Test 1 Review

advertisement
Test 1 Review
Philosophy
•  Love of Wisdom
•  Studies conceptual questions that cannot be
answered solely by an appeal to sense
experience (or mathematical calculation).
•  Relies on logic to evaluate the strength of
arguments.
Main divisions within Philosophy:
•  Metaphysics and Ontology (the study of what
is real or what exists)
•  Epistemology (the study of knowledge)
•  Value Theory (the study of values)
•  Logic (the study of reasoning)
Reasoning
•  An Argument
–  Premises supporting a conclusion
•  What is argued for (the conclusion) is distinct from
what is argued from (the premises or assumptions).
–  Inductive (probabilistic) vs. deductive (which
purports to show that the conclusion follows
necessarily from the premises).
Kinds of Arguments
Inductive:
Deductive:
•  Inductive arguments are
probabilistic. They attempt
to show that if the premises
are true, then the conclusion
is probably true.
•  Deductive arguments are
not probabilistic. They
attempt to show that if the
premises are true, then the
conclusion must be true. A
successful deductive
argument is called a “valid”
argument.
Validity
•  In a valid argument, the truth of the premises
guarantees the truth of the conclusion.
–  I.e., if the premises are all true, then the conclusion
must be true.
•  So, an argument can be valid even with false premises
and a false conclusion. What it cannot have is all true
premises and a false conclusion.
•  Only deductive arguments strive for validity.
In a reductio ad absurdum argument
we begin by assuming the opposite of
what we are trying to prove.
We then derive a contradiction (an
“absurdity”) from this assumption to
show that it cannot be true
(and so that what we are trying to
prove must be true).
Arguments for God’s Existence
•  Ontological:
–  Argues that the concept of God entails God’s
existence
•  Anselm
•  Cosmological:
–  Argues for a cause of the universe
•  Aquinas, Clarke
Knowledge
•  A Priori
–  Claims that can be justified without appeal to sense
experience.
•  The Ontological Argument is the only a priori argument
for the existence of God
•  A Posteriori
–  Claims that can be justified only with (by means
of) an appeal to sense experience.
•  The Cosmological Argument
A priori vs. A posteriori
•  The distinction is not between
–  what caused you to have the idea,
•  but about how
–  how you justify your belief that you know this idea to be true.
•  If an appeal to sense experience (or your memory of one) is
necessary to prove that you know something, this is a
posteriori knowledge.
–  For example, “The sky is blue.
•  If you know something by “pure thinking,” such that no sense
experience could possibly undermine this knowledge, this is a
priori knowledge.
–  For example, “2 + 2 = 4”
Anselm
•  Reasons that the existence of God follows from the
concept of a being than which none greater can be
conceived.
–  Uses a reductio ad absurdum argument
•  Assumes that a being, than which none greater can be conceived,
exists only in the understanding.
•  But, since any being which exists only in the understanding would be
greater if it existed in reality as well, this being is such that a greater
can be conceived.
•  This is a contradiction, and so the assumption must be rejected.
•  Therefore, a being than which none greater can be conceived cannot
fail to exist in reality as well in the understanding.
Anselm’s Argument
(in a nutshell)
•  Claim: A being than which none greater can be
conceived exists necessarily, i.e., its non-existence is
impossible, because denying its existence involves a
contradiction.
•  Reasoning: To say that a being than which none greater
can be conceived exists only in the understanding is to
say that it would be greater if it existed in reality as
well, which means that it (a being than which none
greater can be conceived) is such that I can conceive of
a greater being (the being it would be if existed in
reality as well). And this is contradictory, and so
impossible.
Gaunillo
•  Argues that Anselm’s argument applies equally to an
island such that none greater can be conceived as to a
being than which none greater can be conceived.
•  This means that if Anselm’s argument works to prove
the existence of God, it must also prove the exist of
such an island.
•  But such an island does not exist.
•  So, Anselm’s argument must not work for God either.
Cosmological Argument
•  Begins with a premise, based upon sense experience,
that there are cause/effect relationships in the world.
•  Reasons that there must be a first cause.
•  Aquinas argued that there must be a first cause, or
else the universe would have had an infinitely long
past history, and that it couldn’t have had an infinitely
long past history, because then it wouldn’t have had a
first cause.
–  Aquinas doesn’t take an infinite past seriously, and so his
argument for a first cause begs the question.
Aquinas’s Second Way:
•  1. Some things are caused to exist.
•  2. Nothing can cause itself to exist. (If
so, it would have to “precede itself.”)
•  3. This cannot go on to infinity.
– (His argument for this is on the next
slide.)
•  So, there must be a first cause—an
uncaused causer.
“This cannot go on to infinity.”
“Such a series of [prior] causes must however stop
somewhere…. Now if you eliminate a cause, you also
eliminate its effects, so that you cannot have a last
cause [or “last effect”] … unless you have a first.
Given therefore … no first cause, there would be no
intermediate causes either, and no last effect.”
–  i.e., without a first cause, nothing else would have
happened, and so nothing would be happening now.
–  But things are happening now.
–  So, the series cannot go on to infinity.
Why must the series “stop somewhere?”
•  Aquinas’ Answer:
–  Because without a first cause, nothing else would ever
happen
•  (but, as we know by experience, things have happened).
•  But what is Aquinas trying to prove?
–  That there must be a first cause of the existence of thing,
i.e.,
•  that without a first cause, nothing else would ever have happened!
•  What is wrong here?
Aquinas Begs the Question
•  Aquinas is trying to prove that there must be a “first
cause.”
–  He argues there must be a first cause because otherwise the
series of causes would to on to infinity.
–  He argues the series of causes cannot go on to infinity
because then there would be no first cause.
•  This amounts to arguing that there must be a first
cause because otherwise there wouldn’t be first cause.
“A Modern Formulation of the
Cosmological Argument”
Samuel Clarke
1675-1729
Clarke’s Cosmological Argument
•  Aquinas didn’t seriously consider the possibility that
the universe might have had an infinitely long past
history.
–  Whether or not it could have is the “question” he
“begged.”
•  Clarke says that even if the universe has existed for
eternity, we still need to posit the existence of God to
explain the existence of the entire infinite series of
causes and effects—that is, of the universe as a whole.
Clarke’s Cosmological Argument:
•  1. Suppose (for reductio) that everything
there is is part of an infinite series of
dependent things
–  (where each and every thing is dependent for its
existence upon the existence of some previous
thing, ad infinitum.)
–  that is, suppose that nothing (nothing outside
the natural world) caused the world.
Clarke’s Cosmological Argument:
“´ c Æ” means causes
“∞” means infinity
“D-n” means Dependent Event
∞ .... ´ c Æ D-3´ c Æ D-2´ cÆ D-1´cÆ Now0
An infinite series of dependent events
Clarke’s Cosmological Argument:
•  2. Then the series as a whole has no cause
“from without” (because it is hypothesized to
include everything there is), and
•  3. The series as a whole has no cause “from
within” (If it had a cause from within, then that
thing would be its own cause, making it a
necessary being, violating the assumption).
Clarke’s Cosmological Argument
“´ c Æ” means causes
“∞” means infinity
“D-n” means Dependent Event
∞ .... ´ c Æ D-3´ c Æ D-2´ cÆ D-1´cÆ Now0
An infinite series of dependent events:
What caused it?
Clarke’s Cosmological Argument:
•  4. So the whole series is without any
cause.
•  5. But this cannot be, and so we must
posit the existence of God to explain
the existence of this infinite series.
Question:
•  But why must “the series as a whole”
–  that is, a series of past events, where each is caused
by a previous past event, which is in turn caused
by a previous past event, and so on to infinity-
have a cause or explanation?
•  Can we (must we) explain everything?
Must the whole series have a
cause?
•  There is a deep question here about how
much we can explain.
•  Within Clarke’s “infinite series,” every
individual thing has a cause.
•  Must the series of individual things also
have a cause?
Causes and Explanations
•  We want to explain things.
•  The Cosmological Argument
“posits” (hypothesizes) the existence of
God to explain where the universe (the
“cosmos”) came from.
•  But how much can we explain?
Clarke’s Cosmological Argument
“´ c Æ” means causes
“∞” means infinity
“D-n” means Dependent Event
∞ .... ´ c Æ D-3´ c Æ D-2´ cÆ D-1´cÆ Now0
An infinite series of dependent events:
What caused it?
How much can we explain?
•  If every fact must have an explanation, where can
we stop?
–  If we need God as an explanation of the infinite series,
don’t we need an explanation of God?
–  If some things (like God) don’t need an explanation,
why does the infinite series need an explanation?
•  Which is harder to accept?
–  That some facts cannot, even in principle, ever be
explained; or
–  That there must be some single being that explains
everything, including itself?
What about God?
•  To explain the existence of the entire series of things
and events, Clarke argues
–  we must assume the existence of God.
•  But …
–  If we must explain the existence of everything, mustn’t we
also explain the existence of God?
–  If we don’t have to explain the existence of God, why
should we have to explain the existence of an infinite series
of things and events?
Swinburne:
The Problem of Evil
The Problem of Evil:
•  An all-powerful being would be able to
prevent evil from happening in the world.
•  An all-good being would want to prevent
evil from happening in the world.
•  Evil happens in the world.
•  Therefore, it must not be the case that any
being is both all-powerful and all-good.
“Absence of Good” vs. “Positive
Evil”
•  The problem of evil, many theists say, concerns
not the lack of perfect goodness in the world, but
only the presence of real badness (“positive bad
states”).
•  The theist can admit that the world could be
better in many ways. God, for the theist, is
the source of all goodness, but is not
obligated to create all the goodness she could
have. So, the lack of perfect goodness in the
world is not evidence against the existence of
an all good and all powerful being.
Positive Badness (Real Evil)
•  It is only the existence in the world of
“positive evil” that the theist must explain.
–  These explanations, recall, are called
“theodicies.”
•  Swinburne divides “positive badness” into
to categories, and offers a different theodicy
(explanation) for each. They are:
–  Moral Evil, and
–  Natural Evil
Swinburne’s Theodicy:
Distinguishes moral evil from natural evil.
•  Moral evil is
•  Natural evil is not caused
caused by human
by human beings, but is
beings, and is the
necessary so that human
inevitable result of
beings can use their free
the fact that
will to overcome such evil,
human beings
and so become better
have a free will.
people.
•  He thinks this also applies to
(The “Free Will
animal suffering.
Defense.”)
Swinburne’s Theodicy
•  “Moral Evil” is caused by human freewill, not
by God.
–  So, the “badness” humans cause is “outweighed”
by the goodness of our having free will.
•  “Natural Evil” is created by God because it is
needed in order for us to achieve a greater
amount of goodness.
–  So, again, it’s “badness” is outweighed by a
greater goodness.
Download