their internal affairs, or even form an Imperial
Federation.127 Though a staunch opponent of Imperial Federation, Dicey was
a committed exponent of imperial unity, and lauded the laissez faire attitude
manifest in imperial constitutional arrangements as conducive to the Empire.128
But for Dicey, there was nonetheless a problem with these arrangements: the
settler colonies, liberated from the strict control of the Imperial Government,
could not always be trusted to uphold the rule of law.
One example of colonial lawlessness that Dicey railed against occurred in
Victoria in 1883. The Victorian Government had refused entry to several Irishmen attempting relocation to Victoria after implicating fellow Irish nationalists
in the 1882 murder of the Chief Secretary for Ireland and his undersecretary
in Dublin.129 In a series of letters to The Times in which he clashed with the
Agent-General of Victoria, Dicey denounced the Victorian Government’s actions as unlawful trespasses and assaults and an egregious departure from the
rule of law, which ought to run throughout the Empire as a whole.130 Victoria
was a constituent part of the Empire, and as such there was ‘no reason why the
law should be less respected at Melbourne than in London’.131
A censorious Dicey, reminding Victoria that upholding the ordinary law of
the land was one its ‘duties to the Crown, or, in other words, the whole Empire’, nevertheless pulled back from recommending a restoration of lawfulness
through imperial interference.132 The reason was that this would have violated
established constitutional convention and potentially undermined colonial allegiance to the Empire. As Dicey explained in an 1886 article, the system of
colonial self-government, though subject to the supreme sovereignty of the
Imperial Parliament, was ‘kept in tolerable working order by a series of understandings and mutual concessions’.133 The Victorian incident, Dicey observed,
showed that the rule of law could be an unfortunate casualty of the wide latitude necessarily conceded to the self-governing colonies to secure their loyalty.
‘[C]olonial independence’, he concluded, ‘is hardly consistent with that enforcement throughout the Crown’s dominions of due respect for law which is
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
756
See generally Bell, n 32 above.
ibid, 250–254.
Lino, n 16 above, 777–778.
See further, T. Corfe, The Phoenix Park Murders: Conflict, Compromise and Tragedy in Ireland,
1879–1882 (London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1968).
A. V. Dicey, ‘The Victorian Government and the Informers’, The Times (London), 2 October
1883, 12; A. V. Dicey, ‘The Victorian Government and the Informers’, The Times (London),
10 October 1883, 4; A. V. Dicey, ‘The Victorian Government and the Informers’, The Times
(London), 18 October 1883, 4.
Dicey, ‘The Victorian Government and the Informers’, 10 October 1883, ibid.
Dicey, ‘The Victorian Government and the Informers’, 18 October 1883, n 130 above.
Dicey, n 78 above, 172.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
the main justification for the existence of the British empire.’134 In order to
maintain the Empire, sometimes it was necessary for the metropole to acquiesce in settler-colonial violations of cherished British constitutional principle –
thereby undercutting the Empire’s raison d’être. Such sacrifices of the rule of
law relaxed imperial rule in order to shore up imperialism’s continuity.
Colonial violations of formal legal equality, especially when it came to discrimination against non-white British subjects, represented further departures
from the rule of law which too were – regrettably, thought Dicey – constitutionally shielded from imperial intervention. The late nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries had seen the establishment of a ‘global colour line’ throughout the British settler colonies and the United States: the construction of legal
regimes aimed at sustaining whiteness and excluding and suppressing racial
‘others’.135 These developments came to trouble Dicey’s liberal sensibility, including when they impinged on the rights of ‘uncivilised’ or ‘native’ British
subjects from India and elsewhere.136
In his Introduction to LOTC’s 1915 edition, Dicey lamented that the price
of imperial unity was British toleration of racial discrimination in the settler
colonies:
Events suggest that it may turn out difficult, or even impossible, to establish
throughout the Empire that equal citizenship of all British subjects which exists in
the United Kingdom and which Englishmen in the middle of the nineteenth century hoped to see established throughout the length and breadth of the Empire.137
The ‘events’ that he had in mind included the enactment of severe restrictions
on non-white (especially Asian) immigration in Australia and the Transvaal.138
That the Imperial Parliament had let these enactments stand demonstrated the
extent of settler-colonial independence under constitutional customs established to guarantee the settler colonies’ loyalty.139 Again, the virtuous British
standard of formal equality under the law had, lamentably, to be sacrificed for
the sake of sustaining ultimate imperial supremacy in the settler colonies.
But while Dicey generally tolerated colonial departures from the rule of law
only grudgingly, as the price of sustaining empire, he would himself come dangerously close to advocating official lawlessness to maintain imperial supremacy
in Ireland. The context was the fractious confrontation over the third Irish
134 ibid, 173.
135 M. Lake and H. Reynolds, Drawing the Global Colour Line: White Men’s Countries and the
International Challenge of Racial Equality (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 2008). See
also A. McKeown, Melancholy Order: Asian Migration and the Globalization of Borders (New York,
NY: Columbia University Press, 2008).
136 An Observer [A. V. Dicey], ‘Democratic Assumptions – IV’ 53 (1891) Nation 46, 47; A. V.
Dicey, ‘Mr Bryce on the Relations Between Whites and Blacks’ (1902) 75 Nation 26; R. F.
Shinn and R. A. Cosgrove (eds), Constitutional Reflections: The Correspondence of Albert Venn Dicey
and Arthur Berriedale Keith (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1996) 132–134, 161.
137 A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (London: Macmillan and Co,
8th ed, 1915) xxxvi.
138 ibid, 115 n 2. This footnote cites back to his discussion of the same issue in the Introduction at
xxxvi. See further McKeown, n 135 above, especially chs 5–7.
139 Dicey, n 137 above, 115 n 2.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
757
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
Home Rule Bill in 1911–14.140 Through his earlier writings opposing Home
Rule, Dicey had established a reputation as a strident but fair-minded Unionist,
committed to upholding the British Constitution and its underlying principles.141 However, Dicey’s writings on the Constitution could be – and were –
used in support of the Home Rule cause, a development which, as Hugh
Tulloch has argued, pressed Dicey into adopting ‘various stratagems to remove
those weapons he had initially handed over to his enemies’.142
As Home Rule became ever more likely from 1912, Dicey – the Constitution’s great expounder and defender – underwent a ‘gradual and painful
shift towards extremism’.143 Initially opposed to anything more than passive
resistance to Home Rule (such as withholding taxes), Dicey was by 1913 refusing to denounce armed resistance by militant Unionists in Ulster, and expressly
contemplating ‘recourse to the use of arms’ once ‘all possibility of legal resistance is exhausted’.144 Initially adamant about the British army’s legal duty to
enforce the law even against justified Ulster resistance, Dicey could by 1914 be
counted among those leading Unionist stalwarts publicly encouraging the army
to refuse the forceful imposition of Home Rule in Ulster.145 By sanctioning
army disobedience, Dicey willingly endorsed the very thing he had built his
reputation denouncing: official lawlessness. Recognising a clash between the
rule of law and the rule of empire, Dicey betrayed his own liberal ideals by
sacrificing the former for the sake of the latter.
THE RULE OF LAW AS IMPERIAL DOMINATION
If the practice of imperial rule could reveal incompatibilities with the rule of law,
it could also reveal imperial tendencies internal to the rule of law itself. Whereas
the notion of spreading the rule of law typically provided an apology for
empire – the civilising mission of bringing of order, freedom and justice to
‘uncivilised’ peoples – in practice, the transplantation of the rule of law in
distant lands could instead look a lot like straightforward domination. A key
part of the problem was the cultural specificity – or in Victorian terms, the
civilisational uniqueness – of the rule of law. In the latter half of the nineteenth century, British scholars and administrators increasingly recognised that
to spread British institutions and practices of governance among non-European
societies was to forcefully impose radical societal transformations which threatened the British Empire’s stability. While this ‘culturalist’ turn resulted not so
much in a wholesale critique of imperial rule as a shift in imperial governing strategy, it nonetheless destabilised the prevailing liberal justifications for
140 See A. O’Day, Irish Home Rule, 1867–1921 (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1998)
ch 9.
141 C. Harvie, ‘Ideology and Home Rule: James Bryce, AV Dicey and Ireland, 1880–1887’ (1976)
91 English Historical Review 298, 298–299, 301.
142 Tulloch, n 29 above, 137.
143 ibid, 161.
144 A. V. Dicey, A Fool’s Paradise: Being a Constitutionalist’s Criticism on the Home Rule Bill of 1912
(London: John Murray, 1913) 127; Tulloch, ibid, 161–162; Fletcher, n 107 above, 322–324.
145 Dicey conveyed his support for army subversion of Home Rule as one of the original signatories
of the British Covenant. See further Tulloch, ibid, 161–162; Fletcher, ibid, 324–326.
758
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
empire.146 The impact of this culturalist critique is discernible within Dicey’s
thinking about the rule of law.
Roughly from the 1820s through the 1850s, the predominant imperial
ideology for governing the British Empire’s non-European peoples centred
on a liberal civilising mission.147 On this front, India was the focus of reformist
zeal. Against an earlier approach to imperial rule that professed admiration for
Indian traditions and sought to preserve them, the liberal reformers – a mix of
evangelicals, free traders and utilitarians – saw Indian society as degraded and
in urgent need of improvement.148
For many liberal administrators, the engine of such civilisational progress
among the peoples of India was law.149 Accordingly, during this reformist era,
India would increasingly be governed by legal institutions based, apparently,
on the best European-derived practices and principles (though not, of course,
democracy). Under the sign of utilitarian ideas, this period saw extensive reforms to the British Indian administration and judiciary, to land tenure and
taxation, and to the criminal law through the Indian Penal Code.150 In part,
such reforms were developed and implemented by a succession of British liberal luminaries – including James Mill, Thomas Babington Macaulay and John
Stuart Mill – who held senior posts in the British Indian administration.151
However, after the 1857 Indian Rebellion, British imperial governance of
non-Europeans came to take on more of a culturalist bent, focused increasingly on preserving native traditions rather than the civilising mission.152 As
Karuna Mantena and Mahmood Mamdani have demonstrated, the pivotal figure inaugurating this shift in governing ideology was Henry Maine.153 Beyond
his immense influence as an academic and public intellectual during the midVictorian era, Maine also served as Law Member of the Viceroy’s Council in
India throughout much of the 1860s.154
Now more under the intellectual sway of Maine than Bentham, British
ideologies of imperial governance began to appreciate that the legal ideas and
institutions of ‘civilised’ societies, such as Britain, could not without danger be
transplanted to those societies supposedly much lower in the scale of civilisation,
such as India.155 According to Maine, imperial projects of liberal reform would,
in all likelihood, lead not to civilisational advancement for the governed but to
the too-rapid dissolution of native society and, potentially, to the dissolution
146 Mantena, n 51 above.
147 Stokes, n 15 above; T. R. Metcalf, Ideologies of the Raj (Cambridge: CUP, 1994) 28–43; ibid,
ch 1.
148 Stokes, ibid, ch 1; Mantena, n 51 above, 22–39; Metcalf, ibid, ch 1, 28–43.
149 Stokes, ibid, 55–80, ch 3; Metcalf, ibid, 35–39.
150 Stokes, ibid, chs 2–3.
151 ibid; C. Hall, Macaulay & Son: Architects of Imperial Britain (New Haven, Ct: Yale University
Press, 2012) ch 5; Mantena, n 51 above; L. Zastoupil, John Stuart Mill and India (Stanford. CA:
Stanford University Press, 1994).
152 Mantena, ibid; M. Mamdani, Define and Rule: Native as Political Identity (Cambridge, Mass:
Harvard University Press, 2012); Metcalf, n 147 above, 43–65.
153 Mantena, ibid; Mamdani, ibid, ch 1.
154 On Maine’s influence, see, for example, Feaver, n 51 above; A. Diamond (ed), The Victorian
Achievement of Sir Henry Maine: A Centennial Reappraisal (Cambridge: CUP, 1991). On Maine’s
time on the Viceroy’s Council, see further Feaver, ibid, 65–109.
155 Mantena, n 51 above.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
759
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
of the Empire.156 Maine’s ideas counselled an approach to imperial governance
that sought to conserve indigenous traditions and institutions, or at least arrest
their projected decay.157 While Maine’s own record as an administrator in India
did not always follow the logic of his intellectual contributions, Maine’s ideas
were formative for the generation of imperial administrators that followed him –
in India and beyond.158 Maine’s influence is especially evident in the latenineteenth century ascendance of ‘indirect rule’ as a strategy for governing
non-European peoples throughout the British Empire.159
Dicey’s outlook on imperial rule was impacted by this shift from liberal
reform to cultural accommodation, creating an ongoing tension in his thinking.160 From the mid-1870s, Dicey positively reviewed many of Maine’s writings, and took on board their lessons for the practice of imperial governance,
even as he continued to espouse liberal justifications for imperial rule.161 Reviewing Maine’s 1875 Rede Lecture – an influential contribution titled ‘The
Effects of the Observation of India on Modern European Thought’162 – Dicey
acknowledged that Maine had made plain the difficulty of applying utilitarian
principles to Indian society:
It may be true that the object of government ‘ought to be the greatest happiness
of the greatest number,’ but the application of this principle is difficult when the
sovereign and his subjects form diametrically different estimates of the nature of
happiness. . . . [A]n Englishman must find it hard to draw legitimate deductions
from it when called to rule a race governed by custom rather than by habits
generated by free competition, or to calculate what will be the conduct of men
who think it their ‘interest’ rather to starve than to eat food which might involve
a loss of caste.163
As Maine said in his lecture, he hoped that the study of Indian law would lead to
a ‘wholesome distrust’ of liberal reformism among those imperial administrators
‘who, guided solely by Western social experience, are too eager for innovations
which seem to them indistinguishable from improvements’.164 Maine’s hope
would be partly borne out in Dicey’s thinking.
While Dicey’s views on imperial rule would continue to be shaped by a
culturalist sensibility throughout his life, it was a particular concern of his
journalism in the early 1880s, a few years before LOTC was first published.165
156 ibid, 51–53,138–145.
157 ibid, 51–53.
158 On apparent inconsistencies between Maine’s ideas and his imperial policy-making, see Mantena,
ibid, 150–151. On Maine’s influence in imperial governance, see Mantena, ibid, ch 5; Mamdani,
n 152 above, chs 1–2.
159 Mantena, ibid, ch 5; Mamdani, ibid, chs 1–2; C. Kirkby, ‘Henry Maine and the Re-Constitution
of the British Empire’ (2012) 75 MLR 655.
160 Lino, n 16 above, 764–767.
161 See n 52 above; Lino, ibid, 764–765.
162 H. Maine, The Effects of the Observation of India on Modern European Thought (London: John
Murray, 1875). On the lecture and its influence, see Feaver, n 51 above, ch 12.
163 Dicey, ‘The Influence of India’, n 52 above, 83.
164 Maine, n 162 above, 37.
165 For a later manifestation of this attitude, see, for example, Dicey, n 42 above, 152–156. See also
Lino, n 16 above, 766–767.
760
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
Towards the end of 1882, in the aftermath of Gladstone’s military intervention
in Egypt, Dicey wrote about the inconsistent views of the English public on
Egypt’s future: they supported Egyptian self-government while also wanting to
impose ‘the standard of good administration which approves itself to English
ideas of justice’.166 Like the English public, Dicey himself also seemed torn,
reaching no firm conclusion as to whether Britain should extend or retrench its
intervention in Egypt. But he conceded much power to the idea, itself gaining
wider acceptance, ‘that even the best of European statesmen and administrators
injure rather than benefit Eastern races by forcing upon them the doubtful
blessings of a foreign form of civilization’.167
Writing at around the same time on the relations between England and Ireland, Dicey launched a similar culturalist critique of British rule in Ireland. One
of the primary causes of Irish discontent and ‘the fruitful source of a thousand
ills’ was that ‘England and Ireland have from the beginning of their ill-starred
connection been countries standing at a different level, or a different stage, of
civilization’.168 Dicey’s central example of this problem was the replacement
of Ireland’s customary tenures with English land law during James I’s reign. To
those imposing this change,
it must have appeared that to pass from the irregular dominion of uncertain customs
to the rule of clear, definite law, was little less than a transition from anarchy and
injustice to a condition of order and equity.169
The same attitude, Dicey said, prevailed in his own day, among those
who are absolutely assured that the extension of English maxims of government
throughout India must be a blessing to the population of the country, and are at this
moment shaping their Eastern policy upon their unwavering faith in the benefits
which the European Control must of necessity confer on the Egyptian peasants.170
But according to Dicey, the unreconstructed imposition of English law on
Ireland (and presumably on India and Egypt) ‘led to injustice, litigation, misery, and discontent’. The fundamental problem was that ‘[t]he rulers of the
country were influenced by ideas different from those of their subjects’.171
Though Dicey was certainly no advocate for Irish independence, neither was
he an uncritical apologist for the Union.172 Not entirely consistently, he could
attack the British administration for its failure to uphold the rule of law when
suppressing Irish discontent, while also attacking the British imposition of the
rule of law for fomenting Irish discontent in the first place.
It was in an 1880 article on British rule in India that Dicey most explicitly
connected these concerns over civilisational difference to the rule of law. The
article, a review of James Talboys Wheeler’s A Short History of India, was in fact
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
C
Dicey, ‘Egypt’, n 77 above, 420.
ibid, 419.
[A. V. Dicey], ‘England and Ireland’ (1882) 35 Nation 267, 267.
ibid.
ibid.
ibid, 268.
Tulloch, n 29 above, 147; cf Harvie, n 141 above, 306–309.
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
761
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
one of Dicey’s earliest extended reflections on the rule of law.173 For Dicey,
‘[t]he one permanent, certain, indisputable effect of English government in the
East has been the establishment of the rule of law’.174 From the rule of law’s
establishment in India flowed ‘all the blessing, such as it is, and a good half
(one may suspect) of the curses accruing to the natives from the might of the
English crown’.175
On the one hand, British rule in India, Dicey said, had put an end to the
disordered, arbitrary and at times violent government that had prevailed earlier.
Invoking tales of the sadistic killing of criminals who were slated to be freed,
vicious raids by Mahratha rulers to levy excessive taxes on the population
and chaotic processes of succession, Dicey concluded that ‘[t]he establishment
of English supremacy was the substitution of an administration like that of
Rome for anarchy worse than that of the middle ages’.176 For the supposedly
uncivilised peoples of India, the rule of law represented extraordinary and rapid
advancement.
On the other hand, this ‘sudden creation of legal order’ in India also had a
‘dark side [that] may not be as visible to Englishmen, but it will certainly be
seen by future historians’.177 Explicitly drawing on Maine’s work as well as the
English experience in Ireland, Dicey insisted that the rule of law could become
particularly oppressive ‘where foreign tribunals deal with a society of which
they do not understand either the habits or the ideas’.178 Even when trying
to respect Indian customs, British administrators transformed them, thereby
dangerously disrupting existing social hierarchies and the natural course of
civilisational development.179 In the long run, Dicey worried that Britain’s
imperial government would ‘remain in a state of permanent conflict with
the national spirit of its foreign subjects’ in India. ‘[T]he very merits of its
administration’ – chiefly, the rule of law – ‘are likely to add strength to a spirit
of opposition which if allowed head would be fatal to the existence of the
empire’.180
Dicey closed his article on India with a troubled reflection on the coercion
that underlay the rule of law’s export to the subcontinent:
even the attempts to do justice to India may, without supposing any unnatural
perversity on the part of the natives of the country, yet inflict real suffering, or, what
is very much the same thing, the feeling of injury on the mass of the population. The
rule of law should be the rule of justice; but even at its best the rule of law will not
excite affection, and it will often appear to be the rule of unsympathizing force.181
173 [A. V. Dicey], ‘Wheeler’s Short History of India’ (1880) 31 Nation 240; J. Talboys Wheeler, A
Short History of India and of the Frontier States of Afghanistan, Nipal, and Burma (London: Macmillan
and Co, 1880).
174 Dicey, ibid, 240.
175 ibid.
176 ibid, 240–241.
177 ibid, 241.
178 ibid.
179 ibid.
180 ibid.
181 ibid.
762
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
That liberal British rule in India ultimately relied upon force was a point that had
been emphatically pressed, and wholeheartedly embraced, in the authoritarian
liberalism of Dicey’s cousin James Fitzjames Stephen.182 A prominent jurist and
intellectual as well as Maine’s successor as Law Member on the Viceroy’s India
Council, Stephen became – partly as a result of his Indian experience – one
of the harshest internal critics of liberalism, especially for its blindness to the
necessity of the coercive power of law to serve the greater good.183 But where
Stephen unashamedly lauded force as the beneficent engine of law and order
in India, Dicey scrupled. For the man who would soon become known as the
great expounder and partisan of the rule of law, his frank expression of doubt
about its value is an extraordinary conclusion. While Dicey did not propose an
end to the enforcement of the English rule of law in India, he clearly discerned
its capacity to do harm there.
What Dicey’s ambivalence reveals is an unresolved tension within his account
of the rule of law, the different strands of which could pull in different directions.
There was, on the one hand, the unqualified virtue of rule conducted not by
executive caprice but through law that was formally equal. But on the other
hand, for those qualities to be truly instantiated, they had to emerge from
the bottom up through gradual processes of legal development. Thus, after a
steady, centuries-long civilisational progression, the rule of law had in Britain
reached its apogee. But transplanted to the supposedly much less advanced
India, the rule of law could be indistinguishable from foreign domination.
Dicey’s conclusion was a curious mix of English superiority with sentiment at
times edging towards the anti-imperial – and a moment of ambivalence for the
rule of law as both justification for and practice of empire.
CONCLUSION
With rule-of-law talk more globally ubiquitous than ever, it is worth revisiting
the thinking of the person who first made the phrase famous. In particular,
it is worth examining how Dicey’s thinking on the rule of law was shaped
by and responded to the imperial context in which it developed. For those
who continue to invoke Dicey today, whether sympathetically or critically,
seeing the imperial entanglements of Dicey’s rule of law puts it into a new
and revealing light. This article has sought to show how Dicey’s rule of law
emerged from a constitutional culture that was formed not simply out of the
insular materials of British law, politics and history, but also out of the oftenfraught encounters with diverse peoples around the globe over whom Britain
claimed and exercised sovereignty. In Dicey’s account, the rule of law was a
distinguishing mark of English civilisational superiority, one that justified and
underpinned the exercise of British imperial rule. And yet Dicey was forced to
acknowledge that the exigencies of imperial governance required arbitrariness
182 On Stephen’s authoritarian liberalism, see Stokes, n 15 above, 273–310; Metcalf, n 147 above,
56–59; Mantena, n 51 above, 38–46.
183 See especially J. Fitzjames Stephen, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity (New York, NY: Holt & Williams,
1873). See further Roach, n 28 above, 60–67 and the references in the previous footnote.
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
763
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Dylan Lino
and formal inequality at odds with the rule of law and the liberal Empire it
was supposed to uphold. The very civilisational distinctiveness that apparently
made the rule of law so remarkable, and its English possessors so superior, also
at times led Dicey to doubt the justice and wisdom of imposing it upon the
Empire’s ‘uncivilised’ peoples.
At a time when international institutions and powerful Western states are
once again engaged in a global mission to spread the rule of law, the study
of Dicey’s thought may also be instructive in unearthing enduring tendencies
within thinking about the rule of law – and prompt reflection on the role of
such thinking in supporting consequential and controversial political projects.
Where in Dicey’s day the rule of law was seen as the peak of civilisational
achievement – an achievement that licensed and fed into Britain’s imperial
endeavours – it is difficult to escape the conclusion that in our day discourses
of ‘development’ now play the role that ‘civilisation’ once did in sustaining
transnational interventions for promoting the rule of law.184 Dicey’s struggles to marry his liberalism with his imperialism also demonstrate an abiding
challenge: of reconciling the ideals underpinning the rule of law – justice,
non-arbitrariness, equality – with the hierarchy and violence of empire. In
raising hard questions about the globalisation of the rule of law, as Paul Kahn
reminds us, ‘[w]e should not romanticize the possibility of alternatives – real or
imagined – but neither should we assume that the answer is obvious’.185 If the
rule of law is ‘a cultural achievement of universal significance’, it remains an
open question whether the universal significance of that cultural achievement is
attributable to its unimpeachable political attractiveness or to the potency with
which certain of its exponents have been able to foist it – or at least particular
versions of it – upon the rest of the world.186
184 See, for example, S. Pahuja, Decolonising International Law: Development, Economic Growth and the
Politics of Universality (Cambridge: CUP, 2011) ch 5.
185 P. W. Kahn, The Cultural Study of Law: Reconstructing Legal Scholarship (Chicago. Ill: University
of Chicago Press, 1999) 5.
186 Thompson, n 7 above, 265.
764
C
C 2018 The Modern Law Review Limited.
2018 The Author. The Modern Law Review (2018) 81(5) MLR 739–764
14682230, 2018, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-2230.12363 by University Of Sydney, Wiley Online Library on [18/02/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context
Download