Marcuse: Obstinacy as a Theoretical Virtue Andrew Feenberg

advertisement
[Comment on one of Marcuse's last speeches, first published in Capitalism, Nature,
Socialism, Sept. 1992, pp. 38-40.]
Marcuse: Obstinacy as a Theoretical Virtue
Andrew Feenberg
"The task to be accomplished is not the conservation of the past, but the
redemption of the hopes of the past" (Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectic of
Enlightenment, p. xv).
From this last speech of Marcuse's one can get a good idea what he was all about.
The specifics of doctrine are less important than the tone and thrust.
Marcuse was an old man when he gave this speech. Most of us knew him only as an
old man. He spoke slowly, forcefully, with both seriousness and irony, from out of the
depths of history to us who still had no history. Those depths were visible on his face, in
his strongly accented voice. An auditorium full of young students listening to this
powerful, self-assured indictment of the system must have felt the force of a judgement
made from out of those depths, and taken hope.
Marcuse did not express mere personal opinions as we might have; he had the
authority of an intellectual and political tradition. On that basis he unhesitatingly
confronted the contemporary world, however shocking or bizarre his claims might seem
to the conformist consensus of both the establishment and the left. And often he was
right, on the War in Vietnam, nuclear energy, the bankruptcy of socialism in the Soviet
Union, the greatness and the limitations of the New Left, the decline of the proletarian
threat to capitalism, the coming importance of feminism and ecology.
The central question of Marcuse's thought appears clearly in this short speech:
from what standpoint can society be judged now that it has succeeded in feeding its
members? Recognizing the arbitrariness of mere moral outrage, Marx measured
capitalism by reference to an immanent criterion, the unsatisfied needs of the
population. But that approach collapses as soon as capitalism proves itself capable of
delivering the goods. Then the (fulfilled) needs of the individuals legitimate the
established system. Radicalism means opposition, not just to the failures and
deficiencies of that system, but to its very successes.
It takes astonishing nerve to persist in this challenge. But, as Marcuse once wrote,
"obstinacy [is] a genuine quality of philosophical thought" (Negations, p. 143). To be
obstinate means to reject the easy reconciliation with society, to keep a sense of reality
based on longer time spans, deeper tensions, higher goals, than those recognized today
by a fashionable "post-modernism."
Marcuse maintained a critical stance by reference to several parallel registers of
phenomena. First, there are some hard facts that don't go away: the persistance of war,
hunger, periodic ecological catastrophes. Second, there is the aesthetic failure of
contemporary society, the undeniable contradiction between its daily ugliness and
1
criteria of beauty elaborated in millenia of artistic endeavor, both in folk and high art.
Third, there is the equally undeniable fact of massive manipulation of consciousness
through the media and consumerist ideology. Fourth, there are the self-evident
demands for fulfilling work and security of life that remain unmet for the vast majority.
Finally, there is the proliferation of signs and symptoms of deep psychic disturbances
and dissatisfactions beneath the surface glow of success. These signs and symptoms take
both personal and political forms; indeed the distinction between these two forms is
often difficult to make.
What converts this list of discontents into an indictment of the system is the
contention that the benefits of our society are won at this price, that unlike isolated
"problems" that could be solved piecemeal, these issues reveal the inherent limitations
of contemporary capitalism.
This society, Marcuse argues, has the material potential to "pacify" existence but
artificially maintains competition and violence as the basis for domination and
inequality. As he put it in his last speech: "The specter which haunts advanced industrial
society today is the obsolescence of full-time alienation." And further: radical political
struggle today consists in "existential revolts against an obsolete reality principle."
Marcuse's concept of "obsolescence" situates his critique historically. The
revolutionary judgement has always been made in the future anterior tense, as when
Saint-Just imagined what "cold posterity" will have said concerning the absurdity of
monarchy. Thus Marcuse is not merely complaining about a system he doesn't like. He
is imagining how it will appear to a backward glance rooted in the wider context of
values evolved over past centuries and destined to achieve realization in future ones.
The obsolescence of that system will be obvious in this hypothetical future, justifying the
obstinacy of those who persisted in critique through difficult times.
With the collapse of Soviet communism, the last alibi of historicist opposition to
capitalism has died. We can no longer rest our case for change, if we ever did, on the
realized achievements of "socialism." We are one step closer to a world in which only
Marcuse's type of principled opposition is available. His thought has never been more
relevant.
2
Download